Chapter 3 RISK, PRE-EMPTION, AND THE LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW John Child and Adrian Hunt Introduction At the core of state driven approaches to criminal justice is the concept of criminalisation. Formally speaking, the initial stage of criminalisation involves the identification of behaviour thought serious or dangerous enough to merit criminal punishment. However the mere identification of such behaviour is not sufficient to criminalise the behaviour. Rather the behaviour must be defined in legislation as a criminal offence. This chapter is concerned with a number of key trends and issues associated with the process of identifying behaviour thought worthy of criminalisation, as well as the process of definition of such behaviour as a criminal offence. Our particular focus is the use of the process of criminalisation as a tool for pre-empting harm, and therefore punishing those whose behaviour creates the risk that harm may result from their actions. As will be explained in the next section of this chapter, the use of criminal offences as a pre-emptive tool is distinguishable from their use as an instrument for punishing those who have already caused concrete harms. The popular conception of criminalisation tends to assume it is concerned with behaviour which has caused harm; however in reality the use of the criminal law in its pre-emptive mode – that is to say defining offences which punish those whose behaviour creates the risk that harm may result from their actions – is a pervasive trend. The use of the criminal law in its pre-emptive mode involves extending the boundaries of the criminal law such that it may catch a host of behaviours and actions which are significantly divorced from actually causing concrete harms. In so doing therefore it involves a conscious choice by the state formally to regulate, control or punish actions which would otherwise fall to be controlled, if at all, by informal societal sanctions. Therefore in exploring the use of criminal offences as a pre-emptive tool we are concerned with one of the indicators of the formal boundaries of the “criminal justice system”. In this chapter we raise issues associated with justifications for using criminal law as a pre-emptive tool. In so doing we identify and explain a number of different ways in which criminal offences may be defined or used as instruments of preemption. We then proceed to examine the consequences of different approaches adopted to defining such offences with a view to examining whether the types of preemptive offences currently in use reflect a coherent, consistent and principled justification for criminalisation of such behaviour. ~ 23 ~ Pre-emptive offences and other criminal offences distinguished The paradigm of criminal law in the liberal tradition involves proscribing culpable actions of persons where those actions cause criminal harm.1 All elements of the paradigm are the object of constant debate including questions concerning which type of harm is an appropriate target for criminalisation and what should the relationship be between culpability on the one hand and the type and seriousness of the harm caused on the other. However, one feature of the paradigm which is constant is that criminal liability arises only after the harm has been caused. Although there may be some ex ante protection through the deterrent effect of the threat of punishment, nonetheless criminal liability only arises after the victim has actually suffered the criminal harm. It is arguable that if one accepts that these harms are sufficiently serious and wrongful to justify the imposition of criminal sanction, then it is not unreasonable to suggest that the criminal law ought to be employed to protect people from such harms being caused in the first place by facilitating official intervention before the resulting harm can arise from an offender’s conduct. As Anthony Duff argues ‘[a] law that condemned and punished actually harm-causing conduct as wrong, but was utterly silent on attempts to cause such harms, and on reckless risk-taking with respect to such harms, would speak with a strange moral voice.’2 Thus most developed legal systems have long provided for a mode of criminalisation which departs from the paradigm.3 This mode criminalises conduct or actions where the offence in question may be characterised as ‘non-consummate’ because the conduct proscribed ‘does not cause harm on each and every occasion in which it is performed.’4 These offences, which are variously referred to as ‘inchoate’ [i.e. just begun], or ‘precursor’5 or ‘pre-emptive’6 or ‘preparatory’7 crimes, come in a variety of different forms. The paradigmatic pre-emptive offences are what may be termed the generally applicable inchoate offences, which target persons who attempt8 to commit, or conspire,9 assist or encourage10 others to commit a principal offence. By definition, attempting, conspiring (i.e. agreeing) assisting or encouraging comes before the substantive harm results. These general inchoate offences therefore facilitate intervention at an earlier stage, with no requirement that the substantive harm results at all. Referred to by J.C. Smith as the ‘normal’ mode of definition. ‘The Element of Chance in Criminal Liability’ [1971] Smith, Criminal Law Review 63. 