1 What moves the Intellect: Aristotle on the will (work in progress;please do not quote) Dr. Tolis Malakos Centre for Contemporary Aristotelian Studies in Ethics and Politics(CASEP) London Metropolitan University The concept of the will in different guises has been central to modern moral discourses whereas it is commonly considered to be absent from Aristotle’s ethics. Aristotle is often said to have been unaware of the issue of free will, and this despite his very nuanced and complex theorization of the issues of deliberation, choice and responsibility and will(βούλησις) (in, among other places, book 3 of the NE) as well as his seminal conceptualization of human action in terms of a desiring nous(ορεκτικός νούς) in book 6. Indeed in the light of his discussion of these issues, the claim that he lacks a concept of the will seems paradoxical. This is even more so if one reads the NE in conjunction with the Metaphysics and the De Anima. In particular his discussion in Metaphysics Θ2 and 5 of ‘rational potencies’(δυνάμεις μετά λόγου) and their characterization as “admitting equally of contrary results”1 that is, as being able to bring about both the good they are by nature directed towards and its opposite, seems quite significant and shows that for Aristotle the distinguishing feature of rational beings is that they make a choice between good and bad, i.e. that their actions are contingent. According to Aristotle, whereas irrational, inanimate potencies(άλλογες δυνάμεις) are directed toward their end(good) necessarily and only external forces can obstruct their attaining this end, rational beings strive for their naturally defined good in a contingent way: since they admit of contrary results and since it is impossible to produce contrary effects(both good and bad) at the same time, “there must be another deciding factor, by which I mean desire or conscious choice(όρεξιν ή προαίρεσιν).For whichever of two things a rational being desires and chooses, it will do» 2 1 Metaphysics,Θ2 1046b5-6. 2 Metaphysics Θ5 1048a10-12. 2 The use of ‘desire or choice’ in the first part of the sentence might be an unfortunate use of words, because desire belongs to the non-rational part of the soul and deliberative choice to the rational and the particular expression does not help us in reaching a conclusion but in the second part of the same sentence Aristotle seems to correct himself: desire and choice. Besides desire and conscious choice, here as well as in the NE, Aristotle uses the word βούλησις, a word which has notoriously admitted different translations(wish, rational wish, rational desire), to signify in a lot of cases not just a conscious choice, for which he uses prohairesis, or a desire, for which he uses όρεξις(appetite) or επιθυμία(which is the word for wish), but a deciding, rational will. The main claim of this paper though will bethat Aristotle developed an adequate conceptualization of what we call will, providing a highly innovative, complex and satisfactory account of voluntary action by his novel conceptualization of prohairesis(deliberative choice). Contra Plato he envisaged the rational part of the soul as operating always in conjunction with the non-rational part. A rational being, according to Aristotle in his definition of virtue in Book II of the NE, does not exercise her practical rationality to ‘conquer’ and dominate passions, but to make rational choices always in accordance with a properly educated character which has learned to feel pleasure for the right things and pain for the wrong things.What distinguishes humans according to Aristotle is not only the rational part but also the formative non rational part of the soul which is not by definition the dark, irascible ‘horse’ of Plato’s allegory, but can be trained and learn to develop the virtues of character which enables her to experience pleasure and pain in a way conducive to the good life. If my reading is correct, according to Aristotle it is the whole ‘self’, the partly divided but ultimately unitary soul, and not a mysterious third faculty, which wills a course of action and chooses good or bad by feeling, desiring, deliberating and thinking in conjunction, if not at the same time. Although Aristotle recognizes the independence of these processes, in the very strong sense that one cannot determine and ultimately direct the other, and this is very important, he integrates them within his model of an active soul, a desiring nous that wills to act (βούλεται ποιείν). 3 The ‘dominant’ rational part, according to Aristotle, is not a citadel against non-rational 3 Metaphysics Θ5 1048α22. 3 desires, it cannot eliminate passions, neither conquer nor reform a character that has not learned to be a virtuous character. In other words, an ethically bad character cannot be reformed even by the finest nous, as no combination of ethical virtues or, to use a modern expression, no sheer will power(meaning strength of character) can help a nous lacking the virtue of practical reasoning to overcome this deficiency. The conception of will that dominates moral modern discourses is based on a supposedly autonomous ‘faculty’ of volition which, in its non- Kantian versions, is contrasted to the rational ‘faculty’ which operates on the basis of reasons. Indeed the most significant characteristic of modern conceptions of the will is that, contra Aristotle, they ascribe will either to the rational or to the non-rational part of the soul, albeit by positing a distinct faculty that wills, and in doing so they impoverish human experience which according to Aristotle encompasses both. As A. MacIntyre has claimed both for emotivist moral discourses and for Kierkegardian and Nietzshean understandings of action, “the terminus of justification is thus always … a not further to be justified choice, a choice unguided by criteria.”4 MacIntyre sees modern moral agents as faced with “a criterionless choice for which no rational justification can be given, as they can be offered no reason for preferring one or the other…Even if reasons are offered ..