Accounting, Reality and Sustainability Reporting. Abstract Environmental and social accounting has the potential to contribute to a just and green community. This may be achieved by reforming accounting to consider how the art of interpretation can put us in touch with the world. The works of Donald Davidson, Richard Rorty and Charles Taylor are used to extend our understanding of accounting. The aim is to provide authentic reports about our utilization of the natural environment. The ideal of authentically is critical in representing our impacts on the natural world. This paper examines the philosophical and theoretical journey that compares traditional accounting with recent developments in political philosophy. Keywords: accounting, environmental accounting, facts, hermeneutics, interpretation, interpretivism, objectivity, subjectivity, value. Introduction Research concerning the social and environmental accounting project has been subject to critical insight and deliberation. This paper explores the objectivist implications for accounting and its reform agenda. This task is undertaken by revisting debates concerning whether accounting can provide objective and real information in its discursive reports.1 1 This examination involves the assumptions which connect In part, the argument contributes to Tomkin and Groves’ (1983a; 1983b) work on the role of the accountant in society. Additionally the paper extends Parker & Roffey (1997) and McKernan (2007) to consider how accounting 2 accounting with the natural environment. That is, can accounting provide authentic information about human impacts on the natural environment? On the traditional epistemological view, it is assumed accounting reports provide communicative reports that are ‘real’ and represent ‘facts’. McKernan (2007) used Donald Davidson’s philosophy of language to examine the philosophical assumptions on which accounting has been based. This theory of language was based on the view that there is no distinct separation between mind and world. Accordingly, it was possible for a new accountability framework to be constructed thereby providing real data. However, Davidson’s work has been the subject of criticism in the philosophy of language: the idea that our very best sentences put us in touch with the natural world has been falsified. Following McKernan, it is clear a new accountability framework is needed that examines the objectivity of value in the natural world. This examination is one that aims to revitalize the ethic of the discipline (Gray, 2009; Hopwood, 2009). In reconsidering the objectivity of accounting, its impact on the natural environment is examined.2 To do this, ideas from political interpretivists Hubert Dreyfus, John McDowell and Charles Taylor are used to move beyond instrumental and technical thinking. In questioning modern epistemology, a different way to understand the world is introduced from their work. This involves exploring the moral side of our being which is said to be the avenue through which we engage the natural environment. The moral side of our being involves direct perception and hermeneutics is another social imaginary to understand reporting technologies and its societal impacts (see Gray, 2009). 2 The argument in part is a development not only of McKernan (2007) but also Gray (2009) who has offered a critically informed conception of sustainability. This paper differs by focusing explicitly on the role of our basic sense of engagement in the world to reveal a new accountability model. Here interpretivism refers to that which is revealed when we consider how basic engagements with the world. 3 interpretation which connect us with the world. This philosophical approach has been defined asinterpretivist in directly engaging with objective values. The aim of interpretivism is not to assimilate with the logic of economic reason and instrumental rationality that prioritizes profit and calculation (see Shapiro, 1997; McKernan, 2007). They examine people’s basic coping skills to put us closer to the world than other disengaged philosophies. The idea that we have basic coping skills making us directly accountable to the world is useful for accounting researchers attempting to understand sustainability. This way to think about the world involves not simply reforming the current business system but rethinking our basic assumptions of that world. These assumptions reflect the means we use to understand and interpret the natural environment which in turn shape our accounting practices. The argument proceeds by claiming that environmental and social accounting reforms are on the wrong track. Current reforms such as carbon trading, business models, supply chain management for the environment are unlikely to reform the accounting profession in the public interest. This is partly due to the fact that the craft of environmental and social accounting has been colonized by the logic of instrumental rationality. Instrumental rationality is the type of thinking used by economists to calculate optimal outcomes at minimal cost. Instrumental rationality, therefore, limits the full realization of human perceptions of the world and creates a forgetfulness of our place in the world. By way of contrast, interpretivists search for value in the world utilizing not simply our powers of rationality but also our total bodily engagement in the world. In this paper I suggest a possible solution that involves a radical departure from the dominant philosophical assumption that the mind and world are separate. It is well known that naturalism and scientism separate mind and world as the only way 4 people interact with the world. I argue that this assumption creates an anthropocentric culture that ignores other values in the world. A suggested therapy for accounting ethics is a radical reworking of our understanding of being in the world and a reenchantment of our ethical appreciation of accounting. Structure of the argument Section 1 outlines debates concerning the objectivity of the world in a social and environmental accounting context. Section 2 examines criticisms of Davidson’s antirepresentational work as applied to accounting in the work of McKernan (2007). Section 3 introduces a philosophy of direct moral realism. Section 4 utilises Shapiro’s five philosophical propositions (see Shapiro, 1997). The final section outlines some directions for the future. Section 1: Objectivism and the world – the objectivist view of the world Environmental and social accounting is confronted with a crisis. This crisis has been from two directions. From one side, it has been argued that accounting is simply a social construct and cannot provide objective accounts. From another perspective, the technology of accounting has been submerged by the technical and social vectors it claimed to supersede. Following political interpretivists, it is important to understand how people interact with the world. One way to confront this dilemma is to investigate the assumption people access the external world through the mind. On that view, we can never really observe the world as-it-is (the myth of the given). That it is impossible to directly access the natural environment has introduced a host of dilemmas and problems for accounting and its relationship with philosophy. For accounting the 5 dilemma takes the form that if we do not know what nature is then it is impossible for us to provide discursive and real accounts. For philosophy the dilemma takes the form of a theistic dimension that there are external values existing independently of us. If there are external values in the cosmos that are independent of us, it becomes important to find means to access such value. Charles Taylor (2002a) argued that there is a big mistake operating in our culture. This mistake involves a (mis)understanding of what it is to know and how we know and value the world. If we get this thinking wrong there will be dire effects on both theory and practice in a host of domains, one of which is accounting. The debates involve how mind and world philosophy influence other bodies of knowledge such as accounting. Are other ways available that allow people to engage the world? If so, then, we misunderstand knowledge as mediational. Taylor observes: In its original form, this emerged in the idea that we grasp external reality through internal representations. Descartes in one of his letters, declared himself “assure, que je ne puis avoir aucune connaissance de ce qui est hors de moi, que par l’entremise des idees que j’ai eu en moi”. 3 When states of minds correctly and reliably represent what is out there, there is knowledge. (Taylor, 2004, p. 53) Notice that Taylor argues that the dominant philosophical discourse is based on a sharp separation between thinking minds and the world. The problem with the 3 From the letter to Gibieuf, 19 January 1642, which comes from the mediational passage: You inquire about the principle by which I claim to know that the idea I have of something is not an idea made inadequate by the abstraction of my intellect. I derive this knowledge purely from my own thought or consciousness. I am certain that I can have no knowledge of what is outside me except by means of the ideas I have within me; and so I take great care not to relate my judgements immediately to things in the world, and not to attribute to such things anything positive which I do not first perceive in the ideas of them. (Descartes, 1970, p. 123) 6 dominant way to understand the world is that we lose sight of the fact that we are engaged agents to whom self-interpretation is a feature of our very being. According to interpretivists, the dominant social science approach is assumed to be objective and neutral in its descriptions of the world. These assumptions can be traced back to mind–world dualism, as found in Descartes’ Mediations. The central message of that book was that our concepts and categories are the only means people have to access the external world. This naturalistic thinking, in turn, creates a social imaginary that has led to the supposition that humanity has the ability to control and transform the external world using procedure and technique. The search for unbridled profit gives undue emphasis to appetite, where the good life is reflected in continuing escalations in living standards. According to instrumental and economic reasoning, moral worth is determined by appeal to the appetite of un-regenerated individuals. This is a lesson Plato knew all too well. Section 2: The debate –interpretivists and representationalism Environmental and social accounting is a contested arena. The contest involves whether accounting information can create new pathways in the public spheres of a civil society. Environmental and social accounting has only recently begun to engage broader debates concerning the philosophy of direct realism (see McKernan, 2007; Shearer, 2002). For example, accounting and accountability research has been built on the supposition that reported accounts are objective and reflect reality. Early work in this area did not question the current order of things and simply assumed that financial reports were true and fair. These assumptions were criticized as simple conservative and middle-of-the-road justifications for the status quo. Notably, Hines (1988) and 7 Tinker (1985) challenged the conservative face of accounting and outlined how accounting is a social construct with distributional and social consequences. Moreover, accounting has only recently begun to explore the accounting implications associated with the supposition that humanity is not distinct from the world. This idea is connected with the philosophy of intentionality that maintains that the mind is in the world, and not separate from it. For example, Gray attempted to broaden accounting debates to imagine new ways to report to our communities. He stated: Equally the imagining of new (albeit unambitious) accountings within the terms of conventional accounting is currently experiencing a major upsurge on the back of ‘environmental accounting’. These imaginings carry the same managerialist attractions and detriments as the managerialist agenda envisaged by Preston (1981), only perhaps to a greater degree. Such ‘new accountings’ are largely driven by questions such as ‘how can society?’ or ‘how can the environment? be accommodated within GAAP and/or conventional accounting practice?’ Such accountings, therefore, run into the serious limitation that (in addition to the aesthetic or ethical repugnance that such questions might engender) they (again) leave unquestioned the very mechanisms of capitalism, organisation, accounting and so on, that make the questions so essential. Despite, however, the apparent absence of much awareness within this GAAP-centered social accounting of the alternative/critical project and theoretical issues more generally, such accountings are not entirely without merit. They do raise the issues, change agendas and provide further grist to alternative/critical and other social accounting projects. (Gray, 2002, p. 699). Gray’s call for an imaginative new accounting structure can be addressed by revisiting philosophical ideas concerning how we perceive the world. McKernan (2007) has offered a valuable set of arguments that invite accounting theorists to consider further 8 the work of Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty. These thinkers are useful for accounting research in that they invite us to consider our comportment in the world. The work of Davidson and Rorty is challenged by interpretivists who offer a different, anti-representationalist view of the world and realism. Representationalism has been the dominant philosophical way to understand how the mind takes in the world. Broadly, the representationalist tradition is associated with thinkers such as René Descartes and Immanuel Kant. Representationalists maintain that the way we take in the world is through the mind’s eye where the processing occurs after having visualized the object or thing. In the traditional representationalist model the taking-inward happens through the sense organs and mostly by seeing, where seeing is always “impregnated” by cognition. In the representationalist view it is important to remember that there is a sharp distinction between mind and world. Often representationalism is associated with Locke’s work on primary and secondary qualities: this seems to resonate with the traditional accounting supposition that we can separate ourselves from the external world. Anti-representationalism is the view that objectivity can have no other foundation than from the inter-subjective interactions between people and the world. This simply means that people have direct access to the world and the objects that comprise it. There are two forms of anti-representationalism. First, Davidson’s coherentism maintains that our best sentences are part of the world in a fundamental sense. Second, Dreyfus and Taylor argue that coherentism ignores the role perception plays in putting us in touch with the external world. Like other antirepresentationalists, the interpretivist points out how our thinking is shaped by the dominant mind–world dualism. Indeed, accounting and economics have been based 9 on this strict separation and in turn perpetuate a culture of accumulation. If, however, accounting is to act in the public interest it needs to engage these debates such that we begin to understand the world and our place in it. (i) Davidson’s anti-representationalism It will be recalled that the anti-representationalist does not accept that any statement can be true “simply in virtue of the way things are, quite apart from how we describe them” (Rorty, 1994b, p. 86; Mckernan, 2007, 158). McKernan (2007) provided fresh insight when he argued that Davidson demonstrated that our best sentences and representations are part of a holistic framework that puts us in causal interaction with the external world.4 Davidson is therefore anti-representationalist, but not anti-realist. On this view, an external world exists but is causally independent from people. McKernan summarizes: Anti-representationalists will agree that the world may cause us to be justified in believing a sentence true. But they will not confuse that “platitude” with “the claim that the world splits itself up, on its own initiative, into sentence shaped chunks called ‘facts’” (Rorty, 1989, p. 5) that may make our beliefs true by corresponding to them. The antirepresentationalist will therefore not accept that any statement can be true “simply in virtue of the way things are, quite apart from how we describe them” (Rorty, 1994b, p. 86). But she will think any true statement, whether about the number of chairs in a room, the property rights of a commercial organisation, or human rights, is true “in virtue of the way things are”. True, that is, “in virtue of the way our current descriptions of things are used and the causal interactions we have with those things” (Rorty, 1994b, p. 86). (McKernan, 2007, p. 158) 4 In technical philosophy this relates to not only the “appearance” but also the “things” that make up the external world. 10 Accordingly, our interpretations can be true or false in virtue of the meaning of the account and how the world is arranged. This is provided that we can see the meaning of the account as causally, rather than representationally, related to things in the world. Davidson’s contribution concerns how humanity visualizes the world, comes in contact with that world, and whether it is possible to understand the world in-andof-itself. Therefore, Davidson argues that we cannot have knowledge without communication and this forms his triadic relationship between speakers and the external world. That is, our knowledge and understanding of the world firstly requires exploring how communication itself is possible. For Davidsonians, the task for the interlocutor involves assigning a propositional content to each of the speaker’s utterances. McKernan summarizes the point: Essentially, she must match a sentence of her own with each of the speaker’s sentences. If she “gets things right”, her own sentences will “provide the truth conditions of the speaker’s sentences” (Davidson, 1991, p. 157) and yield the meaning of the speaker’s utterances. But how can the interpreter construct and verify such a framework of truth conditions – a theory of truth and meaning – for the speaker’s utterances? What evidence is available? The interpreter clearly has no direct access to the detailed propositional intentions or beliefs of the speaker – and to assume that she did would be to beg the question of interpretation. The interpreter does, however, have access to the speaker’s utterances, and Davidson suggests that it is reasonable to assume that she can detect which utterances the speaker holds to be true in particular circumstances. A speaker will hold an utterance to be true, or false, in part because of what it means, and in part because of what he believes to be the case. If the interpreter aims to establish meanings on the evidence of prompted assent or dissent (holding true or false) to utterances, 11 she must deal with the problem of the entanglement of meaning and belief. (McKernan, 2007, pp. 156–157) Davidson’s view involves how the scheme of language and the content it represents combine and structure our ability to get around in the world. Sets of beliefs are generally true for him, not because they are proved as propositional attitudes in confrontation with the physical reality, but because they cohere with the whole set of beliefs. The sets of beliefs receive their adaptive appropriateness through causality, which originates from the physical world, and so neither needs the physical world characterized as true, nor our coherent belief system. Our beliefs are mostly true and they do not need further justification. Davidson states that a “major reason ... for accepting a coherence theory is the unintelligibility of the dualism of a conceptual scheme and a ‘world’ waiting to be coped with” (Davidson, 1986, p 303). A coherence theory of truth is in conflict with correspondence-seeking confrontational methodologies. A central claim made by anti-representationalists of the Davidsonian variety is that it is not possible to come in contact with the world as it really is. Put differently, to know something about the external world we can never reduce it to its component parts. We cannot make a precise distinction between what part of it comes from us and what part comes from the “outside world”. We are part of the part of the natural world and are not distinct from it. McKernan claims that Davidson’s argument maintains that an outside reality exists independently of our accounts and interpretations about the external world. When dealing with accounts concerning the subjective and independent external reality, Davidson proposes what he calls a “principle of charity” – this invites interlocutors to exchange with others on fair terms of cooperation. The principle of charity has two key components: namely, correspondence and coherence. The former 12 is the view that in order for some statement to be true there must be a “correspondence” between the things and words that refer to those things. The latter issue – concerning as it does so the concept of “coherence” – requires agreement between a belief and the other elements in the agent’s belief system. The axiom can be put this way: For a particular belief or statement to be true it has to be in agreement with or not contradictory to the rest of the belief system within which the particular belief/statement is found. (adapted from McKernan, 2007). Clearly, for Davidson, the thinking mind is related to the world through the current belief systems currently in vogue (i.e. scheme and content) – only another belief can justify a belief. This invites accountants to rethink their role in society and how they visualize the world: no longer can we simply assume that the natural world is an unlimited gift from nature. However it is entirely problematic whether Davidson’s arguments put us in touch with the world. I argue that financial accounting has drifted towards total unintelligibility due to its infatuation with current beliefs and causal relationships with the natural environment. To borrow a Heideggerian phrase, we are on the wrong track and our ethical practices have been stretched to breaking by certain accounting practices. McKernan reminds us that accounts, explicitly or implicitly, carry values and if those values “were somehow incorrigibly subjective”, the entanglement of descriptive and normative aspects in accounting might preclude objectivity. A key to Davidson’s argument is that subjectivity “might” preclude objectivity. There is, however, no necessary correlation between these two facts. 