2AC FW Our affirmative approach as a foundational criticism is necessary to resolve the structural antagonisms that formulate law – even the most progressive left legal reforms recreate those problems and attempt to disentangle the complexities of gender issues – your framework results in serial policy failure – Our aff is a prerequisite Wendy Brown & Janet Halley, 2002 (Left Legalism/Left Critique, Wendy Brown is First Professor of Political Science at the University of California, Berkeley, where she is also affiliated with the Department of Rhetoric, and where she is a core faculty member in the Designated Emphasis in Critical Theory. Janet Halley is the Royall Professor of Law at Harvard Law School. p. 18-25 // JED) Left legalistic projects, entwined as they are with the regulatory tugs of liberalism and legalism, are going to produce unintended consequences. We want a critical theoretical engagement with left legalism in part because we want to apprehend these side effects. To see and to evaluate them, we need to step back from our legalism, to open up the space for politics that can put legalism under a viewfinder, and to examine both politics and legalism with the attitude of critique. Legalism's Political Outside Is there such a thing as nonlegalistic political practice, a politics even a few degrees outside legalism, especially if legalism is not defined simply in reference to the state and law, but no less institutionally codified practices and So saturated by legalism is contemporary political life that it is often difficult to imagine alternative ways of deliberating about and pursuing justice. Yet the legal realist point that law is politics by other means should not commit us to its converse: that all endeavors to shape and order collective Iife are legalistic. Legalism not only carries a politics (and liberal legalism carries a very specific politics) but also incessantly translates wide-ranging political questions into more narrowly framed legal questions. Thus politics conceived and practiced legalistically bears a certain hostility to discursively open-ended, multigenre, and polyvocal political conversations about how we should live, what we should value and what we should prohibit, and what is possible in collective life. The preemptive conversion of political questions into legal questions can displace open-ended discursive contestation: adversarial and yes/no structures can quash exploration; expert and specialized languages can preclude democratic participation; a pretense that deontological grounds can and must always be found masks the historical embeddedness of many political questions; the covertness of norms and political power within legal spaces repeatedly divests political questions of their most crucial concerns. When the available range of legal remedies preempts exploration of the deep constitutive causes of an injury (think hate speech and the racial order that makes it sting), when the question of which rights pertain overrides attention to what occasions the urgently felt need for the right (think abortion and the way reproductive work is organized, valued and [un]remunerated in maledominant orders), we sacrifice our chance to be deliberative, inventive political beings who create our collective life form. Legalism that draws its parameters of justice from liberalism imposes its own standards of fairness when we might need a public argument about what constitutes fairness; its formulas for equality when we may need to reconsider all the powers that must be negotiated in the making of an egalitarian order; its definitions of liberty at the price of an exploratory argument about the constituent elements of freedom. As we incessantly refer our political life to the law, we not only sacrifice opportunities to take our inherited political condition into our own hands, we sacrifice as well the chance to address at a more fundamental or at least far-reaching level various troubling conditions which appear to require redress. Consider: What if some of the disturbing aspects of contemporary sex harassment doctrine, in which redress of gender subordination has been increasingly usurped by greater sexual regulation, can be traced to a certain failure on the part of second-wave feminism actually to effect a significant transformation in the social construction of women and men, a project that was once deeply constitutive of that political and cultural enterprise? And what if the tendency toward ever more intensive legal effects? regulation of gender and sexuality is a compensatory response to that failure, a response that effectively gives up on the project of transforming gender in favor of protecting a historically subordinated group from some of the most severe effects of that subordination, even as it tacitly defines women through those effects? If feminism once aimed to make women the sexual equals of men, this aim entails the complex social, psychological, and political project of making gender differently, and not simply the legal one of protecting (historically and culturally produced) vulnerable women from (historically and culturally produced) rapacious men. Indeed, the legal project, in its instantiation of sexuality as subordinating, especially of women, may be substantially at odds with the political project of fashioning women as men's substantive equals, that is, as people who cannot be "reduced to their gender" through an unwanted sexualizing gesture or word. This is not to argue that there is some pure left political space independent of legalism, nor that left political projects implicated in legalism inevitably sacrifice their aims and values. Rather, it is to assert the possibility of political life and political projects not fully saturated by legalistic constraints and aims. It