I. Introduction Multiple Realization (MR) is the claim that functional states (including mental states) can be brought about by physically distinct realizers. For the last few decades the argument has been though to refute reductive physicalism, the thesis that mental states and brain states are identical. If a mental state can be brought about by two physical states that are not themselves identical, then the mental state cannot be identified or reduced to those physical states. If this argument is sound, reductive physicalism (at least in its simpler formulations) is false. 1 MR was first advanced as an empirical hypothesis: In the actual world, we can observe organisms with very different neuro-physical constitutions that have the very same mental state.2 Moreover, MR is considered by many to be a ubiquitous phenomenon in the natural world, occurring intra-individual and intra-species, as well as between members of distantly related biological taxa.3 In this paper I call these claims into question. In §2 I give a precise formulation of MR. I argue that MR is actually the conjunction of two separate claims, both of which must be empirically demonstrated. I arrive at the following formulation. (MR) Two organisms T1 and T2 multiply realize the same mental state F iff (MRi) the same Ramsey sentence is true of both T1 and T2 when describing F, and (MRii) T1 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers P, T2 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers Q, and P ≠Q with respect to the relevance criterion I argue further that the standards for each claim are higher than we might expect. While most of the debate over MR has focused on (MRii), I contend that both claims are equally important, and The English word ‘octopus’ derives from a Greek 3 rd declension masculine noun, not a Latin 2nd declension masculine noun. The correct plural is ‘octopodes’, not ‘octopi’, and not ‘octopuses’ (for the same reason we do not say ‘datums’, ‘stimuluses’, ‘phenomenons’ or ‘thesises’). 2 The classic expositions are in Putnam (1967), Block & Fodor (1972), and Fodor (1974) 3 In addition to the sources cited in n. 1, see 1 that the standards for each claim are higher than we might expect. (MRi) makes explicit that the very same mental state must be realized in both cases, which requires causal homogeneity at the functional level. (MRii) calls for functionally relevant heterogeneity, which I argue is not entailed by compositional differences. In the next two sections I argue that neither (MR i) nor (MRii) is satisfied with respect to pain in humans and octopodes, the example Putnam used to begin the debate over MR. In §3 I show that the pain states of humans are functionally distinct from the pain states of octopodes, and are therefore different mental states. I also advocate describing mental states at a specific level of abstraction, which does not beg the question against either side. In §4 I claim that human pain and octopus pain are realized by homologous, and a fortiori causally similar, neural systems, and show that various objections to this claim misunderstand MR and undercut the arguments for it. In §5 I show how the empirical evidence against MR can be applied to other mental states between these two organisms, and to mental states between other organisms. Throughout this paper I will be focusing only on the hypothesis that mental states are multiply realized across biological taxa. This is but one of several empirically-minded arguments for MR, but there are several reasons for focusing here. For one, Shapiro (unpublished) and Polger (2004) have adequately addressed the shortcomings of the neural plasticity argument, which will cover intra-individual and intra-species cases. Similarly, Zangwill (1992) has shown that there is no real evidence of extraterrestrials or artificial intelligence with the same mental states we have, and the mere possibility of such cases does not count as empirical support. So if we are concerned with finding empirical support for MR, diverse organisms seem like the best place to look. 2. Realization and Multiple Realization MR is an inter-level relationship between realizer physical systems and realized functional states, as depicted in Figure 1 below. (Figure 1) As the diagram shows, MR requires different realizations of the very same realized state. This means that MR is actually the conjunction of two separate claims4: (i) at least two organisms realize the very same mental state, and (ii) those organisms realize that mental state via distinct causally relevant powers. What I call the empirical argument for MR is simply that both these claims have empirical support. The two claims for MR each require some fleshing out. We’ll start with (ii). Two camps have dominated recent discussion of realization: the ‘Flat’ view ascribed to Kim, Shoemaker, and Putnam and later defended by Polger and Shapiro, and the ‘Dimensioned’ view attributed to Block and Fodor and defended by Aizawa and Gillett.5 Despite their disagreements, both sides accept the claim that only functionally relevant differences, i.e., differences that directly pertain to how a certain functional role is filled, contribute to MR. Gillett calls this claim the relevance criterion.6 The disagreement centers on how broadly we should understand the relevance criterion. Shapiro (2000, 2004) argues that many characteristics of an object do not influence how that object realizes its functional state, and are therefore functionally irrelevant. His example is the color of a corkscrew: red corkscrews remove corks the 4 Couch (2004) makes a similar point. See Aizawa & Gillett (2009), Gillett (2002, 2003), Polger (2008, 2009), Shapiro (2000, 2008), Polger & Shapiro (2009) 6 Gillett outlines the relevance criterion as follows: “Instances TI, instantiated in sl, and T2, instantiated in s2, are distinct realizations of a property T only if there is a difference between the properties/relations whose contribution of powers are those in virtue of which sl and s2 have the powers individuative of T” (2003:596). 