Mukai 8 1NC 1NC First, legalization reinforces Eurocentric notions of the law that objectify life and enables all modern violence Nunn 1997 [Kenneth B. "Law as a eurocentric enterprise." Law & Ineq. 15 (1997): 323. LEXISNEXIS//BlackMagic] Dichotomous reasoning is a trait of Eurocentricity. n138 Not only are the usual dichotomies found within the law, n139 but the law itself is one half of a larger dichotomy. Law is set in opposition to "custom," which is then deemed inferior n140 since it is produced by habit and not reason. n141 Although European societies have their customs, they are thought to be superior to non-European societies, which do not have law, at least not in the European sense of the word. The absence of law in non-Western societies implies the absence of reason. While Western "law" is for the civilized, non-Western "custom" is for "savages" and "brutes." n142 Thus, dichotomy is central to the mythology of modern law. To quote Peter Fitzpatrick: Modern law emerges, in a negative exaltation, as universal in opposition to the particular, as unified in opposition to the diverse, as omnicompetent in contrast to the incompetent, and as controlling of what has to be controlled ... Law is imbued with this negative transcendence in its own myth of origin where it is imperiously set against certain "others" who concentrate the qualities it opposes. n143 The hierarchical structuring n144 of the law is readily apparent. Hierarchy is inherent in the very notion of positive law, which views law as a command from a superior kkto its inferiors. n145 But both positive and natural law n146 have order as their first principle. n147 In the Eurocentric mind, law is equal to order. n148 Conse- [*346] quently, law takes on a transcendent quality - it exists outside of and within the hierarchy it establishes. n149 There can be no order outside of the law, and law's order is imposed from the top down. Analytic reasoning n150 and extreme rational thought is also a key part of the law. This can be seen in the way in which court decisions are rendered in the form of some seemingly neutral test. n151 For example, in Shaw v. Reno, n152 the Supreme Court upheld the challenge of a white voter to North Carolina's legislative redistricting plan on the grounds that the plan violated his equal protection rights. n153 The Court held that the majority Black electoral district was a constitutionally impermissible classification on the basis of race by applying a three-part test. n154 The Court asked whether the state's concentration of a dispersed minority population in a single district disregarded traditional districting principles including: (1) "compactness," (2) "contiguity" and (3) "respect for political subdivisions." n155 In Shaw, it was the Court's reference to an abstracted and allegedly neutral test that enabled it to pick its way through the thickets of racial politics and determine that the North Carolina legislature's attempt to increase African American political representation was presumptively unconstitutional. The Court, in an opinion by Justice O'Connor, stated, "We emphasize that these criteria are important not because they are constitutionally required - they are not - but because they are objective factors that may serve to defeat a claim that a district has been gerrymandered on racial lines." n156 Here the Court privileges objectivity, as such, over subjectivity. The Court, however, fails to establish any connection between [*347] the objective nature of the factors it has chosen and the capability of those factors to illuminate whether a district has been gerrymandered on racial grounds. n157 It seems the Court would have accomplished more if it had simply asked the central question posed in the case: "What role did race play in the decision to create this district?" But such a straightforward approach would not be recognizable as "legal." The objectification n158 of the law is evident in the way that it is possible to talk about the law as an active force or separate and autonomous entity in Western societies. This gives rise to the mistaken belief that there is no law in non-Western societies. n159 In fact there is law, it is simply not objectified to the degree one finds in the West. In African societies the law is understood as part of the seamless web that binds the community together. n160 It is inconceivable to think of the law as an object, separate and distinct from custom, culture and morality. n161 Eurocentricity, however, insists on "the elevation of "the objects' in a sense encompassing not just a separate material thing but also a distinct constellation of action, such as law." n162 [*348] Consequently, to legalize is to objectify. From there it is a short step to abstraction. n163 Human cooperation, for example, is objectified in the law of contract. Once objectified, the legal document - the contract - becomes the reality. The contract takes significance over the social relationships it supposedly represents. n164 It replaces those relationships in the eyes of the court and becomes the sole or primary basis for the disposition of the case. n165 Although there is some room for the "intent of the parties" in contractual interpretation, its influence is limited to mediating between the language on the face of the contract and the underlying rules of contract. n166 Another example of the prevalence of abstraction within the law may be found in the wide-spread use of such concepts as "consideration" n167 in contracts or "reasonable doubt" n168 in criminal law. The common law itself is an abstraction. It results from the restatement of Anglo-Saxon customs in the opinions of English courts. Once so recorded, what was formerly custom is transformed into a "transcendent entity" - positive law - "operating and elaborated in officially contained systems which are incompatible with custom, although ... some custom-like modalities, survive." n169 So, instead of referring directly to custom, common law jurists refer to something derived from it, an abstraction of it. As law relies on abstraction, it also privileges complexity. Complexity and abstraction go hand in hand. n170 The transformation of English custom into the common law required a new professional class to navigate its complexity. n171 Indeed, "it was the extraordinary technicality of the common law that provided lawyers with their claim to expertise and served, by its very artificiality, to distinguish legal reasoning from the "common-sense" reason of the general populace." n172 Anyone who has ever looked at a law treatise cannot help but be impressed with the complexity of European-centered law. There are sections upon sections in any of the great multi-volumes works, such as Wigmore's Evidence. n173 This complexity is the direct result of the Eurocentric desire to abstract, to rationalize and to objectify. Finally, Eurocentric law is despiritualized and secular. n174 In fact, European positive law was impossible to conceptualize until God had been banished from the material world. n175 The creation of the Eurocentric concept of law was itself a process of desacralization. n176 God was no longer necessary to legitimate postEnlightenment law: Enlightenment replaces God with nature. In terms of the origin myths of modern science, the deific obstacle to humanity's progress in knowledge is eliminated, constraining superstition gives way to incandescent truth, man unaided at last dares to know, and so on. n177 The development of the law followed this general account of the [*350] growth of European science. Positive law was viewed as a science, as the application of rational "laws" of jurisprudence. n178 In the post- God became "captured by "his' creation" n180 and positive law and reason reigned supreme. n181 Consequently, there are no bounds on the Eurocentric rational will. European Man can do what he wants with his law. Within his world, there is no higher authority than that of the law, which is his own creation. With the creation of the law, the European male has become a self-policing entity - one that need answer to no other. n182 Thus far, this Article has demonstrated that what has come to be known as "the law" in Western societies is really a particular social construction that exhibits cultural attributes peculiar to European and European-derived societies. Law is an artifact of a Eurocentric culture, and as such it reflects the cultural logic, epistemology, axiology, ontology, ethos and aesthetic choice of Eurocentric culture. n183 The core attributes of Eurocentricity are readily discernible within the law. But law not only reflects the [*351] character of Eurocentricity, it carries out the functions of Eurocentricity as well. Law organizes society, and indeed the world, in ways that make it easier for Eurocentric culture to assert its dominance. Enlightenment mind, divinity was as subject to these laws as it was to the laws of physics. n179 Thus, And, the legalization of prostitution doesn’t solve the violence or stigma of prostitution, it only conceals it behind legitimate state authority Farley ’06 (Melissa, research and clinical psychologist at Prostitution Research & Education, a San Francisco nonprofit organization. She edited PROSTITUTION, TRAFFICKING, AND TRAUMATIC STRESS in 2003, which contains contributions from important voices in the field, and she has authored or contributed to twenty-five peerreviewed articles. Farley is currently engaged in a series of cross-cultural studies on men who buy women in prostitution, and she is also helping to produce an art exhibition that will help shift the ways that people see prostitution, pornography, and sex trafficking, “Prostitution, Trafficking, and Cultural Amnesia: What We Must Not Know in Order To Keep the Business of Sexual Exploitation Running Smoothly”, http://projectrespect.org.au/system/files/FarleyYaleLaw2006.pdf, AO) The effects of legalized prostitution can be observed in Australia, where researchers have found that it produces a “prostitution culture”174 with increased illegal as well as legal prostitution, increased presence of organized crime, increased demand for prostitution, increased child prostitution, and increased trafficking of women for the purpose of prostitution.175 State sponsored prostitution provides a legal welcome to pimps, traffickers, and johns.176 But does it protect women? Well-intentioned people are confused about how to address what they intuitively understand to be the intrinsic harms of prostitution and trafficking. 177 It is misleading when right-to-prostitution advocates and pimps reframe prostitution as a human rights issue. One organization even proposed that women’s civil rights would be violated if they were denied the “right to work” as a prostitute.178 Laws against pimping or buying women are seen by sex workers’ rights groups as obstacles to conducting business. Another source of confusion about legal prostitution is that sex industry advocates appropriate the names of legitimate human rights or public health organizations. Although their names are similar, the Global Alliance Against Trafficking in Women (GAATW) promotes prostitution as sex work, while the Coalition Against Trafficking in Women (CATW) promotes the abolition of prostitution.179 Legal prostitution and decriminalized prostitution are both state-sanctioned prostitution, but there are differences between them. In legalized prostitution, the state assumes the role of pimp, collecting taxes and regulating the practice of prostitution. Decriminalized prostitution is a radical removal of any and all laws regarding prostitution (including laws against pimping, pandering, purchasing, and procuring) so that the buying and selling of people in prostitution is considered the legal equivalent of buying candy. Although advocates allege that legalizing prostitution would remove its social stigma, in fact, women in legalized prostitution are still physically and socially rejected, whether they are in rural brothels ringed with razor wire or in urban brothels walled-off from the city.180 Zoning of the location of legal or state-tolerated prostitution is a constant source of legal battles, since no one wants prostitution transactions taking place in his neighborhood. Legalization is not only ineffective in removing the stigma of prostitution: it also fails to protect women from violence. Legal control of prostitution targets its “outward appearance rather than the conditions in which women find themselves. On the whole, governments are far more anxious about public order and public health than about abuse and violence.”181 Many women in prostitution tell us that legalized prostitution will not make them any safer than they were in illegal prostitution.182 Thus legal brothels in the Netherlands may have as many as three panic buttons in each room.183 Dutch, South African, and Australian pimps have commented on the extreme physical violence that johns inflict on women in prostitution, 184 and Australian women in prostitution are advised to take classes in hostage negotiation.185 When rapes occur, however, women in legal strip clubs are told to keep silence or be fired.186 Women in prostitution speak constantly of its violence.187 And, policymaking methods are structured by the assumptions of white, male elites. Their analysis is predicated on an instrumental rationality that glosses over gender, race, class and sexuality as being tied to the prevailing relations of power and systemic oppression Shaw in 2004 (Kathleen M., “Using Feminist Critical Policy Analysis in the Realm of Higher Education: The Case of Welfare Reform as Gendered Educational Policy”, Journal of Higher Education, Vol. 75, Issue 1, rcheek) Feminist critical policy analysis has been most clearly articulated in the work of Catherine Marshall, whose two edited volumes both lay out the theoretical and methodological underpinnings of this approach to policy research and also provide examples of the ways in which it can be used to examine both secondary and postsecondary education (Marshall, 1997a, 1997b). Feminist critical policy analysis melds critical theory and feminism in a way that is designed to challenge the traditional, mainstream approaches to policy analysis that have dominated policy research for the last fifty years (Marshall, 1997a). The methods and theoretical frameworks that dominate current policy analysis have been developed and implemented by those in power who, particularly in the world of policy formation and analysis, are overwhelmingly white, male, and well educated. Thus, traditional policy research has, according to Marshall, reflected the assumptions, worldview, and values of this group.