DRAFT Sources, Normative Hierarchies, and Legal Reasoning [Theorizing the Sources of Law] G IOR G IO P INO University of Palermo, Italy | giorgio.pino@unipa.it | www.unipa.it/gpino Contents 1. Introduction 2. Sources of Law in Contemporary Jurisprudence 3. Some Preliminary Definitions and Distinctions 3.1. Legal Acts, Legal Texts, Legal Norms 3.2. ‘Sources of Law’: Disambiguating the Concept 3.3. Type-Sources and Token-Sources 3.4. Institutionalized and Non-Institutionalized Sources; Binding and Permissive Sources 3.5. Formal Validity, Material Validity, Existence, Applicability 4. Normative Hierarchies in the Law 4.1. Normative Hierarchies in Legal Theory 4.2. Towards a Taxonomy of Normative Hierarchies in the Law 5. Sources, Normative Hierarchies, and Legal Interpretation 6. Conclusions: Freedom and Constraint in Legal Argumentation Bibliography 1. Introduction In contemporary, Western legal cultures at least two rather obvious assumptions, or truisms, are commonly associated with the law. On the one hand, the law is regarded as an artifact, a social product, something that is normally deliberately (but occasionally also unintentionally) produced in some social settings and by way of some kind of social or political arrangements – this is the very ‘positivity’ of law. On the other hand, the law is conceived of as a ‘system’, a somewhat ‘ordered unity’, or the like1. These assumptions – I will call them ‘the positivity assumption’ and ‘the systematicity assumption’ respectively – are at play, for instance, when we assume that there is an almost palpable distinction between the law of one jurisdiction and the law of another jurisdiction 2, and that (absent specific arrangements to this effect) a court or an authority of one jurisdiction is not bound nor authorized to apply the laws of another jurisdiction; or when we are concerned with making sense of – or possibly with explaining away – some inconsistencies or lack of coherence in the body of positive law3; or, finally, when we regard some laws as ‘higher’ or ‘superior’ to other laws. Both assumptions, moreover, are strongly connected to a positivistic stance, or at least to the particular shape that legal positivism assumed in Europe in the 19th century – serving as the cultural backbone, as the official ideology of the modern, liberal State4. To be sure, many aspects of the traditional positivistic picture are now under considerable strain, due to the increasing interconnectedness of national legal systems induced by globalization and by the more recent evolutions of international law and so-called global law5 – the European Union is of course the paradigm case of a system of systems, a macro-system that cuts across the many individual systems it comprises6. Still, more than a grain of truth remains with the two basic assumptions above – that the law is deliberately produced through some social arrangement, and that the law is supposed to be structured in accordance to some ordering criteria. 1 I will leave it an open question if and to what extent a third assumption is also commonly associated to the law, namely a requirement or expectation of justice. Arguably, common sense would support both a positive (legislators should pursue the common good), and a negative answer to this question (legislators can do anything they please, can give the law any content whatsoever). This question is, however, immaterial to my present discussion. 2 On the idea that, according to modern legal positivists, the law is always and exclusively regarded as the law of some jurisdiction, see J. Waldron, “Partly Laws Common to All Mankind”, p. 16-17 (Waldron then goes on with questioning this very idea). 3 I am using here the distinction between consistency and normative coherence as it has been introduced by N. MacCormick, ‘Coherence in Legal Justification’ (defining consistency as logical compatibility, i.e. lack of logical contradictions between legal norms; and normative coherence as the possibility of regarding some set of norms as the expression of one substantive underlying principle). See also J. Dickson, ‘Interpretation and Coherence in Legal Reasoning’. 4 In this sense, as John H. Merryman rightly points out, ‘all Western states are positivistic’ (J.H. Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition, p. 21). Norberto Bobbio has famously distinguished between three main senses that are commonly associated with the label ‘legal positivism’: positivism as a theory of law (but one deeply entrenched in the 19th century model of State), positivism as an ideology (abscribing positive moral qualities to the law and to the obedience of the law), and positivism as a methodology (commending a scientific, non-evaluative approach to the study of the law). According to Bobbio, only the third sense – methodological positivism – should be considered as legal positivism proper. Cf N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico, ch £££; G. Pino, ‘Legal Positivism in Contemporary Constitutional States’. 5 See for instance K. Culver, M. Giudice, Legality’s Borders. 6 See J. Dickson, ‘How Many Legal Systems? Some Puzzles Regarding the Identity Conditions of, and Relations between, Legal Systems in the European Union’, and ‘Towards a Theory of European Union Legal Systems’. This is where the theory of the sources of law steps in. As commonly understood, the positivity assumption requires that any law must be traceable back to an appropriate ‘source’; and the systematicity assumption requires that the relevant sources of law be ordered somehow, that they form a kind of hierarchical structure. On the one hand, this is a matter of fundamental political choices – qualifying something as a source of law, and ordering the various sources of law in a hierarchical fashion, is a way of structuring and allocating the law-making power in a political community7. For this reason, sometimes an official list of sources of law, and their hierarchical ordering, is authoritatively provided for by the positive law itself: it may be established in the Constitution, for instance, or in some other important legal document8. On the other hand, the sources of law and their hierarchy are conceived of as a way of structuring the job of the law-applying institutions: the sources of law both bind and guide the interpreter in discharging her adjudicative role, that is, in the charge of applying the law as it is announced in general terms by the relevant sources of law. As a result of all this, a sort of ‘standard picture’ of adjudication emerges: adjudication, and legal interpretation generally, take place within a framework of previously established sources of law: adjudication and interpretation actually presuppose some previously established set of sources of law, whose existence and hierarchical ordering are entirely independent from legal interpretation itself – as we have just seen, in the standard picture the sources of law and their hierarchical ordering depend from the very structure of the State, they are a political question. Sometimes, this picture of adjudication is even supplemented by an official list of methods of legal interpretation: thus, the interpreter is not only confronted with a closed and hierarchically ordered list of legal materials, but also with supposedly binding criteria to interpret them9. (So not only the interpreter is authoritatively told where to find the relevant legal materials, he is also authoritatively told how to proceed to interpret them.) According to the standard picture, then, the sources of law and their hierarchy are a sort of objective element of legal reasoning, a datum that imposes itself on the interpreter. Interpretation works – more or less constrained by officially mandated methods – only on previously and independently established sources of law10. Given this general background, the main aim of this paper is to direct some attention to some jurisprudential questions surrounding the sources of law. First (sec. 2), I will point to some reasons for the persisting importance of a general theoretical inquiry on the topic of the sources of law, and venture in some speculation regarding the decline in the interest of professional legal philosopher – as opposed to, say, constitutional lawyers, comparative lawyers, and international lawyers – for this topic. Then, I will engage in some theoretical analysis on the concept of ‘source of law’: I will do this, first, by distinguishing many senses of the term ‘source of law’ and by relating the question of the sources to some basic jurisprudential concepts and distinctions that, despite their importance, are sometimes 7 M. Troper, ‘Marshall, Kelsen, Barak and the Constitutionalist Fallacy’, p. 37: ‘In a modern state, [the institution of] a hierarchy of norms is the method used to exercise power’. 