is to recover radically democratic political aims from legalism's grip in order to cultivate collective political and cultural deliberation about governing values and practices. We remember a mode of activism among antipornography feminists that was more political than legalistic. Women walked into porn shops and trashed the pornography, shamed the customers, and mock-shamed themselves. They also led tours through the porn districts, offering feminist interpretations of pornographic representations and marketing of women, interpretations which others could and sometimes did argue with. The antiporn activists worked in the name of feminism, and though all feminists did not condone the stance toward porn and the depiction of women that this activism represented, our dissension itself was not monolithic or fully codified. This mode of antiporn activism thus provoked argument and reflection among and across feminists and nonfeminists alike. This political mode presupposed an interlocutory relationship between those who valued pornography and those who condemned it, indeed between porn and its consumers or audiences. In that interlocutory relationship, many women encountered and studied pornography for the first time. As this occurred, women found themselves having all kinds of responses to porn that could not simply be classified as for or against: some were distressed by it but grasped their distress as an index of the sexual shame their gender construction entailed; others were drawn to it and flatly delighted to be let into a sexual order previously designated for men; others were more ambivalent, liking the idea of porn or liking bits of it but troubled or turned off by the misogynistic (or racist or colonial) strains in it (some were confusingly turned on by these very same strains); still others were inspired to try to make good porn for women. What was the political cache of this rich array of responses? It produced a wave old new feminist work on sexuality: new questions, new theories, new domains of research, new practices, new arguments, new positions in every sense of the word. Hence followed as well new possibilities of alliances with gay men as well as new forms of alliance across a presumed heterosexual-homosexual divide, the possibility of queer thought, and the invention of new sexual subjectivities and identities through a proliferation of cultural discourses of and cultural struggles over sexuality. "Feminism" so constituted was a field of widely divergent values, beliefs, and practices, all of which had to contest with one another over the question of "the good" for women. Compare this marvelously fertile political contestation and intellectual exploration with the social and ideological concomitants of antipornography activists' turn to the state. Antipornography activism took a legalistic turn with the invention of a tort claim for damages arising from the injury to women's sexual status supposedly inflicted by pornography (rights legalism) and the deployment of zoning ordinances to shut down the public space devoted to sex commerce (governance the politics of sexuality in feminism and feminist communities, and the form of feminist internal critique, changed dramatically. Defining porn narrowly (and badly) as "the graphic sexual subordination of women," the legalists promulgated local ordinances establishing porn as a violation of women's civil rights. This move brought into play local governments and judges as authoritative decision makers. And the arguments that could then be addressed to those decision makers were as flat and impoverished as the arguments characteristic of the political struggle were multidimensional and rich: to participate in the legalistic moment, feminists had to declare themselves for or against porn, and even for or against sex, as they took a position on the ordinances.4 The debate about porn became framed by the terms of free speech, censorship, and privacy rights. In short, it became consolidated by a narrow rights framework: Should your right not to be violated/offended trump my right to consume what I want? Does Larry Flynt's free speech silence Catharine MacKinnon's? In this consolidation, all the complexities of sexual representation, of the imbrication of sexuality and gender, of the relation of fantasy to reality, and above all, of the extraordinary and detailed range in the sexual construction and desires of women and men were eclipsed. The adversarial structure of rights legalism as deployed by all the parties meant that the stakes legalism). Wherever feminists took this turn, were now "winner takes all." In that context neither side could risk nuance, internal dissension, or differentiation of positions along a continuum. Hence the debates produced a new form of internal silencing of each side's constituents; solidarity and a united front became mandatory. Above all, neither side could afford to break with liberalism (a notoriously impoverished discourse on the subject of sexuality) in its arguments: the terms of the new debate were set not only by established definitions of equality, civil rights, and free speech, but by flat and monolithic conceptions of gender, women, sexuality, and representation. And this debate, desiccated because it adopted rather than contested the terms of liberal legalism, was the form in which the feminist question about open-ended political contestation in unbounded spaces and unregulated by settled rules of engagement can be an arena for raw aggressions and un-self-knowing posturing of the most grandiose sort. Thus, in the political struggle, women pornography hit the mainstream. To be sure, the porn wars in their political mode had their brutal and punitive dimensions; accused each other of false consciousness, mocked each other's sexual