¶ As is the case with much mainstream research in the social sciences, traditional policy analysis can be characterized by the following elements. Among the most important are a belief in a single concept of truth (truth with a capital "T"); the assumption that objectivity on the part of the researcher is both achievable and desirable; the assumption that all research subjects share the same relationship to their social environment, thereby rendering such particularities as gender, race, social class, and sexuality unimportant; and the practice of evaluating women on the basis of male norms (Bensimon & Marshall, 1997, p. 7-8). Since this positivist paradigm is so widely accepted in the policy world, it allows policy analysts to assume a dispassionate, objective stance and at the same time encourages the broader policy community to perceive the research enterprise in this way. Thus, traditional policy analysis will-fully ignores the inherently political nature of all research, and policy research in particular. As Marshall states, "Traditional policy analysis is grounded in a narrow, falsely objective, overly instrumental view of rationality that masks its latent biases and allows policy elites and technocrats to present analyses and plans as neutral and objective when they are actually tied to prevailing relations of power" (1997a, p. 3). And, the impact is constant war and violence Burke in 2007 (Anthony, Senior Lecturer in Politics and International Relations at UNSW, Sydney, “Ontologies of War: Violence, Existence and Reason”, Theory & Event, Volume 10, Issue 2, 2007, pMUSE, cheek) # At the same time, Kissinger's hubris and hunger for control was beset by a corrosive anxiety: that, in an era of nuclear weapons proliferation and constant military modernisation, of geopolitical stalemate in Vietnam, and the emergence and militancy of new post-colonial states, order and mastery were harder to define and impose. He worried over the way 'military bipolarity' between the superpowers had 'encouraged political multipolarity', which 'does not guarantee stability. Rigidity is diminished, but so is manageability...equilibrium is difficult to achieve among states widely divergent in values, goals, expectations and previous experience' (emphasis added). He mourned that 'the greatest need of the contemporary international system is an agreed concept of order'.57 Here were the driving obsessions of the modern rational statesman based around a hunger for stasis and certainty that would entrench U.S. hegemony: For the two decades after 1945, our international activities were based on the assumption that technology plus managerial skills gave us the ability to reshape the international system and to bring about domestic transformations in "emerging countries". This direct "operational" concept of international order has proved too simple. Political multipolarity makes it impossible to impose an American design. Our deepest challenge will be to evoke the creativity of a pluralistic world, to base order on political multipolarity even though overwhelming military strength will remain with the two Kissinger's statement revealed that such cravings for order and certainty continually confront chaos, resistance and uncertainty: clay that won't be worked, flesh that will not yield, enemies that refuse to surrender. This is one of the most powerful lessons of the Indochina wars, which were to continue in a phenomenally destructive fashion for six years after Kissinger wrote these words. Yet as his sinister, Orwellian exhortation to superpowers.58 'evoke the creativity of a pluralistic world' demonstrated, Kissinger's hubris was undiminished. This is a vicious, historic irony: a desire to control nature, technology, society and human beings that is continually frustrated, but never abandoned or rethought. By 1968 U.S. Secretary of Defense Robert McNamara, the rationalist policymaker par excellence, had already decided that U.S. power and technology could not prevail in Vietnam; Nixon and Kissinger's refusal to accept this conclusion, to abandon their Cartesian illusions, was to condemn hundreds of thousands more to die in Indochina and the people of Cambodia to two more decades of horror and misery.59 In 2003 there would be a powerful sense of déja vu as another Republican Administration crowned more than decade of failed and destructive policy on Iraq with a deeply controversial and divisive war to remove Saddam Hussein from power. In this struggle with the lessons of Vietnam, revolutionary resistance, and rapid geopolitical transformation, we are witness to an enduring political and cultural theme: of a craving for order, control and certainty in the face of continual uncertainty. Closely related to this anxiety was the way that Kissinger's thinking -- and that of McNamara and earlier imperialists like the British Governor of Egypt Cromer -- was embedded in instrumental images of technology and the machine: the machine as both a tool of power and an image of social and political order. In his essay 'The Government of Subject Races' Cromer envisaged effective imperial rule -- over numerous societies and billions of human beings -- as best achieved by a central authority working 'to ensure the harmonious working of the different parts of the machine'.60 Kissinger analogously invoked the virtues of 'equilibrium', 'manageability' and 'stability' yet, writing some six decades later, was anxious that technological progress no longer brought untroubled control: the Westernising 'spread of technology and its associated rationality...does not inevitably produce a similar concept of reality'.61 # We sense the rational policymaker's frustrated desire: the world is supposed to work like a machine, ordered by a form of power and governmental reason which deploys machines and whose desires and processes are meant to run along ordered, rational lines like a machine. Kissinger's desire was little different from that of Cromer who, wrote Edward Said: ...envisions a seat of power in the West and radiating out from it towards the East a great embracing machine, sustaining the central authority yet commanded by it. What the machine's branches feed into it from the East -- human material, material wealth, knowledge, what have you -- is processed by the machine, then converted into more power...the immediate translation of mere Oriental matter This desire for order in the shadow of chaos and uncertainty -- the constant war with an intractable and volatile matter -- has deep roots in modern thought, and was a major impetus to the development of technological reason and its supporting theories of knowledge. As Kissinger's claims about the West's Newtonian desire for the 'accurate' gathering and classification of 'data' suggest, modern strategy, foreign policy and Realpolitik have been thrust deep into the apparently stable soil of natural science, in the hope of finding immovable and unchallengeable roots there. While this process has origins in ancient Judaic and Greek thought, it crystallised in into useful substance.62 # philosophical terms most powerfully during and after the Renaissance. The key figures in this process were Francis Bacon, Galileo, Isaac Newton, and René Descartes, who all combined a hunger for political and ontological certainty, a positivist epistemology and a naïve faith in the goodness of invention. Bacon sought to create certainty and order, and with it a new human power over the world, through a new empirical methodology based on a harmonious combination of experiment, the senses and the understanding. With this method, he argued, we can 'derive hope from a purer alliance of the faculties (the experimental and rational) than has yet been attempted'.63 In a similar move, Descartes sought to conjure certainty from uncertainty through the application of a new method that moved progressively out from a few basic certainties (the existence of God, the certitude of individual consciousness and a divinely granted faculty of judgement) in a search for pure fixed truths. Mathematics formed the ideal image of this method, with its strict logical reasoning, its quantifiable results and its uncanny insights into the hidden structure of the cosmos.64 Earlier, Galileo had argued that scientists should privilege 'objective', quantifiable Such doctrines of mathematically verifiable truth were to have powerful echoes in the 20th Century, in the ascendancy of systems analysis, game theory, cybernetics and computing in defense policy and strategic decisions, and in the awesome scientific breakthroughs of nuclear physics, which unlocked the innermost secrets of matter and energy and applied the most advanced applications of mathematics and computing to create the atomic bomb. Yet this new scientific power was marked by a terrible irony: as even Morgenthau understood, the control over matter afforded by the science could never be translated into the control of the weapons themselves, into political utility and rational strategy.66 qualities over 'merely perceptible' ones; that 'only by means of an exclusively quantitative analysis could science attain certain knowledge of the world'.65 Finally, vote negative to reject the law. The state is only a fiction. Only the abandonment of any notion of “legalization” can solve the worst forms of colonial violence Nunn 1997 [Kenneth B. "Law as a eurocentric enterprise." Law & Ineq. 15 (1997): 323. LEXIS//BlackMagic] The law supports Eurocentricity through its false universalism and its privileging of the European historical experience. Eurocentric law presents itself as rational, transcendent, objective, without ideological content and applicable to all. n211 The law is depicted as a necessity; without it, chaos would reign and civilization would perish. Consider for example the following comments from a leading American legal historian: The rule of law is one of our culture's most important concepts and one of the great forces in the history of western civilization... The rule of law meant that there existed a body of rules and procedures governing human and governmental behavior that have an autonomy and logic of their own. The rule of law - the rule of rules, if you will - proposed to make all persons equal before a neutral and impartial authority. Its legitimacy derived largely from the possibility of applying it on a reasoned basis free from the whim and caprice of both individuals and government [independent of considerations of] social position, governmental office, family of birth, wealth, and race ... n212 [*359] Notwithstanding such heady rhetoric, the law's autonomy and universality may be brought into question. The law's claim to universality is merely its thinly disguised cultural chauvinism. This is especially evident in the law's treatment of the doctrine of precedent, or stare decisis. Stare decisis, or the assumption that the law is best built piece by piece on the decisions of the past, supposedly guides and shapes the development of the law. n213 It is assumed that reliance on past precedents gives a greater degree of certainty to legal decisions. n214 But the doctrine of precedent has an ideological function as well. n215 This can be seen by considering the origins of legal precedents. In commonlaw jurisdictions, the precedents come from England. Thus, a link is established between United States jurisprudence and England that gives English law priority and elevates it to a special place of privilege in the decision-making process. n216 Precedent serves to tie United States jurisprudence to its place of origin. n217 If law were truly universal, then courts in the United States would cast around and choose their precedents from among the world's best reasoned decisions. By relying solely on English precedents, n218 United States law makes the ideological assertion that English law - white law - is superior to all others. Looked at objectively, this reverence for the common law seems bizarre. It is absurd to argue that the historical and cultural developments of English landholders and peasants are so universal, and so transcendent that they can be called upon to resolve problems and settle disputes in Nigeria, Ghana or Singapore. n219 This state of affairs is acceptable only if the culture of England is accepted as a paradigm for all other cultures, everywhere. And English culture can only be accepted as paradigmatic if it is believed in some way to be superior or "better" than others. In this way, the law becomes an instrument of cultural hegemony. It celebrates the superiority of European culture in an allegedly multicultural world. This problem is replicated in any attempt to address law as a discipline, whether one is in a common law or a civil law jurisdiction. To speak of law, one must pay homage to all the great white thinkers who laid its foundation, or added to its reach: Cicero, Holmes, Pound, Hand, Austin, Rawls, to name but a few. No matter how illustrious the career of a nonwhite jurist or how well-developed the legal philosophy of nonWestern cultures, they are not so acknowledged. To understand why, one need only consider the essentially racist character of Eurocentric thought. Racism, Fitzpatrick shows, is the consequence of Eurocentricity's hunger for dichotomy: n220 "With the creation of modern European identity ... the world was reduced to European terms and those terms were equated with universality. That which stood outside of the absolutely universal could only be absolutely different to it." n221 Difference, however, can only be tolerated in European culture if it is subsumed in hierarchy. n222 That is what Eurocentricity does with those it perceives as "other." This is done through the elevation of European standards to the level of the universal. As European standards are elevated, non-European standards are lowered, n223 a process in which the law plays a central role. Again, to quote Fitzpatrick: "True' nationalism ... resides with the nations of the West. It sets norms of performance which other "newer' nations can [*361] seek to achieve but to which they only, so far and in varying degrees, approximate. These norms exemplified by the West are transcendent and universal yet also specifically national. So, the use of "objective' criteria, the achievement of a rational and "industrial' culture, "the establishment of an anonymous, impersonal society,' institutional differentiation and the depersonalization of power are all values and achievements which can both typify the West yet be universal because of their ultimate constitution in the negation of what is local and personal, status-ridden, traditional, irrational, undifferentiated, agricultural, and so on. n224 Over the course of their history, and even to this day, European and Europeandominated countries have shown no hesitancy in imposing their laws and customs on other peoples, usually on the grounds that indigenous law was inferior. In 1900, President McKinley gave instructions to the Philippine Commission established to revise the laws of the Philippines, then a colony of the United States. n225 He stated: The Commission should bear in mind, and the people of the Islands should be made plainly to understand, that there are certain great principles of government which have been made the basis of our governmental system, ... and that these principles and these rules of government must be established and maintained in their islands for the sake of their liberty and happiness, however much they may conflict with the customs or laws of procedure with which they are familiar. n226 Thus, law in European and European-derived countries was considered to be part of a grand, transcendent tradition. Although it was different and considered superior to the legal concepts found in the rest of the world, it was also considered universal. And so there was little reason not to export this "gift," often through force of arms, to the majority peoples of the world. Although the European was liberal with his law, he was parsimonious with his rights, and this is especially true in regard to the right of self-determination. n227 