8 EXAMPLES. In a similar vein, the explicit provisions dedicated to the sources of law used to be considered as enjoying of ‘constitutional’ status, independently from the nature of the legal document that proclaimed them. This was a rather widespread opinion in European legal scholarship, especially before the enactment of the ‘rigid’ constitutions’ in the second half of the 20 th century. Hans Kelsen’s distinction between ‘formal’ and ‘material’ constitutional provisions is inspired by the same logic. See H. Kelsen, £££ 9 This is the case, for instance, with the Italian legal system, which provides both a list of sources (apparently ordered according to an order of priority), and a few criteria for their interpretation (literal meaning and intention of legislator); see artt. 1 and 12 of the ‘Provisions on the Law in General (‘Preleggi’), placed at the beginning of the Civil Code. See J.H. Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition, p. 10 See for instance J.H. Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition, pp. 25-26 (the traditional theory of sources of law represents ‘the basic truth’, ‘it is a part of his [scil., the average Continental lawyer’s] ideology’); T. Spaak, ‘Legal Positivism and the Objectivity of Law’. overlooked in contemporary jurisprudential discussions (sec. 3); and, second, by analyzing the concept of normative hierarchy (sec. 4) – to this last regard I will try to show that in the law we should expect to find not just one concept of normative hierarchy at work, but many. (For instance, what is the actual concept of normative hierarchy at play when we say that some constitutional norms are ‘superior’ to other constitutional norms?) On a more general level (sec. 5), I will challenge the standard picture of the relation between sources and interpretation by underscoring the role of legal interpretation and argumentation in both the operation and the establishment of sources of law and their hierarchies11. My working hypothesis here is that legal interpretation, and the one performed by courts in the first place, is the place where normative hierarchies are in fact established. Sometimes, indeed, and contrary to the standard picture hinted at above, interpretation precedes, and may even establish, the sources themselves, rather than the other way round. I will then conclude with some general remarks on the scope of freedom and constraint in legal argumentation (sec. 6). Unfashionably, in this paper I will be mainly concerned with the viewpoint of national, municipal legal systems, and of the legal actors operating therein. Accordingly, I will not deal with the issue of sources and their hierarchies in international law, or with the sources associated to the emerging body of global law and global constitutionalism. This limitation in the scope of my analysis is not meant to convey the impression that the question of the hierarchy of sources in international law, or in non-municipal systems generally, is not practically important or not worth of theoretical investigation – far from it12. Rather, the reason for limiting the scope of my analysis in this way is that by situating my argument to the context of national legal systems I intend to make my point – that sources of law and their hierarchies entertain a bidirectional relation with legal interpretation – more visible and striking. On the contrary, in non-state institutional contexts it is indeed almost obvious that interpreters enjoy a wide margin of appreciation in determining the respective strength and hierarchical position of the various legal sources13. 2. Sources of Law in Contemporary Jurisprudence Generally speaking, the topic of legal sources as such is normally neglected in contemporary legal theory. True, recently there has been some notable jurisprudential work on 11 The standard picture is obviously disavowed by legal realists (as well as by other anti-formalistic movements, such as the Critical Legal Studies), according to whom there are no such things as binding sources of law, let alone a binding and definite hierarchy of sources of law. In the legal realist picture of adjudication, legal reasoning is influenced by all kind of factors (policy arguments, cultural factors, individual sense of justice), and the hierarchy of legal sources may act only as an ideological a posteriori rationalization, a window-dressing in fact, of the judicial decision. See A. Ross, ‘Review of H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law’, and On Law and Justice, £££; J. Frank, ‘The Intermittent Sovereign’; B. Leiter; L. Green, ‘Law and the Causes of Judicial Decisions’. 12 Recent work on this topic, with remarkable jurisprudential implications, include M. Koskenniemi, ‘Hierarchy in International Law: A Sketch’; J.J.H. Weiler, A. Paulus, ‘The Structure of Change in International Law or Is There a Hierarchy of Norms in International Law?’; S. Besson, ‘Theorizing the Sources of International Law’. 13 See A.M. Slaughter, A Global Community of Courts; S. Cassese, I tribunali di Babele; J. Allard, A. Garapon, Les juges dans la mondialisation. The alleged absence of a rule of recognition (i.e. the rule that lists and orders the criteria of validity and so the very sources of the law) in international law is what prompted H.L.A. Hart to regarding international law as a borderline case of law. See H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, ch X; M. Payandeh, ‘The Concept of International Law in the Jurisprudence of H.L.A. Hart’; J. Waldron, ‘International Law: “A Relatively Small and Unimportant” Part of Jurisprudence?’. single types of sources of law, e.g. constitutions, legislation, precedents, and custom14; but there is comparative little on the concept of source as such15. This is particularly unfortunate since, as we have seen in sec. 1 above, the topic of the sources of law is intrinsically related to the positivity requirement of the law, which in turn is central to our common understanding of the law, and is also relevant to several important topics in legal and political philosophy such as the following ones: - The topic of sources is crucial in distinguishing law from non-law, and is closely related to the concept of legal validity; - The topic of sources points to, and explains, the idea of change in the law; - The topic of sources is crucial to some Rule of Law requirements, namely the ones related to the publicity and accountability of the law-making process16. In addition to all this, the concept of source of law is all the more crucial for a positivist theory of law – the whole point of legal positivism being that of conceiving of the law just as ‘positive law’17. Indeed, it is essential to any positivist understanding of the law that a) the law is conceptually distinct and distinguishable from other normative phenomena – from morality in the first place; and relatedly that b) the law has boundaries, it has a ‘limited domain’18. It is easy to see how these two positivistic requirements are related to the ‘positivity assumption’ introduced above (sec. 1), and in turn to the topic of the sources of law. While morality is not deliberately created in social settings, law is typically created therein: the law of a jurisdiction is identifiable through the sources of the law that are in place in that jurisdiction19. H.L.A. Hart’s doctrine of the rule of recognition (a social rule that lists the finite set of criteria of validity – the sources of law – in place within a certain social setting) compounds nicely all these positivistic theoretical requirements20. The champions of 20th century legal positivism had indeed paid some attention to the topic of the sources of law. Hans Kelsen….; Alf Ross….; H.L.A Hart… But in the second half of the 20th century, jurisprudential interest in the topic of the sources of law has rapidly declined. From the point of view of a micro-history of ideas, this may be due to two concurring factors. On the one hand, in the second half of the 20th century (say, from the late ‘60s onward) the main focus of jurisprudential enquiry has progressively shifted from the point of view of the ‘legal system’ – its structural features, its components, its dynamics – to the point of view of ‘legal reasoning’21. On the other hand, a large strand in the jurisprudential debate – especially in the positivistic camp – has become more and more preoccupied with ‘conceptual’ questions, i.e. questions such as the abstract possibility of conceiving of a legal system that does not refer to morality as a criterion of validity of its J. Gardner, ‘Some Types of Law’. On constitutions, J. Gardner, ‘Can There Be a Written Constitution?’