Christine Hill Dr. Monica Torres Eng 555 May 4, 2010 I can only describe my experience in The Rhetoric of Science class as a journey that eventually came full-circle. With each reading throughout the semester I found myself more and more intrigued by the ideas of how knowledge is constructed and what is considered “objective” in scientific discoveries. How has science uncovered certain “truths” and how has that knowledge been conveyed? Each reading strengthened and reinforced by understanding of epistemology. We began our readings with Donna Haraway’s Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective. Having no background in the sciences I read the piece and appreciated Haraway’s argument, but had nowhere to place it in my repertoire of feminist understanding . As we continued to read, however, about the social construction of certain types of “truths”, Haraway’s article kept creeping back to me. The fact that science has been a “man’s game” for centuries was hard to get around. It seemed to me that a man’s “situation” or place in the world inevitably influenced him as a scientist and his “objective” knowledge had to be bias given his position. As Simone de Beauvoir said, “Representation of the world, like the world itself, is the work of men; they describe it from their own point of view, which they confuse with the absolute truth” (de Beauvoir 143). It wasn’t until we read The Rhetoric of Risk by Beverly Sauer that I realized I wanted to investigate further the ideas of feminist epistemology and the possible influence more “feminist sciences” would have on the scientific community. Sauer’s discussion in Chapter 5 of “The 79 Rhetoric of Risk” focuses on multiple viewpoints or standpoints and she references Haraway when she says “theories of knowledge production must take into account the situated viewpoints of individuals within economic and social communities” (179). She continues with different arguments that uphold the importance of feminism in rhetorical theory and translates the necessity of feminist theory to the sciences. This chapter more or less solidified my interest in further exploring the ideas of feminist epistemology. What I would like to explore in this paper and in the literature I’ve chosen to discuss1 are varying ideas and theories with regard to feminist epistemology. As I tend to lean toward a more postmodern view of the world I do not place notions of “objectivity” or “truth” as things that are commonly “discovered”. On the other hand, I am not a relativist, and I do acknowledge that science has brought forth discoveries that certainly I cannot argue with given my complete lack of scientific understanding. What I want to uncover are the ways in which “objective” knowledge in science, which has been a traditionally male-dominated field, have been biased, and how feminist epistemology can “un-do” and “re-do” some of the “damage” - damage that has propagated the subjugation of women and other marginalized others. The Egg and the Sperm: How Science Has Constructed a Romance Based on Stereotypical Male-Female Roles by Emily Martin This article originally appeared in Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society in 1991. I begin with this article because it addresses some fundamental issues with regard to I am indebted to Lauren Pressley’s annotated bibliography in finding many of these articles. I have cited her bibliography on my Works Cited page. 1 80 ideological bias in producing “objective” scientific knowledge and how the metaphors used in transmitting this knowledge propagates gendered stereotypes about men and women/boys and girls. The article discusses the metaphors that are used when discussing the reproductive systems of men and women and, primarily, the egg and the sperm. Traditionally and, as the article argues, well into the present, even after new scientific discoveries of the natures of the egg and the sperm have been disclosed, these metaphors persist. Martin gives the histories of how the reproductive system of women have been surrounded by metaphors of death or failure (486). Menstruation has been described as the result of the “death” of the tissue and the “debris” of the uterine lining. Male reproductive systems, on the other hand have been described as “remarkable”, “amazing” and “productive” (486). The roles of the egg and sperm have been translated in textbooks and scholarly articles using much the same rhetoric. The egg, “passive”, the “damsel in distress”, waiting to be “rescued”, “drifts along the fallopian tube”. The sperm on the other hand, undertake a remarkable journey through the deep, dark vaginal passage. The sperm are streamlined, and have an amazing “velocity” that “propels” them along in order to “penetrate” the egg (489). Even when more recent studies in the 1980s revealed the egg’s role as quite active and the sperm’s “velocity” and “strength” not exactly what was originally thought, the metaphors persisted. The egg, with its new active role, was given a Black Widow, spider-like metaphors. The egg “captures and tethers” the sperm and has membrane-bound projections that “reach out and clasp the sperm” (498). Martin argues that we need more egalitarian metaphors and that this is clearly a feminist challenge: to “wake up sleeping metaphors in science”. By doing so, she argues, we can “become aware of their implications” and diminish their power to “naturalize our social conventions about gender”. 