This potent combination is a constant feature of European contact with other cultures and thus merits further attention. European colonizers dominated the majority peoples of the [*362] world, took their land, and destroyed or corrupted their cultures. n228 Yet these colonizers always proceeded "legally" through treaties or the dictates of international law. n229 Ani argues convincingly that the European preoccupation with "legalizing" their conquests served the double purpose of disarming their victims and bolstering the European self-image. n230 A key part of the European belief system is faith in the linear notion of "progress," n231 the belief that later historical developments are superior to preceding ones and that the course of human history flows from worse to better. This, in combination with the European conviction that white culture was superior to the world's other cultures made European conquest a matter of pride and self-esteem. n232 Their conquests needed to be "legal" in order to provide the full psychological benefits. In addition, the export of European law was deemed as synonymous with the export of European "civilization" and thus synonymous with progress: The concept of "codified law" is a definite ingredient of that of civilization; for with civilization, according to European ideology, comes order and legality assures "lasting order" - not moral conduct but consistent and predictable conduct. So that the "civilized" way - the European way - is to bring laws, however forcibly, and the structures of European culture ("civilization") to those whom one treats immorally and for whom one has no respect. n233 From a pragmatic perspective, then, the law cannot be viewed as a positive force for change. The law must be viewed for what it is, a necessary component for the extension of white power around the globe. Although the introduction of law into indigenous societies brought order, it did not - it could not - bring peace. Instead "law was in the vanguard of what its own proponents saw as a "belligerent civilization,' bringing "grim presents' with its penal regulation and, in the process, inflicting an immense violence." n234 Consequently, the best choice for people of color who choose to resist white dominance is to reject the law, to become "out/laws," since "by refusing to relate to Western order, these individuals [*363] ... succeed in robbing [Europeans] of a potent tool for psychological and ideological enslavement." n235 1NC GENDER POLITICS RENDER THE UNIVERSAL CONNECTIONS OF CLASS INVISIBLE, INDIVIDUALIZING OPPRESSION HENNESSY (Prof @ SUNY Albany) 2000 [Rosemary, Profit and Pleasure: Sexual Identities in Late Capitalism, Routledge //wyo-tjc] As I will argue throughout this book, these and other contradictions are not so disparate as they may seem. Yet the complex social structures and power relations they span and that undergird the lived reality of late capitalism often remain invisible. This problem of visibility— which includes how we know and recognize certain identities It is now a given that we cannot see homosexualtiy as a monolithic or universal identity, and it has become axiomatic that all sexual identities as they are lived and experienced are intimately inflected by gender, race, nationality, ability, age. How these markers of difference have shaped lesbian and gay (a very basic feature of the history of sexual identity)— will be one of the recurring issues in this book . history and the history of sexuality in general is finally being studied, and in the process many of the cultural presuppositions and divisions on which the very concept of sexual identity is premised are being questioned . But often this work still leaves unexamined why the cultural differences that shape identities are organized as they are, and the relationship between sexual identities and capitalism remains for the most part an unexplored— even unspeakable— area of inquiry. 1 Against this trend, I begin with the assumption that the history of sexual identity— in all of the varied ways it has been culturally differentiated and lived— has been fundamentally, though never simply, affected by several aspects of capitalism: wage labor, commodity production and consumption. 2 Because the relationship between capitalism and sexual identity is complex, indirect, and historically variable, and because there is not a readily accessible conceptual vocabulary for explaining these connections, I give some extended attention to concepts (late capitalism, gendered divisions of labor, ideology, patriarchal structures) that may not seem to be related to sexual identity in any obvious way. I invite the reader to be patient with these seeming detours. I offer them because I hope they will serve as interventions into the . Over the course of the past two decades, capital expansion has increasingly eroded traditional social relations. The drive to accumulate has drawn more and more women into waged work, more thoroughly rerouted the state’s provision for human needs into the profit-making sector, increased the transnational migration of people and capital, extended commodity marketing farther than ever into the body and the unconscious, and heightened the manipulation of human needs and desires for corporate profit. In the process, many of the prevailing structures of family, gender, sexual, and national identity have been altered. These changes are the effects of the historical condition of late capitalism. 3 power of more obvious and perhaps more compelling ways of seeing “Late capitalism” is not just a vague abstraction; it is an array of contradictory global and local structural adjustments in the organization of production and consumption that are altering the way life is lived. These adjustments have registered in the work people do and in the conditions under which they do it, in the state’s relationship to While phrases like “contradictory,” “structural adjustments,” and “late capitalism” may seem quite abstract, the myriad ways they affect people’s lives are in fact concrete, immediate, and palpable. Under capitalism, most people’s lives are laced with contradictions. For most of us, the contradiction between being “free” to work yet barred the “private” sector, and in the forms of identity and the ways of knowing that make the world intelligible . from reaping the full value of our labor is a very basic one, but it may not be the contradiction we experience as the most distressing. In fact, what we experience more painfully may be the ways this contradiction is both compounded and played out in racist institutional practices, in the shaming effects of homophobia, or in any of the other oppressive ways difference is made intelligible and translated into strategies of exclusion and abjection. These include mechanisms for closing some people out of resources like food, housing, education, and health care, as well as the more amorphous but nonetheless vital array of material needs that also comprise one’s ability to As an example of how identities are affected by the contradictions of capitalism, we might consider what it means to be a “woman.” The example of “woman” also indicates the ways sexual identity is sutured onto hierarchical organizations of gender, even though women are differently positioned in relation to one another and to men. Women are contradictorily positioned in capitalism as free workers and citizens, yet devalued as females. For many women, adding to the unpaid value of our wage work is the socially necessary yet unvalued and appropriated labor thrive— for example, the need to be safe, loved, and treated with dignity and respect . we perform in feeding, clothing, and educating people in our households, in caring for children, the elderly, and the sick, and in the myriad forms taken by our unpaid and In many developed and overdeveloped sectors of the world, the traditional mandate that women serve others is contradicted by capitalism’s prescriptions that we serve ourselves, be in control, and compete with others as fully autonomous individuals. While most women underpaid caretaking in the workplace. share some aspects of this contradictory structural position under capitalism, for many it is compounded by their position within social structures that organize racial difference or by their position in the working class. Women provide most of the world’s socially necessary labor— that is, labor that is necessary to collective survival— The contradiction between the material realities that shape individual lives and our ways of experiencing them (feeling we are “good” women for the exploited work we do, blaming ourselves when we fail to juggle the pressures to compete and to serve, etc.) are inevitable in capitalism because capitalism relies on and continually reproduces ways of knowing and feeling that conceal the exploitative human relations that the accumulation of profit requires. Capitalism’s contradictory social arrangements affect but much of it is rendered invisible, both in and outside the value system of commodity exchange, not least of all to women themselves. societies across the globe differently and unevenly, and yet the ways these effects register and are known— or are distorted— in local communities and individual lives . Many contradictions are not seen or experienced as local instances of a global social system because the ways of knowing that are most available do not allow them to be understood this way. Moreover, the social mechanisms for keeping capitalism’s structures and abuses invisible are longstanding, widely shared, often unconscious, and very effective. may often share common patterns Prostitution is the commodification of bodies through the market system Ericsson 1980 [Lars O. "Charges against prostitution: an attempt at a philosophical assessment." Ethics (1980): 335-366.JSTOR //BlackMagic] V. THE MARXIST CHARGE Generally speaking, Marxist opposition to prostitution forms part and parcel of Marxist opposition to capitalism and to the property and family relations created by it. Harlotry is regarded as the offspring of class society, and, says Engels, it "is based on private property and falls with it."7 One of the most refreshing and original features of the Marxist analysis and critique of prostitution is that it is comparatively free from conventional moralism. At least this is true of the classics, Marx and Engels. Far from morally condemning the courtesan, they put her on a par with the woman in the holiest of bourgeois institutions, the family: "In both cases [in Catholic and Protestant bourgeois marriage], however, marriage is determined by the class position of the participants, and to that extent always remains marriage of convenience. In both cases, this marriage of convenience often enough turns into the crassest prostitution- sometimes on both sides, but much more generally on the part of the wife, who differs from the ordinary courtesan only in that she does not hire out her body, like a wageworker, on piece-work, but sells it prostitution and wage labor. Thus, for instance, Aleksandra Kollontai contends that "bargaining over the female body is closely related to the bargaining over female working power. Prostitution can only finally disappear when wage labor does."9 In a similar vein, a contemporary socialist, Sheila Rowbotham, writes: "Just as the prostitute gives the substitute of love for money, the worker hands over his work and his life for a daily wage."'0 What these passages suggest is that the difference between, on the one hand, courtesan and the married bourgeois woman and, on the other, harlot and wage worker is one of degree and not one of kind. The general condition of women and wage workers in capitalist society is an inhuman one. The specific condition of the prostitute does not consist in her being morally depraved or "vicious" but in her being the most degraded and miserable of her class. The strength of the Marxist analysis is, it seems to me, twofold. First, it resolutely brushes aside the moralistic veil, which lures us to place the prostitute in a category of her own-a category that creates a barrier between her and ordinary, "decent" people. Second, it does not regard prostitution as an isolated phenomenon but places it in its socioeconomic context. "To fight prostitution," says Kollontai, "is to fight the foundations of capitalist society."" To her, prostitution is a tumor on the unjust and inhuman economic system which is capitalism. THE REDUCTION OF CLASS TO A NEUTRAL LEVEL AMONG A LIST OF OTHER OPPRESSIONS DESTROYS THE EMANCIPATORY POTENTIAL OF CLASS TO REACH ACROSS ALL LINES OF INDENTITY AND FORGE POLITICAL ACTION. CLASS MUST BE RECOGNIZED AS QUALITATIVELY MORE IMPORTANT—OTHERWISE THE SYSTEM IS ABLE TO SATISFY DEMANDS ON GROUNDS OF FORMAL EQUALITY GIMENEZ (Prof. Sociology at UC Boulder) 2001 [Martha, “Marxism and Class; Gender and Race”, Race, Gender and Class, Vol. 8, p. online: http://www.colorado.edu/Sociology/gimenez/work/cgr.html //wyo-tjc] There are many competing theories of race, gender, class, American society, political economy, power, etc. but no specific theory is invoked to define how the terms race, gender and class are used, or to identify how they are related to the rest of the social system. To some extent, race, gender and class and their intersections and interlockings have become a mantra to be invoked in any and all theoretical contexts, for a tacit agreement about their ubiquitousness and meaning seems to have developed among RGC studies advocates, so that all that remains to be dome is This pragmatic acceptance of race, gender and class, as givens, results in the downplaying of theory, and the resort to experience as the source of knowledge. The emphasis on experience in the construction of knowledge is intended as a corrective to theories that, presumably, reflect only the experience of the powerful. RGC seems to offer a subjectivist understanding empirically to document their intersections everywhere, for everything that happens is, by definition, raced, classed, and gendered . of theory as simply a reflection of the experience and consciousness of the individual theorist, rather than as a body of propositions which is collectively and systematically produced under historically specific conditions of possibility which grant them historical validity for as long as those conditions prevail. Instead, knowledge and theory are pragmatically conceived as the products or reflection of experience and, as such, unavoidably partial, so that greater accuracy and relative completeness can be approximated only through gathering the experiential accounts of all groups. Such is the importance given to the role of experience in the production of knowledge that in the eight page introduction to the first section of an RGC anthology, the word experience is repeated thirty six times (Andersen and Collins, 1995: 1-9). I agree with the importance of learning from the experience of all groups, especially those who have been silenced by oppression and exclusion and by the effects of ideologies that mystify their actual conditions of existence. To learn how people describe their understanding of their lives is very illuminating, for "ideas are the conscious expression -real or illusory -- of (our) actual relations and activities" (Marx, 1994: 111), because "social existence determines consciousness" (Marx, 1994: 