. On legislation, J. Waldron, ‘Legislating with Integrity’, and ‘Principles of Legislation’. On precedent and judgemade law, R. Siltala [AND MANY OTHERS]. On custom as a source of law, Perreau-Saussine, Celano, Schauer. 15 Notable exceptions include: A. Peczenik, On Law and Reason; R. Guastini, ‘Fragments of a Theory of Legal Sources’; R. Shiner, £££. For the concept of source in the jurisprudence of Joseph Raz, see infra fn 18. 16 J. Waldron, ‘Can There Be a Democratic Jurisprudence?’ 17 But even anti-positivists or non-positivists do not dream of overlooking the ‘factual’ dimension of the law: see J. Finnis, ‘On the Incoherence of Legal Positivism’; R. Alexy, ‘The Dual Nature of the Law’. 18 J. Raz, ‘Legal Principles and the Limits of Law’; F. Schauer, ‘The Limited Domain of Law’; L. Alexander, F. Schauer, ‘Law’s Limited Domain Confronts Morality’s Universal Empire’; F. Schauer, V. Wise, ‘Legal Positivism as Legal Information’. 19 N. Bobbio, Teoria dell’ordinamento giuridico, p. 179 (noting that the description of a given legal system begins with the description of the sources of law that it comprises). 20 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, ch . For recent critical discussion on the concept of rule of recognition, see the various essays in M. Adler, K. Himma (eds.), The Rule of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution; G. Pino, ‘Farewell to the Rule of Recognition?’ 21 N. MacCormick, ‘The Rediscovery of Practical Reason’ and Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory; A. Aarnio, R. Alexy, A. Peczenik; R. Alexy, Theory of Legal Argumentation; R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire 14 norms. In this more ‘conceptual’ debate, also the idea of a source of law surfaces sometimes, but only in a very rarefied and stipulative way22. 3. Some Preliminary Definitions and Distinctions Having duly recognized the central place of the concept of legal sources for any understanding of the law, and with particular magnitude for a positivistic theory of law, a survey of some useful theoretical concepts is in order, to be in a better position to understand what a source is, and how it works. The following subsections will briefly introduce some important definitions and distinctions to this effect. 3.1. Legal Acts, Legal Texts, Legal Norms The first distinction to be drawn is between acts, texts and norms. By a legal act I mean the procedure that has to be followed by a duly empowered body or institution in order to achieve the result of changing the law, by way of creation of new law, or derogation, modification, or abrogation of existing law – in short, the law-making process. In contemporary legal systems, the law-making process is normally and heavily regulated by the law itself: by (secondary) rules of change, or norms of competence23. The legal regulation of the law-making process usually includes: the identification of a body, or more accurately of a set of bodies that are empowered to take that part in the law-making process (i.e., to exercise law-making power), and their respective roles therein; the procedures to be followed in order to properly achieve the result of creating new law, or of derogating, modifying, or abrogating existing law; sometimes, the material limits to the proper exercise of the law-making power. By legal text, or legal document, I mean the normal outcome of a law-making process – in contemporary legal systems, the law-making process typically results in an official legal document24. By legal norm I mean the content of meaning that is normally expressed by a legal text – or more accurately, by specific portions of it25. Legal interpretation, or textual interpretation, is See F. Schauer, V. Wise, ‘Legal Positivism as Legal Information’, pp. 1093-1094 (observing that in contemporary jurisprudential debate, ‘source’ denotes any kind of contingent social decision about what is to count as law). Much in this spirit, the concept of source plays a crucial role in the version of legal positivism elaborated by Joseph Raz (the ‘sources thesis’), but Raz’s notion of ‘source’ is rather technical and admittedly different from the one prevalent in the common usage of lawyers; see J. Raz, ‘Legal Positivism and the Sources of Law’, pp. 47-48, and ‘Legal Reasons, Sources and Gaps’, p. 63. See also J. Gardner, ‘Legal Positivism: 5 and ½ Myths’, p. 20; L. Green, ‘Legal Positivism’. 23 On rules of change, see H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, ch £££; on norms of competence, see T. Spaak, The Concept of Legal Competence, and ‘Explicating the Concept of Legal Competence’; on the idea that the law regulates its own creation, H. Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State, £££. Norms of competence are sometimes included in the general class of ‘meta-norms’. Still, as should appear clear from the discussion in this subsection, defining norms of competence as meta-norms is mistaken, since norms of competence do not refer to norms proper, but to legal acts. 24 The obvious exception here is custom, whose production does not necessarily – and not even typically – result in a formal document. The role of custom as a source of law in contemporary legal systems is notoriously a marginal one. 25 The distinction between legal texts and their meanings (the norms they convey) is reminiscent of von Wright’s distinction between a norm and a norm-formulation (see G.H. von Wright, Norm and Action, pp. 93-95); this distinction is not always duly acknowledged in contemporary analytical legal theory. For some notable exceptions, see R. Guastini, ‘Rule-Scepticism Restated’, p. 147; D. Priel, ‘Trouble For Legal Positivism?’; see also F. Schauer, Playing by the Rules, pp. 62-64 (acknowledging that the distinction between the rule and the ruleformulation is important, but adding that ‘the implications of that lesson are limited, and likely to be exaggerated’, at 64). 22 the process of ascertaining the meaning of a legal text. Accordingly, legal norms are identified by way of legal interpretation. As we have seen (sec. 1 above), the process of legal interpretation is sometimes regulated by the law itself; but normally the various methods or ‘canons’ of legal interpretation, and their respective order of priority, are in actual fact the product of the relevant legal culture. In the definition of legal norm provided at the beginning of this paragraph, I have said that a legal norm is ‘normally’ expressed by a legal text. By this I mean that legal norms may be established also by way of an argument that does not have the form of textual interpretation – one that does not present itself has the ascription of meaning to a legal text. This is the case of legal norms established by analogical reasoning, and of some legal unstated legal principles26. In such cases we may use the label ‘unstated norms’, to mark the difference with (and the different role played by the interpreter in the case of) the other, textually stated legal norms. 3.2. ‘Sources of Law’: Disambiguating the Concept Now, with the above distinctions in mind, we can see that sometimes the concept of ‘source’ is referred to the law-making act, and sometimes it is referred to the documents that are typically created by way of those law-making acts. This ambiguity is rather innocuous. Nonetheless, and unless stated otherwise, in the following of this paper I will use ‘source’ only in the second sense, as a document duly produced as the result of a law-making process, and typically subject to legal interpretation in order to ascertain its meaning (i.e., the norms it expresses). 