5 same way that yellow corkscrews do. Shapiro claims that many compositional differences are also irrelevant: steel corkscrews remove corks the same way aluminum ones do. Gillett (2003) disagrees, arguing that the composition is relevant, because aluminum molecules and steel molecules are chemically bonded in different ways, and these bonds directly contribute to the metals’ respective rigidity. Resolving this particular disagreement will bring out important considerations for MR more generally. Aluminum is a highly reactive element, which forms electron bonds that are difficult to break. Steel is an iron alloy, which is made by combining iron with carbon to form bonds that are difficult to break. These bonds are, in both cases, formed by the interactions between the electrons of each element. Though the differences are causally relevant, they are not causally distinct; both steel and aluminum are rigid in the same way, and that rigidity allows them to open corks the same way. But this does not entail that compositional differences are never relevant. If steel were rigid in virtue of, say, its molecules being densely packed and unable to move, while aluminum were rigid in virtue of its molecules forming strong electron bonds, then their respective rigidity would contribute to MR for corkscrews. This shows us that compositional differences are relevant to realization only when those differences contribute causal powers in distinct ways.7 One may be tempted to respond here that steel and aluminum have to be causally distinct, simply in virtue of being compositionally distinct. But there are problems to such an approach. For one, this stipulation seems to beg the question in favor of MR. More importantly, the 7 This entails that, pace Polger (2008) and Shapiro (2000,2008), MR can be transitive. But the transitivity occurs only in special prescribed circumstances, i.e., when specific lower-level causal powers are instantiated via different mechanisms, which powers themselves contribute to the realization of some higher-level functional state. In other words, lower-level differences are “screened off” only when those lower-level differences don’t result in higherlevel differences. Polger and Shapiro are correct, however, that MR is not always transitive; in many cases, lowerlevel differences do not result in causally-relevant higher-level differences (as with aluminum and steel corkscrews). consequences of the view that all compositional differences entail functional differences are untenable. Taking this suggestion seriously would commit us to holding that different samples of water are realized in distinct ways, because they are compositionally distinct at the level of quarks or strings, a la Funkhouser (2007). This entails that water (and many other natural kinds) are multiply realized. And if MR prevents the identification of a kind with its realizer base, as MR proponents suggest, then water cannot be identified with H2O (because H2O cannot be identified with a certain combination of hydrogen and oxygen, which cannot themselves be identified with clusters of protons, neutrons, and electrons, and so on).8 This strikes me as a reductio of the position. A further point concerns realizer-level and realized-level laws. If we allow that multiply realized objects cannot be adequately described by the laws of their realizers (Fodor 1974), then the laws of subatomic particles would not adequately describe water. But microphysical laws do adequately describe water. Therefore either a) multiply realized objects can be adequately described by the laws of their realizers (in which case MR is not a threat to reductionism), or b) water is not multiply realized despite its being composed in different ways. Proponents of MR are advised to choose the latter conclusion. With these considerations in mind, we can formulate (ii) more precisely as follows. (MRii) Two organisms T1 and T2 are distinct realizers of the mental state F only if T1 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers P, T2 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers Q, and P ≠Q with respect to the relevance criterion Now on to claim (i). Before addressing it, I should note that far less attention has been paid to (i) than to (ii) in most discussion of MR. One of the theses of this paper is that MR comprises two distinct claims, each of which has higher standards of proof than is commonly regarded, especially with respect to claims at the realized level. By precisely formulated exactly what (i) 8 It is no longer taken for granted that MR prevents reduction. See Bickle, 1998, 2003; Clapp, 2001; Keeley, 2001; Kim, 1992; Kim, forthcoming, Polger, 2004; Richardson, 2008; Rosenberg, 2001; Shapiro, 2000, 2004; Sober, 1999b states, we can see that MR advocates must do more than simply apply the same predicate to two mental states.9 Or so I shall argue. In what follows, I will use a functional analysis of mental states 10 There are several reasons for doing so. Many proponents of MR are also functionalists, and indeed the earliest expositions of MR were used to argue for functionalism in place of identity theory. 11 Second, there is reason to think that realization is a special kind of metaphysical relationship which holds between functional states and physical systems. If realization is not restricted, it is difficult to distinguish realization from other metaphysical relationships like composition, supervenience, and the like.12 It seems intuitive enough that realization is special – just compare the relationship between the software and hardware of a computer to a heap of sand and its grains or the moral properties of a world and its physical properties. Restricting realization to functional states helps make sense of this special kind of relationship. Lastly, both sides of the debate over MR agree that properties should be delineated causally, so that two properties with different causal profiles are different properties.13 Since functional states are, in essence, causal states, talking about mental states as functional states makes it easy to focus on the causal profiles of these states. 9 Cf. Heil 1999, 2003. Heil argues that we can make sense of MR if we think of second-order realized properties as causally similar rather than identical. But as Shapiro (2008) argues, this way explicating MR does not do it justice. If there is no single functional role or property to be realized, then it can’t be multiply realized. MR requires realized and realizer states to be “same-different”, not “(slightly) different – different.” Even so, Heil’s distinction between predicates and properties in this debate is significant. He is certainly right that language does not determine ontology. 10 Though I will talk about mental states as functional states, my analysis does not require one to assume that functionalism is true. Functionalism has its own problems (See Block 1978, Putnam 1988, among others). But a functional analysis of mental states does not entail functionalism full-blown. If, for instance, mental states have unique neural realizers, then identity theory might steel be true even if mental states can be described as functional states. 