211). Given that our existence is shaped by the capitalist mode of production, experience, to be fully understood in its broader social and political implications, has to be situated in the Experience in itself, however, is suspect because, dialectically, it is a unity of opposites; it is, at the same time, unique, personal, insightful and revealing and, at the same time, thoroughly social, partial, mystifying, itself the product of historical forces about which individuals may know little or nothing about (for a critical assessment of experience as a source of knowledge see Sherry Gorelick, "Contradictions of feminist methodology," in Chow, context of the capitalist forces and relations that produce it. Wilkinson, and Baca Zinn, 1996; applicable to the role of experience in contemporary RGC and feminist research is Jacoby's critique of the 1960s politics of subjectivity: it is through the analytical tools of Marxist theory that it can move forward, beyond the impasse revealed by the constant reiteration of variations on the "interlocking" metaphor. This would require, however, a) a rethinking and modification of the postulated relationships between race, class and gender, and b) a reconsideration of the notion that, because everyone is located at the intersection of these structures, all social relations and interactions are "raced," "classed," and "gendered." In the RGC perspective, race, gender and class are presented as equivalent systems of oppression with extremely negative consequences for the oppressed. It is also asserted that the theorization of the connections between these systems require "a working hypothesis of equivalency" Jacoby, 1973: 37- 49). Given the emancipatory goals of the RGC perspective , (Collins, 1997:74). Whether or not it is possible to view class as just another system of oppression depends on the theoretical framework within class is defined. If defined within the traditional sociology of stratification perspective, in terms of a gradation perspective, class refers simply to strata or population aggregates ranked on the basis of standard SES indicators (income, occupation, and education) (for an excellent discussion of the difference between gradational and relational concepts of Class in this non-relational, descriptive sense has no claims to being more fundamental than gender or racial oppression; it simply refers to the set of individual attributes that place individuals within an aggregate or strata arbitrarily defined by the researcher (i.e., depending on their data and research purposes, anywhere from three or four to twelve "classes" can be identified). From the standpoint of Marxist theory , however, class is qualitatively different from gender and race and cannot be considered just another system of oppression. As Eagleton points out, whereas racism and sexism are unremittingly bad, class is not entirely a "bad thing" even though socialists would like to abolish it. The bourgeoisie in its revolutionary stage was instrumental in ushering a new era in historical development, one which liberated the average person from the oppressions of feudalism and put forth the ideals of liberty, equality and fraternity. Today, however, it has an unquestionably negative role to play as it expands and deepens the rule of capital over the entire globe. The working class, on the other hand, is pivotally located to wage the final struggle against capital and, class, see Ossowski, 1963). consequently, it is "an excellent thing" (Eagleton, 1996: 57). While racism and sexism have no redeeming feature, class relations are, dialectically, a unity of opposites; both a site of exploitation and, objectively, a site where the potential agents of social change are forged. To argue that the working class is the fundamental agent of change does not entail the notion that it is the only agent of change. The working class is of course composed of women and men who belong to different races, ethnicities, national origins, cultures, and so forth, so that gender and racial/ethnic struggles have the potential of fueling class struggles because, given the patterns of wealth ownership and income distribution in this and all capitalist countries, those who raise the banners of gender and racial struggles are overwhelmingly propertyless workers, technically members of the working class, people who need to work for economic survival whether it is for a wage or a salary, for whom racism, sexism and class exploitation matter . But this vision of a mobilized working class where gender and racial struggles are not subsumed but are nevertheless related requires a class conscious effort to link RGC studies to the Marxist analysis of historical change. In so far as the "class" in RGC remains a neutral concept, open to any and all theoretical meanings, just one oppression among others, intersectionality will not realize its revolutionary potential. Nevertheless, I want to argue against the notion that class should be considered equivalent to gender and race. I find the grounds for my argument not only on the crucial role class struggles play in processes of epochal change but also in the very assumptions of RGC studies and the ethnomethodological insights put forth by West and Fenstermaker (1994). The assumption of the simultaneity of experience (i.e., all interactions are raced, classed, gendered) together with the ambiguity inherent in the interactions themselves, so that while one person might think he or she is "doing gender," another might interpret those "doings" in terms of "doing class," highlight the basic issue that Collins accurately identifies when she argues that ethnomethodology ignores power relations. Power relations underlie all processes of social interaction and this is why social facts are constraining upon people. But the pervasiveness of power ought not to obfuscate the fact that some power relations are more important and consequential than others. For example, the power that physical attractiveness might confer a woman in her interactions with her less attractive female supervisor or employer does not match the economic power of the latter over the former. In my view , the flattening or erasure of the qualitative difference between class, race and gender in the RGC perspective is the foundation for the recognition that it is important to deal with "basic relations of domination and subordination" which now appear disembodied, outside class relations. In the effort to reject "class reductionism," by postulating the equivalence between class and other forms of oppression, the RGC perspective both negates the fundamental importance of class but it is forced to acknowledge its importance by postulating some other "basic" structures of domination. Class relations -- whether we are referring to the relations between capitalist and wage workers, or to the relations between workers (salaried and waged) and their managers and supervisors, those who are placed in are of paramount importance, for most people's economic survival is determined by them. Those in dominant class positions do exert power over their employees and subordinates and a crucial way in which that power is used is through their choosing the identity they impute their workers. Whatever identity workers might claim or "do," employers can, in turn, disregard their claims and "read" their "doings" differently as "raced" or "gendered" or both, rather than as "classed," thus downplaying their class location and the class nature of their grievances. To argue, then, that class is fundamental is not to "reduce" gender or racial oppression to class, but to acknowledge that the underlying basic and "contradictory class locations," (Wright, 1978) -- "nameless" power at the root of what happens in social interactions grounded in "intersectionality" is class power. THE DETERMINISM OF CAPITAL IS RESPONSIBLE FOR THE INSTRUMENTALIZATION OF ALL LIFE—IT IS THIS LOGIC THAT MOBILIZES AND ALLOWS FOR THE OPPRESSIONS HIGHLIGHTED BY THE 1AC DYER-WITHERFORD (professor of Library and Info. Sciences at the U of Western Ontario) 1999 [Nick. Cyber Marx: Cycles and Circuits of Struggle in High Technology Capitalism.] For capitalism, the use of machines as organs of “will over nature” is an imperative. The great insight of the Frankfurt School—an insight subsequently improved and amplified by feminists and ecologists—was that capital’s dual project of dominating both humanity and nature was intimately tied to the cultivation of “instrumental reason” that systematically objectifies, reduces, quantifies and fragments the world for the purposes of technological control. Business’s systemic need to cheapen labor, cut the costs of raw materials, and expand consumer markets gives it an inherent bias toward the piling-up of technological power. This priority—enshrined in phrases such as “progress,” “efficiency,” “productivity,” “modernization,” and “growth”—assumes an automatism that is used to override any objection or alternative, regardless of the environmental and social consequences. Today, we witness global vistas of toxification, deforestation, desertification, dying oceans, disappearing ozone layers, and disintegrating immune systems, all interacting in ways that perhaps threaten the very existence of humanity and are undeniably inflicting social collapse, disease, and immiseration across the planet. The degree to which this project of mastery has backfired is all too obvious. Vote negative to endorse a structural historical analysis of the material conditions underlying heteropatriarchy METHOD IS THE FOREMOST POLITICAL QUESTION—GROUNDING SITES OF POLITICAL CONTESTATION OUTSIDE OF LABOR MERELY SERVE TO HUMANIZE CAPITAL AND PREVENT A TRANSITION TO A SOCIETY BEYOND OPPRESSION TUMINO (Prof. English @ Pitt) 2001 [Stephen, “What is Orthodox Marxism and Why it Matters Now More than Ever”, Red Critique, p. online //wyo-tjc] Any effective political theory will have to do at least two things: it will have to offer an integrated understanding of social practices and, based on such an interrelated knowledge, offer a guideline for praxis. My main argument here is that among all contesting social theories now, only Orthodox Marxism has been able to produce an integrated knowledge of the existing social totality and provide lines of praxis that will lead to building a society free from necessity. But first I must clarify what I mean by Orthodox Marxism. Like all other modes and forms of political theory, the very theoretical identity of Orthodox Marxism is itself contested—not just from non-and anti-Marxists who question the very "real" (by which they mean the "practical" as under free-market criteria) existence of any kind of Marxism now but, perhaps more tellingly, from within the Marxist tradition itself. I will, therefore, first say what I regard to be the distinguishing marks of Orthodox Marxism and then outline a short polemical map of contestation over Orthodox Marxism within the Marxist theories now. I will end by arguing for its effectivity in bringing about a new society based not on human rights but on freedom from necessity. I will argue that to know contemporary society—and to be able to act on such knowledge—one has to first of all know what makes the existing social totality. I will argue that the dominant social totality is based on inequality— not just inequality of power but inequality of economic access (which then determines access to health care, education, housing, diet, transportation, . . . ). This systematic inequality cannot be explained by gender, race, sexuality, disability, ethnicity, or nationality. These are all secondary contradictions and are all determined by the fundamental contradiction of capitalism which is inscribed in the relation of capital and labor. All modes of Marxism now explain social inequalities primarily on the basis of these secondary contradictions and in doing so—and this is my main argument—legitimate capitalism. Why? Because such arguments authorize capitalism without gender, race, discrimination and thus accept economic inequality as an integral part of human societies. They accept a sunny capitalism—a capitalism beyond capitalism. Such a society, based on cultural equality but economic inequality, has always been the not-so-hidden agenda of the bourgeois left—whether it has been called "new left," "postmarxism," or "radical democracy." This is, by the way, the main reason for its popularity in the culture industry—from the academy (Jameson, Harvey, Haraway, Butler,. . . ) to daily politics (Michael Harrington, Ralph Nader, Jesse Jackson,. . . ) to. . . . For all, capitalism is here to stay and the best that can be done is to make its cruelties more tolerable, more humane. This humanization (not eradication) of capitalism is the sole goal of ALL contemporary lefts (marxism, feminism, anti-racism, queeries, . . . ). Such an understanding of social inequality is based on the fundamental understanding that the source of wealth is human knowledge and not human labor. That is, wealth is produced by the human mind and is thus free from the actual objective conditions that shape the historical relations of labor and capital. Only Orthodox Marxism recognizes the historicity of labor and its primacy as the source of all human wealth. In this paper I argue that any emancipatory theory has to be founded on recognition of the priority of Marx's labor theory of value and not repeat the technological determinism of corporate theory ("knowledge work") that masquerades as social theory. Systematic Violence The sex industry is inherently violent and patriarchal. Their valorizing acceptance of prostitution empties sexuality of eros and turns the aff Faber 04 [Alyda, B.A., M.A., B.Th., M.Div., Ph.D Theology Associate Professor of Christian Theology and Ethics at The Atlantic School of Theology “Eros and Violence” Feminist Theology 2004 12: 319 The Continuum Publishing Group http://fth.sagepub.com/content/12/3/319.full.pdf+html c.shack] Like many theories of violence, Carter Heyward’s Touching Our Strength is a return to human beginnings. Key to her theology is Martin Buber’s phrase, ’In the beginning is the relation’. Relation is the primordial and essential good in human life that may be experienced as a sensual and immediate kind of knowing. From the shore of a possible return to our relational beginnings, Heyward recounts the phantasie of feminist eros as a vision of profound yearning. This phantasie is utopian, and bears expectant hope for material changes in a society riven by forms of violence : alienation, dispassion, domination, submission, broken bonds. The formations of the shore where Heyward stands provokes her frustrations and her longings. In the patriarchal, capitalist, heterosexist, misogynistic, and racist culture in which she finds herself, violence and sexuality are confused in bodies and their practices. This culture accentuates boundaries as barriers between discrete monadic and autonomous selves. Crossing these boundaries takes the form of male domination and female submission, his ’power-over’ complimented by her ’power-under’. The word Heyward uses most often to describe the social context of sexual violence is ’perversion’. She writes, ’to pervert is to turn something completely around from itself. Sexual perversion is the complete twisting, the total misconstruction of erotic power’.9 A dictionary definition may