2 Criminal Attempts (1996), Duff R.A, Clarendon Press: Oxford, 134. 3 For example, see ‘Taking the Will for the Deed: The Mediaeval Criminal Attempt’ (1992) Kiralfy, The Journal of Legal History 95. 4 ‘The Nature and Justifiability of Non-consummate Offenses’ (1995) Husak, 37 Arizona Law Review 151, 158. 5 Blackstone’s Guide to The Ant-Terrorism Legislation (2nd ed. 2009) Walker C, Oxford University Press, 182. 6 ‘Seeking Security by Eroding Rights: The Side-stepping of Due Process’ in Security and Human Rights (2007) Zednar, in Goold B J and Lazarus L (eds), Hart Oxford, 259 7 ‘Expanding the Boundaries of Inchoate Crimes The Growing Reliance on Preparatory Offences’ in Regulating Deviance The Redirection of Criminalisation and the Futures of Criminal Law (2009) McSherry, in McSherry B, Norrie A, and Bronitt S (eds), Hart, Oxford, 141. 8 Contrary to the Criminal Attempts Act 1981, s1. 9 Contrary to the Criminal Law Act 1977, s1. 10 Contrary to the Serious Crime Act 2007, Part 2. 1 ~ 24 ~ It should be recognised that there are difficult decisions to be made about criminalising conduct which is prior or preparatory to perceived or feared resulting harms. The legislature and/or the courts have to determine ‘the point – within the succession of stages along the criminal path’11 at which it is justifiable to impose criminal liability and punishment. Should criminal liability attach to early preparatory acts, or should it be confined to acts which are close in causal and time related proximity to the feared or intended resulting harm? Imposing liability for the former certainly facilitates pre-emptive action; but it involves an even more tenuous link with the harm paradigm. Thus in the current British law of attempts, for instance, criminal liability attaches only to acts which are ‘more than merely preparatory to the commission of the offence’.12 Therefore, although attempt in British law is clearly a departure from the paradigm since it clearly allows for intervention before any harm has resulted, nonetheless there is some relationship between the conduct and the feared resulting harm in the sense that clearly the risk that the harm may result is greater the further along the path of criminal preparation the offender has progressed. However, the catalogue of non-consummate offences available to British authorities is not confined to the general inchoate offences. It also includes: Double/infinite inchoate General Offences: For example conspiring with someone to encourage someone else to commit a principal offence; Bespoke inchoate offences: these are substantive offences that are defined in an inchoate form. For example, the harm associated with fraud by false representation relates to the causing of an illicit gain or loss by way of a misrepresentation. The Fraud Act 200613 does not require that gain or loss actually occurs as a consequence of the misrepresentation (it merely requires the person intended his or her misrepresentation to cause this harm); Endangerment offences: focusing on risk creating conduct. For example, the offence of driving having drunk more than the prescribed limit of alcohol14 criminalises a driver for creating the risks associated with drink driving, regardless of whether they cause any damage/harm as a consequence of their drink driving; and Possession offences: Where persons are criminalised for mere possession of things which are considered to be dangerous and therefore may (in the future) lead to harm. For example, possession of a firearm without a certificate.15 Hereafter, we will refer to these offences collectively as preparatory offences. 16 Not only are these forms of inchoate liability very common within the criminal law, as we will later explore, they are also capable of biting very much earlier in the process than is the case with the general inchoate offences. ‘Responding to Acts Preparatory to the Commission of a Crime: Criminalization or Prevention?’ (2006) Ohana, 25 Criminal Justice Ethics 23. 12 Criminal Attempts Act 1981, s. 1(1) 13 S. 2. 14 Contrary to the Road Traffic Act 1988, s5(1). 15 Contrary to the Firearms Act 1968, s1. 16 We employ the label preparatory offences to distinguish these kinds of inchoate offences from the general inchoate offences. It is a distinction in form and labelling that is explored by Mc Sherry in ‘Expanding the Boundaries of Inchoate Crimes The Growing Reliance on Preparatory Offences’ in Regulating Deviance The Redirection of Criminalisation and the Futures of Criminal Law (2009) McSherry B, Norrie A, and Bronitt S (eds), Hart, Oxford, 141. 