[the moral agent] still has to choose his first principles and just because they are first principles…no more ultimate reasons can be adduced to support them”5 MacIntyre talks about a ‘radical and ultimate choice’(p.40) and ‘a reduction of morality to personal preference’ (p.20).. Whether representing a distinct part of the soul or the whole self, this slightly mysterious but certainly undecipherable in principle, voluntaristic and groundless center of the ‘essence’ of the self, which is capable of leaps both to the dark and to the sublime, is characterized by its ability to command and direct itself as well as paradoxically at times to resist its own commands, if it so wills. We are talking, of course, here about what Henry Frankfurt has called a second order volition, namely a will to will rather than a will to something. 4 5 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, p.20. ibid, p.39-40. 4 In its Kantian guise, on the contrary, willing is equated to reasoning, in the sense that when reasoning about action, an agent does not dwell on her interests and desires, subjecting herself to what Kant calls ‘the causality of nature’, but motivates herself on the basis of ‘subjective principles of volition’(GMM,p.16) called maxims which totally exclude inclinations and desires from the reckoning in a choice. Kant claims that any particular aim or end cannot act upon the will in a way that will confer on it an ‘unconditioned’ and unconditional moral worth. It is only reason which makes a will unconditionally good: “Reason’s true vocation must therefore be not to produce volition as a means to some other aim, but rather to produce a will good in itself.”6 Even reasoning that is in any way particular, in the sense that it takes as its aim any particular end and is directed to the means for its fulfillment, cannot serve as the ground of a good will according to Kant. It is not reasoning as such but a certain type of ‘pure’ reasoning which makes human willing unconditionally good, since Kant is interested from the start for the unconditional good, good which is done not in conformity to ‘goodness’ but for goodness’ own sake. In the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, although not in later works, Kant draws a very sharp opposition between all human acts which take place for the sake of ends which are considered parts of ‘happiness’ and are the effects of inclinations, and good acts which are good for no other reason than goodness itself, and are grounded on “the quality of the good will of being a law to itself”(p.63). For the will to be unconditionally good, it cannot be determined by anything else but its quality to legislate, to become a law unto itself but only if it issues in “unchangeable laws”, which are the distinguishing mark, not of natural causality in which everything is subject to change, but of what Kant calls ‘rational causality’. A rational agent is characterized by definition by the ability to not obey alien causes but legislate onto herself according to maxims which, in order to be changeless and universalizable. Here the famous therefore unconditional, have to be Kantian principle ‘nothing for myself that is not for others’ finds ample justification, since a rational, free being cannot Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Yale University Press, New Haven and London,2002, p.12. 6 5 legislate something for herself unless she legislates the same as valid for all others. Unconditionality has the meaning of unexceptionality for Kant and therefore moral principles cannot be based on “certain alleged experiences of human nature”(p.64),that is, cannot be a posteriori, nor be founded on any particular, substantive law whatsoever, but on ‘lawfulness itself’, on the formal principle of universalizability: “the universal lawfulness of the action in general which alone is to serve the will as its principle, i.e. never to conduct myself except so that I could also will that my maxim become a universal law.”7 Despite the fact that Kant thinks of the will as a specific form of rationality and equates it with practical rationality, a certain form of tension between practical reason which legislates according to universalizable principles and the autonomous will which is a law to itself remains. This is because it is of the essence of free willing to will on a choice, to be open to alternative outcomes and to be non-obligated to anything, even itself. But since Kant equates practical rationality with the free will, only a good will is possible, determined in its outcome by the objective principle of volition, the practical law handed down to it by a formal, a priori type of reasoning whose outcome is unexceptionable and cannot