13 Moreover, on the anti-representationalist view developed in response to Davidson it is our relationships in the world that are true as a consequence of our engagement in the world. For traditional accounting theory, there is an “outside” (natural) world that we can report as a profit or loss. However, the concept of an independently existing reality presents humanity with the ability to manipulate and transform the natural world. On the dominant view, what is expressed through language is said to represent that external reality: accordingly, the objective world is commonly referred to as antirepresentationalist (see Shapiro, 1997; 1998). (ii) The anti-representationalism of Dreyfus and Taylor: challenging environmental and social accounting In this section I challenge the anti-representationalism associated with the philosophies of Davidson, McKernan, Quine and Rorty. This is undertaken by exploring a more basic and primordial way to understand our place in the world – this is the philosophy associated with perception and fundamental coping. It involves engaging with the world so that humanity can come in contact with the way the world is as-it-is-in-itself. On this view, we are in touch with the world as we act in the world. Interpretivists, such as Dreyfus and Taylor, argue that Davidson’s antirepresentationalism nevertheless remains committed to Cartesian mind–world dichotomies. They maintain Davidson has ignored a more basic way to cope in the world. To think in this interpretivist way is to suggest another path for environmental and social accounting. It is a path involving a radical rethinking about how we live in the world, which in turn requires escaping the current restrictive epistemological vision of the world. 14 Interpretivists point out that people actually engage in self-interpretation and this is something that instrumental and procedural thinking ignores. This creates an economic and social system built on the edifice of economic and procedural assumptions. This is because procedural thinking limits practical reason and language theory to designative and instrumental process thinking. Accounting has emerged from that worldview such that what is reported is assumed to measure and reflect accurately our external impacts on that world. However it is entirely problematic whether accounting and audit reports accurately reflect the way humans are using the planet. The argument for objectivity and interpretivism presented here is one from the Counter-Enlightenment, associated as it is with the work of Hegel, Herder and Hamman. Their work represents an attempt to put people in touch with the world. This step in the argument engages criticisms of classical empirical epistemology (see Section 1 above). This involves understanding the limitations associated with economic and procedural reason: principles shaped by the Enlightenment that gave rise to a scientific revolution. The Enlightenment, in turn, shaped a social thinking – a social imaginary (see Taylor, 2004) – that has created a predilection for measurement, procedure and technique. Nevertheless, there has been a growing body of literature that challenges the obsession with technicist measurement and KPI fetish in accounting (see Dillard, 2006). Furthermore, the dominant instrumental vision of the world is antirepresentationalist and often anti-realist (though Davidson is committed to the argument that there is an external world existing beyond us). According to Taylor this is a consequence of our buffered view of the self: the “buffered” self relies on a sharp dichotomy between the mind and the world. Taylor explains: 15 Modern Westerners have a clear boundary between mind and world, even mind and body. Moral and other meanings are “in the mind.” They cannot reside outside, and thus the boundary is firm. But formerly it was not so. Let us take a well-known example of influence inhering in an inanimate substance, as this was understood in earlier times. Consider melancholy: black bile was not the cause of melancholy, it embodied, it was melancholy. The emotional life was porous here; it didn’t simply exist in an inner, mental space. Our vulnerability to the evil, the inwardly destructive, extended to more than just spirits that are malevolent. It went beyond them to things that have no wills, but are nevertheless redolent with the evil meanings. (Taylor, 2008 accessed Immanent Frame, 2009). Taylor is simply claiming that modern thinking has lost sight of other ways to engage with the world. The boundary between self and other is nebulous and porous and this has to be seen as a fact of experience, not a matter of “theory” or “belief.” As I stated a few paragraphs ago, this argument means that humanity can never come in contact with reality as-it-really-is. It is for this reason that Davidson’s anti-representational view is referred to as a form of coherentism, or coherentist-empiricism. At first sight it seems to develop a theory of perception and language that challenges designative approaches to language and the world. However, as the previous two steps have illustrated, there is no discussion about whether we are actually in touch with the world as we act and live in the world. This is important to accounting if it is to remain relevant and develop engagement that allows us to determine the legitimacy of corporate and consultancy firms’ discussions of environmental reporting [that] still place far too much attention on changing strategy and far too little on changing action! (Hopwood, 2009, p. 437). 16 Dreyfus and Taylor offer a different anti-representational frame to explore how the thinking mind is directly engaged with the world. This suggests a therapy for modern accounting and its preoccupation with procedure – it involves an art of interpretation that recognizes everyday coping skills putting us in contact with the world. This interpretative methodology is directly in conflict with the dominant empirical view that knowledge of the world simply arises from experience and is then processed in the mind. In sum, interpretation is associated with an essentially antirepresentationalist view that the thinking mind is in some fundamental sense in the world (Dreyfus’s and Taylor’s position). Another way to think about the ethic of interpretivism is to consider it as an (anti)-epistemology – on this view, people are considered to be purposive beings who “pursue their goals in a context imbued meaning” (Abbey, 2003, p. 127). Accordingly our engagements with the world are more fundamental than empiricists and coherentists have recognised. Rather, people are self-interpreting entities whose perceptual coping skills need to be explored as well as their conceptual abilities. They challenge Davidson’s coherentism in the way it ignores the role of the background and coping. (It will be recalled that Davidson argued that our understanding about the world occurs only from other beliefs.) Taylor explains that Davidson’s coherentist claim that reasoning from other beliefs is the only way particular beliefs can be grounded is so far from obvious as to be plain false. The anti-representationalist view offered by interpretivists suggests we need to step outside the mediational picture, and think in terms of the kind of embedded knowing that Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty and Todes have thematized. Taylor uses an example about how people get about in the world without necessarily processing images in the mind. He explains: 17 Of course, we check our claims against reality. “Johnny go into the room and tell me whether the picture is crooked”. Johnny emerges from the room with a view of the matter, but checking isn’t comparing the problematized belief with his belief about the matter; checking is forming a belief about the matter, in this case by going and looking. What is assumed when we give the order is that Johnny knows, as most of us do, how to form a reliable view of this kind of matter. He knows how to go and stand at the appropriate distance and in the right orientation, to get what Merleau-Ponty calls a maximal grip on the object. What justifies Johnny’s belief is his being able to deal with objects in this way, which is, of course, inseparable from the other ways he is able to use them, manipulate, get around among them, etc. When he goes and checks he uses this multiple ability to cope, and his sense of his ability to cope gives him confidence in his judgement as he reports it to us. (Taylor, quoted in Dreyfus, 2004, p. 56) As Dreyfus explains, this simple example shows that representationalism is not the only way people interact with the world. This anti-representationalist view maintains that theory does not need to posit the human being primarily as the subject of mental representations to understand rule-following behavior, or something like checking the picture on the wall. Following interpretivists such as Dreyfus, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Michael Polanyi, Taylor and Wittgenstein, I argue that it is mistaken to presuppose that we are inherently cut off and detached from the world; that is, our understanding of the external world is essentially mediated by mental representations. When we act, for example, we act with our bodies whether linguistically or through grasping with the hand (to borrow a phrase from Heideggerian phenomenology). According to Dreyfus, in particular, little of what is involved in our action, whether the goals of action or the rule-specifying movements, is consciously articulated. In essence, “we are in the 18 world” as “we live and act”. This thinking puts people in touch with the external world and in this manner offers a new way for accounting to reform itself. Dreyfus was a chief exponent of this view that the ontological level influences but does not determine the social, political and cultural goods communities may choose to follow. Thus, a first step in hermeneutic and interpretive thinking involves restructuring debates, such as those over the natural environment, as ontological ones. On this view, ontological features involve “the