3.3. Type-Sources and Token-Sources Legal sources present themselves, typically, in the form of documents enacted as the outcome of a certain – legally regulated – procedure. Now, to this regard it is possible to further distinguish between a kind of legal source (a type-source), and a specific instance of a legal source (a token-source). Accordingly, it is possible to talk of legislation as a source of law (in the ‘type’ sense of source), as well as of a single statute as a source of law (now in the ‘token’ sense of source). Much on the same footing, it makes perfect sense to say that while legislation is a source of law (in the ‘type’ sense of source) in a certain jurisdiction J, a specific statute is disallowed to serve as a source of law (in the ‘token’ sense of source), due to some fatal defects in the procedure of enactment, or to the fact that it has been repealed by subsequent legislation. 3.4. Institutionalized and Non-Institutionalized Sources; Binding and Permissive Sources I have defined a ‘source’ as, typically, a document duly produced as the result of a lawmaking process (see sec. 2.1 above). This, in fact, can be considered as the definition of an ‘institutionalized source’, i.e. a source whose production is regulated, with variable degrees of intensity, by other norms of the legal system. But ‘source of law’ is sometimes used in a different, more loose way, to refer to all the possible factors that determine or influence the decision of a legal actor – typically a judge. These factors could be any number of things: sense of justice, equity, cultural and political orientation, policy arguments, judicial precedents (in 26 See N. MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory, £££. The idea that legal principles lack ‘pedigree’ – i.e., are not formally enacted – is stressed by R. Dworkin, ‘The Model of Rules I’; but Dworkin patently overstates the case here, since of course there may be – and there often are – legal principles expressly formulated in legal documents. civil law countries), legislative intentions and preparatory materials, foreign legal materials, and so on. We can call all these ‘non-institutionalized sources’27. The distinction between ‘institutionalized’ and ‘non-institutionalized’ sources is ‘structural’ in character: it pertains to what a certain source is, and how it is produced (an aspect on which I will have more to say shortly, sec. 3 below). And this structural distinction should not be confused with a distinction pertaining a ‘functional’ aspect – what certain sources do, or can typically be expected to do. With reference to this aspect, the function of legal sources is to guide and determine decisions that are to be assumed by legal actors (legal actors are supposed to act on reasons provided by legal sources, with exclusion of those other reasons that have been excluded or not allowed by legal sources). More precisely, sources of law are expected to determine a legal decision (i.e., a judge is bound to apply a certain statute, as a legal source, even if she does not agree with the content of the source) – once they have been duly interpreted of course. So, a legal source is expected to provide legal actors with a place where to look for the legal norms that will then ground a legal decision28. Now, as far as the functional dimension of legal sources is concerned, it is possible to distinguish between ‘binding’ sources and ‘permissive’ sources29. Binding sources are those sources that the legal actor is bound to apply – if a legal actor disregards a binding source, his decision will be legally wrong (the decision will be invalid; or it will be considered as a reason to impose some kind of fine or liability on that legal actor; and so on). Permissive sources, on the other hand, have lesser, and variable, weight: they can be disregarded without affecting the validity of the relevant legal decision (or without producing otherwise adverse consequences for the legal actor in question); their use is permitted, and it can improve the degree of persuasiveness, acceptability to the relevant legal decision. I will return to the distinction between binding and permissive sources shortly (sec. 4 above). What I mean to stress here is that the ‘institutionalized’/‘non-institutionalized’ distinction and the ‘binding’/’permissive’ one are not symmetric. A certain institutionalized source may be (perceived as) merely permissive, and a non-institutionalized legal source may (be perceived as) binding by the relevant legal actors. 3.5. Formal Validity, Material Validity, Existence, Applicability As we have already seen (sec. 1 above), legal sources are what determines the distinction between law and non-law – something can count as law only if it is traceable back to a legal source. And in jurisprudential jargon there is a specific, magic word that is used to refer to what belongs to law (to a legal system) – validity. So it would seem natural indeed to relate directly legal sources (the basis of legality) to legal validity (the property of being legally existent). Things are somewhat more complicated than this, though. For one thing, contemporary legal systems usually resort to both ‘formal’ and ‘material’ criteria of legal validity (borrowing from Kelsen’s terminology, legal systems usually combine See A. Ross, On Law and Justice, pp. 75-78 (‘completely objectivated’, partially objectivated’, ‘nonobjectivated’ sources); A. Peczenik, On Law and Reason, p. 257 (‘substantive reasons’ v. ‘authority reasons’); R. Shiner, Legal Institutions and the Sources of Law, p. 3; R. Guastini, ‘On the Theory of Legal Sources. A Continental Point of View’, p. 305 (but note that Shiner and Guastini do not define the relevant distinction in exactly the same way). 28 See supra, fn 9 and accompanying text. 29 Various ways to present this distinction are provided by H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, p. 294; A. Peczenick, On Law and Reason, pp. 261-264; L. Green, ‘Law and the causes of Judicial Decisions’, § 3. 27 both ‘static’ and ‘dynamic’ criteria of legal validity30). Accordingly, we should conveniently distinguish between a formal and a material dimension of legal validity. Formal validity obtains when a legal act is enacted in accordance to all the procedural requirements that surround that specific kind of law-making activity; when this is the case, then the relevant legal act, and the legal document produced thereby, are formally valid. Material validity obtains when a legal norm is compatible (i.e., it lacks logical contradictions to and is substantially coherent, in the sense introduce above, fn 4) with another, ‘superior’ norm31. Accordingly, material validity is not source-based, but content-based. Its ascertainment requires the comparison of its content with the content of another norm. As a consequence of the definitions above, formal validity is a quality of legal sources, whereas material validity is a quality of norms. (Since formal validity and material validity are distinct properties, it is possible to introduce even a third concept, such as ‘full validity’, that would obtain when a legal norm is both materially valid and is expressed by a legal source that is formally valid32.) The importance of separating the two faces of legal validity lies not only in the fact that they are different from a conceptual point of view (one pertains to procedures, the other to meanings), but also in some aspects of legal practice. For instance, in jurisdictions where a judicial review of legislation is in place, it can happen that a statute is challenged either on formal or on material grounds; or it can happen that a constitutional challenge targets only a single allegedly materially invalid norm, among the many alternative norms that can be derived by means of interpretation by a single statute. Moreover, if we recall the possibility (hinted at above, sec. 2.1) that some legal norms cannot be considered as the meaning of a legal text, such as in the case of analogy and of some legal principles, then we have legal norms that are not evaluable in terms of the formal