but be always good. As this objective principle of volition is taken up by a will and transformed into a maxim,i.e. a subjective principle of volition, it cannot fail itself but it can fail only externally, because Kant recognizes that human beings are rational beings that, alas, are subject to inclinations and desires. By itself then a Kantian free will cannot be bad and cannot will anything bad, which is never the result of willing but of the fallen human nature. A bad human action cannot be the result of willing for Kant- there can be no failings of the will- but of desiring. In a sense, the huge gulf that Kant envisages between willing and desiring, makes the will as such almost redundant, since what Kant wants to ground is the intersubjective and therefore objective nature of moral discourse, simultaneously rejecting Hume’s conception of morality as causally determined by human nature and the latter’s founding of morality on the subjectivity of passions. By being objective by definition, by being a rational will and a rational will only, however, the will runs the risk of not being free, in the sense of having one 7 ibid p.18. 6 capacity only, to legislate and choose what reason dictates as good. A free will is for Kant by definition a rational will and therefore an unconditionally good will. For him there is no bad will as such, only bad desires and inclinations, of course not in the sense of morally bad but in the sense of humanly bad. Indeed it might be argued that at least in the Groundwork there is no conception of ‘moral badness’, because it is our human nature that sins and our rational will that does good. On the other hand as John Hare among others has pointed out Kant in the later Religion Within the Bounds of Reason Alone provides a richer and more nuanced account of the will: “ The fundamental moral battle as it is presented in Religion..is not between respect for the moral law and respect for the inclinations. Rather it is between the good maxim, which subordinates the inclinations to duty, and the evil maxim which reverses this order of incentives. The good maxim tells us to pursue our own happiness only in as far as this is consistent with our duty. The evil maxim makes our happiness a condition of following the moral law.”8 Unlike the Groundwork in which only the good maxim resides in the will, in this later work Kant insists that “both of these maxims reside in the will, and a fundamental choice has to be made between them”9. But still the evil maxim resides in the desiring part of the self and the good maxim in the rational part. The latter should impose itself on the former. Nevertheless, Kant makes such a conception of will central to his moral theory, even though his argument might ultimately be failing on his radically dualist conception of the human self, which is eternally torn and tortured between rationality and desire. In some respects the modern emphasis on the will, in all its guises, builds upon the Augustinian conception of the will. As A. McIntyre claims in Whose Justice? Which Rationality, “For Augustine intellect itself needs to be moved to activity by will. It is will which guides attention in one direction rather than the other.”10 8 J.E. Hare, Augustine, Kant and the Moral Gap in Gareth B. Mathews(ed.) The Augustinian Tradition, University of California Press, Berkeley,1999, p.254 ibid. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice, Which Rationality, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 1988, p.156. 9 10 7 Augustine seems to claim that the root cause of any action which provides the limit to any inquiry on the causal chain of action is the will itself, i.e. willing is a sui generis, spontaneous capacity which causes itself and functions as an ultimate arbitrator between possible courses of action. In other words, the supposition is that acts of will have no efficient cause other than the will itself,11 and that reasoning on an action is not leading to action unless will consents to it. Up to this point though, Augustine’s conception seems not much different from Aristotle’s conception. However, Augustine conceives of the will as belonging to a distinct, independent faculty that wills and belongs to the superior part of the soul.12 The will is presented as the controlling faculty which when not initiating action, is letting all actions happen since it does not prevent them.13 For Augustine being alive means having a will: “ I knew myself to have a will in the same way that I knew myself to be alive. Therefore when I willed or did not will something I was utterly certain that none other than myself was willing or not willing.”14 But for Augustine the human will is corrupted and not able to resist the improper promptings of the lower inclinations effectively. Augustine conceived passions as spontaneous motions of the lower part of the soul and the will as consenting or dissenting from them. But given the corrupted state of the human will, it is only divine grace that can restore its orientation against evil inclinations: “Can men do anything by the free determination of their own will? Far be it, for it was by the evil use of his free will that man destroyed both it and himself.”15 Augustine thought that we do not sin when we have an evil desire, but when our will consents to it. 16 Although somehow representing the superior rational part of the soul, the will is conceived as an autonomous faculty which wills itself. It seems that for Augustine the will is a phantom, an unmoved mover, which motivates the agent by itself, introducing a ghost Augustine, De libero arbitrio 1.16.3.3. c.f. Augustine, City of God,13.11.12. 