clarify some of Heyward’s connotations of the perversions of erotic power challenged by her elaboration of erotic power as a moral good and the love of God: ’Disposed to be obstinately contrary to what is true or good or to go counter to what is reasonable or required’ (OED). The ’praxis of death’1° that Heyward witnesses in contemporary society (and in much of Christian theology) involves sadomasochism, antieroticism, pornography, and erotophobia. It is a praxis turned away from the ’life force’ of erotic power in mutual relation, and which takes the form of ’death-dealing distortions of what is real and good, of what is possible’.11 This praxis reaches the depths of our personal and social existence, forming our physical, spiritual and emotional being, through practices in which sex and violence mingle in dangerous embodied confusion.12 We are socialized into these structures of alienated power, and restoration from such a pervasive social evil requires ’revolutionary transformation’.13 This revolutionary transformation is anticipated through Heyward’s model of eros, the ultimacy and dynamism of which immediately brings into question the pervasiveness of human formation through structures of perverted sexual violence. Feminist eros, for Heyward, represents a common good and a common vision, a testament of faith that the good can be experienced in the sensual and erotic, and can energize justice seeking within social alignments of power. Feminist eros, as an embodied expression of the goodness of God, unites the intellectual, the physical, and the spiritual. By drawing the power of God within configurations of human flesh, Heyward celebrates human efforts in the co-creation of goodness and justice in the world. A profound experience of ’our bodyselves’ discovers a renewed hopefulness, an openness to flourishing in human life, that she calls prayer. Heyward expresses this radical possibility as an invocation that takes the form of a prayer, not to God, but rather to human capacities for receptiveness to growth and flowering: And you whose spirits are sad or unsure, try to remember the very best parts of your life, the loveliest feelings in your bodyself, occasions of bold delight and quiet confidence, moments of unambivalent commitment and unrestrained joy. Try to remember when you have believed passionately in something or someone, human or divine. Try to imagine that someone now believes in you because she trusts your loveliest feelings...commitments...confidence...joy... She comes in the knowledge that together you, she, and others embody a moving image of sacred power, a fresh wellspring of relational integrity.14 The sensationalized image of a prostitute sanitizes the horrific exploitation and misogyny experienced by prostitutes and re-entrenches the violence done to them. Fitzgerald 13 Laura is a leading Socialist Party organiser in Dublin, and an activist with ROSA, a pro-choice, anti-sexist campaign and discussion group initiated by female members of the Socialist Party. A socialist perspective on the sex industry & prostitution. http://socialistparty.ie/2013/08/a-socialistperspective-on-the-sex-industry-a-prostitution/ {Shoell} Media promotion of the sanitised ‘Belle de Jour’ image of a so-called high-class prostitute who is deeply empowered is an anathema to the experiences of most prostitutes and bears no relation to their lives. The promotion of this vision of prostitution is part of a backlash, minimising and even denying the continued existence of the oppression of women in society and consciously aiming to sanitise a deeply sexist and exploitative industry. If there was no question of a power gap between men and women, if women’s oppression was no longer a factor in society, if it wasn’t the case that we live in a world that’s motivated by the quest for profits with those in power willing to commodify all in this pursuit, including sex and women’s bodies, then perhaps we could believe the propaganda. Rachel Moran, Irish survivor of prostitution and author of Paid For: My Journey Through Prostitution has very articulately challenged the myth of the ‘happy hooker’: The first step to being a happy hooker is, of course, consenting to be one. Consent to prostitution is viewed as a one-dimensional thing; in reality, it is anything but… I have never come across an example of prostitution in any woman’s life that was not an attempt to get out of a situation, rather than to get into one. In other words, the plethora of women I met over the years were attempting to remove themselves from financial problems; not simply because they’d developed a penchant for expensive handbags. The assumption of choice leads to the conclusion of consent, but choice and consent are erroneous concepts here. Their invalidity rests on the fact that a woman’s compliance in prostitution is a response to circumstances beyond her control, and this produces an environment which prohibits even the possibility of true consent. There is a difference between consent and reluctant submission. Data from the Netherlands spanning several years show consistent increases in human trafficking that can only be attributed to result from legalizing prostitution. James 12 [Marinova, Nadejda K. and Patrick James. (2012) The Tragedy of Human Trafficking: Competing Theories and European Evidence. Foreign Policy Analysis, doi: 10.1111/j.1743-8594.2011.00162.x, BM] Trafficking data from the Netherlands in Table 2 reveal an increase in victim numbers. The victims in 1998 and 1999, before legalization, are 228 and 287, respectively. The following years reveal no number lower than 257, in 2003. Finally, for 2004, the number reaches 405. Data for 2006, 2007, and 2008 show a clear increase. The number of victims for 2008 is 3.6 times that in 1998. Additionally, for 2004–2008, the number of victims more than doubled, from 405 in 2004 to 826 in 2008. There is a twofold possible interpretation for this data: (1) there is an increase in the number of victims trafficked into the Netherlands or, alternatively (2) when brothels are legal, there is increased police enforcement, and therefore, the number of victims of trafficking discovered and registered is higher (Daalder 2007). The information shows a rising number of investigations, which for 1998–2004 grew from 14 to 60. Nonetheless, investigations are not keeping pace with the growth in victim numbers, which contradicts the argument about effective police activity. Empirical concludes that legalizing prostitution increases trafficking and doesn’t result in higher transparency James 12 [Marinova, Nadejda K. and Patrick James. (2012) The Tragedy of Human Trafficking: Competing Theories and European Evidence. Foreign Policy Analysis, doi: 10.1111/j.1743-8594.2011.00162.x, BM] What can be said of the preceding cases, individually and collectively? Swedish policy epitomizes an abolitionist approach in both domestic and foreign policy. While quantitative data are scarce, interview information with law enforcement officers and traffickers in Sweden points toward the importance of state action in the policy and law enforcement realm. Swedish police reports also underline that, in combating trafficking, the efforts and priority specifically accorded to the problem are crucial (NCID 2009:5). Research on the Netherlands and Germany finds that legalization of prostitution does lead to an increase in trafficking. Thus, based on the comparative country studies, the implications of the abolitionist and repressive theories for trafficking are confirmed. The data also challenge the laborist approach with regard to its argument that legalization results in increased transparency and discovery of more trafficking victims. It is concerted state action, in terms of adoption of an anti-trafficking legal framework, as well as active law enforcement, that prove most important for combating trafficking. Overall, we conclude that legalization of prostitution does lead to an increase in trafficking. However, swift, effective, and consistent law enforcement, as in the case of Germany, can reverse that trend. Alternatively, when law enforcement efforts are insufficient, as in the Netherlands, the number of trafficking victims continues to increase after that legalization. More intensive measures on the part of the Dutch state have been seen in the past 2 or 3 years, yet strong law enforcement and consistency over time will be required to adequately curb this trafficking increase. The secondary cases of Belgium, Greece, and Switzerland (see online Appendix for these cases in addition to Norway and Iceland), all of which have legalized brothels, also indicate, based on the (limited) available data, that legality of prostitution means higher trafficking. The preliminary information on Norway (which, like Sweden, has an abolitionist regime) also appears to point out that outlawing the purchase of sex curbs trafficking. Our conclusions are in line with the findings of the UNODC, which regarding human trafficking worldwide, underscores that progress is determined by individual national initiative and that most of the trafficking convictions come from a few countries that undertake such initiatives (UNODC 2009a:9). Doesn’t solve the double standard, empirics prove compulsory testing of women but never men Jeffreys ‘09 (Sheila, “The Industrial Vagina: The political economy of the global sex trade”, Book, Chapter 8, p. 173-197, AO) Lie explains that prostitution does not occur simply from ‘men’s sexual desires or “deviant” women’s willingness to offer sex for money’ but from ‘the underlying structural conditions and concrete organizations’. After the end of ‘feudal relations’, ‘modern’ prostitution requires the ‘regulating or administrative state, urbanization and the commodification of social life’. In fact, he points out, the state needs to play an active role because ‘prostitution usually entails organizations – be it the state or private sexual entrepreneurs – to sustain relations of sexual exchange between prostitutes and their clients’ (Lie, 1997, p. 260). The history of prostitution demonstrates that whilst some states, like Japan, set up licensed prostitution systems to service male citizens, others merely tolerated prostitution as a ‘necessary evil’ through discriminatory legislation and practice in which male buyers were protected and women were persecuted (Frances, 2007). This was effected through the Contagious Diseases Acts, for instance, in the 19th century in the UK and Australia that forced women suspected of being prostituted to undergo examination for venereal diseases and to be incarcerated in lock hospitals if found to be infected (Jeffreys, 1985a). With the modernization of patriarchy in the 20th century in western states, more efficiency, and thus the legalization of the delivery of male sexual privileges, was required. In legalized brothel systems today the women are assumed to be a threat to public health, and once more compulsorily inspected, whilst the male buyers are exempt. This practice of compulsory examination of women, but not male buyers, was identified by feminists in the late 19th and early 20th centuries as one aspect of the ‘double standard’ in relation to sexuality (Jeffreys, 1985a). This ‘double standard’ is the basis of legalization and toleration, in which women are rostered on in warehouse brothels to service men’s sexual pleasures while the state benignly oversees or looks the other way. Sequestration of ‘fallen’ women from ‘pure’ women has been, and continues to be, necessary to the continuation of this double standard, which separates out women who may be treated as the common property of all men from those whose bodies are the private perquisite of their male partners. Solvency Prostitute has negative connotations and is stigmatizing. Ehrlich ’12 (Richard S., reported news for international media from Asia since 1978, based in Hong Kong, New Delhi and now Bangkok, also co-author of a nonfiction book of investigative journalism titled: "Hello My Big Big Honey!" Love Letters to Bangkok Bar Girls and Their Revealing Interviews, The Washington Times, “U.N. report calls for decriminalizing prostitution”, http://www.washingtontimes.com/news/2012/oct/24/un-report-calls-decriminalizingprostitution/?page=1, AO) The report also called for euphemisms. "The terms 'prostitution' and 'prostitute' have negative connotations and are considered by advocates of sex workers to be stigmatizing," said the 210-page report, authored by Australian human rights lawyer John Godwin. "The term 'sex work' is preferred," said the report, issued by the UNDP, the U.N. Population Fund, the Joint United Nations Program on HIV/AIDS (UNAIDS) and several nongovernmental organizations across Asia. New Zealand and Australia's New South Wales province are models of how decriminalization of prostitution boosted condom use and slowed the spread of HIV, resulting in "extremely low or nonexistent" transmission of sexual diseases among prostitutes, said the report. "I would like to be a sex worker in New Zealand," said Mandeep Dhaliwal, director of the UNDP's HIV, Health and Development Practice, when asked which countries in Asia were the best places for them to earn a living as a prostitute. Thailand is also a relatively safe place to be a prostitute. Although prostitution is illegal, authorities usually ignore the sex trade, enabling many upmarket Thai and foreign sex workers to enjoy higher wages, cleaner environments and less hassle compared with elsewhere in Asia, said Chantawipa Apisuk, who directs Empower, a Thai foundation led by prostitutes. "In Thailand, although it's illegal, it's still open, and a lot of people, my friends, are working," she added. Sex workers should enjoy the same labor conditions as factory workers or entertainers, said Ms. Chantawipa, who wore a T-shirt emblazoned with her favorite slogan: "Good girls go to heaven. Bad girls go everywhere." The report also studied call girls, street walkers and brothels and found that, in many Asian countries, they were "illegal, illegal, illegal," said the report. Problems are exacerbated when reformers and authorities voice shrill warnings about human-trafficking and forcibly "rescue" prostitutes who do not want to be "saved," the report said. "The language of some international and regional instruments have either implied a strong link between trafficking and sex work, or conflated these concepts," it said, referring to local laws, international agreements and other formal legal arrangements. Legalization of prostitution continues the violence the 1AC criticizes Jeffreys ‘09 (Sheila, “The Industrial Vagina: The political economy of the global sex trade”, Book, Chapter 8, p. 173-197, AO) In the post-World War II period, in response to a considerable campaign by feminist activists and abolitionist organizations to end state regulation of prostitution and the base it provides for trafficking, both states which had signed up to the 1949 Convention against Trafficking in Persons and those which did not, closed the brothels they had previously regulated or tolerated (Jeffreys, 1997). But in the last 20 years, a campaign for legalization by sex industry lobby groups has caused a normalization of prostitution and an acceptance by many states that it should be treated as a legitimate business and state regulated once more. The policies of legalizing or decriminalizing brothels