validity of their sources. Moreover, formal and material validity do not seem to exhaust all the possible ways in which a source or a norm can have effect in a legal system33. Indeed, it can happen that a legal source or a legal norm is actually used by the legal actors of a legal system despite the fact that that source is formally invalid, or the fact that that norm is materially invalid. This can happen in two ways. On the one hand, it can happen that a legal source or legal norm is actually invalid, but some actors of the system do not have the power to declare its invalidity; or it can happen that its invalidity has been mistakenly ignored by the competent legal actor. In such cases, there can be an obligation on some legal actors to give effect to a legal source or norm that is actually invalid. On the other hand, it can be the case that a legal source is formally invalid, but legal actors decide that the relevant fault is indeed irrelevant, a minor one, and so they decide to treat that source as actually formally valid. So there seem to be cases in which an invalid source or norm is actually treated as valid: the fact that the procedure for the production of a legal document (formal validity) has not been perfectly complied with, or that the content of the legal norms derived by a source is not perfectly compatible with a higher norm, do not necessarily prevent legal actors from using and giving legal effect to the formally invalid 30 For the static/dynamic distinction, see H. Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, £££, and General Theory of Law and State, £££. 31 I qualify ‘superior’ with inverted commas here, because I want to stress that as far as this definition is concerned we do not still have any criterion whatsoever in order to ascertain the ‘superiority’ of one norm over another. This point will be specifically taken up at sec. 3.2 below. 32 R. Guastini, ‘Invalidity’, p. 224; Wil Waluchow uses a similar concept, ‘systemic validity’, to refer to ‘full validity’ plus the fact that the fully valid norm is accepted and treated by the relevant legal actors as a valid norms: W. Waluchow, ‘Four Concepts of Validity’, p. 140 (Waluchow’s notion of ‘systemic validity’ is in turn borrowed and adapted from J. Raz, ‘Legal Validity’). 33 I am here ignoring the case of foreign norms whose operation in a legal system may be required by those system’s private international law provisions. This case is immaterial to my present concerns. source or to the materially invalid norm. In order to describe such cases, we cannot resort to the concept of validity: we need a different concept – ‘existence’34. From the point of view of legal theory, two interesting lessons can be drawn from what has been said in this subsection. First, both formal and material validity are a matter of interpretation, and as such they can be a matter of substantial disagreement between lawyers; likewise, treating an invalid item as nonetheless ‘existent’ is entirely an interpreter’s decision (on both points we will return shortly, see sec. 4 below). Second, any legal system is populated by various legal norms that somehow ‘belong’ to that system without being valid according to the criteria of validity of that legal system; this is so because legal actors will routinely use (treat as valid) certain laws that are not really valid, and because some norms of the legal system are not validated by other, ‘superior’ norms of that legal system, and so they are neither valid nor invalid – typically, this is the status of constitutional norms35. Accordingly, it is not true (actually, it cannot be true) that the legal system is the sum total of all the laws that are valid according to the criteria set by that legal system. 3. Normative Hierarchies in the Law As noted at the beginning of sec. 3, the general interest to the topic in contemporary jurisprudential discussion has been rather scarce; and, as a matter of fact, the interest in a theoretical analysis of normative hierarchies in the law has been even more meager36. Sociologically, this may probably be related to the conjunction of two circumstances: the fact that the since the last few decades the agenda of contemporary debates in legal theory is mainly dictated by the Anglo-Saxon academe, and the fact that – due exceptions allowed – in the common perception of the average Anglo-Saxon legal scholar the hierarchy of legal sources does not really seem to be an issue worth exploring (this, in turn, is probably due to some perceived lack of ‘verticality’ in the structure of common law legal systems, as opposed to the pyramidal structure of civil law systems37). Be that as it may, I believe that there is some important theoretical work to be done on the concept of normative hierarchy, and that this work may produce useful tools for both civil and common law countries. And, at any rate, it is now almost a commonplace to note the ever increasing convergence between the civil law and common law traditions. I will begin with a brief exploration of the ways in which the concept of normative hierarchy appears – albeit not always under this label – in some landmark work in contemporary legal philosophy (sec. 3.1). Then I will try to elaborate and defend a possible taxonomy of different senses of normative hierarchy that are relevant to the law (sec. 3.2). 3.1. Normative Hierarchies in Legal Theory R. Guastini, ‘Invalidity’, p. 224; W. Waluchow, ‘Four Concepts of Validity’, p. 140. R. Guastini, ‘On Legal Order: Some Criticism of the Received View’. 36 Apart from the few ‘classics’ that I will present shortly, some recent investigations in the topic of normative hierarchies have been provided by R. Guastini, M. Troper, O. Pfersmann, G. Pino, J. Ferrer, J. Rodriguez. 37 In a recent book devoted to the theory of legal sources, written by a Canadian scholar but intended for an international audience, the topic of normative hierarchies is hardly noticed: see R. Shiner, Legal Institutions and the Sources of Law. Significantly, this absence has been immediately recorded by two European Continental reviewers of that book: J. Wolenski, R. Guastini, ‘On the Theory of Legal Sources. A Continental Point of View’. See also J.H. Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition, p. 26 (stating that in common law countries ‘there is no systematic, hierarchical theory of sources of law’). 34 35 The topic of normative hierarchies appears prominently in Hans Kelsen’s legal theory. According to Kelsen, the legal system is characteristically structured in a hierarchical fashion (Stufenbau)38. This is so, because each valid norm of the legal system, N1, derives its validity from another (valid) norm N2, which prescribes the mode of production of N1. By mode of production, Kelsen basically means the forms and procedures to be adopted by the competent body in order to validly enact N1; to some extent, N2 may also predetermine the content of N1. Accordingly, “the relation between the norm that regulates the creation of another norm and the norm created in conformity with the former can be metaphorically presented as a relation of super- and subordination. The norm which regulates the creation of another norm is the higher, the norm created in conformity with the former is the lower one”39. H.L.A. Hart has deployed some conceptual tools that make room for two, or maybe three, different kinds of normative hierarchies in modern, municipal legal systems. On the one hand, there is the fact that such legal systems comprise two kinds of rules, primary rules and secondary rules; primary rules are rules of obligation, secondary rules are rules that regulate the creation and modification (rules of change), individuation (rule of recognition), and application (rule of adjudication) of the primary rules. Accordingly, between secondary rules and primary rules a certain kind of relation is in place, and this relation can be usefully defined as a certain kind of normative hierarchy: primary rules are the object of secondary rules; secondary rules are meta-norms that refer to primary rules40. On the other hand, Hart associates the topic of sources and legal validity to the concept of the rule of recognition, and states that a rule of recognition can provide either a) an order of priority between the various sources it refers to41, or b) a principle of derivation of validity, such that one rule derives its validity from another rule, in hierarchical order42. Hart describes these last two hypotheses as cases of “a complex rule of recognition with [a] hierarchical ordering of distinct criteria”43. But indeed here we seem to have two separate instances of hierarchical ordering of norms or of sources, as Hart himself is ready do admit: a relation of derivation, and a relation of subordination44. 