factors that you invoke to account for social life” – the way that we explain the world and involve the terms “that you accept as ultimate in the order of explanation” and provide the structures through which we define and explore values (Taylor, 1989, p. 160). Advocacy issues, on the other hand, concern the moral stand or policy that one adopts, and include the connections between common goods, individual rights and ecological values. Taylor has explained these differences and the implications that follow: Taking an ontological position doesn’t amount to advocating something; but at the same time, the ontological does help to define the options it is meaningful to support by advocacy. The latter connection explains how ontological theses can be far from innocent. Your ontological proposition, if true, can show that your neighbor’s favorite social order is an impossibility or carries a price he or she did not count [on] But this should not induce us to think that the proposition amounts to the advocacy of some alternative. (Taylor, 1989, p. 161) Taylor’s work on authenticity and ontology frames the field of possibilities available to people in a way that traditional frameworks cannot. This is because our stance towards the natural environment is related to the way we visualize and come in contact with it. Interpretivists would require that accounting should begin to consider not simply extending its functional reach, but also enabling and enriching the public 19 spheres of modern communities. In particular, the accountant’s role would be to provide accounts that are cognizant and informed by the ontological level in a manner that does not impose external values on citizens. Often, though not always, the ontological level involves recognizing how significant issues are associated with our history and background horizons of value.5 Dreyfus reminds us of the background factors that we need to recognize to understand that there is more to the human condition than instrumental reason discloses. Dreyfus explains: “what allows us to make the difference is a rich, largely implicit, and of course inherently contestable understanding of what the important meanings and purposes of human life are” (Taylor, 1989b. p. 280). Dreyfus and Taylor have independently developed a direct realism that supports the supposition that our perception of reality is, at least in part, a construction of our own theory. From these observations, interpretivists argue that a naturalistic and scientific approach engulfs our everyday lives and ignores our self-interpretations of the world. Interpretivists argue that the dominant forms of empiricism and naturalism create visions of the natural environment as a simple commodity. The environment is commodified and seen as manageable through environmental trading schemes, carbon taxes and other pricing frameworks. An interpretivist perspective, however, takes a different direction and emphasizes that people are part of the world. This in turn requires nurturing and developing the spiritual side of our being as opposed to the instrumental and technical. Section 3: Accounting implications and engaging with the world 4 This would entail accounting education creating an appreciation of the importance of the historical dimensions of the craft for understanding identity factors. 20 The argument and critique of Davidsonian reforms provide a lens to examine the limitations of environmental and social accounting. The interpretivist treatise is about re-enchanting and putting us back in touch with the external world. Interpretivists argue that anti-realists and anti-representationalists end up submerging environmental and social intrinsic values: this results from the fact that they remain trapped by dualisms like that between mind and world. This bifurcated understanding of the relationship between mind and world is one reason for the infatuation with procedure. Accounting emphasizes neutral standards of adjudicating accounting; ethical and moral disputes are submerged. Consequently, modern accounting and social science have been preoccupied with the development of more procedure to adjudicate, through so-called ‘neutral’ procedures, our activities in the world. At the same time, efforts to explore how we access the world have been underplayed if not sidestepped. On the Dreyfus/Taylor view, one escape path from the dominant epistemology is to appreciate a more fundamental and perceptual engagement with the world. Dreyfus summarized this aspect of the interpretative method: “we can only understand how we are normally in touch with the cosmos … when we see that we are not disembodied, detached, contemplators, but rather, embodied, involved coping agents” (Dreyfus, 2004, p. 68). This means that our perceptual and coping skills put us in touch with the world at a more basic level than traditional procedural models allow. Accounting as a craft besotted by instrumental reason can benefit by exploring how other values can be integrated into accounting standards – how issues of significance such as the use of the environment can be made explicit and articulate in communicative reports. Therefore, accounting theory itself can be used to investigate and examine the implications associated with questioning the supposition that the mind is actually in 21 the world. A first obvious point is that our appreciation of the world is on the wrong track. A second observation is that accounting and accountability must continually search to integrate expressive and moral values into the lexicon of the accountant. This way to think about the world involves tackling the entrenched interests often associated with the atomism and individualism that shapes modern procedural liberal democracies. The art of interpretation, by way of contrast, invites us to think about our impacts on the planet as well as to consider values other than those associated with economic gain and profit maximization. In this article, interpretivism is itself used to consider connections between language, perception and realism. Often critics of this form of realism argue that such a vision of nature makes it an external standard that we must defer to. That way to think about the world, however, ignores how a direct realism can put us in touch with the natural world. This involves two steps. In the first step our practices reveal different ways to consider the world. Second, if we directly access the world, we escape the notion of a buffered self and the supposition that economic reason is the only means on which we construct our accounting and accountability systems. This gives rise to further accounting, ethical and moral conundrums as they concern how public reports are themselves shaped by the limitations of instrumental rationality. Until recently, technical accounting reports have ignored environmental impacts within the current social system and merely reinforced technical behaviour. Technical accounting methods ignore the pervasive influence of hierarchical structures of control and procedural reason at the expense of interpretation and an enriched engagement with the world.6 6 Accordingly, accounting remains merely a technical and procedural ideology that perpetuates a sharp division between humanity and the external world. Humanity remains at a distance from the natural world and our spiritual engagements with the world are submerged by a social science that perpetuates a technical and procedural mindset. Debates concerning the 22 The interpretive and hermeneutic strategy offered in this paper is not about promoting more triple-bottom-line reporting or constructing more accounting codes for ethical conduct. Rather, the argument involves considering people as selfinterpreting beings and world-disclosers. The strategy reveals further limitations with the ontology of traditional financial accounting and reporting practices that perpetuate an anthropocentric culture. The reform of accounting must consider fully the sources of the self and the objective values in the world. Following an observation from Heidegger the problem modernity is to think about the limitations associated with a technological world view and the logic that suppresses recognition of other values. It is for that reason the argument in this paper questions whether procedural reason and associated techniques can give an accurate reflection of the external world. This develops a social imagining that gives rise to ethical codes, instrumentalism and other products that have been commodified. The task confronting accounting is to provide data and information that not only counters and reveals the inadequacies of traditional practices but to open new avenues to disclose the practices that would enhance people’s opportunities. Likewise, environmental and social accounting projects assume that accounting reports can tame corporate rationality and align business with the communities it operates in. Central to interpretivism is an optimistic account of practice reason that provides other means to investigate the world which have not been given full consideration in accounting and reform accounting theory. Furthermore, what this argument shows is that total unintelligibility of another culture’s accounting practices is not an option. For to experience another group as philosophy of realism have the potential to rethink our place in the world and visualize an accounting that engages with multiple cultures thereby reaching other shores. 