11 ~ 25 ~ There remains considerable academic controversy about inchoate offences despite their seemingly increasing popularity with the legislature. How remote from or proximate to the anticipated or feared prospective harm may/must the conduct in question be in order to give rise to criminal liability? Is remoteness or proximity in this context to be judged by reference to causative effect; temporal factors; level or degree of danger or possibility that the harm would result or a combination of the all of the above? How relevant is the relative seriousness of the prospective harm anticipated or feared to the decision to impose criminal liability for the conduct? To what extent, if any, is the person’s culpability as regards the feared resulting or anticipated harm relevant to the imposition of criminal liability? Must they intend their conduct to result in the harm, or at least be aware of the danger that it will result, or is likely to result in it; or is it sufficient that they are indifferent to, or perhaps subjectively entirely unaware of, the danger even if a ‘reasonable’ person would be alive to it? In acknowledging these issues we are presented with the problem that if we maintain harm as the paradigm of the criminal law, then we must recognise inchoate liability as an exception to or (minimally) an extension of that paradigm. Therefore, to employ the criminal law to punish persons in the absence of primary resulting harms – to extend the boundaries of the criminal liability – we must identify special justifications.17 The requirement of a special justification or a compelling reason for extending the law in this way is most expressly evident within debates surrounding the general inchoate offences. In a recent flurry of Law Commission18 publications in this area, the Commission evidently still believes that it not only has to restate the advantages of inchoate liability in terms of pre-empting future harm, but that in certain cases it must do so in order to justify their very existence. 19 Then, having established a basis, we are led in each case through a detailed discussion of where the lines of criminal intervention should be drawn. We balance the ability of the police to make a timely intervention against the opportunity of the defendant to change his or her mind: we examine whether reliance placed on the mental element of the offence (often gained through confessions) will expose the defendant to the risk of police abuse: and we examine the relative culpability of an offender as his or her conduct moves closer to the principal harm and so on. Consistent principles of liability are identified and then applied.20 However, as we have already identified, inchoate liability extends back considerably further than the core general inchoate offences. Therefore, in the light of our discussion above, it would be reasonable to imagine that these preparatory offences are subject to a similar level of scrutiny. In fact, as many of these offences are designed to criminalise persons at a considerably earlier stage than is the case with the general inchoate offences, (hence the need for the offences at all), the justifications for their existence must surely be even more special. However, preparatory offences have too often been perceived as special exceptions that are not subject to the more general rules and not subject to the same levels of scrutiny. Indeed, it is almost as if their specialism somehow exempts them from any discussion about whether they cast the net of criminality too widely. This is a phenomenon that It is the exploration of these ‘special’ justifications that we turn to in the second part of this chapter. The Law Commission was established by the Law Commissioners Act 1965, with the express statutory purpose of promoting the reform of the law. 19 See, for example, Conspiracy and Attempts: A Consultation Paper (Law Com Consultation No. 183, 2007) The Law Commission, Part 2. 20 This is discussed in the second part of this chapter. 17 18 ~ 26 ~ seems to touch the work of several academics,21 and can be perceived in the work of the Law Commission. For example, in the recent review of attempts liability, the Commission sets out a list of preparatory offences that criminalise the conduct of persons before they have reached the stage of an attempt.22 They also observe that, aside from hypothetical examples, the list of offences is so comprehensive that they are not able to demonstrate any previous cases that fell short of an attempt that were not caught by one of these preparatory offences. Yet despite the cumulative breadth of these offences, despite their inconsistencies in terms of physical and mental elements, the Commission simply presents them as a background to their sole focus of the general offence of attempt. The problem with this is that when we reach a discussion of the boundaries of the criminal law based upon the consultation questions, we are not discussing the true boundary. Even if consultees had accepted the modest extension proposed by the Commission to create a new offence of criminal preparation,23 such an offence would still be preceded by a collection of preparatory offences. In the next part of this chapter, we explore the potential justifications for inchoate non-consummate offences. We analyse not only the principles governing the boundaries of attempts and conspiracies, but also those governing other inchoate exceptions to the harm paradigm. In so doing it is important not to imply that justifications have never or could never be made for the various preparatory offences. The problem is not always simply a lack of justification, but that such offences are too often viewed, and therefore appraised, within a vacuum rather than as part of a system of preparatory offences which ought to form a coherent whole. Therefore we ask whether the justifications which are offered for the general inchoate offences can be generalised across other similar offences, and if not, why not? A Search for Coherence A search for coherence requires a search for legal principles