have been suggested as cures for many of the other social harms that prostitution brings in its train, besides the trafficking in women. These touted benefits do not eventuate. As Janice Raymond of CATW puts it: ‘The alleged benefits of legalizing/decriminalizing prostitution sound a lot like the promised land of trickle-down economics’ (Raymond, 2004, p. 1184). In states that ‘legalize’, the ordinary buying and selling of sexual access to prostituted women is usually already legal and remains unchanged by ‘legalization’. Only certain activities that are associated with prostitution have usually been subject to penalty, such as solicitation in the street by prostituted women and/or the male buyers, and the extraction of third party profits from prostitution, known as pimping, ‘living off the earnings of prostitution’ or brothel keeping. There is usually no decriminalization of street prostitution. All that gets legalized is pimping, through the acceptance of a small minority of brothels as legitimate businesses and the requirement that they apply for licences to operate. Most of the industry of prostitution remains illegal, but the foundation is created for the industrialization of prostitution. This is the system in the states of Victoria and Queensland in Australia (M. Sullivan, 2007). Legalization decriminalization of prostitution does not enhance women’s choice. Raymond ‘3 (Janice G., radical lesbian feminist activist known for her work against violence, sexual exploitation and the "medical abuse" of women, she is also the author of five books and multiple articles, translated into several languages, on issues ranging among transsexualism, violence against women, women’s health, feminist theory and bio-medicine. She has published numerous articles on prostitution and sex trafficking, “Ten Reasons for Not Legalizing Prostitution and a Legal Response to the Demand for Prostitution”, Journal of Trauma Practice, 2, 2003: pp. 315-332; and in Prostitution, Trafficking and Traumatic Stress. Melissa Farley (Ed.). Binghamton: Haworth Press) AO Most women in prostitution did not make a rational choice to enter prostitution from among a range of other options. They did not sit down one day and decide that they wanted to be prostitutes. They did not have other real options such as medicine, law, nursing or politics. Instead, their “options” were more in the realm of how to feed themselves and their children. Such choices are better termed survival strategies. Rather than consenting to prostitution, a prostituted woman more accurately complies with the extremely limited options available to her. Her compliance is required by the fact of having to adapt to conditions of inequality that are set by the customer who pays her to do what he wants her to do. Most of the women interviewed in the studies authored by Raymond et al. reported that choice in entering the sex industry could only be discussed in the context of a lack of other options. Many described prostitution as their last choice, or as an involuntary way of making ends meet (Raymond et al., 2001; Raymond et al., 2002). In one study, 67% of a group of law enforcement officials expressed the opinion that women did not enter prostitution voluntarily. Similarly, 72% of social service providers did not think that women voluntarily choose to enter the sex industry (Raymond et al 2001, p. 91). The distinction between forced and voluntary prostitution is precisely what the sex industry is promoting because it will give the industry more legal security and market stability if this distinction can be utilized to legalize prostitution, pimping and brothels. Women who consider bringing charges against pimps and perpetrators will bear the burden of proving that they were “forced.” How will marginalized women ever be able to prove coercion? If prostituted women must prove that force was used in recruitment or in their “working conditions,” very few women in prostitution will have legal recourse, and very few offenders will be prosecuted. Women in prostitution must continually lie about their lives, their bodies, and their sexual responses. Lying is part of the job definition when the customer asks, “did you enjoy it?” The very edifice of prostitution is built on the lie that “women like it.” Some prostitution survivors have stated that it took them years after leaving prostitution to acknowledge that prostitution wasn’t a free choice because to deny their own capacity to choose was to deny themselves. There is no doubt that a small number of women say they choose to be in prostitution, especially in public contexts orchestrated by the sex industry. In the same way, some people choose to take dangerous drugs such as amphetamine. However, even when some people consent to use dangerous drugs, we still recognize that is harmful to them, and most people do not seek to legalize amphetamine. In this situation, it is harm to the person, not the consent of the person that is the governing standard. A 1998 International Labor Organization (United Nations ILO) report suggested that the sex industry be treated as a legitimate economic sector, but still found that …prostitution is one of the most alienated forms of labour; the surveys [in 4 countries] show that women worked ‘with a heavy heart,’ ‘felt forced,’ or were ‘conscience-stricken’ and had negative self-identities. . A significant proportion claimed they wanted to leave sex work [sic] if they could (Lim, 1998, p. 213). When a woman remains in an abusive relationship with a partner who batters her, or even when she defends his actions, concerned people now understand that she is not there voluntarily. They recognize the complexity of her compliance. Like battered women, women in prostitution may deny their abuse if they are not provided with meaningful alternatives. 2NC And, roleplaying a state policymaker colludes with an imperialist agenda that maintains status quo power, privilege, and oppression by distancing debaters from real world participation in the political contexts we debate about. Reid-Brinkley in 2008 (Dr. Shanara Reid-Brinkley, University of Pittsburgh Department of Communications, “THE HARSH REALITIES OF “ACTING BLACK”: HOW AFRICAN-AMERICAN POLICY DEBATERS NEGOTIATE REPRESENTATION THROUGH RACIAL PERFORMANCE AND STYLE” 2008) Mitchell observes that the stance of the policymaker in debate comes with a “sense of detachment associated with the spectator posture.”115 In other words, its participants are able to engage in debates where they are able to distance themselves from the events that are the subjects of debates. Debaters can throw around terms like torture, terrorism, genocide and nuclear war without blinking. Debate simulations can only serve to distance the debaters from real world participation in the political contexts they debate about. As William Shanahan remarks: …the topic established a relationship through interpellation that inhered irrespective of what the particular political affinities of the debaters were. The relationship was both political and ethical, and needed to be debated as such. When we blithely call for United States Federal Government policymaking, we are not immune to the colonialist legacy that establishes our place on this continent. We cannot wish away the horrific atrocities perpetrated everyday in our name simply by refusing to acknowledge these implications” (emphasis in original).116 118 The “objective” stance of the policymaker is an impersonal or imperialist persona. The policymaker relies upon “acceptable” forms of evidence, engaging in logical discussion, producing rational thoughts. As Shanahan, and the Louisville debaters’ note, such a stance is integrally linked to the normative, historical and contemporary practices of power that produce and maintain varying networks of oppression. In other words, the discursive practices of policy-oriented debate are developed within, through and from systems of power and privilege. Thus, these practices are critically implicated in the maintenance of hegemony. So, rather than seeing themselves as government or state actors, Jones and Green choose to perform themselves in debate, violating the more “objective” stance of the “policymaker” and require their opponents to do the same. Their method reproduces exceptionalist violence and oppression. Vote negative to join a revolution in debate capable of instigating the critical consciousness necessary to avert immanent global disaster. Spanos in 2004 (William V., professor @ Binghamton, printed in Joe Millers’ book “Cross-X” (pg. 467) 2004 and on edebate) Dear Joe MIller, Yes, the statement about the American debate circuit you refer to was made by me, though some years ago. I strongly believed then --and still do, even though a certain uneasiness about "objectivity" has crept into the "philosophy of debate" -- that debate in both the high schools and colleges in this assumed to take place nowhere, even though the issues that are debated are profoundly historical, which means that positions are always represented from the perspective of power, and a matter of life and death. I find it grotesque that in the debate world, it doesn't matter which position you take on an issue -- say, the United States' unilateral wars of preemption -- as long as you "score points". The world we live in is a world entirely dominated by an "exceptionalist" America which has perennially claimed that it has been chosen by God or History to fulfill his/its "errand in the wilderness." That claim is powerful because American economic and country is military power lies behind it. And any alternative position in such a world is virtually powerless. Given this inexorable historical reality, to assume, as the protocols of debate do, that all positions are equal is to efface the imbalances of power that are the fundamental condition of history and to annul the Moral authority inhering in the position of the oppressed. This is why I have said that the appropriation of my interested work on education and empire to this transcendental debate world constitute a travesty of my intentions. My scholarship is not "disinterested." It is militant and intended to ameliorate as much as possible the pain and suffering of those who have been oppressed by the "democratic" institutions that have power precisely by way of showing that their language if "truth," far from being "disinterested" or "objective" as it is always claimed, is informed by the will to power over all manner of "others." This is also why I told my interlocutor that he and those in the debate world who felt like him should call into question the traditional "objective" debate protocols and the instrumentalist language they privilege in favor of a concept of debate and of language in which life and death mattered. I am very much aware that the arrogant neocons who now saturate the government of the Bush administration -- judges, pentagon planners, state department officials, etc. learned their "disinterested" argumentative skills in the high school and college debate societies and that, accordingly, they have become masters at disarming the just causes of the oppressed. This kind leadership will reproduce itself (along with the invisible oppression it perpetrates) as long as the training ground and the debate protocols from which it emerges remains in tact. A revolution in the debate world must occur. It must force that unworldly world down into the historical arena where positions make a difference. To invoke the late Edward Said, only such a revolution will be capable of "deterring democracy" (in Noam Chomsky's ironic phrase), of instigating the secular critical consciousness that is, in my mind, the sine qua non for avoiding the immanent global disaster towards which the blind arrogance of Bush Administration and his neocon policy makers is leading. State-centricity makes critical understanding of the world impossible. Shampa Biswas, Professor of Politics at Whitman College, December 2007, “Empire and Global Public Intellectuals: Reading Edward Said as an International Relations Theorist,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies, Vol. 36, No. 1, p. 125-126 In making a case for the exilic orientation, it is the powerful hold of the nation-state upon intellectual thinking that Said most bemoans. 31 The nation-state of course has a particular pride of place in the study of global politics. The state-centricity of International Relations has not just circumscribed the ability of scholars to understand a vast ensemble of globally oriented movements, exchanges and practices not reducible to the state, but also inhibited a critical intellectual orientation to the world outside the national borders within which scholarship is produced. Said acknowledges the fact that all intellectual work occurs in a (national) context which imposes upon one’s intellect certain linguistic boundaries, particular (nationally framed) issues and, most invidiously, certain domestic political constraints and pressures, but he cautions against the dangers of such restrictions upon the intellectual imagination. 32 Comparing the development of IR in two different national contexts – the French and the German ones – Gerard Holden has argued that different intellectual influences, different historical resonances of different issues, different domestic exigencies shape the discipline in different contexts. 33 While this is to be expected to an extent, there is good reason to be cautious about how scholarly sympathies are expressed and circumscribed when the reach of one’s work (issues covered, people affected) so obviously extends beyond the national context. For scholars of the global, the (often unconscious) hold of the nation-state can be especially pernicious in the ways that it limits the scope and range of the intellectual imagination. Said argues that the hold of the nation is such that even intellectuals progressive on domestic issues become collaborators of empire when it comes to state actions abroad. 34 Specifically, he critiques nationalistically based systems of education and the tendency in much of political commentary to frame analysis in terms of ‘we’, ‘us’ and ‘our’ - particularly evident in coverage of the war on terrorism - which automatically sets up a series of (often hostile) oppositions to ‘others’. He points in this context to the rather common intellectual tendency to be alert to the abuses of others while remaining blind to those of one’s own. 35 Agency can only be articulated in opposition to the restrictive structuralisms of the status quo—in other words, we can claim our agency only by rejecting the state-centric view of politics. Bleiker, 00 Ph.D. visiting research and teaching affiliations at Harvard, Cambridge, Humboldt, Tampere, Yonsei and Pusan National University as well as the Swiss Federal Institute of Technology and the Institute of Social Studies in The Hague,(Roland, Popular Dissent, Human Agency and Global Politics, Cambridge University Press) Questions of agency have been discussed extensively in international theory, mostly in the context of the so-called structure—agency debate. Although strongly wedded to a state-centric view, this debate nevertheless evokes a number of important conceptual issues that are relevant as well to an understanding of transversal dynamics. The roots of the structure—agency debate can be traced back to a feeling of discontent about how traditional approaches to international theory have dealt with issues of agency. Sketched in an overly broad manner, the point of departure looked as follows: At one end of the spectrum were neorealists, who explain state identity and behaviour through a series of structural restraints that are said to emanate from the anarchical nature of the international system. At the other end we find neoliberals, who accept the existence of anarchy but seek to understand the behaviour of states and other international actors in terms of their individual attributes and their ability to engage in cooperative bargaining. If pushed to their logical end-point, the two positions amount, respectively, to a structural determinism and an equally farfetched belief in the autonomy of rational actors. 