23 unintelligible over some range of their practices, we have to find them quite understandable over other (very substantial) ranges. Taylor explains: We have to be able to understand them as framing intentions, carrying out actions and trying to communicate orders, truths, and so forth. If we imagine even this away, then we no longer have the basis that allows us to recognize them as agents. But then there is nothing left to be puzzled about. Concerning nonagents, there is no question about what they are up to, and hence no possibility of being baffled on this score. (Taylor, 2002a, p. 137) A further problem with Davidson’s argument is that it is too strong and too powerful. As Taylor explains, it slays the ‘beast of total and irremediable incomprehensibility’ – thus, in the real life situation Davidson’s theory discredits the idea of ‘conceptual schemes altogether’ – in spite of the fact that the Davidsonian argument ‘rules out our meeting a totally unintelligible one’ (Taylor, 2002a, p. 137). In real-life ethical and pragmatic situations we need to be able to identify what is ‘blocking us’ and this is achieved through a theory of language that works to reveal and provide better interpretations of reality (intentionality) Therefore, we need some way of picking out the ‘systematic differences in construal between two different cultures, without either reifying them or branding them as ineradicable’ (Taylor, 2002a, p. 138). On an interpretivist view, this is achieved through a fusion of horizons where language plays a key role. Gadamer states: Our first point is that the language in which something comes to speak is not a possession at the disposal of one or the other of the interlocutors. Every conversation presupposes a common language, or better, creates a common language. Something is placed in the center, as the Greeks say, which the partners 24 in dialogue both share, and concerning which they can exchange ideas with one another. Hence reaching an understanding on the subject matter of a conversation necessarily means that a common language must be first worked out in the conversation. This is not an external matter of simply adjusting our tools; nor is it even right to say that the partners adapt themselves to one another but, rather, in a successful conversation they both come under the influence of the truth of the object and are thus bound to one another in a new community. To reach an understanding in a dialogue is not merely a matter of putting oneself forward and successfully asserting one’s own point of view, but being transformed into a communion in which we do not remain what we were. (Gadamer, 1975, pp. 378– 379) Language cannot be constrained by procedure, as Habermas argued (1991; 1999), nor by any principle of charity. The role of language must be developed from an entirely different point of view and involves putting ourselves in the position of the other interlocutor. For accounting this means a total transformation in how we communicate, inter-relate and teach the craft of accounting. Moreover, this thinking involves understanding that numbers and values cannot be simply harmonized and transferred between cultures. Attempts to arbitrate discourse and evaluate the claims made in the discursive arena are unlikely to achieve their objectives without being transformed in the communicative process (Shapiro, 1997). Modern accounting frameworks reinforce the processes of economic reification as they do not theorise how different cultural systems and values involve complex patterns and relationships. For example, international accounting standards assume that comparability and harmonization are the means to create stable capital markets. Moreover, even if capital markets could be stabilized it remains problematic whether local cultures can be tamed according to the processes of accounting and 25 economic instrumentalization. Here it is useful to refer to the interpretivism of Gadamer and his fusion of horizons: in a successful fusion we are transformed and our life world broadened to understand and come in contact with others and the external world. Section 4: Accounting implications and directions for the future I have argued that the dominant instrumental and procedural discourse has not fully considered how moral and spiritual values may work to put us in touch with the natural world. These ideas can be given expression through the development and adaptation of Shapiro’s (1997) argument that theoretical debates can inform how accountants arrive at decisions and the rationale that shaped them. Shapiro observed: Accounting academics can contribute to a constructive debate over accounting policy, in several respects. First, accounting researchers and educators can use the five philosophical presuppositions and the related principles of rationality and objectivity to examine critically the evidence or justification people give for their assertions. Second, researchers who disagree with any of the five presuppositions should be encouraged to develop and defend an alternative set of logically and empirically consistent presuppositions. Third, researchers who disagree with the principles of rationality espoused in this article should be encouraged to develop an alternative set of non-self-refuting principles on which to base a productive critical discussion. Fourth, researchers could apply a conditional-normative methodology to issues of cultural relativity and the problems it can create for general acceptance of international standards. Tinker et al. (1982) persuasively argued that all ideologies and research methods involve normative commitments, whether or not those commitments are explicitly stated. (Shapiro, 1997, p. 183) 26 Shapiro advocates reasoned arguments and provides five maxims relevant for external financial reporting. These maxims are designed to provide means to consider valid arguments as they involve critical accounting arguments. Shapiro (1997) offered five presuppositions for financial reporting to debate. The debate involved the objectivity of what accountants and financial reports refer (ontological theses). Second, how accountants may come to know or believe those things (epistemological theses). The following subsections contribute briefly to Shapiro’s presuppositions and their implications for critical accounting. The five propositions for accountants, as identified by Shapiro, involve: P1. External realism: External reality exists independently of the financial statements that represent it. P2. Correspondence theory of truth: A financial representation is true if it corresponds (at least approximately) to the underlying economic reality that it purports to represent. P3. Conceptual relativism: All systems of representations such as conceptual frameworks are human creations and thus socially constructed. P4. Subjective judgement (epistemological subjectivity): Accountants’ judgments about what constitutes valid descriptions of economic reality are influenced by many factors: cultural, economic, political, psychological and so on. P5. Commitment to rationalism (epistemological objectivity): Knowing is epistemologically objective to the extent that a community can agree on the criteria for evaluating the justification of evidence for assertions. Furthermore, an instrumentalist understanding of corporate objectives promotes individualism, wealthaccumulating practices that generate excessive waste and destruction, and fails to promote practices that enable individuals to develop themselves as complete and 27 authentic persons (see Hopwood, 2009). The instrumentalism that currently prevails in the corporate world prioritizes profits over people. Following Shapiro (1997) it is important to shape this debate further utilizing hermeneutic and interpretivist resources. I will do this by addressing each maxim in turn. P1. External realism: External reality exists independently of the financial statements that represent it McKernan (2007) offered a detailed critique of Shapiro’s representational perspective concerning how to reform modern accountability structures. He argued that “accounting practice does not directly rely on any philosophical presuppositions [and] accounting might become more responsive to human need if it were to free itself of the dubious comforts of representationalist philosophy” (McKernan, 2007, p. 156). McKernan does not explain how accounting might become more responsive to human need. This is a problem that echoes issues in the work of Richard Rorty, who has been influenced by Davidson’s coherentism. Rorty suggested that we have no duties to anything non-human as one implication of his postmodern form of liberalism. This thinking, however, leaves us within the present social system, with limited philosophical tools to escape the current ways to perceive the world. For example, Rorty offers a significant postmodern and anti-realist statement when he explains: “there is no authority outside of convenience for human purposes that can be appealed to in order to legitimize the use of a vocabulary. We have no duties to anything nonhuman” (Rorty, 1998, p. 127). Rather, it is not that we have one less reason to change our practices but an overwhelming reason to explain how 28 practices such as accounting shape the way we relate to others and our world. These are increasingly important observations given how sustainable and postmodern methods focus on one very important issue as it concerns the long-term viability of the planet. Humanity’s ability to perceive intrinsic values reflects an embedded set of relationships with nature (see Sections 2 and 3 above). The essential connections between people and the world become submerged when our methodologies rely solely on current concepts and categories. Nevertheless, if we follow Rorty’s reading of Davidson we are co-opted by a pragmatism that invites us to simply enjoy the possibilities that the world provides to us. Interpretivist debates are therefore rendered meaningless and the reforms to our ethical thinking as advanced in this paper become superfluous. However, an interpretivist response to Davidson and Rorty involves exploring the role feeling and perception play in putting us in touch with the world (Section 2 above). That thinking, it will be recalled, involved how accounting remains committed to the provision of (allegedly) true and fair views themselves shaped by that particular discursive tradition. In sum, it is somewhat paradoxical that in our reasoning about the world we have utilized the technical dimensions of our practical reason but excluded the very capacities that allow us to fully appreciate the value of nature in the first place. The instrumental process that dominates modern social imaginaries cannot help but lead to a bifurcated understanding of the relationships between the mind and the external world, the factors that make up our identity, and the role that language plays in shaping “being”. P2. Correspondence theory of truth 29 McKernan (2007) explains that the pragmatism of Davidson and Rorty is used to reflect the fact that philosophers have been unable to convincingly specify any sense in which a statement of a true sentence can take us beyond language to how things are in the world prior to our descriptions. This argument, however, only creates a causal connection between mind and world thereby perpetuating the anthropocentricism that dominates the modern world (see Gray 2009). The rebuttal to McKernan (2007) was contained in the point about the picture and Johnny getting it right (see Section 2). The point was about our perceptual coping skills putting us in touch with the world as-it-is: that we have basic coping skills that allow us to engage with the world. In recent accounting literature the question becomes whether it is possible for participants in an accounting conversation to be divorced from background values, such as culture, community and locality. From one direction Shapiro (1997; 1998) explored this from a Habermasian perspective to adjudicate between accounting disputes (such as pension plans, retirement income, and derivate formations). Parker and Roffey (2001) analysed this issue from a grounded theory point of view, but my arguments attempt to extend hermeneutics, interpretivism and truth to reconsider our comportment in the world at the most basic level of engagement (Johnny’s aligning himself with the mirror). However, Shapiro’s early work pointed to Habermas’s rule-based approach to language, which is based