3.2. Towards a Taxonomy of Normative Hierarchies in the Law The concept of normative hierarchy is ambiguous, it can be used to describe different kinds of relations between legal norms, relations that can produce different effects, and so it is important to make it clear what concept of hierarchy is relevant in which context. It is high time 38 H. Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, ch V; General Theory of Law and State. H. Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, p. 221. Hence, Kelsen adds, ‘the legal order is […] a hierarchy of different levels of legal norms’. Kelsen is here indebted to Adolf Merkl’s ‘gradualistic’ approach to law. But note that Merkl’s approach to normative hierarchies was more nuanced than Kelsen’s, comprising both the kind of hierarchies envisaged also by Kelsen, and hierarchies related to ‘legal strength’ – if a norm N1 can derogate to a norm N2, then N1 is hierarchically superior to N2 (see A. Merkl, ‘Prolegomena einer Theorie des rechtlichen Stufenbaues’). 40 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, £££. For a critical appraisal of this point, see D. Gerber, ‘Levels of Rules and Hart’s Concept of Law’. 41 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, p. 101. 42 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, p. 107: ‘if the question is raised whether some suggested rule is legally valid, we must, in order to answer the question, use a criterion of validity provided by some other rule’. 43 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, p. 101. On the hierarchical structure of the criteria of validity enlisted in the rule of recognition, see M. Kramer, Where Law and Morality Meet, £££. Other Hartian scholars prefer to talk of different, hierarchically ordered rules of recognition: see J. Raz, ‘Legal Validity’, pp. 150-151; F. Schauer, £££. 44 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, p. 101. In much the same vein, see also R. Shiner, Legal Institutions and the Sources of Law, p. 38 (subordination ‘by derivation’, and subordination ‘by power of abrogation’). 39 to propose a more-fine grained account of normative hierarchies in the law, one that takes into account the several important legal concepts and distinctions that we have introduced in precedent sections (legal sources, norms, formal validity, material validity). Following the lead of some recent work on the concept of normative hierarchy in the law 45, I will propose a distinction between several relevant senses in which a hierarchical relation may obtain in the law. (I will deal mainly with hierarchies of sources and hierarchies of norms; I will leave out of direct consideration here the topic of hierarchies of organs and institutions.) A structural, or formal, hierarchy obtains when a norm, or more likely a set of norm, N1, regulates the production of a certain source (i.e., of a type-source). As a consequence, in order to count as a valid source, a given token-source S1 must have been enacted in conformity to the formal and procedural requirements set forth by norm N1. Clearly enough, this concept of normative hierarchy is directly related to the concept of formal validity (see sec. 2.3 above). A norm N1 is structurally or formally superior to a source S1, if it regulates the production of S1, or in other words if it is condition for the formal validity of S146. Differently put, a structural hierarchy obtains between a norm of competence (power-conferring norms, rules of change), and the legal sources that are produced as the effect of the correct exercise of that legal competence of power47. A material hierarchy obtains when a norm N1 cannot be incompatible with another norm (or set of norms) N2; if it is the case that N1 is in actual fact incompatible with N2, then N1 is materially invalid48. So in this case there is a relation of material hierarchy between N1 and N2, such that N2 is superior, in the specified sense, to N1; N2 is thus condition of material validity of N1. The obvious problem, here, is to make sense of the status of N2: when is it the case that N2 is actually superior, in the relevant sense, to N1? The most obvious answer – that N2 is superior to N1 if the former is condition of material validity of the latter – is, of course, questionbegging: indeed, being a condition of validity means being superior. We need a way out of the circle, and this can only be another norm, N3, that provides the required hierarchical ordering of N1 and N2. This will typically be done when N3 provides for a mechanism for the removal of N1 in case it conflicts with N2 (for instance, a system of judicial review of legislation). Accordingly, a material hierarchy between N1 and N2 obtains when a third norm (or set of norms) N3 states that in cases of conflict between N1 and N2, N1 shall be declared null and void. So, it is a norm of the kind of N3 that allows to – actually, it is N3 that establishes the material hierarchy between N1 and N2: absent N3, there would be no criterion whatsoever to the effect that N2 is superior to N1. In the terms of the example above, it is the existence of a system of judicial review of legislation that allows to claim that the constitution is hierarchically superior, in this sense, to legislation. Absent such a system, there would not be a relation of material hierarchy between legislation and the constitution – but there still could be a structural hierarchical relation, if it is the case that the conditions of valid enactment of statutes are regulated by the constitution. Most notably the work of R. Guastini, ‘Fragments of a Theory of Legal Sources’, and ‘On Legal Order: Some Criticism of the Received View’. My account is not entirely identical to the one provided by Guastini, though. 46 In a similar vein, M. Adler, M. Dorf, ‘Constitutional Existence Conditions and the Constitution’, talk of ‘existence conditions’ provided by the constitution to infra-constitutional sources (i.e., the constitution states the conditions in accordance to which infra-constitutional sources can count as valid instances of the relevant typesource). 47 Cf W. Waluchow, ‘Four Concepts of Validity’, p. 137: ‘failure to observe a condition for the valid exercise of a Hohfeldian power of law creation must, as a sheer conceptual matter, be a nullity’. 48 According to M. Adler, M. Dorf, ‘Constitutional Existence Conditions and the Constitution’, in this case N2 acts as a ‘application condition’ of N1. 45 A logical hierarchy obtains when a norm (or set of norms) N1 has the function of regulating the application of other norms N2. For instance, a norm N1 that expressly abrogates or derogates to a norm N2, is hierarchically superior, in this sense, to N2. A semantic hierarchy obtains when a norm regulates the interpretation of some sources49. An axiological hierarchy obtains when one norm (or set of norms), is deemed more important in respect to another norm (or set of norms). For instance, legal principles are usually deemed more important than detailed rules (principles can make rules defeasible). Normally, and absent a material hierarchy to the same effect, the operation of an axiological hierarchy will consist in a judgment of preference or of applicability between the norms involved. So, if N1 is considered superior, in this sense, to N2, the consequence will be the application of N1, without resorting to a declaration of invalidity of N2. N2 will be just ‘set aside’ for the instant case, but it will still be in force in the legal system, and potentially applicable in another case in which it does not conflict with N150. An axiological hierarchy can coexist with a material hierarchy to the same effect – this is the normal way to understand the relation between a rigid constitution and legislation in a system with judicial review. In this case, legal actors may be confronted with the decision of giving effect to the material hierarchy (= declaration of invalidity of the inferior norm that conflicts with the superior one), or to the axiological hierarchy (= giving effect to the superior norm and setting aside the inferior one, with a declaration of invalidity). But sometimes an axiological hierarchy can be established absent a material hierarchy to the same effect – indeed, it can be established between norms that have the same status as far as the material hierarchy is concerned (more on this below, sec. 4). 