24 The structure—agency debate is located somewhere between these two poles. Neither structure nor agency receive analytical priority. Instead, the idea is to understand the interdependent and mutually constitutive relationship between them. The discussions that have evolved in the wake of this assumption are highly complex and cannot possibly be summarised here. 25 Some of the key premises, though, can be recognised by observing how the work of Anthony Giddens has shaped the structure—agency debate in international relations. Giddens speaks of the 'duality of structure,' of structural properties that are constraining as well as enabling. They are both 'the medium and outcome of the contingently accomplished activities of situated actors'. 26 Expressed in other words, neither agents nor structures have the final word. Human actions are always embedded in and constrained by the structural context within which they form and evolve. But structures are not immutable either. A human being, Giddens stresses, will 'know a great deal about the conditions of reproduction of the society of which he or she is a member'. 27 The actions that emerge from this awareness then shape the processes through which social systems are structurally maintained and reproduced. 1NR 1NR---Alt Merely the process of theorizing life outside of capital is enough to access all of our impacts Johnston ‘7 Adrian Johnston, interdisciplinary research fellow in psychoanalysis at Emory University, “The Cynic’s Fetish: Slavoj Zizek and the Dynamics of Belief,” International Journal of Zizek Studies, Vol. 1 No. 0., 24 August 2007, pp. 93-94, accessed 1/27/10 http://www.zizekstudies.org/index.php/ijzs/article/view/8/24 Perhaps the absence of a detailed political roadmap in Zizek's recent writings isn't a major shortcoming. Maybe, at least for the time being, the most important task is simply the negativity of the critical struggle, the effort to cure an intellectual constipation resulting from capitalist ideology and thereby to truly open up the space for imagining authentic alternatives to the prevailing state of the situation. Another definition of materialism offered by Zizek is that it amounts to accepting the internal inherence of what fantasmatically appears as an external deadlock or hindrance (Zizek, 2001d, pp 22-23) (with fantasy itself being defined as the false externalization of something within the subject, namely, the illusory projection of an inner obstacle, Zizek, 2000a, p 16). From this perspective, seeing through ideological fantasies by learning how to think again outside the confines of current restrictions has, in and of itself, the potential to operate as a form of real revolutionary practice (rather than remaining merely an instance of negative/critical intellectual reflection). Why is this the case? Recalling the analysis of commodity fetishism, the social efficacy of money as the universal medium of exchange (and the entire political economy grounded upon it) ultimately relies upon nothing more than a kind of "magic," that is, the belief in money's social efficacy by those using it in the processes of exchange. Since the value of currency is, at bottom, reducible to the belief that it has the value attributed to it (and that everyone believes that everyone else believes this as well), derailing capitalism by destroying its essential financial substance is, in a certain respect, as easy as dissolving the mere belief in this substance's powers. The "external" obstacle of the capitalist system exists exclusively on the condition that subjects, whether consciously or unconsciously, "internally" believe in it--capitalism's life-blood, money, is simply a fetishistic crystallization of a belief in others' belief in the socio-performative force emanating from this same material. And yet, this point of capitalism's frail vulnerability is simultaneously the source of its enormous strength: its vampiric symbiosis with individual human desire, and the fact that the late-capitalist cynic's fetishism enables the disavowal of his/her de facto belief in capitalism, makes it highly unlikely that people can simply be persuaded to stop believing and start thinking (especially since, as Zizek claims, many of these people are convinced that they already have ceased believing). Or, the more disquieting possibility to entertain is that some people today, even if one succeeds in exposing them to the underlying logic of their position, might respond in a manner resembling that of the Judas-like character Cypher in the film The Matrix (Cypher opts to embrace enslavement by illusion rather than cope with the discomfort of dwelling in the "desert of the real"): faced with the choice between living the capitalist lie or wrestling with certain unpleasant truths, many individuals might very well deliberately decide to accept what they know full well to be a false pseudo-reality, a deceptively comforting fiction ("Capitalist commodity fetishism or the truth? I choose fetishism"). Talking About the Other Their abstract descriptions of others that we need to save are a product of capitalistabstraction that lets us ignore the most proximate and allow suffering to continue. Zizek ‘2 Slavoj Zizek, Professor of Sociology at the Institute for Sociology, Ljubljana University, 2002, Revolution at the Gates, p. 205-07 Atom Egoyan’s film Exotica tackles the fragile status of the frontier that separates public from private space. When we share a common space with outsiders — say, when a delivery man or a repair man enters our apartment — we politely ignore each other, refraining from probing into the other’s privacy (what do they desire, what are their secret dreams?); Exotica, however, constantly violates this frontier, suddenly establishing a more intimate contact between two people brought together by some official duty. The Lacanian big Other is, among other things, one of the names for this Wall which enables us to maintain the proper distance, guaranteeing that the other’s proximity will not overwhelm us — when we talk with a clerk, we “do not get personal”. (The paradox is that this very Wall is not just negative: at the same time, it generates fantasies about what lurks behind it, about what the other really desires.70) Our late capitalist daily life involves an unprecedented disavowal of the other’s experience: In order to pass a homeless person crouched in a doorway and keep walking, in order to enjoy dinner when children are hungry, in order to rest at night when suffering is incessant — atomized daily function demands that we systematically foreclose our affections for and connections with others (in the words of dominant culture, our economy is comprised of individuals who respect each other’s individuality). Behind the caricature of the bleeding-heart liberal is the truth of politics: how you feel is how you act.71 Here we are dealing not with individual psychology, but with capitalist subjectivity as a form of abstraction inscribed in and determined by the very nexus of “objective” social relations: Indifference towards specific labours corresponds to a form of society in which individuals can with ease transfer from one labour to another, and where the specific kind is a matter of chance for them, hence of indifference. Not only the category, labour, but labour in reality has here become the means of creating wealth in general, and has ceased to be organically linked with particular individuals in any specific form. Such a state of affairs is at its most developed in the most modern form of existence of bourgeois society, in the United States. Here, then, for the first time, the point of departure of modern economics, namely the abstraction of the category “labour”, “labour as such”, labour pure and simple, becomes true in practice.72 So, just as Marx described how, within the market economy, abstraction is inscribed into individual experience itself (a worker directly experiences his particular profession as a contingent actualization of his abstract capacity to work, not as an organic component of his personality; an “alienated” lover experiences his sexual partner as a contingent fill-in that satisfied his need for sexual and/or emotional gratification; etc.), abstraction is also inscribed into the way we relate to others at the most immediate level: we ignore them in the fundamental sense of the word, reducing them to bearers of abstract social functions. And the point here, of course, is that “systems of power necessitate specific emotional configurations”: the fundamental “coldness” of the late capitalist subject is supplanted/concealed by the phantom of a rich private emotional life which serves as a fantasy-screen protecting us from the shattering experience of the Real of other people’s suffering. Today, the old joke about a rich man telling his servant “Throw out this destitute beggar — I’m so sensitive that I can’t stand seeing people suffer!” is more appropriate than ever. The necessary price of this abstraction is that the very sphere of privacy gets “reified”, turned into a domain of calculated satisfactions: is there anything more depressingly anti-erotic than the proverbial appeal of a yuppie to his partner: “Let’s spend some quality time together!”? No wonder, then, that the obverse of this distance are brutal and humiliating intrusions into the other’s intimate space: from confessionary talk-shows to cam-websites where we can observe other people defecating from the bottom of the toilet bowl. AT---Gibson Graham Their epistemology is incoherent—we have to make strong truth claims to change anything Castree ’99 N. Castree, Professor of Geography, 1999 [Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, June 1999] Capitalism (as we knew it) arguably suffers from serious epistemological, ontological and theoretical problems. The epistemological problems are threefold. First, while Gibson-Graham is right to stress the performativity of representation, she hades towards what Bhaskar (1989, 127) calls the ‘epistemic fallacy’, in which knowledge and the world are conflated. Secondly, this links to a distinct and paradoxical reticence to make truth claims about the world. This reticence arguably stems from the dual theoretical inspiration for Gibson-Graham’s ideas – Resnick and Wolff’s ‘overdeterminist Marxism’ and Derridean deconstruction – both of which, in very different ways, see knowledge as non-mimetic. This reticence is paradoxical, since GibsonGraham does, of course, argue for an economic ‘reality’ in which capitalism and class look quite different to how we previously saw them. Thirdly, all this neglects that fact that, in certain circumstances, making strong claims to ‘truth’ is strategically and practically necessary and important. These epistemological issues feed into several ontological complaints about Gibson-Graham’s position. First, after Resnick andWolff (1987), she is right that capitalism does not exist in isolation but is ‘overdetermined’ by all other elements of social life.21 However, this fact does not preclude attempts to specify theoretically the ‘essential’ characteristics of capitalism and class even though, in practice, they do not exist in a ‘pure’ state (Albritton 1993). Second, in the absence of such specification, social analysis declines into a flabby pluralism or explanatory ‘everythingism’. Third, in this respect Gibson-Graham’s charter for a small c capitalism and a pluralized class category, while appealing, is much too general and inchoate to be serviceable as an explanatory political economic analysis. This leads, finally, to the main theoretical – and arguably most worrying – problem with The end of capitalism. In her concern to deconstruct Marxism, Capitalism and Class, we are left with no effort of reconstruction beyond the otherwise important point that all three miss out a great deal. What, if anything, can usefully be salvaged from Marx’s political economy – with its categories of use and exchange value, concrete and abstract labour, labour power and surplus value – remains a mystery. Though I quite appreciate that the intent of The end of capitalism is not to rebuild Marxism, I would suggest that leaving things at the level of deconstruction is nonetheless unsatisfactory. Notwithstanding the validity of parts of Gibson- Graham’s critique, Marx’s abstract account of capitalism does not necessarily feature in an overblown vision of an no-longer-credible totality. There are other alternatives.22 Gibson-Graham concede that capitalist globalization forces specific identities and subjectivities upon people and that their alternative isn’t possible without the creation of non-capitalist subjects Gibson-Graham ‘2 J.K. Gibson-Graham, the pen name of Katherine Gibson, Senior Fellow of Human Geography at Australian National University, and Julie Graham, professor of Geography at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst, 2002, online: http://www.communityeconomies.org/papers/rethink/rethinkp3.rtf, accessed December 26, 2004 We are enticed to think not about how the world is subjected to globalization (and the global capitalist economy) but how we are subjected to the discourse of globalization and the identities (and narratives) it dictates for us . In The End of Capitalism (as we knew it), we gained insight into how economic subjects might be subjected within globalization discourse by examining the work of Sharon Marcus on rape. Marcus (1992) points to the important role of language, narrative, and discursive constructions of sexual identity in circumscribing women’s ability to act powerfully during the rape event. This resonated for us with the limited options for economic identity and power offered to local subjects by a capitalocentric discourse of globalization.14 We likened freeing ourselves from the discourse of globalization to women shaking away their embodied self-understanding as always already It seems to us that a politics of the local (an anti-globalization politics that is not simply “grassroots go nowhere without subjects who can experience themselves as free from capitalist globalization. Our project of revaluing the local as a site of politics is not about “liberation” from subjection as such, but about creating new discourses that subject in different ways, thus enabling subjects to assume power in new forms.15 Liberating the subject victimized within the discourse of rape. globalization”) will from the economic identities provided by the discourse of globalization requires creating alternative economic identities that subjects can take on (Gibson-Graham, 