underpinning and shaping the expansion of the criminal law beyond the harm paradigm. As the physical part (otherwise known as the conduct element or actus reus) of the inchoate offences move further away from the anticipated harm, how are these offences constructed in order to justify the continued use of criminal sanctions? The obvious starting point for this inquiry is to focus on the governing principles which the Law Commission recently identified as being relevant for the purposes of justifying the imposition of criminal liability for the general inchoate offences of attempt, conspiracy and assisting and encouraging. The Commission’s recent review of these offences, which resulted in recommendations for a further 21 For example, most criminal law textbooks discuss the boundaries of the criminal law in relation to general inchoate offences without more than a passing aside about other preparatory offences that will criminalise certain conduct at a considerably earlier stage. 22 Conspiracy and Attempts: A Consultation Paper (Law Com Consultation No. 183, 2007) The Law Commission, Appendix C. 23 Conspiracy and Attempts (Law Com No. 318, 2009) The Law Commission [8.1-8.82]. The Commission have presented this not as an extension, but as a return to the original intentions of the legislature. ~ 27 ~ broadening of the law,24 identified two separate (but interrelated) governing principles which are important within this context. The first principle is that, although the future harm may not yet have arisen, the actus reus of the offence must still target conduct which (of its nature) gives rise to a sufficient cause for concern: conduct that creates a risk or danger of the ultimate harm occurring such that this justifies official intervention before it comes about. Thus, for criminal attempts, in the Commission’s view, this required police to wait until a person’s actions have gone beyond mere preparation towards the commission of the principal offence; they must therefore have reached a stage in the criminal pathway such that the risk of harm occurring effectively outweighs the potential that they may desist voluntarily.25 For conspiracy and assisting and encouraging, the Commission focused on the increased likelihood of the harm coming about where people collude in their activities.26 Thus, although a person’s actions might be further removed from the eventual harm than is the case with an attempt (not going beyond mere preparation), the act of collusion itself manifests a comparable level of danger that the harm may come about, such as to justify official intervention. The second principle focuses on the blameworthiness (otherwise known as the mental element or the mens rea) of the offender. Here, adopting the language of Ashworth, the Commission states that: ... as the form of criminal liability moves further away from the infliction of harm, so the grounds of liability should become more narrow. 27 Starting with the remoteness of the actus reus from the eventual harm, this second principle (which the Commission calls the remoteness principle) goes considerably further than the first in terms of satisfying the objectives of our current inquiry. This is not simply because the remoteness principle dictates that inchoate offences should require high threshold levels of mens rea. It is also because it purports to provide a basis for extending liability in an objectively measurable coherent manner: as we move further from the feared resulting harm, a higher degree of mens rea is required in order to maintain a broadly consistent level of culpability, 28 a level required to justify the imposition of criminal sanctions. The normative and practical importance of this second principle (if applied consistently) and the logic of its approach should not be underestimated. Seeking to maintain a constant standard through the balancing of actus reus and mens rea requirements, the remoteness principle purports to provide a basis for safeguarding 24 The broadening has focused particularly on the mens rea requirements of each offence. See, Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime (Law Com No 300, 2006) The Law Commission, and Conspiracy and Attempts (Law Com No 318, 2009) The Law Commission. The former provided the basis of the Serious Crime Act 2007, Part 2. 25 This does not represent a change from the position under the current law as stated in the Criminal Attempts Act 1981, s1. 26 Conspiracy and Attempts: A Consultation Paper (Law Com Consultation 183, 2007) The Law Commission [2.11-2.19]. 27 Principles of Criminal Law (5th ed, 2006) Ashworth, Oxford University Press, 423. Endorsed by the Commission in Conspiracy and Attempts: A Consultation Paper (Law Com Consultation 183, 2007) The Law Commission [1.6-1.7] and Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime (Law Com No 300, 2006) The Law Commission [5.86]. 