around a set of procedures that test whether particular accounting maxims are right or wrong (Shapiro, 1997). While this approach tests accounting maxims from “the point of view from which action norms can be impartially grounded” it remains an open question whether principles of rationality lead to impartial outcomes (Habermas, 1996, p. 140, original emphasis). Again it is Rorty who continues his critique of interpretivism by arguing there is no truth or 30 objectivity independent of the rules of discourse. He concurs that only beliefs can justify other beliefs in a Davidsonian sense: the task of philosophy is to continue the conversation of humanity. There are no other means to glimpse and come in contact with nature’s intrinsic value. On that view, knowledge is constructed only through our current beliefs expressed by language beings. Once such distinctions are established, any subsequent dichotomies become futile, and knowledge and foundations that we believe to be concrete truth are no more than the result of an accepted, or generally agreed upon, form of discourse. In sum, Davidson (1992), Rorty (1979) and McKernan (2007) challenge the direct realism of Dreyfus (1980) and Taylor (2002a, 2002b). For example, Rorty claims that the art of interpretation and world disclosure offer unhelpful philosophical constructs and this means that there are no means to glimpse nature’s intrinsic value. Essentially, Rorty is a pragmatist who relies on solidarity and common sense to question our current belief structures. I argue that this is unlikely to create an accountability vision that puts people in touch with the natural world. Interestingly, McKernan (2007) reminds us that Rorty questioned the role of philosophy when he claimed radical hermeneutics offers only interesting but limited possibilities, or reminders. Thus Rorty suggests that “philosophical reflection does not attempt a radical criticism of contemporary culture, does not attempt to refound or remotivate it, but simply assembles reminders and suggests some interesting possibilities” (Rorty, 1991b, p. 6). Interpretivists attempt to reformulate our engagements with the world by focusing on commonalities between people. They do this in a manner that point toward possible connections that are not yet evident and available. Davidson, 31 McKernan and Rorty cut off this opportunity in their causal approach to the universe. Rorty continues and challenges interpretivists to explain how their argument can zero in on reality; that is, if all interpretations are actually shaped by background practices how can they escape their own terms of reference? However, Rorty’s argument simply copies the neutrality embodied in the natural sciences. Rorty ignores how the background in turn shapes context as it relates to how perception puts us in touch with the world. One response to Rorty’s charge of essentialism is to remind ourselves of the double hermeneutic insight outlined in Section 2, which posits connections between ontology and advocacy. In this context, this involves the role that nature plays in shaping our being and the significant features of identity. Dreyfus (2004) continues and criticizes Rorty’s flirtation with postmodernism by emphasizing how it takes us toward an anti-realism that encourages irony and difference. It downplays the most fundamental levels of coping and how matters of significance are revealed in context. The self is not simply a contingent set of values but involves taking critically rather than just pragmatically the conditions that make possible our very being and identity. Dreyfus draws on an example from the work of Samuel Todes: [Todes] points out that our experience of having to balance in a gravitational field gives us the sense of a force independent of us that we have to conform to, a force which sustains our coping only if, by balancing, we relate to it on its own terms. But again one can ask whether our relation to this force as something that pulls us down but also enables us to stand up, isn’t our way of making sense of nature in our world, rather than an experience of how the universe is in itself. (Dreyfus, 2004, p. 67) 32 The fact that the self is embedded in the world creates a raft of different necessities. I have argued that a response to Rorty’s anti-realism takes our thinking in a different direction and overcomes the tendency toward postmodern nihilism. In recent work, Dreyfus noted that Taylor’s approach goes even further than Rorty’s postmodern understanding of what it is to be a person in the universe. Dreyfus argues that in ‘skilful coping, as in balancing in the vertical field, or climbing over boulders’ (Dreyfus, 2004, p. 68), we have abilities that allow us to harmonise our activities with the structure of the universe. Dreyfus continues that as embodied beings we have abilities to move to the appropriate distance and specify by making sense of things that are independent of our everyday significance attributions.7 For accounting these arguments imply two key factors (i) the limitations associated with our traditional understanding of the objective world and (ii) a need exists to continually provide accounts about the world so that we may better cope in that world. At the very least, the argument shows how it is through the provision of better interpretations that allow us to understand how the environment is something more important than an instrumental economic, or quantifiable good. This then lends support to Gray’s (2009) argument that we need critical and sustainable accounts that report on our impacts in the world. P3. Conceptual relativism of financial reporting schemes This section responds to McKernan’s argument that “different systems of representations can be used to represent that reality” (Shapiro, 1997, p. 167). Again, 7 Dreyfus (2004) adds to his argument the example of people’s ability to drink from a glass without error as an example of realism’s inescapable hold on us. He explains that we must first perceive the glass and then we have abilities to align ourselves with the causal structures of the universe. That is, in getting in synchronicity with all the forces and vectors that allow us to take a sip from the glass it is clear that the self is not simply contingently related to the world . 33 McKernan uses Davidson and Rorty to critique a view propounded by Searle that there are no conceptual schemes that allow alternative accounting schemes to construct alternative realities. But Searle’s work is not the only one that attempts to explain that “we do not make worlds; we make descriptions that the actual world may fit or fail to fit” (Searle, 1995, p. 166, in McKernan, 2007, p. 163). Therefore, we are provided with opportunities to “better cope with” reality and are provided with means to “see” important values for a good society. Davidson, Rorty, and Searle overlook the role our coping plays in getting about in the world. The examples provided by Dreyfus are designed to show how humans are embodied beings with innate coping skills. On this view, we are skilled interpreters who get things right as we act in the world. This links with the art of interpretation that moves beyond simple conceptual frameworks to guide our action. Interpretation and disclosure reflect a disclosing potential in language that can be used to reshape the social role of accounting. The reformulated communicative strategy is not only concerned with the reformation of accounting but also with its transformation. Usefully, Shapiro (1998) referred us to Habermas’s ethic to put different claims on trial through a process that determines whether claims legitimately bind participants. Again Habermas demonstrated his predilection for procedure. He stated: Discourse theory attempts to reconstruct this self-understanding [that of a universalistic moral consciousness and the liberal institutions of the democratic state] in a way that empowers its intrinsic normative meaning and logic to resist both scientific reductions and aesthetic assimilations … After a century that more than any other has taught us the horror of existing unreason, the last remains of an essentialist trust in reason are destroyed. Yet modernity, now aware of its contingencies, depends all the more on a procedural reason, that is, a reason that puts itself on trial. The critique of reason is its own work: this Kantian double 34 meaning is due to the radically anti-Platonic insight that there is neither a higher nor a deeper reality to which we could appeal – we who find ourselves already situated in our linguistically structured forms of life. (Habermas, 1996, p. 11) For Habermas rational thought can under certain circumstances lead to just outcomes. This form of reasoning is also evident in Laughlin and Broadbent who stated “there is a need to debate whether this really is ‘good’ from the perspective of these key institutions and society more generally” (1993, p. 364). The question remains whether such an approach to regulation can arrive at fair outcomes when the decision model is based on a series of rational validity claims and procedural structures from that point of view. It is, therefore, arguable whether a process of rational deliberation without a full discussion of the processes of impartiality can respond fully to the urgencies of cultural and social values in a spirit of openness and democratic accountability. Another pathway is a “phenomenology” that postulates how we may not arrive at truth, but better interpretations of that reality. Taylor and Dreyfus go further than other interpretivists to explore how interpretation reveals values as we cope in the world. Dreyfus makes the fascinating point that in fact we come to terms with the structure of the universe and the layout of the world as-it-is-in-itself. Here, Dreyfus and also Taylor explore Heidegger’s work on the clearing provided by language to articulate the links between our perception of the world and our shared values in communities. In turn, the non-conformist stance advanced in this paper reflects an expressive dimension between people and nature. These dimensions connect with the social audit work of Humphrey and Owen (2000). Interestingly, their paper developed Power’s The audit society (1997) to consider the connections between social audit and society. They claim a therapy for the failures of accounting involves “regarding the type of values that society wishes to prevail” (p. 37). Their analysis supports a 35 normative stance that shapes an accountability structure that nurtures the nexus between social practice and the language mechanisms that shape a good society. P4. Subjective judgement (epistemological subjectivity) I have argued that accounting can benefit by exploring what constitutes valid descriptions of economic reality and how they are influenced by cultural, economic, political, psychological factors. The work of Humphrey and Owen has provided a valuable review of Michael Power’s The audit society, advocating “keep[ing] the debate going with respect to the audit society” (2000, p. 37). From such a perspective, social and environmental auditing does not simply focus on reforming democratic structures; it becomes part of an endeavour to enrich that process by understanding the “factors, causes and motives underlying or driving the rise of the audit society” (p. 37). An escape path from the iron cage of bureaucratic reason and the restrictions of the conceptual framework can be conceived through a social audit that reveals meaning and the reality of corporate logic. Or, put differently, this involves how accounting can act to reveal differences as this involves a way of thinking about the public sphere such that citizens, shareholders and stakeholders can understand others and what corporations are in fact doing. This, of course, is an optimistic account of the way in which practical reason can assist us to redefine the role of accounting and offer a positive role for it to play. Again, it is Taylor who develops Gadamer’s earlier work on the commonalities that actually shape society. He states: [I]t is related rather to the kind of understanding we invoke in personal relations when we say, for instance: “I find him hard to understand”; or “at last I understand her”. To switch for a minute to another language, it is the kind of 36 understanding one invokes in French when one says “maintenant on s’entend”. We are talking here in these cases of what you could call human understanding, understanding what makes someone tick, or how he feels or acts as a human being. (Taylor, 1980, p. 30) Taylor claims that when an interlocutor finally understands what another conversationalist is talking about they recognise their identity and values. This poses a further challenge for technical accounting as it involves how to accommodate different values such as culture and different accounting systems. For accounting theory, this involves the art of interpretation to reveal social audit and considers “the possibilities for auditing to serve a more positive role in society” (Humphrey & Owen, 2000, p. 29). Here, language theory invites reconciliation between accounting and society; namely, one where the limitations of corporate rationality are made explicit and can open up new ways to think.8 In sum, the social audit movement provides a path to open up new vistas thereby offering a realistic account of corporate affairs (see Arnold & Hammond, 1994; Arnold & Sikka, 2002). P5. Commitment to rationalism (epistemological objectivity) Knowing is epistemologically objective to the extent that a community can agree on the criteria for evaluating the justification of evidence for assertions. Accordingly, the nexus between accountability and society involves challenging accounting researchers to consider questions of virtue in the cultivation of a sense of forgiveness, magnanimity, and reasonableness. Francis (1994) considered the function of practices whereby accounting and auditing professionals exercise a sense of moral judgement 8 A strategy to re-align corporate rationality with the common values that are revealed through language involves a regulative structure (such as a social audit) that is backed not simply by the rule of law but a social system that nurtures these values. 37 (phronesis). It is not that the practices mirror reality, but they allow us to understand the structures and values in which we live; the very values that require articulation in accounting theory debates. Francis (1994) posits a role for accountability research to extend the “due process” and consider the common goods that shape people’s significant claims. The focus is to create and maintain the highest standards of accounting, governance and political morality. As Shearer (2002) explained this is unlikely to be achieved when econom ic goods are the primary focus and this paper takes this point further by exploring the focal practices that accounting is supposed to interpret. This argument to reform accounting attempts a broader understanding of the role of language than that offered by other accounting reform theorists (McKernan, 2007; Shearer, 2002). On the view in this comment, the role of perception and language aims to provide better interpretations about how humans have emerged from nature without being cut off from it. Language is a conduit to articulate the expressive values emerging from our interactions with the world. Heidegger’s difficult notion of the clearing provided by language is relevant to this discussion. For Heidegger, it is language that acts as a means by which humanity utilizes to glimpse not only nature’s extrinsic values but also its intrinsic values. These intrinsic values can be “explained by [humanity] as something they cause, or one of their properties, or as grounded in them” (Taylor, 1992c, p. 247). The clearing, which is related to humanity but not ultimately controlled by it, therefore involves all people coming together in a community. Taylor explains: “The clearing is the fact of representation; and this only takes place in minds, or in the striving of subjects, or in their uses of various forms of depiction, including language” (Taylor, 1992c, p. 257). 38 Following Heidegger, Taylor argues the clearing is the space through which expressive language opens up the full dimensions of the human person as a “Shepherd of Being”. The notion of shepherd connects with Heidegger’s exploration of the parameters of what it is to be a person (Dasein). Moreover, it shapes Taylor’s interpretation of Heidegger’s supposition that modern philosophy offers predominantly an instrumental stance towards being a human person.9 Language, therefore, is the conduit through which what is “significant” for an identity is revealed as a dimension made manifest in the clearing itself, opened to us by our ability to speak. The difficult Heideggerian notion of the clearing is where language acts to disclose humanity’s relationships with other entities and the world. Moreover, the clearing provides a means to connect with the external world in a manner not available using other environmental and procedural positions. It is not that language allows us to visualise nature, but language is the expressive medium through which we explore the values received by our capacities of receptivity and spontaneity. Heidegger argues that the clearing is where the “mortal10 and divine beings11, earth12 and sky”13 are seen to come together. The clearing is both Dasein-related, but 9 10 11 12 In this sense, Taylor’s interpretation extends Gadamer’s argument that it is through language that people’s moral sources can also be given expression to satisfy people’s need for recognition. For the purposes of ecological politics, as an example, it explores that ground where nature’s value can be revealed as it shapes the development of freedom. By mortals Heidegger is describing humans as disclosers and he thinks ‘that death primarily reveals our disclosive way of being to us. When he speaks of death, he does not mean demise or a medically defined death but how ‘human practices work that causes mortals to understand that they have no fixed identity and ready to relinquish their current identity in order to assume the identity that their practices next call them into attunement with’ (Dreyfus and Spinosa, 1997). Gray (2009) alludes to this aspect of language in his analysis of unsustainable accounting – we are at a bifurcation point and must begin to explore new ways to engage with the world. By divinities Heidegger is thinking about the moment when all parts of the social are working – when one feels extraordinarily in tune with all that is happening, ‘a special graceful ease takes over, and events seem to unfold of their own momentum--all combining to make the moment all the more centered and more a gift (Dreyfus and Spinosa, 1997). Lehman (1999) explored aspects of this idea in discussing how accounting can assist the public sphere in moving from a profit-centred focus to a new way of reporting to relevant publics). When Heidegger and Taylor speak of earth they are referring to the taken-for-granted practices that ground situations and make them matter to us (Dreyfus and Spinosa, 1997). 39 yet not Dasein controlled where language is not arbitrary and the properties of entities show up without distortion. That is, people’s authenticity is revealed in context which involves a deeper social accounting that interprets and contributes to the good society. It is through the capacity to use language, Taylor argues in utilizing Heidegger’s insights, that it is possible that we can rebuild our world so that values of significance are revealed in an open and transparent civil society. These ideas can be used to construct an accounting strategy designed to transcend the modernist assumption that language does not count in the development of, and articulation of, the intrinsic values that shape a “full life”. Dreyfus and Taylor reconstruct how we consider language and develop political space not only to respect different values but to combine them democratically (Taylor, 2001, p. 79). It offers accounting, environmental theorists, and social theory with a new means to glimpse the otherness of the natural world, rethink our relationships with the world, and develop commonalities to support these observations. Conclusion Environmental and social accounting have rarely considered connections between mind and world. I argue that this creates a limited vision of the natural world such that sustainability, in its current guise, will offer a means to come in contact with the natural world. In Heideggerian fashion I offer a counter argument to the dominant analytical perspective in philosophy and social science. Those approaches were found to offer a neutral and scientific means to access the world. I have argued that this thinking ignores important background values that involve recognition and exploration. I then argued that this involved thinking about 13 By sky, Heidegger means the disclosed or manifest stable possibilities for action that arise in focal situations (Dreyfus and Spinosa, 1997). McKernan (2007) alludes to this form of disclosure in his work on Davidson’s triadic structure. 