1994). Ultimately, then, the political project is one of resubjectivation, a process that is both prior to, and concomitant with, the building of alternative economic institutions and practices. Our strategies for resubjectivation involve two major steps. The first involves creating a discourse of the diverse economy, where non-capitalist activities are visible and viable in the economic terrain. The second engages in the micropolitics of enabling subjects to inhabit that terrain— taking on novel economic identities within a diverse economy and assuming the powers these new identities bestow. AT---Perm Perm’s co-opted—causes extinction—the alt alone is key to revolutionary agency Parr ’13 Adrian Parr, The Wrath of Capital, 2013, p. 2-5 The fable provides an intriguing persp ective on freedom and autonomy. The golem has no freedom: it is the rabbi who brings it to life and sentences it to death. Yet by returning the creature to earth, the rabbi holds the golem accountable for the destruction it wrought despite not being free. This is the basic premis e of this book. We are not free, yet we are autonomous. We are constrained by the historical circumstances into which we are born, along with the institutions and structures that contain us. Nonetheless, each and every one of us also participates in and thereby confirms the legitimacy of those selfsame institutions and structures that dominate us, along with the violence they sustain.3 In this way, we are both the rabbi creator and the creature creation. Insofar as we are socially constituted, we are constrained by the historical and institutional forces that construct us. As political agents, we realize our autonomy as we interrupt and contest the historical and institutional conditions that regulate and organize the frames of reference through which we think and act. This structure of rupture and continuity is the modern narrative par excellence. Fredric Jameson neatly summarizes the narrative condition of modernity as the dialectic between the modality of rupture that inaugurates a new period and the definition of that new period in turn by continuity.4 The ironical outcome, as I describe it in the pages that follow, is that despite the narrative category driving change in the modern world, everything continues to stay the same-perhaps because what this narrative produces is a virulent strain of amnesia. Every change or historical rupture contains within it the dialectical narrative structure of modernity such that the New and the period it launches into existence are mere ritual. What persists is the condition of violence embedded in neoliberal capitalism as it robs each and every one of us (other species and ecosystems included) of a future. The narrative of modernity and the optimistic feeling of newness it generates are merely a distraction. Distractions such as decarbonizing the freemarket economy, buying carbon offsets, handing out contraceptives to poor women in developing countries, drinking tap water in place of bottled water, changing personal eating habits, installing green roofs on city hall, and expressing moral outrage at British Petroleum (BP) for the oil spill in the Gulf of Mexico, although well meaning, are merely symptomatic of the uselessness of free-market "solutions" to environmental change. Indeed, such widespread distraction leads to denial. With the proclamation of the twenty- first century to be the era of climate change, the Trojan horse of neoliberal restructuring entered the political arena of climate change talks and policy, and a more virulent strain of capital accumulation began . For this reason, delegates from the African nations, with the support of the Group of 77 (developing countries), walked out of the 2009 United Nations (UN) climate talks in Copenhagen, accusing rich countries of dragging their heels on reducing greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions and destroying the mechanism through which this reduction can be achieved-the Ky oto Protocol. In the absence of an internationally birfding agreement on emissions reductions, all individual actions taken to reduce emissions-a flat global carbon tax, recycling, hyb rid cars, carbon offsets, a few solar panels here and there, and so on-are mere theatrics. In this book, I argue that underpinning the massive environmental changes happening around the world, of which climate change is an important factor, is an unchanging socioeconomic condition (neoliberal capitalism), and the magnitude of this situation is that of a political crisis. So, at the risk of extending my literary license too far, it is fair to say that the human race is currently in the middle of an earth-shattering historical moment. Glaciers in the Himalayas, Andes, Rockies, and Alps are receding. The social impact of environmental change is now acute, with the International Organization for Migration predicting there will be approximately two hundred million environmental refugees by 2050, with estimates expecting as many as up to one billion.5 We are poised between needing to radically transform how we live and becoming extinct. Modern (postindustrial) society inaugurated what geologists refer to as the ''Anthropocene age;' when human activities began to drive environmental change, replacing the Holocene, which for the previous ten thousand years was the era when the earth regulated the environment. 6 Since then people have been pumping GHGs into the atmosphere at a faster rate than the earth can reabsorb them. If we remain on our current course of global GHG emissions, the earth's average climate will rise 3°C by the end of the twenty-first century (with a 2 to 4.5° probable range of uncertainty) . The warmer the world gets, the less effectively the earth's biological systems can absorb carbon. The more the earth's climate heats up, the more carbon dioxide (C02) plants and soils will release; this fe edback loop will further increase climate heating. When carbon feedback is factored into the climate equation, climate models predict that the rise in average climate temperature will be 6°C by 2100 (with a 4 to 8°C probable range of uncertainty) .7 For this reason, even if emissions were reduced from now on by approximately 3 percent annually, there is only a fifty-fifty chance that we can stay within the 2°C benchmark set by the UN Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) in 2007. However, given that in 2010 the world's annual growth rate of atmospheric carbon was the largest in a decade, bringing the world's C02 concentrations to 389.6 parts per million (ppm) and pushing concentrations to 39 percent higher than what they were in 1750 at the beginning of the Industrial Revolution (approximately 278 ppm), and that there is no sign of growth slowing, then even the fifty-fifty window of opportunity not to exceed 2°C warming is quickly closing. If we continue at the current rate of GHG emissions growth, we will be on course for a devastating scenario.8 We need to change course now.9 Climate change poses several environmental problems, many of which now have a clear focus. The scientific problem: How can the high amounts of C02 in the atmosphere causing the earth's climate to change be lowered to 350 ppm? The economic problem: How can the economy be decarbonized while addressing global economic disparities? The social problem: How can human societies change their climate-altering behaviors and adapt to changes in climate?10 The cultural problem: How can commodity culture be reigned in? The problem policymakers face: What regulations can be introduced to inhibit environmental degradation, promote GHG reductions, and assist the people, species, and ecosystems most vulnerable to environmental change? The political problem is less clear, however, perhaps because of its philosophical implications. Political philosophy examines how these questions are dealt with and the assumptions upon which they are premised. It studies the myriad ways in which individuals, corporations, the world's leaders, nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), and communities respond to climate change and the larger issue of environmental change characteristic of the Anthropocene age. philosophy considers how these responses reinforce social and economic structures of More important, political power. In light of this consideration, how do we make the dramatic and necessary changes needed to adapt equitably to environmental change without the economically powerful claiming ownership over the collective impetus and goals that this historical juncture presents? By drawing attention to the political problem of equality in the context of environmental change, I need to stress that I am not a market Luddite; rather, I am critical of the neoliberal paradigm of economic activity that advances deregulation, competition, individualism, and privatization, all the while rolling back on social services and producing widespread inequities and uneven patterns of development and social prosperity. I am also not intending to make negotiable the "non-negotiable planetary preconditions that humanity needs to respect in order to avoid the risk of deleterious or even catastrophic environmental change at continental to global scales:'11 Indeed, my argument is that by focusing too much on free-market solutions to the detriment of the world's most vulnerable (the poor, other species, ecosystems, and future generations), we make these preconditions negotiable: the free market is left to negotiate our future for us. Capitalism generates internal contradictions erupting in imperialism, nuclear war, and ecocide Foster ‘5 John Bellamy Foster, professor of sociology at the University of Oregon, "Naked Imperialism," Monthly Review, Vol. 57 No. 4, 2005 From the longer view offered by a historical-materialist critique of capitalism, the direction that would be taken by U.S. imperialism following the fall of the Soviet Union was never in doubt. Capitalism by its very logic is a globally expansive system. The contradiction between its transnational economic aspirations and the fact that politically it remains rooted in particular nation states is insurmountable for the system. Yet, ill-fated attempts by individual states to overcome this contradiction are just as much a part of its fundamental logic. In present world circumstances, when one capitalist state has a virtual monopoly of the means of destruction, the temptation for that state to attempt to seize full-spectrum dominance and to transform itself into the de facto global state governing the world economy is irresistible. As the noted Marxian philosopher István Mészáros observed in Socialism or Barbarism? (2001)—written, significantly, before George W. Bush became president: “[W]hat is at stake today is not the control of a particular part of the planet—no matter how large—putting at a the control of its totality by one hegemonic economic and military superpower, with all means—even the most extreme authoritarian and, if needed, violent military ones—at its disposal.” The unprecedented dangers of this new global disorder are revealed in the twin cataclysms to which the world is heading at present: nuclear proliferation and hence increased chances of the outbreak of nuclear war, and planetary ecological destruction. These are symbolized by the Bush administration’s refusal to disadvantage but still tolerating the independent actions of some rivals, but sign the Comprehensive Test Ban Treaty to limit nuclear weapons development and by its failure to sign the Kyoto Protocol as a first step in controlling global warming. As former U.S. Secretary of Defense (in the Kennedy and Johnson administrations) Robert McNamara stated in an article entitled “Apocalypse Soon” in the May–June 2005 issue of Foreign Policy: “The United States has never endorsed the policy of ‘no first use,’ not during my seven years as secretary or since. We have been and remain prepared to initiate the use of nuclear weapons—by the decision of one person, the president— against either a nuclear or nonnuclear enemy whenever we believe it is in our interest to do so.” The nation with the greatest conventional military force and the willingness to use it unilaterally to enlarge its global power is also the nation with the greatest nuclear force and the readiness to use it whenever it sees fit—setting the whole world on edge. The nation that contributes more to carbon dioxide emissions leading to global warming than any other (representing approximately a quarter of the world’s total) has become the greatest obstacle to addressing global warming and the world’s growing environmental problems—raising the possibility of the collapse of civilization itself if present trends continue. AT---Transition Wars Capitalism will continually appeal to fear of collapse to justify its existence - these rely on a logic that is epistemologically disabling and self-fulfilling Zizek ’97 Slavoj Zizek, Senior Researcher in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Ljubljana and Codirector of the Center for Humanities at Birkbeck College, "Multiculturalism, or, the Cultural Logic of Multinational Capitalism," New Left Review, No. 224, 1997, pp.25-27 Today, financial crisis is a permanent state of things the reference to which legitimizes the demands to cut social spending, health care, support of culture and scientific research, in short, the dismantling of the welfare state. Is, however, this permanent crisis really an objective feature of our socio-economic life? Is it not rather one of the effects of the shift of balance in the ‘class struggle’ towards Capital, resulting from the growing role of new technologies as well as from the direct internationalization of Capital and the co- dependent diminished role of the Nation-State which was further able to impose certain minimal requirements and limitations to exploitation? In other words, the crisis is an ‘objective fact’ if and only if one accepts in advance as an unquestionable premise the inherent logic of Capital—as more and more left-wing or liberal parties have done. We are thus witnessing the uncanny spectacle of social-democratic parties which came to power with the between-the-lines message to Capital ‘we will do the necessary job for you in an even more efficient and painless way than the conservatives’. The problem, of course, is that, in today’s global socio-political circumstances, it is practically impossible effectively to call into question the logic of Capital: even a modest social-democratic attempt to redistribute wealth beyond the limit acceptable to the Capital ‘effectively’ leads to economic crisis, inflation, a fall in revenues and so on. Nevertheless, one should always bear in mind how the connection between ‘cause’ (rising social expenditure) and ‘effect’ (economic crisis) is not a direct objective causal one: it is always-already embedded in a situation of social antagonism [MARKED] and struggle. The fact that, if one does not obey the limits set by Capital, a crisis ‘really follows’, in no way ‘proves’ that the necessity of these limits is an objective necessity of economic life. It should rather be conceived as a proof of the privileged position Capital holds in the economic and political struggle, as in the situation where a stronger partner threatens that if you do X, you will be punished by Y, and then, upon your doing X, Y effectively ensues.