Husserl Intentionality and Temporality Last time we focused our attention on the two reductions which reveal and explore the object of Husserlian phenomenology: sphere of pure consciousness. Our consideration of the results of the phenomenological epoché revealed a 'phenomenological residuum.' This residuum was provisionally and inadequately characterized as the 'halo of consciousness' which accompanies any intending. Without phenomenologically clarifying the being of this residuum (we'll talk about that today) Husserl draws a fundamental distinction between the mediate, limited, adumbrative character of our intuition of a 'transcendent' object and the immediate, absolute and entire intuition of an act of consciousness. Giving this distinction an epistemological spin, Husserl concludes that there is an indubitability in the intuition of an act of consciousness that is wholly lacking in the intuition of a transcendent thing. Truth, "absolute actuality," is a feature of the intuition of immanent, rather than transcendent, objects. The eidetic reduction focuses on this 'absolute actuality' and in the process highlights the "counter-sensical" (to the natural attitude) implications of the reduction itself. Fundamental to the natural attitude is a commitment to a dualistic phenomenalism. But even in the natural attitude, there is no logical impossibility in the idea that there is no 'deeper' reality beyond that which we experience. We can go even further by noting that whatever we have to say about this 'other world' it is nonetheless true that "whatever physical things are…they are as experienceable physical things." By implication, the essential feature of any experience is precisely that it is experienced, i.e., that it refers back to consciousness itself, that what is, is for consciousness per se. Once again, the natural attitude is shown to suggest its own limits, motivating the epoché. What is revealed in this instance is the being of the phenomenological residuum: consciousness itself. It survives the absolute annihilation of the epoché. As such its being is absolute; all other beings refer necessarily to it and it refers to nothing else. Pure consciousness is then an entirely self-contained complex. As the Heidegger quotation (IHP 89) highlights, one of the most important dimensions revealed by the reductions is the theme of intentionality: the fact that consciousness is always ‘consciousness of.’ The key aspect of the theme as Husserl articulates it here is its horizonality. Every actual intentive process is accompanied by a horizon of potential processes. For example, when consciousness is directed at a physical object, accompanying horizons include: the intended but not directly perceived adumbrations of the thing, the other possible objects of our perceptive attention that could become actual objects of perception, temporal horizons, etc. It is important to recognize that these horizons are not indeterminate 'somethings.' They are what Husserl calls "predelineated" potentialities, which means that they reveal a conformity to type that can be reflectively revealed in eidetic analysis. This opens up the possibility of what Husserl calls "intentional analysis." This is not analysis of the psychological or logical sort (which consists of breaking a phenomenon up into its constitutive parts) but is rather, "…an uncovering of the potentialities 'implicit' in actualities of consciousness…" Noesis and Noema In order to understand the structure of the intentionality of consciousness, Husserl again points us to the "threshold of phenomenology," but instead of attempting to motivate the epoché, he is here concerned with a "wholly fundamental" distinction between two moments of the intentional structure: there are those elements of the structure which are part of the intentive process and there are those elements which are part of the intentional correlates of those intentive processes. The task of intentional analysis, in its most rigorous form, is the elucidation of the essential (eidetic) structures of the noetic and noematic moments of the intention. The really inherent moments of the intentive process are labeled by Husserl Noetic. Their shared essence lies in the animation of a sense or sense-complex, what the text characterizes as “presenting…an objectivity” (IHP 91). Starting in the Logical Investigations, Husserl typically distinguishes two dimensions of this presentation, which together specify any intentional act’s ‘essence:’ quality and material. Quality refers to the mode of the intention, for example, as being posited (the modes/qualities of doubting, wishing, questioning). The material of the intentional act refers to the internal structure of the act, which can be simple or complex. The really inherent moments of the correlates of the intentive process are labled by Husserl Noematic. Their shared essence is animation by Sinngebung (sense-giving or sense-bestowal). Ex.: Remembering. The noetic moment is the animation of a sense in the particular mode of "recollection;" the noematic moment is the remembered as remembered. Of the two, it is the Noematic moments of the intentional analysis that are the most likely to cause confusion. This is because there is a common tendency to confuse the noematic structures of a meaning-giving act, with the object of the act itself. It is the remembered as remembered, not the remembered itself which has phenomenological significance. Evidence The theme of evidence is one of the most important in Husserl's phenomenology. Remember that from the beginning (Kant) the issues animating the transcendental turn have been truth and skepticism. The analysis of what counts as evidence for an assertion is Husserl's response to these issues. Husserl definitively links truth/acutality with rational showing/grounding. As we will see, Husserl thinks this connection between reason and truth in terms of 'presence.' There are a number of distinctions that recommend themselves when we establish the link between truth and showing. 1. In the intending of a thing, the thing can be given to us "originally," or it can be given to us "non-originally" (ex., apple tree, remembering the apple tree). 2. In the intending of a thing, the thing can be given to us "adequately" or it can be given to us "inadequately" (ex., 2+2=4, remembering the apple tree). 3. In the intending of a thing can be given to us "purely" or it can be given to us "impurely" (ex., strata of sense 'material' in perception of apple tree, apple tree). The task we face is to determine what, in the relationship between these distinctions, determine whether a given intentional structure is adequately or inadequately evident. Husserl's analysis here should be anticipated: physical presentation is never adequate, only intellectual is. What may not be anticipated is the flexibility of the criteria: each mode of givenness admits of a specific evidentiary requirment. What connects them all is the primacy given to a specific mode of presentation--a specific mode of the present. Temporality Though intentionality is the fundamental form of consciousness, when we turn to consciousness itself, we find as its most fundamental structure what Husserl calls “time consciousness” (IHP 101).