11 Interestingly enough, Block & Fodor (1972) also discuss problems with functionalism, as does Block (1978). Similarly, though Putnam (1967) used MR to argue for functionalism, Putnam (1988) repudiated the theory. 12 Cf. Polger (2004) and Polger & Shapiro (2009) 13 On the anti-MR side, see Polger (2004, 2008, 2009), Polger & Shapiro (2008), and Shapiro (2000, 2008). For the pro-MR side, see Aizawa & Gillett (2009, unpublished), Gillett (2002, 2003). A mental state, according to Lewis (1972) and others, can be described by a Ramsey sentence in the following form: ∃x(x is caused by stimuli S1-n, & x tends to cause behaviors B1-m & x tends to cause other mental states M1-k & ….)14 For our purposes, x refers to the realized mental state under investigation, while the S, B, and M variables describe disjunctions of stimuli, behavior, and other mental states, respectively. Two organisms realize the same mental state only if the same Ramsey sentence is true of both them. Hence we can formulate (i) more precisely as follows: (MRi) Two organisms T1 and T2 realize the same mental state F only if the same Ramsey sentence is true of both T1 and T2 when describing F. The same Ramsey sentence will be true of both T1 and T2 when the S, B, and M variables are filled by the same stimuli, behavior, and mental states, more-or-less. I say “more-or-less” because, technically speaking, the failure of any single part of the sentence to accurately describe the world entails that the whole sentence is false. This would result in an incredibly low probability of there ever being two instances of the same mental state. But as long as the sentence describing each mental state has the S, B, and M variables filled in such that the two sentences are (at least) more similar than different, we need not infer that the two mental states are different.15 To use Lewis’ term, near realization of the Ramsey sentence is good enough. If the same Ramsey sentence is true of two mental states, then they will generate similar behavioral and mental effects from similar stimuli. But if we find a high degree of causal heterogeneity (e.g., sets of stimuli or behaviors with more different members than members in Strictly speaking this picture is overly simplistic, because the sentence I’ve given describes only one mental state, and the Ramsey sentence method is typically used to define all mental terms at once. However, since we are talking about only a few different mental states, using a Ramsey sentence to describe only one state at a time will help focus and simplify the conversation. It may help to think of the specific Ramsey sentences I discuss below as parts of a conjuncts of a larger sentence which contains all mental terms. 15 One way to think about this relatively lenient standard is the type-token distinction. If the Ramsey sentence describes mental state types, then the sentence should sustain rather significant intra-type variation when applied to token mental states. 14 common, stimuli that produce opposite reactions in different organisms, etc), then we have good reason to think that the mental states in question are different functional states. And if we don’t have the same functional state in both cases, we don’t have MR. With both (i) and (ii) more clearly articulated, we can give more precise conditions for MR. (MR) Two organisms T1 and T2 multiply realize the same mental state F iff (MRi) the same Ramsey sentence is true of both T1 and T2 when describing F, and (MRii) T1 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers P, T2 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers Q, and P ≠Q with respect to the relevance criterion (MRi) and (MRii) are each necessary for MR. They are jointly sufficient for MR. In the next two sections I will argue that neither (MRi) nor (MRii) are empirically supported. But before doing so, it will be helpful to briefly discuss what sorts of evidence we will look for. When testing (MRi), we will look for causal homogeneity between two mental states. Of course, mental states are not themselves directly observable. But their causes and effects are. By observing the stimuli and behavior that serve as the causes and effects of mental states, we can make an inductive argument about those mental states. If we observe the same stimuli causing the same behavior in two different organisms, we have reason to believe these organisms share the same mental state. But if we see too much causal heterogeneity between the stimuli and behavior of different organisms, we can infer that they do not share the same mental state. When testing (MRii), we will look for causal heterogeneity in the neurology of the two organisms. If the causal powers by which the brains of humans and octopodes realize pain states are different, then we have evidence for MR. If these organisms realize pain states via the same causal powers, we have evidence against MR. 3. Not of One Mind: Mental States in Humans and Octopodes I’ve argued so far that MR is actually the conjunction of two claims, each of which requires empirical support. In this section I show that observations of octopus behavior suggest that they do not realize the same mental states that humans realize. Since there is not one mental state realized between the two organisms, there can be no MR. The Ramsey sentence which describes the mental states of octopodes takes the following form: ∃x(x is caused by stimuli S1-n, & x tends to cause behaviors B1-m & x tends to cause other mental states M1-k & ….) I argue that the S, B, and M variables that make the sentences true for each organism are simply too diverse.16 I should emphasize from the outset that this is not simply a matter of finding one or two differences. Rather, the causal roles of human and octopus pain are radically dissimilar, with far more differences than similarities. This diversity holds for both qualitative states and propositional attitudes. Though the body of literature on octopus psychology is vast, I will focus here only on pain.17 Hanlon & Messenger (1996) report that [D]eliberately inflicted pain, in the form of a small electric shock (4-10 V, ac) has been consistently and successfully employed to shape octopuses’ responses to objects during discrimination training. In these circumstances octopuses react as a human does when stung by a nettle.18 This suggests that octopodes and humans do share some behavioral responses, which gives prima facie support to the claim that humans and octopodes occupy the very same ‘pain’ role. But closer inspection reveals that this is an oversimplification. Humans and octopodes are 16 Since this is a discussion of empirical arguments for MR, we must restrict ourselves I should also note that I will be ascribing mental states to octopodes rather liberally. Our awareness of the sophistication of animal cognition is steadily increasing, so the idea of, say, invertebrates with complex mental states is not as controversial as it once was. In any case, if we can’t ascribe the same (complex) mental states to octopodes as we do to humans, MR never gets off the ground. 