28 We are assuming that other variables, for example the maximum penalty for the principal offence and the wrong constituted by the actus reus of that offence, remain constant. For a wider discussion of the role played by these variables, see ‘Crimes of ulterior intent’ (1996) Horder in Harm and Culpability, Simester and Smith (eds), Clarendon Press, 153. ~ 28 ~ against the creation of inchoate offences that criminalise insufficiently culpable behaviour.29 Indeed, there is a relationship between the mental element and the risk/dangerousness associated with the conduct element where the former has an impact on the latter. Engaging in particular conduct with the intention that that conduct will contribute towards the commission of a criminal offence clearly presents a greater prospect that the resulting harm (the criminal offence) will occur than might be the case if the person engaging in the conduct has some version of mens rea below ‘intention’. The remoteness principle ought also to operate as a basis for ensuring that offences targeting the different stages of a person’s behaviour leading up to an eventual harm do not undermine one another. Thus, for a criminal attempt it is always necessary for a person to intend to bring about the principal offence,30 even if the definition of the principal offence itself does not require intention. Therefore, where it is clear that the defendant has satisfied the actus reus of the principal offence (brought about the harm), it will always be more appropriate for a prosecutor to charge them with that principal offence rather than with criminal attempt. Were the mens rea of the attempt or conspiracy or other inchoate offence to be less restrictive than that of the principal offence, prosecutors would have an incentive to charge the inchoate offence even where the harm had been brought about. This would cause problems both in terms of sentencing and fair labelling, since the charge would not reflect the full extent of the defendant’s crime, and would have the potential to make the substantive offences redundant.31 In this manner, an apparently straightforward principle linking the remoteness of a person’s conduct to the level of mens rea required for inchoate liability has the potential to provide the consistency and coherence that we are searching for. Just as we can identify the natural limits of the spectrum of mens rea (intention), so we may also identify the limits of the actus reus: the most remote behaviour that a person can be justifiably criminalised for on the basis of his or her intention to cause a future harm. Furthermore, in practice it can serve to discourage prosecutors from undercutting substantive offences, and contribute to the normative concerns associated with fair labelling. However, as the physical remoteness of the general inchoate offences have already required a mens rea of ‘intention’,32 it is arguable that it is difficult to see how 29 For example, if a shopkeeper sells a product intending the buyer to use that product for an illegal purpose then it is right to prosecute him for assisting the future offence. However, if the shopkeeper sells the product merely foreseeing the possibility that it might be used for such a purpose, the imposition of criminal sanctions are likely to appear unwarranted. For further discussion, see Inchoate Liability for Assisting and Encouraging Crime (Law Com No 300, 2006) The Law Commission [5.87]. 30 The Criminal Attempts Act 1981, s1. Although recklessness may in some instances be sufficient in relation to the circumstance element (see, R v Khan [1990] 1 W.L.R. 813), this will only arise where the circumstance element of the principal offence requires a mens rea of recklessness or less. Further, intention is still required for the act and result elements. In this manner, the essence of the offence is still the requirement of intention. 31 The Commission also recognises this danger in their discussion of conspiracy, stating unequivocally that the creation of a disincentive to charge a substantive offence in favour of an inchoate alternative would ‘not be right’. Conspiracy and Attempts: A Consultation Paper (Law Com Consultation 183, 2007) The Law Commission [4.55-4.56]. 32 The exception being the reformed offences of assisting and encouraging (Serious Crime Act 2007, Part 2) that require varying levels of mens rea including belief as to the principal offender’s future conduct and recklessness as to the future consequences and surrounding circumstances of that conduct. However, it is important to note that where the mens rea of the principal offence requires a higher ~ 29 ~ preparatory offences can be structured to target conduct that is further removed from the eventual harm: if ‘intention’ is the highest level of fault then it is arguable that the general inchoate offences should also mark the physical boundaries of the criminal law. However, as we have already explained above, the statute book contains a multitude of preparatory offences that target conduct that is more remote from harm than that targeted by the general inchoate offences. The first category of preparatory offences targets conduct (more remote from harm than the general inchoate offences) only when the person intends that the eventual harm should come about. The most widely applicable example of this form of liability can be identified through double or infinite inchoate liability. This form of liability criminalises a person (D) for conduct which is a further step removed from the principal offence, for example, where D conspires with Y to encourage Z to commit an offence.33 For liability to arise D must intend that Y should encourage Z, and must also intend that Z commit the principal offence. The problem here