desires, set themselves up as sexually righteous, and denounced each other viciously for their positions in these battles. But the political mode had several virtues that the legalistic mode distinctively lacked: it was open-ended in the questioning and conversations it incited; it was accessible to a wide variety of participants (and was probably the most interracial, cross-class, and intersexual political moment second-wave feminism had); and it occurred in a range of different idioms, from analytic position papers to poetry to biography. Perhaps most important, because the arguments were about sex, gender, and representation rather than free speech, censorship, and civil rights, the political mode incited a substantial body of rich new political, cultural, and psychological inquiry and political understandings that were both valuable in themselves and gave new life to the social movements that bred them. Deliberation is a fallacy – framework uses masculine claims of rationality to determine what knowledge is legitimate for public debate pushing unproductive knowledge to the private sphere – We must interrogate the façade of a neutral stasis point of political and academic argument Tomlinson, 10 [Barbara, “Feminism and Affect at the scene of argument”, Ch 1 – transforming the terms of reading] Contemporary U.S. political and academic discourse abounds with a recurring set of formulaic claims that feminist scholars (and feminists in general) are angry, unreasoning, shrill, humorless, ugly, man- hating, perverse, and peculiar. This “trope of the angry feminist” is designed to delegitimize feminist argument even before the argument begins, to undermine feminist politics by making its costs personal, and to foreclose feminist futures by making feminism seem repulsive to young women. The trope is a convention, a plot trick, a setup, a narrative structure, a character type. 2 Its incessant repetition constitutes part of a cultural training program that makes antifeminism and misogyny a routine element in everyday speech and written argument. Instigated by expressly po liti calopposition to feminism, deploying affectively charged strategies that float free of evidence, clichés like the angry feminist put animosity— not argument— at the center of politi cal discussions, interpellating readers as always already antifeminist. The repetition and circulation of such tropes produces a cumulative overdetermined quality that makes them seem already true before the moment of argument. One never encounters the feminist’s argument for the first time because it comes already discredited. Because the trope of the angry feminist encourages unacknowledged ways of interpreting feminist affect, its inveterate irruption is consequential in journalism, entertainment, po liti cal, and quasi- intellectual arenas, as I describe in this introductory chapter. It is perhaps even more consequential in its influence on academic discourses, the subject of the remainder of the book: affect in academic discourses on social justice is often policed through “ideologies of style” that purport to be neutral but operate to entrench current conditions of power. In this book I argue that we have failed to theorize adequately the role of such pervasive affective and ideologically encapsulated arguments in academic and political discourses. In consequence, we do not recognize that our conventional reading practices mislead us about ways to comprehend and counter them. I argue that transforming the terms of reading can reframe the problem, and propose for that purpose a critical toolkit that I call “feminist socioforensic discursive analysis.” My argument here constitutes a provocation to transform the terms of reading, to reframe interpretation of affect in both feminist and antifeminist writing. Th e trope of the angry feminist is a familiar conceit, like many similar phrases deployed to delegitimize social criticism, one that draws on a deep well of related clichés, affective rhetorical strategies, and familiar tropes. Th ese discursive moves circulate as instantiations of power. Th e trope of the angry feminist presents itself as fresh each time it is uttered, its repetitious banality framed as mere reflection of the repetitious banality of the feminist’s argument. Th is leads to the absurd but po liti cally effi cacious situation where readers are weary of arguments they have never heard. These argumentative tactics often succeed in part because our normal reading and writing practices lead us to object or counterargue in ways that fail to come to grips with the specific nature of the rhetorical situation that the tropes instantiate. Our conventional reading practices reinscribe ways of thinking that seem “logical” or “fair” because they are so familiar; they lead us to treat the tropes as surface features of discourse that serve to “skew” debate from its direct and proper form. These conventional practices, permeated by unacknowledged power relations, encourage us to respond to the tropes “normatively,” with reproaches about textual etiquette, textual responsibility, or textual appropriateness, to complain about inadequate evidence, to provide counterexamples, or to condemn the person proffering the trope, as though its use violates an agreement about the proper nature of civic discussion, and as if there is a mechanism of accountability. None of this is the case. Responses that might chastise, correct, or even complain about the trope of the angry feminist are inadequate in part because they rest, ultimately, on an imaginary ideal: a Framing political and even academic discussion in this commonsense way treats rhetoric as a neutral technology to be deployed or evaluated in isolation from its conditions of production, the situations of speakers, or the general