18 Hanlon & Messenger 1996, p. 21 17 significantly different with regard to both the causal stimuli of their pain states and the behavioral effects. Clearly, pain-inducing stimuli for humans and octopodes differ significantly. Humans feel pain from a whole range of stimuli that do not affect octopodes. There are, of course, the psychological and emotional sources of pain, like betrayal, injustice, envy, or unrequited love. But there are also many stimuli that both organisms are capable of processing, but which would only serve as a pain stimulus for one organism. For instance, many octopodes live in cold water, and are most active at night.19 These conditions would certainly be a stimulus with a high probability of inducing a pain-state transition for humans (at least until hypothermia set in), but it is not a pain-state input for octopodes. Similarly, eating large quantities of uncooked fish and mollusks would likely be an input to cause humans to occupy a pain state, but this is not the case for octopodes. We could tell similar stories about stimuli that would cause octopodes to transition to a pain state, but not humans (e.g., being out of the water for several hours). The same causal differences occur in behavior. When an octopus occupies the ‘pain’ role, its behavioral outputs might include swimming away, retracting its tentacles, or changing its color pattern.20 When a human occupies the ‘pain’ role, her outputs might include uttering “Ouch”, crying, or imitating a super-Spartan.21 Obviously, these two classes of behaviors have far more different members than members in common. As before, the S, B, and M variables that make the Ramsey sentence for pain true of octopodes make the same sentence false for humans. Hence we can infer that there are two functional states, not one. 19 Nixon & Young (2003) Smith (199) 21 See Putnam (1967) 20 This is not to say that humans and octopodes have no stimuli or behavior in common. There are some areas of overlap between human and octopus psychology: for instance, both sometimes flinch when poked by something sharp. To be sure, the simple fact that a stimulus elicits one behavior in me and another in you is not enough to show we do not realize the same mental state. But a few similarities are not enough to constitute the very same functional state. Given the multitude of causal differences between the mental states of humans and octopodes, we must conclude that their mental states are functionally distinct. Since there are two mental states realized, not one, we do not have a case of MR. One plausible response to my argument is to attempt to use a coarser grain to describe mental states. As many authors have noted, the level of abstraction at which one describes possible cases of MR makes a substantial difference to the analysis of such cases. 22 It may be that I’ve just chosen the wrong level. We might fill in the S variable of the Ramsey sentence with “a noxious stimulus”, the B variable with “avoidance behavior”, and the M variables with “anxiety, distress, etc”, and come up with a sentence that is true for the pain states of both humans and octopodes. This method might generate true Ramsey sentences for many of the mental states of both organisms. But there are several problems with this approach. For one, there is always the worry that one is looking for a level of abstraction that makes the results come out right. If we assume that mental states are multiply realized, we would look for a grain of description that bears out this assumption. But clearly this approach begs the question when we are trying to determine whether or not mental states are multiply realized in the first place. Furthermore, the method I’ve used to describe mental states is sympathetic to how proponents of MR describe it. In fact, by insisting only on near realization, I’ve presented a 22 Bechtel and McCauley, 1999; Bechtel and Mundale, 1999; Couch, forthcoming; Polger, 2004; Shapiro, 2008; Sober, 1999; Sullivan, 2008 more charitable conception of functional similarity than may be needed.23 If principled, functionalist-inspired reasons for determining the level of specificity at which to describe functional states are not fair, I do not know what is. Moreover, the grain of description I’ve used is also the grain used by scientists who study octopus psychology. Yet even if one could motivate pursuing another level of abstraction, there are still problems. Suppose I poke my Roomba with a pointed stick and it moves to the other side of the room. It has exhibited avoidance behavior in response to a noxious stimulus; does that mean my Roomba realized a pain state, and moreover the same pain state I realize?24 This level of description commits us to being too liberal with our mental talk, ascribing mental states to beings that lack them (Block 1978).25 In order to avoid this problem, we need to be more specific in our descriptions of functional states. I contend that in doing so we will be unable to avoid arriving at different functional states for humans and octopodes. At any but the vaguest level of description, it is clear that the stimuli which cause human mental states are different from the causes of octopus mental states, as are the behaviors caused by that state. This precludes us from describing the mental states of these organisms with the same Ramsey sentence, without which we cannot satisfactorily demonstrate MR. Another worry about using a coarser grain to describe functional states is that the approach cuts both ways. If we can use a coarse grain to describe mental states, why can we not use an equally coarse grain to describe brain states? After all, “Whatever neural activity occurs when the organism encounters a noxious stimulus” is at the same level of abstraction as 23 Strictly speaking, a functionalist analysis of mental states seems committed to saying that any difference between entails a difference in functional states. This is because functional states are defined holistically, i.e., with reference to the whole machine table or Ramsey sentence of which they are a part (see, for instance, Kim (2006), p. 137-142). But this suggests that no two mental states are in fact the same functional state (or at least that the probability of this happening is very low). If no two mental states are functionally identical, then MR never gets off the ground. 