81 Martin’s article about uncovering basic, fundamental biases begins my journey into the exploration of finding out how feminist epistemology can aid in uncovering more complex systems of bias and subjugation that exist in the production of scientific “objective” knowledge. Why Gender Is a Relevant Factor in the Social Epistemology of Scientific Inquiry by Kristina Rolin Kristina Rolin’s article is a defense of feminist epistemology and feminist philosophy from critics’ accusations that center around theories of “noncognitive values”. I appreciate Rolin’s extensive description of how social aspects of science are often gendered. Her article and discussion of credibility echoed Latour’s and Woolgar’s discussion only in a more gendered way. Rolin’s main argument is that “1) producing gender-sensitive analyses of the social dimensions of scientific inquiry and 2) examining the relevance of these analyses for normative issues in the philosophy of science” (881) are the main ways in which feminist theories in the sciences contribute to our understanding and production of knowledge. In order to support her argument she explores existing, social, “noncognitive” aspects of epistemology in the scientific community. She focuses on trust, the dynamics of communication, and the distribution of research effort among theories and research programs. Gender, she says, can be both a negative and positive aspect. In a negative light, “gender bias interferes with scientists’ evaluations of colleagues’ trustworthiness or when the gendered dynamics of communication function as obstacles to inclusive and critical dialogue” that make it impossible to reach goals. On the positive side, “sensitivity to gender bias generates a distribution of research effort, thereby increasing the likelihood that alternative theories and hypotheses will be 82 developed and tested” (881). Because of these reasons, she states, gender is a relevant methodological factor in science. The Very Idea of Feminist Epistemology by Lynn Hankinson Nelson Lynn Hankinson Nelson undertakes another defense of feminist epistemology in her article, only she defends it against other feminists and epistemologists. This article outlines important aspects of disagreement among feminists. Some critics, and Nelson quotes Susan Haack, have claimed that “feminist epistemology” is as incongruous - as incongruous as, say, “Republican epistemology” (33). A general claim for such incongruity is “analyses or theories of knowledge which are informed by feminism are incongruous because they constitue a mix of politics and apolitical inquiry and knowledge” (39). Haack, says Nelson, is worried that inquiry will become politicized. Another critic of feminist epistemology, Lorraine Code, has said that epistemology is “a project to construct a monolithic, comprehensive theory of knowledge” (34). Her view of feminist epistemology is that it “would seem to require a basis in assumptions about the essence of women” (34). Code has suggested, says Nelson, that feminist intervene in order to unmask “claims of universality” (40), there needs to be a distance between feminism and epistemology. Nelson, however, sees this as both unnecessary and detrimental. She believes that this would give rise to a justification of “ignoring the insights feminist analysis afford”. Abandoning epistemology - vowing to intervene only from the sidelines in the role of ‘spoilers’ or whistle-blowers - threatens to minimize the force of feminist critiques aimed at revealing these consequences and identifying their sources and implications (41). 83 Nelson argues that epistemology (in general) and feminist epistemology are both nebulous and ambiguous, and must always change. She calls for “…less dismissiveness acrossand more skepticism concerning-the lines alleged to divide us” (45). In Search of Feminist Epistemology by Helen Longino Helen Longino’s article is an dense exploration on what can or should be considered feminist epistemology and, once we have our criteria, what can be done with it? After dismissing both standpoint theory and embodied knowledge as not epistemological she offers her view of “doing” science and “doing” epistemology as feminists. In this way, she says, an approach may be taken to scientific activity with a “feminist sensibility”. Longino goes into a lengthy discussion of six criteria of epistemology and how a feminist sensibility can enhance it. Empirical adequacy entails a general agreement on observational or experiential claims. The standard, according to a feminist sensibility, “is one shared with raceand-class-sensitive research communities as well as with most mainstream communities” (474). Novelty asks that we take an oppositional stance. This would be in line with the works of both Harding and Haraway. Ontological heterogeneity rejects theories of inferiority and “permits equal standing for different types: “difference is resource, not failure” (475). Complexity of relationship draws from work by Evelyn Fox Keller and Anne Fausto-Sterling in that all factors influence others. Applicability to current human needs strives to improve the material aspects of human life (475). Diffusion of power she calls the “practical version” of complexity of relationship. All of these criteria, says Longino, require interpretation in order to fit into a certain context. She advocates “treating them as components of a community set of public standards” 84 that can be applied to the “assessment of theories [and] guiding theory acceptance and rejection” (476). As other authors on my reading list emphasize, Longino realizes that these criteria must constantly change as the “foundations” of epistemology are not fixed (478). Much like other critics of feminist epistemology such as Lorraine Code, to whom Nelson