societal power relations that give utterances friendly to prevailing power relations an overdetermined “reasonableness” while rendering most oppositional arguments automatically suspect. Our reading practices already rest on uninterrogated and deeply gendered and racialized models of textuality, argument, authorship, politeness, and emotion. Under such conditions, affect is a potent tool of dominance, infusing the reading discursive arena regulated by impartial principles in which utterances are adjudicated by unbiased observers. situation to teach us what power is, who has it, how to get it, how to be rewarded, and how to avoid the punishments power can deliver. Louis Althusser (1971) argues that concrete individuals become constituted as “subjects” through ideology, but the most powerful ideological influences do not come to us in the form of ideological pronouncements. Th at would make them visible, controversial, and refutable. Instead, he argues, the most powerful ideologies exist in “apparatuses,” in practices, and these practices are always material. Reading, writing, and argument are social practices sedimented with ideologies of legitimacy, propriety and fairness so powerful and pervasive that we presuppose their value rather than examining their effects. 2AC Neolib 2AC They are in a double bind - if they do not think the body is material – that’s a DA to the alt – they erase the ways bodily difference and experiences result in violence towards prostitution. OR, the body is material, which makes it a necessary component of Historical Materialism; ONLY the perm can solve. Coole and Frost 2010 – Dr. Diane Coole is a Professor of Political and Social Theory in the School of Politics and Sociology at the University of London. Dr. Samantha Frost is a Professor of Political Science at the University of Illinois at Urbana – Champaign. 2010 New Materialisms Ontology) Agency) and Politics DUKE UNIVERSITY PRESS Durham & London For new materialists, no adequate political theory can ignore the importance of bodies in situating empirical actors within a material environment of nature, other bodies, and the socioeconomic structures that dictate where and how they find sustenance, satisfy their desires, or obtain the resources necessary for participating in political life. This is in fact something that feminists and class theorists have often insisted upon, and we would add in this context only our concern that such material dimensions have recently been marginalized by fashionable constructivist approaches and identity politics. Of course, the latter have had a good deal to say about the body and its imbrication in relationships of power, but we are not convinced that they pay sufficient attention to the material efficacy of bodies or have the theoretical resources to do so. From this perspective we draw attention to a new materialist predilection for a more phenomenological approach to embodiment. In addition to focusing on the way power constitutes and is reproduced by bodies, phenomenological studies emphasize the active, self-transformative, practical aspects of corporeality as it participates in relationships of power. They find bodies exhibiting agentic capacities in the way they structure or stylize their perceptual milieu, where they discover, organize, and respond to patterns that are corporeally significant. Such theories thus introduce elements of creative contingency, meaning, difference, efficacy, and a limited freedom for improvisation or resistance into nature before cognition begins. In other words, they complement ontologies of immanently productive matter by describing how living matter structures natural and social worlds before (and while) they are encountered by rational actors. Again, they give materiality its due. This emphasis on corporeality further dislocates agency as the property of a discrete, self-knowing subject in as much as the corpus is now recognized as exhibiting capacities that have significant effects on social and political situations. Thus bodies communicate with other bodies through their gestures and conduct to arouse visceral responses and prompt forms of judgment that do not necessarily pass through conscious awareness. They are significant players in games of power whenever face-to-face encounters are involved, such as in deliberative models of democracy. Paying attention to corporeality as a practical and efficacious series of emergent capacities thus reveals both the materiality of agency and agentic properties inherent in nature itself.29 Both have important implications for the way we understand political processes. In this emphasis on corporeality, we also glimpse one of the most distinctive characteristics of the new materialist ontologies: their avowed posthumanism. They displace what Giorgio Agamben calls "the anthropological machine of humanism."3o While new materialists' conceptualization of materialization is not anthropocentric, it does not even privilege human bodies. There is increasing agreement here that all bodies, including those of animals (and perhaps certain machines, too), evince certain capacities for agency. As a consequence, the human species, and the qualities of self-reflection, self-awareness, and rationality traditionally used to distinguish it from the rest of nature, may now seem little more than contingent and provisional forms or processes within a broader evolutionary or cosmic productivity. If human perfection or redemption is no longer understood as the destiny of history, neither is it the goal of evolution. While it does not follow that cognitive capacities for symbolism or reflexivity are no longer valued, the new materialism does prompt away of reconsidering them as diffuse, chance products of a self-generative nature from which they never entirely