24 Roombas are small household robots that clean floors autonomously. I don’t really have one (which, incidentally, causes me to realize a pain state), and if I did I would not poke it with a pointed stick. 25 See Block (1978) “Whatever is going on in the organism’s head when it exhibits avoidance behavior in response to a noxious stimulus.” If we can describe the mental state at a high level of abstraction, why can we not describe the brain state in the same manner? The result, of course, would be mental states are not multiply realized after all, because the very broadly understood functional state turns out to be realized by a single, broadly understood neurological state. Trying to salvage MR by using a broader level of abstraction might help at the functional level, but it will enervate the case for MR at the realizer level. I’ve attempted to show that making a case for MR is more difficult than it might appear, especially at the realized level. The empirical argument for MR must provide evidence to satisfy (MRi). But behavioral observations show us that (MRi) is not satisfied with respect to humans and octopodes. The Ramsey sentences which are true of octopus pain are false when applied to human pain, because the stimuli, behavior, and other mental states associated with the mental state for each organism are too diverse. The same predicates may be applied to the mental states of both organisms, but this is not sufficient to show that the organisms realize the very same mental states.26 When the pain states of humans and octopodes are examined with sufficient care and precision, it is clear that they are not the same state. Without evidence that the same mental state is realized in both cases, (MRi) is not satisfied, and hence the empirical argument for MR is unsubstantiated. 4. Man Pain, Mollusc Pain MR requires both that the same functional state be realized by two physical systems and that the physical systems realize that functional state in causally distinct ways. I formulated this claim as follows. 26 Cf. Heil 1999, 2003, Shapiro 2008 (MRii) Two organisms T1 and T2 are distinct realizers of the mental state F only if T1 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers P, T2 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers Q, and P ≠Q with respect to the relevance criterion. I this section I argue that this claim is not empirically supported. As before, I’ll focus on pain. I argued in §II that not all differences in the realizers of a functional state result in MR. Shapiro (2000, 2004) argues that two corkscrews that differ in color are not ipso facto multiply realized, because color does not contribute to the exercise of a corkscrew’s functional state. Similarly, aluminum and steel corkscrews do not count as cases of MR simply in virtue of their differing molecular composition, because the property through which the corkscrews open bottles (rigidity) is instantiated in the same way in both cases (chemical bonding between electrons). In short, not all compositional differences satisfy the relevance criterion because compositional differences do not entail functionally relevant causal differences. When examining the neural realizers of pain in humans and octopodes, we must keep this lesson in mind. Not all differences in the brains of these two organisms contribute to MR. For instance, the octopus brain surrounds the esophagus, while the human brain does not. But the property “surrounding the esophagus” has nothing to do with realizing the functional state “pain”. It does not meet the relevance criterion, and therefore does not count toward MR. What MR requires is for the brains of humans and octopodes to realize pain in causally distinct ways. It turns out that just the opposite is true. First we’ll examine the realizers of pain states in octopodes. Not only are the realizers of pain for humans and octopodes causally similar; they’re the very same physical system. The data gathered by Stefano et al (2002) speaks for itself: Past studies on neuronal mechanisms in insects and mollusks have revealed remarkable structural, functional, and biochemical parallelisms with those in vertebrates…. Numerous studies, in a variety of invertebrate species, have identified neuropeptides in parts of the neuroendocrine and nervous system apparatus, which is analogous to the hypothalamic-hypophysical system of vertebrates. The list includes substances closely resembling the following vertebrate neuropeptides and hormones: oxycotin, vasopressin, adrenocorticotropin (ACTH), α melanocyts stimulating hormose (MSH), somatosostatin, substance P, neurotensin, hypothalamic growth hormone releasing favor, insulin, glucagon, gastrin/cholecystokinin, vasoactive intestinal peptide (VIP), pancreatic polypeptide (PP), secretin, luteinizing hormone releasing favor (LHRF), and several endogenous opioids.27 Even the scientifically uninitiated will recognize some of the substances common to the nervous systems of both humans and octopodes, like oxycotin and insulin. But these similarities are not limited only to the chemicals used by invertebrate and vertebrates brains; they also have the same structure and function. Stefano and his colleagues conclude these commonalities of signal molecules, activities, and regulatory mechanisms, must be viewed as demonstrating a continuity of information during the development of various response systems throughout evolution, rather than the appearance of “chance” similarities. One is therefore only left to conclude that the invertebrate perturbation-stress systems developed many of the strategies for mammalian stress phenomena.28 In other words, the conclusion is not simply that the organisms converged on similar physical solutions, but rather that the reactions to pain between distantly related taxa are in fact instances of the same process, modified by selection pressures over time but nevertheless essentially the same. It is important to remember here that the level of similarity we are looking for here is functionally relevant causal similarity, not identity. The pain response systems of humans and octopodes are not identical, nor are their memory consolidation systems. But they do not need to be. Aizawa claims that “It is not enough that ordinary language, or even ordinary scientific language, says that two structures are the same. Even if one can say that two structures are the same, it does not follow that they are physically or chemically the same.”29 But this point goes both ways. Saying that two structures are different does not entail that they are evidence of 27 Stefano et al (2002), p. 86, emphasis