is that, although D’s conduct is a further step removed from the eventual harm than is the case with conspiracy to commit the principal offence, the mens rea of intention is not fundamentally different from that required if D was conspiring with Y to commit the offence directly. As a result, double inchoate liability appears to be inconsistent with the remoteness principle, leading to potential problems relating to inappropriate extensions of the law and the undermining of more proximate offences. Of course it is possible to construct a justification for double inchoate liability. In the above example, it is not sufficient that D intended Z to commit the principal offence; D must also intend Y to encourage Z to do so. Therefore, although the level of fault (intention) has not changed from a standard conspiracy, there are further aspects of the offence that must be intended. However, even if one were to accept this justification of double inchoate liability,34 several other preparatory offences of similar physical remoteness do not include this added double intention requirement. For example, section 25(1) of the Theft Act 1968 criminalises persons for possession of any article with the intention to use that article to commit theft or burglary. With this offence, as with others of a similar construction, the conduct element is considerably further removed than a criminal attempt for example, and yet an intention to commit the future offence is deemed as a sufficient mens rea. The problems which this approach throws up can be demonstrated by the simple example of someone (D) intentionally shooting a victim (V). In this example, when D first acquires the firearm, they may well become liable for a possession offence (possession of a firearm with intent by means thereof to endanger life);35 as D goes beyond mere preparation towards the shooting of V, there will be liability for attempted murder;36 and when the harm (V’s death) is brought about, D will be liable degree of fault, D’s mens rea will reflect that higher standard. Therefore, for the most serious offences (used as examples in much of this chapter) D will still require intention. 33 The breadth of conduct coming within this form of liability has been considerably expanded by the Serious Crime Act 2007, Part 2. Notably, for example, it is now an offence for D to assist or encourage P to form a conspiracy with another party to commit a principal offence. 34 Although we recognise the desirability of certain forms of double inchoate liability, we are not inclined to accept this line of defence. This is because, as D moves further steps from the eventual harm, the causal role played by his or her conduct will be significantly reduced. We do not accept that an intention that another party should play their intermediate part is sufficient replacement. 35 The Firearms Act 1968, s16(1). 36 Contrary to the Criminal Attempts Act 1981, s1. We are assuming that D does not have a valid defence. ~ 30 ~ for murder.37 One can identify a raising of the mens rea requirement between the substantive offence and the attempt38 (in line with the principle explained above) since liability for murder will arise if D intends to kill or intends to cause grievous bodily harm, whereas liability for attempted murder will only arise if D intends to cause death. However, there appears to be little difference in mens rea terms to mark the difference between attempt and the possession offence. Whilst it is not our suggestion that this behaviour with the appropriate intent ought not necessarily to be a criminal offence, it is not consistent with the remoteness principle which it is claimed ought to provide a consistent basis for deciding where to draw the line between conduct which may or may not justifiably be criminalised. Furthermore the possession offence provides the distinct possibility of undermining more proximate offences (in this case the criminal attempt).39 Despite the problems just explained with this category of inchoate offences, we can identify other categories of offence which present an even more serious challenge to the coherence of the law in this area. This is because, although the majority of preparatory offences, like those just mentioned, require persons to intend to bring about a future harm, there are other offences which in addition to targeting similarly remote conduct, require a mens rea less than full intention. For example, section 15(2) of the Terrorism Act 2000 provides that a person commits an offence if they receive money and they either intend using that money for terrorist purposes, or have ‘reasonable cause to suspect that it may be used’ for such purposes. Although receiving money is considerably earlier in the criminal pathway than an attempt to provide financial support for terrorist purposes, the ‘reasonable cause to suspect’ requirement involves a standard of mens rea which is lower than intention. Therefore this offence departs considerably from the remoteness principle in relation to both actus reus and mens rea requirements, rendering it almost impossible to reconcile within our search for coherence. As such, offences within this category pose a considerable risk of inappropriate criminalisation as well as undermining other more proximate offences. Of course, it is certainly the