4. Sources, Normative Hierarchies, and Legal Interpretation Now that we have shed some theoretical light (or so the author hopes) on some important jurisprudential concepts, as well as on the various sense and types of normative hierarchies that operate in legal systems, we are in a better position to grasp the many ways in which legal interpretation (or legal reasoning more generally) actually shapes, or concurs in shaping, the relevant legal sources and the hierarchical relations – the other main aim of this paper. Recall that the backdrop of this discussion will be the widespread cultural and ideological assumption that legal sources and their hierarchies are the objective starting point of legal interpretation, something on which the interpreter has no say, no decisive power – quite to the contrary, legal sources and their hierarchical ordering is a given, an objective constraint for the interpreters. We have referred to this as the ‘standard picture’ of adjudication (see sec. 1 above). I will make two kind of remarks, here: one pertaining to the relation between sources as such and interpretation, the other pertaining to the relation between normative hierarchies and interpretation. (I will separate the two kinds of remarks for convenience’s sake, but they are actually interrelated on many accounts.) The first remark is, generally put, that the relation between legal sources and legal interpretation is not ‘unidirectional’, as it were, but indeed ‘bidirectional’. A unidirectional account is exactly the one that is assumed by the standard picture of adjudication: the interpreter merely acknowledges, as a matter of objective fact, the existence of some sources, and then proceeds to interpret it (the only margin of discretion for the interpreter, if such a margin indeed there is, lies with the choice and the operation of the various canons of interpretation). On the contrary, I will stress the case for a bidirectional account of the relation On ‘secondary rules of interpretation’, see W. Waluchow, Inclusive Legal Positivism. The establishment of an axiological hierarchy is an apt description of what happens, for instance, when a court resorts to ‘ad hoc balancing’ between competing constitutional principles. 49 50 between legal sources and legal interpretation: it is not the case that legal interpretation takes place only on independently established legal sources. To begin with, some amount of legal interpretation is actually required already at that stage of legal reasoning where the interpreter ‘finds’ and selects the legal sources that are relevant for his argument51. Indeed, since (as we have seen above, sec. 2) a legal source is normally a document enacted as the outcome of a certain procedure, and since this procedure is normally regulated by several legal norms, the judgment that the item S1 is a valid legal source will normally presuppose a) having interpreted the relevant power-conferring norms (i.e., the relevant norms that provide the conditions of formal validity for the source in question – the norms that superior from the point of view of the relevant structural hierarchy); b) having ascertained that the item in question actually fulfils the relevant conditions of formal validity52. This operation becomes increasingly more complex, and involves an increasing degree of interpretive contribution from the interpreter, when we move to the case of what the Italian legal culture calls ‘combinato disposto’, i.e. the practice of deriving a single legal norm from sentences that are distributed in multiple, diverse legal texts (from an article of the Civil Code and from an article of a statute enacted decades later, for instance) – sometimes even distributed in texts that belong to different levels of the hierarchy of sources: for instance, a statute and the Constitution. But we can easily consider many other important examples in which the interpreter plays an active role – actually, almost a creative role – vis-a-vis legal sources. In some cases, interpreters may have to decide if a certain kind of act (of document) is actually a source – more precisely, they decide if some kinds of acts can amount to typesources (in the sense defined above, sec. 2.2). For instance, a legalistic legal culture may be tempted to deny the quality of legal source proper to a written constitution – they can consider it just a political manifesto, serving as a source of inspiration for the action of political actors. Or, in a civil law legal context it can be debated if, under what conditions and with what legal strength judicial precedents are sources of law. Or, it may be necessary to decide if some kind of soft law may amount to a legal source proper. In some cases, interpreters may have to decide if a certain specific act (or document) is actually a source – more precisely, they decide if some acts can amount to token-sources (again, in the sense defined above, sec. 2.2). Here the question facing the interpreter will be: is this specific item, that prima facie appears to be a formally valid piece of legislation, really a source of law? Is it still in force? Does it express a normative content? Questions like these may rise, for instance, in circumstances of implied repeal – when, in fact, it is left to the interpreter to decide if a piece of legislation, that the competent authority has not explicitly repealed, is still in force. Or, it can happen that a piece of legislation includes ‘things’ that the interpreters do not wish to consider as strictly normative, or binding: canons of interpretation, for instance, or legislative definitions, and the like. Similarly, sometimes the interpreters have to decide what is the actual strength of a purported legal source (sometimes, rarely, this is positively prescribed by legal sources themselves: see art. 288.5 TFEU, ‘Recommendations and opinions shall have no binding force’): here is where the distinction between binding and persuasive sources becomes relevant, and this distinction is usually decided by the interpreters themselves53. So, theoretical and interpretive disagreement about legal sources may involve either the status of something as a legal source in the sense of a token-source, or – even more radically – 51 Dworkin, Troper (una teoria realista), Adler-Dorf 53 J. Bell, ‘Comparing Precedent’, pp. 1254-1255; F. Schauer, Thinking Like a Lawyer, p. 80. 52 its status as a type-source54. But indeed, legal interpretation may not only involve the establishment of legal sources as such – it may also establish normative hierarchies as well. For one thing, axiological hierarchies are usually – albeit not necessarily – established by means of legal interpretation and argumentation, or by use of doctrinal concepts and constructions. Moreover, axiological hierarchies are often established (by the interpreters) upon norms that belong to the same level as far as the material hierarchy is concerned. Accordingly, interpreters actually introduce a hierarchy (here understood as an axiological hierarchy) where there was none (the relevant norms are on the same level from the point of view of material hierarchies). Here is an example: one begins with a distinction between the ‘formal’ and the ‘material’ constitution55: the former is the actual text that is formally labeled ‘Constitution’, the latter is the set of norms that regulate the procedures of law-making and – according to some – also the procedures of law-application56; as it happens, the norms that compound the ‘material’ constitution usually, are as a matter of formal hierarchy, statutory norms; but since they are part of the ‘material’ constitution, they deserve more importance than other statutory norms – with all probability, they