added Ibid, p. 92, emphasis added 29 Aizawa (2007), p. 82 28 MR.30 For MR we need differences that satisfy the relevance criterion. We need evidence that the same function is brought about in causally distinct ways. In several works Bickle has argued that memory-consolidation is uniquely realized across the animal kingdom, in virtue of the fact that distantly related organisms, including mice, fruit flies, snails, all use the same physio-chemical system for memory.31 Aizawa counters that the memory-consolidation systems used by these organisms are not compositionally identical, and therefore provide evidence for MR instead. For example, the cAMP response element binding (CREB) proteins for fruit flies and mice share only 95% of the same amino acids.32 Even if the same basic chemical are used by the same basic structures in the same basic way, they are not completely similar, and therefore still count toward MR. We can construct an analogous argument with regard to the neurological realizers of pain in humans and octopodes. Now, this argument is partly based on the assumption that any compositional difference is sufficient for MR, which I have argued is false. But even if we only consider functionally relevant differences, the argument does not go through. The differences between the proteins in the brains of humans and octopodes is analogous to the differences between the molecules of steel and aluminum. Even though they are compositionally distinct, they are not functionally distinct. Both steel and aluminum instantiate the property of rigidity in virtue of the bonding of their constituent electrons. Similarly, the amino acid sequences in octopus and human brains transmit information through nerves via chemical interactions. Though there are some differences in the amino acid sequences in the various proteins shared between humans and octopodes, the amino 30 Cf. Kim (1992) Bickle (2003, 2006, 2008). It turns out that octopodes may be added to this list. I’ll return to this point in the next section. 32 Aizawa (2007), p. 71 31 acids still function the same way, and therefore contribute to the realization of a functional state in the same way. But even if we insist that these small differences between the brains of humans and octopodes must somehow be causally relevant, they still do not make the case for MR. As many have pointed out, if two realized states share the same basic set of realizer properties, then it is unclear why we cannot reduce the realized property to that set of realizer properties. 33 For instance, if pain in octopodes is realized by properties {A, B, C, D, E} and pain in humans is realized by properties {A, B, C, F, G} then it seems perfectly reasonable to reduce pain to {A, B, C, X}, where X is a finite and well-behaved disjunction of similar but not identical properties. Moreover, given that the mental states are not identical in humans and octopodes, we arrive at a situation where the functional similarities between humans and octopodes are the result of their sharing A, B, and C, and the differences are the result of possessing different members of the disjunct X. As Shapiro (2008) notes, this recipe – “Sort of the same but sort of different” – does not work for MR. And lastly, as I argued in the last section, describing realizer states at a high level of specificity invites us to do the same to realized states. If, as Aizawa suggests, 5% difference is enough to count as distinct at the realizer level, then by parity of reasoning 5% difference should count as distinct at the functional level. The result is that (MRii) is satisfied at the expense of (MRi). Despite the physiological dissimilarities between humans and octopodes, the brains of the two organisms are not different in the way MR requires. Rather, it appears that the painresponse systems of humans and octopodes are in fact the very same physical systems. These systems are not, of course, identical, but they are functionally similar in a way that precludes MR. Even the small differences between them are not enough to support the case for MR, 33 See, for example, Kim (1992), Heil (2003) because the remaining similarities permit us to reduce the mental states in question to the conjunction of their shared properties and the members of an orderly disjunct of other similar properties, and because level of distinction at the realizer level undercuts the case for MR at the realized level. Hence (MRii) is not satisfied, and the empirical argument for MR is unsupported. V. Discussion I argued above that MR is the conjunction of two separate claims, which I formulated as follows: (MR) Two organisms T1 and T2 multiply realize the same mental state F iff (MRi) the same Ramsey sentence is true of both T1 and T2 when describing F, and (MRii) T1 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers P, T2 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers Q, and P ≠Q with respect to the relevance criterion The empirical argument for MR claims that both (MRi) and (MRii) are empirically supported. I have attempted to show that this is not the case. Behavioral data show us that the mental states of humans and octopodes are too causally diverse to be counted as the same mental state, as evidenced by the fact that the same Ramsey sentence cannot accurately describe both organisms. Neurological evidence suggests that humans and octopodes realize a pain state by means of the same neuro-physical system and therefore the same causally relevant properties. Hence the evidence tells against both claims of MR, which leads us to conclude that the empirical argument for MR fails. One might justifiably wonder what the significance of this conclusion is. After all, one bit of empirical evidence is not particularly compelling on its own. Even if pain is not multiply realized in humans and octopodes, it might be that other mental states are. Or, we might think that pain is multiply realized in other creatures. Alternatively, we might think that pain is such a basic mental state that it would find common expression throughout the animal kingdom, but that other, more complex mental states might be more sporadic and therefore more likely to be multiply realized. In short, failure to find evidence of MR in one case does not entail that MR is unsubstantiated tout court. As the dictum goes, absence of evidence is not evidence of absence. This is a reasonable response to make. Something needs to be said about how to generalize from a particular case to MR more generally. My response will come in stages. The first reply is that pain is not the only mental state for which empirical arguments for MR are not empirically supported. The