emerge. Marxism operates from a starting point that ignores sexual difference and footnotes any feminist struggle Hartmann, 2006 - Heidi Hartmann is a feminist economist and the founder of the Institute for Women's Policy Research, a scientific research organization formed to meet the need for women-centered, public policy research, The Unhappy Marriage of Marxism and Feminism: Towards a More Progressive Union, HEIDI I. HARTMANN, United States 1945- . Economist. Founding Director of the Institute for Women's Policy Research (1987). Capitalism and Women's Work in the Home, 1900-1930 (1976), Women's Work, Aden's Work: Sex Segregation on the Job (1981), Comparable Worth: New Directions for Research (1985), Women, Work, and Poverty: Woman-Centered Research for Policy Change (2006). The "marriage" of marxism and feminism has been like the marriage husband and wife depicted in English common law: marxism and feminism are one, and that one is Marxism. Recent attempts to integrate marxism and feminism are unsatisfactory to us as feminists because they subsume the feminist struggle into the "larger" struggle against capital. To continue our simile further, either we need a healthier marriage or we need a divorce. The inequalities in this marriage, like most social phenomena, are no accident. Many marxists typically argue that feminism is at best less important than class conflict and at worst divisive of the working class. This political stance produces an analysis that absorbs feminism into the class struggle. Moreover, the analytic power of marxism with respect to capital has obscured its limitations with respect to sexism. We will argue here that while marxist analysis provides essential insight into the laws of historical development, and those of capital in particular, the categories of marxism are sex-blind. Only a specifically feminist analysis reveals the systemic character of relations between men and women. Yet feminist analysis by itself is inadequate because it has been blind to history and insufficiency materialist. Both Marxist analysis, particularly its historical and materialist method, and feminist analysis, especially the identification of patriarchy as a social and historical structure, must be drawn upon if we are to understand the development of western capitalist societies and the predicament of women within them. In this essay we suggest a new direction for marxist feminist analysis. I MARXISM AND THE WOMAN QUESTION The woman question has never been the "feminist question." The feminist question is directed at the causes of sexual inequality between women and men, of male dominance over women. Most marxist analyses of women's position take as their question the relationship of women to the economic system, rather than that of women to men, apparently assuming the latter will be explained in their discussion of the former. Marxist analysis of the woman question has taken three main forms. All see women's oppression .in our connection (or lack of it) to production, Defining women as part of the working class, these analyses consistently subsume women's relation to men under worker's relation to capital. First, early marxists, including Marx, Engels, Kautsky, and Lenin, saw capitalism drawing, all women into the wage labor force, and saw this process destroying the sexual division, of labor. Second, contemporary marxists have incorporated, women into an analysis of evervdav life in capitalism. In this view, all aspects of our lives are seen to reproduce the capitalist system and we are all workers in the system. And third,, marxist feminists have focused on housework and its relation to capital, some arguing that housework produces surplus value and that houseworkers work directly for capitalists. . . . While the approach of the early marxists ignored housework and stressed women's labor force participation, the two more recent approaches emphasize housework to such an extent they ignore women's current role in the labor market. Nevertheless, all three attempt to include women in the category working class and to understand women's oppression as another aspect of class oppression. In doing so all give short shrift to the object of feminist analysis, the relations between women and men. While our "problems" have been elegantly analyzed, they have been misunderstood. The focus of Marxist analysis has been class relations; the object of marxist analysis has been understanding the laws of motion of capitalist society. While we believe marxist methodology can be used to formulate feminist strategy, these marxist feminist approaches discussed above clearly do not do so; their marxism clearly dominates their feminism. Marxism enables us to understand many aspects of capitalist societies: the structure of production, the generation of a particular occupational structure, and the nature of the dominant ideology. Marx's theory of the development of capitalism is a theory of the development of "empty places." Marx predicted, for example, the growth of the proletariat and the demise of the petit bourgeoisie. More precisely and in more detail, Braverman among others has explained the creation of the "places" clerical worker and service worker in advanced capitalist societies.2 Just as capital creates these places indifferent to the individuals who fill them, the categories of marxist analysis, class, reserve army of labor, wage laborer, do not explain why particular people, fill particular places. They give no clues about why women are subordinate to men inside and outside the family and why it is not the other way around. Marxist categories, like capital itself, are sex-blind. The categories of Marxism cannot tell us who will fill the empty places. Marxist analysis of the woman question has suffered from this basic problem.