will be deemed more ‘resistant’ to abrogation and amendment than other ‘ordinary’ statutory norms. Moreover, when interpreters envisage a relation of axiological hierarchy between some norms (when they consider that some norms are particularly important, regardless of their actual status from the point of view of material hierarchies), they will often tend to devise some means of ‘protection’ of the relevant norms. More precisely, they will try to introduce – by means of legal interpretation and argumentation – some mechanism of invalidation of those norms that violate the other (axiologically superior) norms. Following the terminology deployed in this paper, they will tend to convert an axiological hierarchy into a material one. We may illustrate this practice of converting an axiological hierarchy into a material one are with at least two particularly striking, and well-known, examples. For one thing, there is the practice of many constitutional courts around the world of recognizing material limits to constitutional amendments (absent any formal attribution of a power of judicial review of constitutional amendments). As is well-known, many Constitutional courts have explicitly claimed their legal and constitutional power to declare the unconstitutionality of constitutional amendments, in case of violation of certain constitutional clauses. Moreover, the establishment of judicial review itself in the United States has followed exactly this pattern: in the legal reasoning of Justice Marshall, the acknowledgement of the (axiological) superiority of the Constitution ‘logically’57 requires the establishment of a mechanism of judicial review of legislation – and now we are in the position to see exactly why: absent judicial review, the Constitution would not be superior at all, at least from the point of view of material hierarchies. 5. Conclusions: Freedom and Constraint in Legal Argumentation I understand in this second sense Ronald Dworkin’s challenge to legal positivism based on the pervasiveness of theoretical disagreements in law (see R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire): I take Dworkin as pointing here not merely to interpretive disagreements on the meaning and validity of specific legal sources, but on the status itself of certain things as sources of the law – for instance, principles and other moral arguments. On this, see A. Dolcetti, G.B. Ratti, ‘Legal Disagreements and the Dual Nature of the Law’. 55 Kelsen accepts such a distinction, for instance. See H. Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, £££ 56 According to our taxonomy, these cases would entail a logical and a semantic hierarchy, respectively, among the relevant norms (see sec. 3.2 above). 57 Of course this is not a logical requirement at all – it is a political, substantive requirement. 54 I have tried to show that the relation between legal sources and interpretation is not unidirectional, but bidirectional. In doing this, I have highlighted the many ways in which interpreters may actively intervene in the individuation of legal sources and in determining their status as sources as well as their legal strength. Moreover, I have tried to show that interpreters may play a decisive role also in the working and in the establishment itself of normative hierarchies – and for this reason I have provided a taxonomy of normative hierarchies that is intended to be both descriptively more accurate than the common sense, catch-all idea of hierarchy of legal sources (as well as more detailed than some approaches present in contemporary legal theory), and apt to bring into relief the manifold interpretive and argumentative practices related to normative hierarchies. Now, the argument that I have tried to develop in this paper could be taken to suggest the following conclusion: the entire legal system (not only legal norms, that are utterly the product of legal interpretation, but also legal sources and their hierarchy) is, at the end of the day, produced by the interpreters. This paper has begun with some apparent platitudes on the role of legal sources and their hierarchy as guides on the activities of interpreters, and now we seem to be left with exactly the opposite conclusion. But this need not be the case. The impossibility of attaining the ‘noble dream’ of legalism (“the law completely predetermines judicial decisions”) need not have us automatically embracing the ‘nightmare’ of global skepticism (“the law is entirely created by judges”)58. Indeed, even if judges enjoy some latitude in the ascertainment, establishment, and operation of legal sources, they are bound to operate within multiple constraints. First of all, legal interpretation does not take place in a vacuum, rather it is a sort of collective enterprise. By this I mean that legal decisions require to be justified, and they can be justified only on the ground of reasons that the other legal actors can be disposed to regard as legally acceptable. Accordingly, it is simply not true that any single judge enjoys absolute freedom to decide whatever she pleases on, for instance, the legal strength – or the lack thereof – of some legal source. It is true, on the contrary, that such decisions happen to be taken collectively, as it were, by means of the stratification of several decisions and of the arguments put on their behalf. (It is nevertheless true, of course, that the margin of interpretive discretion becomes increasingly more significant the more one moves towards the top of the echelon of judicial institutions.) Moreover, there are also wider institutional constraints on the interpretive decisions of judges – most notably, the foreseeable reactions of other political actors, such as legislators59. At the end of the day, all these constraints are more cultural, sociological and political, then legal in character. But their operation normally ensures some balanced sense of continuity and innovation in the legal system. The obvious reference is to H.L.A. Hart, ‘American Jurisprudence Through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream’. See also J.J. Moreso, Legal Indeterminacy and Constitutional Interpretation. 59 M. Troper, Le droit et la necessité, £££; V. Ferreres Comella, Constitutional Courts and Democratic Values, pp. £££ 58 Bibliography [partial and unpolished] Besson S., ‘Theorizing the Sources of International Law’ Bobbio N., Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico, Culver K., Giudice M., Legality’s Borders. An Essay in General Jurisprudence, OUP, Oxford, 2010. Dickson J., ‘Interpretation and Coherence in Legal Reasoning’, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2001 (revised version 2010). --, ‘How Many Legal Systems? Some Puzzles Regarding the Identity Conditions of, and Relations between, Legal Systems in the European Union’, Problema. Anuario de Filosofia y Teoría del Derecho, 2, 2008, pp. 9-50. --, ‘Towards a Theory of European Union Legal Systems’, in J. Dickson and P. Eleftheriadis (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of European Union Law, OUP, Oxford, 2012, pp. 25-53. Hart H.L.A., The Concept of Law Koskenniemi M., ‘Hierarchy in International Law: A Sketch’, European Journal of International Law, 8, 1997, pp. 566-582. MacCormick N., ‘Coherence in Legal Justification’, in A. Peczenik (ed.), Theory of Legal Science, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1984, pp. 235-251. Merryman J.H., The Civil Law Tradition, Pino G., ‘Legal Positivism in Contemporary Constitutional States’ Raz J., ‘Legal Positivism and the Sources of Law’, --, ‘Legal Reasons, Sources and Gaps’, Spaak T., The Concept of Legal Competence. An Essay in Conceptual Analysis, Dartmouth, London, 1994. --, ‘Explicating the Concept of Legal Competence’, in J.C. Hage, D. von der Pfordten (eds.), Concepts in Law, Springer, Dordrecht, 2009, pp. 67-80. --, ‘Legal Positivism and the Objectivity of Law’, Analisi e diritto, 2004, pp. 253-268. Waldron J., “Partly Laws Common to All Mankind”, --, ‘International Law: “A Relatively Small and Unimportant” Part of Jurisprudence?’, Weiler J.H.H., Paulus A., ‘The Structure of Change in International Law or Is There a Hierarchy of Norms in International Law?’, European Journal of International Law, 8, 1997, pp. 545-565. von Wright G.H., Norm and Action,