second reply is that evidence against MR for these particular mental states are representative of other mental states. The third reply is that looking at other organisms is unlikely to provide different results. My response here cannot, of course, prove that there are no cases of MR in the natural world. But it does put the burden of proof on the MR advocate to supply evidence to corroborate his claims. Showing that pain is not multiply realized in humans and octopodes does not prove that all mental states are not realized in humans and octopodes. But evidence suggests that pain is the rule, not the exception. A similar story can be told about the perceptual states and propositional states of octopodes. One dramatic difference between octopus and human psychology is their sensory modalities. Each possesses senses the other simply lacks. One of these, ‘infrasound’, is an analogue of hearing in humans.34 Cephalopods lack the air-filled cavities and hard, vibrating body parts necessary for hearing sound. But they are sensitive to low-frequency vibrations undetectable by humans.35 A second sensory difference between humans and octopodes is the latter’s possession of chemoreception, which roughly corresponds to taste and smell in the former. Octopodes are sensitive to chemical stimuli, especially in the suckers located on their 34 35 Hanlon & Messenger 1996 Packard, Karlsen, & Sand (1990) eight tentacles.36 This chemical sense can be used both tactically and at a distance, and it plays an important role in the search for food and in navigation.37 The sensory diversity between humans and octopodes also holds for the modalities that both organisms have in common. Much has been made of the similarity in the eyes of octopodes and mammals.38 Yet despite the structural similarities, there is one striking difference: octopodes are colorblind.39 Vision is a dominant sense for octopodes, but they use differences in contrast rather than differences in hue to make visual discriminations.40 Another difference with octopodes is that control and function of their limbs are largely decentralized.41 Each arm contains about 43.75 million nerve cells (350 million total), while the brain contains roughly 150 million nerve cells. 42 The result is that many of the limbs actions are “curiously divorced from” and “performed without reference to” the brain.43 This would be like having legs that always got you where you need to go, even though you don’t feel them moving. Both with respect to the senses unique to octopodes and to the senses we have in common, octopus psychology and human psychology look quite different. Clearly, if octopodes have different senses than humans then the mental states corresponding to those senses will also be different. For instance, because octopus vision is based on contrast rather than color, the visual-state stimuli for octopodes differ from human visual stimuli. A red object in a field of green could cause a perceptual state in humans, but it would not serve as such an input for an octopus. This point is even stronger when applied to senses the two organisms do not share. Obviously chemical signals in the water are not stimuli 36 Rossi & Graziadei, 1958 Mather 1995; Hanlon & Messenger 1996; Nixon & Young 2003 38 Putnam 1967; Block & Fodor 1972; Messenger 1991; Mather 1998; Shapiro 2000; Gilett 2003; Gleadhall & Shashar 2004 39 Hanlon & Messenger 1996 40 Messenger, 1977; Messenger, Wilson & Hedge 1973 41 Nixon & Young 2003 42 Young 1971 43 Hanlon & Messenger, 1996, p. 15 37 for human psychological states, nor are vibrations of air stimuli for octopodes. This point applies not only to perceptual states themselves, but also to the propositional attitudes that are the outputs of that perception. For instance, both humans and octopodes may hold the belief “There is a fish nearby”. But the stimuli which can cause the belief for an octopus (e.g., chemicals in the water, the low-frequency vibration of the water, etc) are not remotely close to the stimuli which might cause the belief for humans (e.g., a bright red, fish-shapped sense datum, a sound argument that entails “There’s a fish nearby”, etc.). As with pain, the Ramsey sentence that accurately describes the perceptual states or propositional attitudes of an octopus is true only when the S, B, and M variables are filled in such a way that makes the sentence false when describing human mental states.44 At the realizer level, more neural similarity can be found with regard to memory and learning. Aizawa (2007) Aizawa & Gillett (2009) and Bickle (2006, 2008) discusses long-term potentiation (LTP) as a possible “molecular mechanism” for memory consolidation using Nmenthly-D-aspartate (NMDA) receptors. Shamrat et al (2008) show that octopodes also use LTP for memory consolidation.45 At the structural/functional level, they demonstrate that the octopus, like vertebrates, shows a clear separation between the sites of shortand long-term storage…. Short- and long-term memory of nonreflexive behaviors thus appear to have a universal organization principle in which short-term traces are stored in the behavior-controlling circuitry separate from the site acquiring or controlling the consolidation of long-term memory traces.46 At the molecular level, they suggest that the mechanisms are N-menthly-D-aspartate (NMDA) dependent, much like the analogous mechanisms in the hippocampus of vertebrates (also see Tsesarsaia et al, 2009). Llinás & Sugimori (1995) and Augustine et al (1995) discuss the cylic 44 A similar story can be told for the behavioral effects of these perceptual and propositional states. Holding the mental state “There’s a fish nearby” will likely result in the octopus behavior “Grab with tentacle”, while it cause me to exhibit “take a photograph for the vacation scrap-book” behavior. 