case that when offences within this category are examined individually, out of context with other inchoate offences, it may be possible to justify their existence. This is because, although they are inconsistent with principles identified generally to guide the expansion of inchoate liability, we certainly would not deny that the future harms that they are designed to prevent (focusing overwhelmingly in recent times upon terrorism and sexual offences) represent some of the most potentially serious within the criminal law. Indeed, there are several interrelated reasons that could be invoked to defend the creation of such offences that focus on the seriousness of the future harm and the difficulty of securing convictions if a higher standard of mens rea were to be required. However, the problem with this kind of focused justification for the offence is that it begs a simple question. If such reasons are sufficiently powerful to set aside the remoteness principle, and if it is these reasons that are guiding the outer boundaries of criminal liability, then why are they applied in such an inconsistent manner? 37 Again, we are assuming that D does not have a valid defence. For attempted murder, D must intend to cause death. An intention to cause GBH, sufficient for a substantive murder charge, will not be enough. 39 In the case of certain preparatory offences, it may be contended that a significantly lower maximum sentence will mitigate the chance of more proximate offences being undermined. However, this is not always the case. Each of the offences in this example, including the possession offence, carries a maximum penalty of life imprisonment. 38 ~ 31 ~ In order to demonstrate the inconsistency of the current law, and the absurdities that it can lead to, we may take the example of section 58(1) of the Sexual Offences Act 2003, which is useful because it is capable of coming within either of the two categories of preparatory offence just discussed. Section 58 of the Act provides: 58(1) A person [D] commits an offence if he intentionally arranges or facilitates travel within the United Kingdom by another person (B) and either— (a) he intends to do anything to or in respect of B, during or after the journey and in any part of the world, which if done will involve the commission of a relevant offence, [e.g. rape and sexual offences including child sex offences] or (b) he believes that another person is likely to do something to or in respect of B, during or after the journey and in any part of the world, which if done will involve the commission of a relevant offence Section 58(1)(a) provides an example of the first category of offences, criminalising a person (D) at a very remote stage, based on his or her intention to commit a future sexual offence. Section 58(1)(b), on the other hand, comes into the second category. This is because, for D to be liable under this provision, although the actus reus requirement remains very remote from the eventual harm, D’s mens rea (in relation to the potential future offence to be committed by someone else) is set at a level akin to a form of recklessness: belief in a likelihood. Focusing first on section 58(1)(b) and the second category currently under discussion, once again one may be able to justify the manner in which the offence has been constructed. Clearly, the remoteness of D’s actus reus and the lower levels of mens rea demonstrate an abandonment of the remoteness principle, which it will be recalled is that ‘as the form of criminal liability moves further away from the infliction of harm, so the grounds of liability should become more narrow’. However, if D is willing to arrange travel for another, knowing that that person is likely to become a victim of a serious sexual assault at some stage during that journey or shortly afterwards, they certainly demonstrate a high level of culpability. The use of criminal sanction seems justified. But if this is indeed an adequate justification, why is it not extended to other future harms not catered for within this section? Murder is one of the most serious offences in English law. However, if D arranges travel for, and even travels with another person believing that it is likely that that person will be killed by someone else, D will not have committed an offence: in order to be liable for assisting the murder of B, D must (at least) believe that the conduct of that other person leading to B’s death will take place.40 Turning to section 58(1)(a) which is an example of the first category of preparatory offence, here too a similar level of inconsistency is apparent. Section 58(1)(a) criminalises the same remote conduct of D (arranging or facilitating the movement of B), but this time on the basis that D intends to personally commit a relevant sexual offence at some point during or shortly after that journey. Again, one might make the case that such an offence is justified: if D intends to commit a relevant offence and has already started on the road towards its commission by arranging travel, why wait until he or she has actually gone beyond mere preparation towards the commission of that offence before intervening with the criminal law. However, again using the offence of murder as our point of comparison, such a 40 The Serious Crime Act 2007, Part 2. ~ 32 ~ justification