40 the language of accounting and how it can be constructed to provide better interpretations of the world. This involved two main hermeneutic and interpretive insights. The first insight involves recognising that culture, language, and tradition shape people’s being-in-the-world. The second insight involves the commitment to “get things right”; the portrait involves improved interpretations and political structures committed to these goals of articulation and expression, being in tune with the way things are in, and of, themselves. In this paper I have considered the connections between environmental and social accounting and the logic of economic and market forces. The argument has shown that accounting is on a wrong track and mistakenly maintains it provides an accurate representation of humanity’s use of the planet. Humanity is in the world thereby requiring a fundamental reformulation of the type of information needed to appreciate the value of the natural world. Utilising ideas from interpretivist thinkers such as Davidson, Dreyfus, McDowell and Taylor, I maintained that our being-in-theworld involves a fundamental reformulation of the mind–world dualism. This involves engaging with not only the natural world but also significant others with whom we come in contact. I have offered a different means for accounting theorists and practitioners to think about how they relate to the world. The external world is not a mysterious given that grounds our accounts and visions about the world: rather it is an experiential force with whom we interact all of the time. It was for this reason that I have moved beyond the current base on which the environmental and social accounting project has been constructed to reformulate how we interact, measure and mediate our interactions with those with whom we come in contact. A key policy implication of the paper is that accounting needs to rethink its ethical base and in Heideggerian fashion counter the dominant analytical perspective 41 in accounting, philosophy and social science. Accounting needs to think about how it informs and mediates between different cultures and their visions of the world. No longer can we assume that the external world can be modelled with neutral and scientific techniques. We are part of the world and our innate coping abilities allow us to access the world. I argued that this thinking ignores important background values that involve recognition and exploration. I argued that this involved thinking about the language of accounting and how it can be constructed to provide better interpretations of the world. Consequently, empathy and perception are underplayed as a means to engage the external world. The values experienced in this process can be given expression in our communications, reports and other transmissions. Clearly, there is more to the human condition than the construction of procedure and technique. Accounting must engage debates about the ideal of “authentic” accounts to re-connect our perceptions about the world and to re-enchant our beliefs about the natural world. Despite many notable accountability and sustainability models it is unlikely that they will enchant our thinking and re-invigorate our visions of nature unless they engage moral realist debates. 42 References Abbey, R. (2003). Recognising Taylor rightly. Ethnicities 3, 1, 127. Arnold, P., & Hammond, T. (1994). The role of accounting in ideological conflict: lessons from the South African disinvestment movement. Accounting Organizations and Society 19, 111–126. Arnold, P.J. & Sikka, P. (2001). Globalization and the state–profession relationship: the case the Bank of Credit and Commerce International, Accounting, Organizations and Society 26, 6, 475–501. Davidson, D. (1986). A nice derangement of epitaphs. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 433–446). Oxford: Blackwell. Davidson, D. (1988). The myth of the subjective. In M. Benedikt & R. Burger (Eds.), Bewusstsein, Sprache und die Kunst (pp. 45–54). Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Staatsdruckerei Reprinted in M. Krausz, Relativism: interpretation and confrontation (1989, pp. 159–172). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Davidson, D. (1990). The structure and content of truth. The Journal of Philosophy, LXXXVII(6), 279–328. 43 Davidson, D. (1991). Three varieties of knowledge. In A. Phillips GriYths (Ed.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement (vol. 30). A.J. Ayer: Memorial essays (pp. 153–166). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Davidson, D. (1993). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In E. LePore, Truth and interpretation. Oxford: Blackwell. Descartes, R. (1970). Descartes Philosophical Letters, trans. A. Kenny. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Dillard, J. E. & Ruchala, L. (2005). The rules are no game: From instrumental rationality to administrative evil, Accounting, Auditing and Accountability, 18, 5, 608630. Dreyfus, H. (1980). Holism and hermeneutics. Review of Metaphysics 34, 1, 3–23. Dreyfus, H. L. & Spinosa, C. (1997).Highway bridges and feasts: Heidegger and Borgmann on how to affirm technology, Man and World, 30, 2, 159–177. Dreyfus, H. (2004). Taylor’s (anti-)epistemology. In R. Abbey, Charles Taylor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Francis, J. (1990). After virtue? Accounting as a moral and discursive practice. Accounting, Auditing and Accountability 3, 3, 5–17. 44 Francis, J. (1994). Auditing, Hermeneutics, and Subjectivity, Accounting, Organizations and Society 19, 3, 235-269. Gadamer, H.C. (1975). Truth and method. New York: Sheed and Ward. Gray, R. (2002). The social accounting project and Accounting, Organizations and Society: Privileging engagement, imaginings and pragmatism over critique?, Accounting, Organizations and Society 27, 7, 687-709. Gray, R. (2009). Is accounting for sustainability actually accounting for sustainability and how would we know? An exploration of narratives of organisations and the planet, Accounting, Organizations and Society, (http://www.sciencedirect.com.ezlibproxy.unisa.edu.au/science). Habermas, J. (1999). From Kant to Hegel and Back Again – The Moves Toward Detranscendentalization’, The European Journal of Philosophy 7, 2, 129–157. Hines, R.D. (1988). Financial Accounting: In Communicating Reality, we Construct Reality, Accounting, Organizations and Society 13, 3, 251-262. Hopwood, A. (2009). Accounting and the environment. Accounting, Organizations and Society 34, 3–4, 433–439. Humphrey, C., & Owen, D. (2000). Debating the Power of Audit. International Journal of Auditing 4, 29–50. 45 Laughlin, R.C. (1987). Accounting systems in organizational contexts: a case for critical theory. Accounting, Organizations and Society 12, 5, 479–502. Laughlin, R. and Broadbent, J. (1993). Accounting and Law: Partners in the Juridification of the Public Sector in the UK, Critical Perspectives on Accounting,4, 4, 337-369. McKernan, J.F. (2007). Objectivity in Accounting. Accounting, Organizations and Society 32, 1–2, 155–180. Parker, L. D. & B. Roffey. (1997). Back to the drawing board: revisiting grounded theory and the everyday accountant’s and manager’s reality, Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal, 10, 2, 212-246. Power, M. (1997). The audit society: rituals of verification. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Rorty, R. (1988). The priority of democracy to philosophy. In M.D. Peterson, & R.C. Vaughan, The Virginia statute of religious freedom: its evolution and consequences in American history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rorty, R. (1991a). Objectivity, relativism and truth: philosophical papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 46 Rorty, R. (1991b). Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rorty, R. (1991c). Postmodernist bourgeois liberalism. In R. Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rorty, R. (1991d). Priority of democracy to philosophy. In R. Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rorty, R. (1994a). Does academic freedom have philosophical presuppositions. Academe, 80, 52–63 Reproduced under the title: John Searle on realism and relativism. In R. Rorty (Ed.), Truth and progress: Philosophical papers (1998, pp. 63–83). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Rorty, R. (1994b). Charles Taylor on truth. In J. Tully (Ed.), Philosophy in an age of pluralism: The philosophy of Charles Taylor in question. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Reproduced in R. Rorty, Truth and progress: Philosophical papers (1998, pp. 84–97). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rorty, R. (1998). Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, Vol.3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shearer, T. (2002). Ethics and Accountability: from the for-itself to the for-the-other, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 27, 6, 541-575. 47 Shapiro, B. (1997). Objectivity, relativism, and truth in external financial reporting: what’s really at stake in the disputes? Accounting, Organizations and Society 22, 2, 165–185. Shapiro, B. (1998). Toward a Normative Model of Rational Argumentation For Critical Accounting Discussions, Accounting, Organizations and Society, 23, 7, 641663. Taylor, C. (1980). Understanding in Human Sciences, Review of Metaphysics, 34, 1, 25-38. Taylor, C. (1980b). Rorty, Taylor and Dreyfus: A Discussion, Review of Metaphysics, 34, 1, 47-57. Taylor, C. (1989). Cross-purposes: the liberal-communitarian debate. In N. Rosenblum, Liberalism and the moral life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Taylor, C. (1989b). Taylor and Foucault on Power and Freedom: A Reply, Political Studies 37, 2, 280. Taylor, C. (1992a). The ethics of authenticity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Taylor, C. (1992b). Multiculturalism and the politics of recognition, ed. A. Gutmann. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Taylor, C. (1992c). ‘Heidegger, Language, and Ecology’, in Dreyfus, H. L. and Hall, H. (eds.), Heidegger: A Critical Reader, Blackwells, Oxford, 1992, pp. 247-269 (reprinted in Taylor, C. (1995). ‘Heidegger, Language and Ecology’, in Taylor, C., Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 100126. 48 Williams, P.F., ‘The Legitimate Concern with Fairness’, Accounting, Organizations and Society, Volume 12, Number 2, pp.169-189, 1987. Taylor, C. (2000). What’s Wrong with Foundationalism?: Knowledge, Agency and World. In M.A. Wrathall, & J. Malpas, Heidegger, Coping and Cognitive Science. Massachusetts: University of Massachusetts Press. Taylor, C. (2001). A Tension in Modern Democracy. In A. Botwinick, & W. Conolly, Democracy and vision. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Taylor, C. (2002a). Understanding the Other: a Gadamerian View on Conceptual Schemes. In J. Malpas, U. Arnswald, & J. Kertshcer, Gadamer’s century: essays in honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer. Massachusetts: MIT Press. Taylor, C. (2002b). Varieties of Religion Today. Harvard: Harvard University Press. Taylor, C. Modern Social Imaginaries. London: Duke University Press; 2004. Taylor, C. (2008). A Secular Age: Buffered and Porous Selves. http://www.ssrc.org/blogs/immanent_frame/2008/09/02/buffered-and-porous-selves/ accessed 5th of June, 2009. Tinker, T., Paper Prophets: A Social Critique of Accounting, Holt Reinhart and Winston, 1985. 49 Tomkins, C., & Groves, R. (1983a). The everyday accountant and researching his reality. Accounting, Organizations and Society 8, 4, 361–374. Tomkins, C., & Groves, R. (1983b). The everyday accountant and researching his reality: further thoughts. Accounting, Organizations and Society 8, 4, 407–415.