45 See also Glanzman, 2008; Hochner et 2006; Hochner et al 2003 46 Shamrat et al (2008), p. 341, emphasis added adenosine monophostphate (cAMP) and calcium binding proteins found in the synapses of the cephalopod brain; these substances are also discussed at length by empirically-minded philosophers.47 The similarities between the two organisms are so similar, in fact, that researchers using research on cephalopods as a complement for the studying of diseases in humans, going so far as to investigate the effects of using compounds based on chemicals extracted from octopodes to treat human neurological conditions.48 The upshot of all this is that pain is not the only mental state which is not multiply realized in humans and octopodes. The perceptual states and propositional attitudes of the two organisms are also functionally distinct, while the memory-consolidation systems are causally homogenous. This brings me to my second reply, that these specific mental states are representative of other mental states we might consider. Qualitative states, perceptual states, and propositional attitudes are all very broad categories of mental states. They might not be exhaustive, but they come close. Further investigation is likely to show that the patterns I’ve discussed apply to other similar mental states. Even if we cannot conclude that no mental states are multiply realized by humans and octopodes, we can conclude that the evidence of MR is not yet forthcoming. But what about MR in other organisms? Regarding MR for specific psychological states, there are grounds for generalization here too. Pain is likely a very basic mental state, which is likely to be found throughout the animal kingdom. So even if it is realized the same way in humans and octopodes, it might be multiply realized elsewhere. But this response cuts both ways. Because pain is so pervasive, there are more opportunities to multiply realize it. So the probability of it being realized in the same way by such distantly related organisms with such 47 48 See Aizawa (2007) Aizawa & Gillett (2009) and Bickle (2006, 2008) Budlemann et al 2008; D’este et al 2008; Boyle et al 1999 different selection pressures is all the more surprising.49 A similar worry holds for more complex mental states. In virtue of being more complex, there are more places for the mental state to differ, which lowers the probability of two different organisms realizing it. For instance, the mental state “not surprised but still disappointed” is a rather nuanced mental state, the functional identification of which is very close to other mental states like “stoically resigned” or “not surprised but still annoyed”. Fine-grained mental states like these require subtle functional differences to differentiate them, making it far less likely that the very same state is realized in different ways. Lastly, it is not at all clear that the prospects for MR would be improved by looking elsewhere. I suspect one of the reasons that Putnam used octopodes in his discussion is that they are such radically different creatures. The octopus is intelligent enough for interesting psychological investigation, yet in appearance it is physiologically alien. Moreover, the evolutionary distance between humans and octopodes is vast; their last common ancestor, Urbilateria, is hypothesized to have lived 5.5 million years ago (See figure 2). 50 Yet despite all this, octopodes are far more intelligent than other invertebrates. All in all, the octopus seems an ideal candidate for MR. So the question is “If not here, where?” If we cannot find MR in such diverse organisms as humans and octopodes, where can we find it? If MR were true, we would predict a much higher probability of finding genuine cases in the most distantly related taxa, and lower probability in closely related organisms. We didn’t find MR where it was most likely to be, so the odds of finding it elsewhere are slim. We can frame the issue as a dilemma: The less 49 It should also be noted that Stefano et al (2002) discuss the pain-response system in terms of vertebrates and invertebrates, not specific species. This suggests that pain is realized the same way in all organisms that realize pain. 50 Chen 2004, Erwin & Davidson, 2002 Fendokin & Wagner 1997 similar two organisms are, the less likely we are to ascribe the same mental states to them. But the more similar they are, the more likely it is that they have similar realizers.51 (Figure 2) Image adapted from Nielson, 2001. So it seems that the empirical evidence against pain being multiply realized in humans and octopodes is less isolated than might first appear. Pain is not the only mental state for which we have evidence against MR. Other kinds of mental states, like propositional attitude, are not multiply realized either. Since the pattern is clearly against MR, some clear evidence must be supplied before we take MR seriously as an empirical hypothesis. Moreover, it is highly unlikely that further investigation will come up with different results. The odds of finding other mental states that satisfy the criteria for MR is low, as are the odds of finding other organisms that stand a better chance of supporting MR. It is the nature of empirical evidence that one data set is rarely conclusive. But the weight of the evidence is clearly against MR, and at the very least its proponents must do more to defend it. 6. Conclusion 51 Polger (2002) raises a similar worry about MR is a slightly different context. In this paper I have argued that MR is actually two separate claims: (MR) Two organisms T1 and T2 multiply realize the same mental state F iff (MRi) the same Ramsey sentence is true of both T1 and T2 when describing F, and (MRii) T1 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers P, T2 realizes F in virtue of instantiating causal powers Q, and P ≠Q with respect to the relevance criterion The empirical argument for MR holds that both (MRi) and (MRii) enjoy evidential support. I have argued that for pain in humans and octopodes, MR is false. At the realized level, behavioral observations suggest that pain is not functionally equivalent, and is therefore not the same mental state in both organisms. At the realizer level, neurological evidence shows that the pain-response systems of both organisms are incredibly similar, as it is a homologous trait shared by both creatures. The same pattern holds for other mental states between the two organisms. Further, the odds of finding genuine cases of MR between other organisms are low. The more diverse the organisms, the less likely their mental states are functionally equivalent; the more similar the organisms, the less likely their brains are functionally distinct. Instead of the obvious and ubiquitous natural phenomenon suggested by Putnam (1967) or Block & Fodor (1974), we find that the preponderance of evidence is against MR. So where do we go from here? I’m inclined to think that the answer to this question depends on how much one cares about contingency, possible worlds, and the like. If you’re optimistic about the prospects of AI, then finding evidence of MR may be simply a matter of time. If all you’re after is the logical possibility of MR, then the lack of evidence for it won’t matter much. But if you’re a stickler for what really exists in the actually world, then the lack of evidence for MR is telling. Without evidence for MR, it isn’t clear what the ramifications of the hypothesis are. If I’m right, finding that evidence may be more difficult than we realize.