must surely fail. If D arranges for the travel of B with the intention to kill B at some point during or shortly after that journey, there can be no criminal liability until a very late stage: since liability for attempted murder will not arise until D has gone beyond mere preparation towards the killing of B. Given that the remoteness principle is identified as the basis for regulating or controlling the acceptable limits of the criminal law the discussion above indicates a basic inconsistency in its application, and a consequent incoherence in the approach to non-consummate offences. Of course, we are aware that the consistency argument may lead to a different conclusion. It might be argued that if the problem is merely with the consistency of application of the remoteness principle then this could be resolved by allowing all serious offences (including murder) to be covered by both categories of preparatory offence. In other words intention would not be required. The problem with such a suggestion, however, is that it would create a very strange relationship between the preparatory offences and the substantive offence itself. One could only be convicted of murder if one intended to kill or cause grievous bodily harm. Whereas one could be convicted of attempted murder, say, on the basis that one is reckless as to whether conduct [which does not actually result in death] might actually do so. The practical confines of this chapter do not allow us to enter this secondary debate with any degree of detail. However, the recognition that this is a debate that should be waged, and the recognition that it is preparatory offences, as distinct from the general inchoate offences, which mark the true boundary of the criminal law, at least provides us with a more appropriate starting point for engaging in a coherent discussion of the issues. Issues associated with deciding the most appropriate approach conceptually to criminalising non-consummate harms, as well as allowing for a principled approach to examining how such offences individually should be defined. It is our contention that it is only when preparatory offences of this kind are recognised, not as the exception, but as fundamental parts of our criminal law, that they will be given the same level of scrutiny that is currently focused upon the general inchoate offences of attempt, conspiracy and assisting and encouraging. As we noted in relation to these general offences, reform is not simply focused upon whether we would like to be able to intervene using the criminal law, but rather it is based upon the balancing of a range of factors including the importance of individual autonomy and the confining of the criminal law to the most culpable offenders (as protected by the remoteness principle). Conclusion As we move ever more into an age of intelligence led policing, the increasing role of inchoate liability may be viewed as a measure of success: the criminal law is intervening to protect the community from the risk of harm by facilitating official action before the harm is brought about. However, criminalisation requires principled justification, and theory and practice need to accord with one another. The current approach which regards the proliferation of preparatory offences, not as further extensions of the criminal law that must be subjected to the same scrutiny as the general inchoate offences, but as exceptions that can be tolerated without further examination, is not acceptable for a number of reasons. First it disengages these other inchoate offences from the remoteness principle which is the principled basis offered both as a justification for inchoate liability as well as the organising principle for ~ 33 ~ defining such offences. Secondly, it serves to present an inaccurate account of where the true boundary for criminalisation lies: the true boundary is not the general inchoate offences; rather it is the forms of preparatory offence which we have examined above, which target conduct prior to that which is caught by the general inchoate offences, and in doing so may apply lower standards of mens rea than is the case with the general inchoate offences. In addition to the practical problem which this presents in terms of undercutting general inchoate offences, this means that we have no coherent theory which justifies the exception in the light of the apparent rule. In arriving at this conclusion we are aware that we have not provided solutions to the problems of theoretical and practical dissonance which we have identified. This is a task which requires considerably more in terms of space and scope than the current practical constraints of this chapter allow. We have instead here contented ourselves with the more limited, but important, preliminary task of asking the question whether the first principles as conventionally offered make sense in the light of current practice. For the reasons set out above, we conclude they do not, which in turn makes it all the more incumbent on those with an interest in this field to begin to engage in a deeper and grander exploration of the conceptual basis for criminalisation, as well as a more extensive examination and systematic identification of different types of preparatory offences than has been possible within the scope of this chapter. ~ 34 ~