refers, it seems to me that Longino is calling for more intervention by feminists in epistemology. I do not see in Longino’s argument, however, the “dismissiveness” that Nelson sees in Code’s argument. Perhaps that is because throughout Longino’s article she consistently uses and references the term “feminist epistemology”. Feminist Epistemology: An Interpretation and a Defense by Elizabeth Anderson Elizabeth Anderson’s article aims to place feminist epistemology within the branch of “naturalized, social epistemology” in that it studies the influences of gender and gendered experiences on the production of knowledge. She explains that naturalized epistemologists “ask of science that it provide an account of its own activity” (54). Social epistemology, she continues, asks what social or cultural factors contribute to knowledge production. Because both naturalized and social epistemology ask empirical questions it is important to Anderson that a notion of “modest” empiricism be retained and employed by feminist epistemologists even though the very thought of this notion might seem impossible. Empiricism, however, in the “modest” sense, says Anderson, is a “purely methodological doctrine, which rejects a priori commitments to what the content of our theories and models must be”. In this way, the empirical claims feminist epistemologists make about the influence of gender on science can be supported. 85 Anderson investigates certain areas gendered categories such as the “gendered division of theoretical labor”, “gender symbolism and the hierarchy of knowledge”, and “gender symbolism: the content of theories” and, “androcentrism”. Within each of these categories she describes and gives examples of cases of sexism and bias within the scientific community and the knowledge that is produced. She discusses mixed-gender schools and the disadvantages that girls have at the hands of biased teachers and disrupting boys in classrooms; scientists such as Barbara McClintock’s inability to get hired as a professor despite her impressive credentials; and the bias of the literature in science text books with regard to reproduction. She has this to say about gendered symbolism in theoretical models: the models are not sexist but the “trouble lies rather in the extraordinary political salience and rhetorical power of sexist gender ideology, which generates numerous cognitive distortions” (68). In a section entitled “The Local Character of Naturalized Feminist Epistemology” Anderson discusses that feminist epistemologists need not depend upon “global” or “transcendental” claims that “all knowledge is gendered or that rationality as a regulatory epistemic ideal is masculine” (80). She continues by explaining that mixed-gendered communities must work together in their inquiries. Anderson ends her article by saying “without claiming that women, or feminists, have a globally different or privileged way or knowing, naturalized feminist epistemology explains how feminist theory can productively transform the field of theoretical knowledge” (81). By ending her article on this note I think she is simply warning that feminist researchers and critics must take great care not to generalize or over-generalize an idea of “privileged positioning”. This “warning” to take care is a recurrent theme in many of these articles. 86 The Concept of Truth in Feminist Sciences by Geoffrey Gorham Geoffrey Gorham’s article explores and summarizes many of the theorists on my reading list. His article is paramount in helping to deconstruct these arguments regarding “feminist sciences” and he sets up his own theory of how feminist sciences or feminist epistemology might best combat traditional male-dominated scientific “objective” knowledge and “truths”. His argument is to find a “conception of knowledge that captures the objective (epistemic) superiority of the feminist sciences without resorting to the objectivist ‘god-trick’ of traditional epistemology” (100). He investigates the theories of Sandra Harding, Donna Haraway, Helen Longino and Susan Hekman. He quotes Hekman, saying “we need to consider how the feminist sciences can embrace epistemic progress without falling into ‘the universalism and absolutisms of the epistemology they claim to be replacing” (104). He says that ideas of “absolute truth” and “relative truth” are dangerous. He states “it is unclear what is to keep internal realism from degenerating into vulgar epistemological relativism” (106). Based on his understanding of these theorists, he advocates what he calls “truthlikeness”, an idea or theory that is more like the “truth” than an alternative theory. He gives examples of both a linguistic and semantic approach to “truthlinkeness”. A linguistic approach can cause problems with regard to a truth that involve a uniqueness and a fixation that could be construed as an “absolute truth” (107-8). We need more “semantic” alternatives that do not presume a single “truth” and adopts Longino’s call for a “model” that can count as knowledge. “The theories of masculinst sciences can be faulted for importing into models gender relations and stereotypes that have no real-world structural correlate” (111). He continues by saying the models that feminist sciences can offer are more similar to the real-world (111). 87 Gorham’s article helped me to understand of some of the theorists I read, Longino, in particular. I appreciate his ideas of “truthlikeness” and think that there are ways in which “approaching” the “truth”, rather than claiming it, can be beneficial, however I have reservations. My understanding of pragmatism is little to none but its relationship to relativism raises a red flag for me. I do not think, however, that Gorham is rigid in his understanding of “truthlikeness”. It seems to me that he is simply trying to avoid what he calls “epistemological contortions” by looking forward to theoretical progress (111). Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective by Donna Haraway In this article Haraway discusses different “standpoints” from which to criticize traditional Western claims of (objective) knowledge - scientific knowledge, in particular. She is asking not for universal truths but for responsible and accountable theories as to how meaning is made. How can science be objective if it simply another rhetorical practice? Situated knowledge is what I understand to be gained more through experience - cultural or otherwise. Haraway says “I am arguing for politics and epistemologies of location, positioning, and situating, where partiality and not universality is the condition of being heard to make rational knowledge claims” (589). Knowledge is not infinite or universal. Haraway is disturbed by a history of scientific “vision” that claims to be “universal”, limitless - the “gaze” that objectifies everything. She suggests reclaiming the sense of vision in order to unmask the scientific tricks in order to make objectivity more grounded and “particular” rather than limitless and “irresponsible”. Again, she is stressing accountability. “Only partial perspective”, she says, “promises objective vision” (583). Haraway introduces her vision for 88 feminist objectivity: it is about “limited located and situated knowledge, not about transcendence and splitting of subject and object. It allows us to become answerable for what we learn and see” (583). Also discussed are the different standpoints and the “preferred” positions of seeing, of “vision”. The “standpoint of the subjugated” is one such preferred position because in principle they are seen as “least likely to allow denial of the critical and interpretive core of all knowledge” (584). However, “subjectivity is multidimensional; so, therefore is vision” subjugation is “not grounds for an ontology”. Haraway also discusses the agency of the world in emphasizing her claim that humans simply aren’t in charge. We are as finite as the knowledge we are able to produce. Rather than trying to control what we are given I agree with Haraway that we must simply get along with it and “structure” it as best we can. Conclusion The articles that I have discussed barely scratch the surface of the literature on feminist epistemology. Many of the authors I read stress the importance of realizing the “great care” that must be taken when doing the work of feminist epistemology. Care must be taken not to fall into the trap of ideological bias. I was surprised to learn of the criticisms within the feminist community but was incredibly impressed with how these authors deftly handled the criticisms. Their arguments are valid, strong and well-articulated. Another surprise was the realization that these articles were sort of locked within a certain time-frame. Curiously, with the exception of Kristina Rolin’s article most on my list were written in the 1980s and 90s as were the majority of the readings in Lauren Pressley’s bibliography. This leads me to ask several questions: Why has 89 this discussion taken a “back seat” in the first decade of the twenty-first century? Was it simply fashionable in the last two decades of last century? Are we already so entrenched in a postfeminist era that this issue has become “irrelevant”? I look forward to investigating these questions and continuing this incredibly interesting journey that I’ve begun. I am also looking forward to the possibly arduous task of unearthing contemporary authors, articles and views that also discuss theories of feminist epistemology that include other marginalized groups. This subject has become infinitely fascinating and important to me on one level as a scholar but on another level as a mother of a young daughter. After researching the literature on this subject I will forever be aware and try to instill in her an awareness of the biases that are so often at the heart of what is conveyed as “objective” and “true”. 90 Works Cited Anderson, Elizabeth. "Feminist Epistemology: An Interpretation and a Defense." Hypatia 10.3 (1995): 50-84. Print. de Beauvoir, Simone. “The Second Sex. Trans. H. M Parshley. New York: Vintage, 1989. 143. Print. Gorham, Geoffrey. "The Concept of Truth in Feminist Sciences." Hypatia 10.3 (1995): 99-116. Print. Haraway, Donna. "Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective." Feminist Studies 14.3 (1988): 575-99. Print. Longino, Helen E. "In Search of Feminist Epistemology." Monist 77.4 (1994): 472-79. Print. Martin, Emily. "The Egg and the Sperm: How Science has Constructed a Romance Based on Stereotypical Male-Female Roles." Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 16.3 (1991): 485-501. Print. Nelson, Lynn Hankinson. "The Very Idea of Feminist Epistemology." Hypatia 10.3 (1995): 3149. Print. Pressley, Lauren. "Whose Knowledge is it Anyway? Feminist Epistemology and Science: An Annotated Bibliography." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Edward Zalta. N.p., 1 Dec. 2005. Web. 6 May 2010. <http://laurenpressley.com/papers/feminist_epistemology.pdf>. Rolin, Kristina. "Why Gender is a Relevant Factor in the Social Epistemology of Scientific Inquiry." Philosophy of Science 71 (2004): 880-91. Print. Sauer, Beverly. The Rhetoric of Risk. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 2003. 179. Print. 91