13 c.f. Augustine, De spiritu et littera 31.53 14 c.f. Augustine, Confessions 7.3.5. 15 c.f. Augustine, Enchiridion 30. 16 C.f. Augustine, Ad Romanos, in Migne, Patrologia Latina, 35:2066. 11 12 8 which haunts practical reasoning and contra Kant causes it to perennially fail. But Augustine was not the one who introduced the concept of free will to Christian thought: “The pre-Augustinian theological tradition is practically of one voice in asserting the freedom of the human will.”17 To mention only one paradigmatic case here, Gregory of Nyssa asserted that despite losing what he calls their ‘structural’ freedom of the will at the fall, humans still retain their ‘functional’ freedom by whose proper use they can regain even their lost ‘structural freedom”. It seems that by the beginning of the 3rd century CE, the Stoic, secular concept of selfdetermination (αυτεξουσία) has been ‘translated’ and used in the Christian theological discourse. The incorporation and reconceptualization of the concept of the will seems to have become central to visions of man as a suffering being as well as a homo peccator, a sinful being. Suffering had become central for the Christian vision of the world from very early on. Not only Tertullian’s testimony to the effect that «the blood of Christians is seed»(Apologia 50) and that Christians are «a race ready for death»(Apologia 1.12) but also Justin’s «who joining us does not wish to suffer» as well as Ignatius’ of Antiocheia, «if I suffer I shall be Jesus Christ’s freedman»(Ad Romanos 4.3) can be mentioned here. Indeed, «Christian texts of the late first and second centuries almost without exception assidsuously project the message that to be a Christian was to suffer and die.»18 The vision of the self as the sufferer was founded on an understanding of suffering as caused by the human will which did not introduce but nevertheless consented and chose evil. If God’s will was essentially good, evil’s reality was admited albeit as the absence of goodness, as a par-hypostasis dependent on the good, by the consent of the free human will. In a double movement, the concept of will was utilized to conceive both of God’s beneficence as unlimited and founded in His absolutely good and omniscient will, and of human propensity to sinfulness 17 A. McGrath, Justitia Dei, p.20. 18 Judith Perkins, The Suffering Self,p.24 9 and justified suffering. Sin was founded on the human notorious weakness of the will which was a basic Pauline conception(Romans,7). Unlike modern and Christian conceptualizations of the will, according to Albrecht Dihle’s, The Theory of the Will in Classical Antiquity, there was no explicit conception of will in ancient philosophy. Dihle claims that passions and emotions provided the only alternative to reasoning with regard to the psychological mechanism of motivation for action, and that consequently will and intention were never theorized in their own right but treated instead as the results of reasoning or desire. Although it is correct that Aristotle does not posit any other ‘faculty’ of the soul apart from the desiring and the reasoning ones, it is of crucial importance that Aristotle provides a very complex picture of the motivational mechanism which does not conceive of these as alternatives but as complementing each other. It is, however, incorrect to claim that, because of this complementarity, he did not conceptually distinguish desiring and reasoning from moving to action and willing. To Aristotle, neither desire nor reasoning are sufficient for moving to action. One reason for the above misconception though might be that for Aristotle, willing(βούλησις) and moving to action was considered the result of a process of deciding which included desire, deliberation and deliberative choice, all performed by a desiring nous(ορεκτικός νούς), and not by a distinct faculty. As J.L. Ackrill has stated, “Aristotle shows that choosing is not simply a kind of thinking, and is not simply a kind of desiring, but that it involves both.”19 In Aristotle’s own words, “What we decide to do is whatever action, among those up to us, we deliberate about and desire to do. Hence also decision will be deliberative desire to do an action that is up to us.”20 Aristotle describes in the first 5 chapters of book 3 of the NE the complex mechanism by which an agent moves herself to action and as J.O. Urmson points out, being one of the exceptions among commentators, “in so doing he is facing the set of problems collectively called the problem of free will. Aristotle is often said to be unaware of this problem, and it is true that he 19 J.L.Ackrill, Aristotle, the philosopher, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1981, p.143. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics,1113a10-12, translated by Terence Irwin, Hackett, Indianapolis and Cambridge,1999,. 20 10 does not approach it against the background either of theological predestination or of scientific determinism, as is typically the case in later times. But to me it seems obvious that he is concerned with the same obvious issues.”21 As elsewhere, where he explicitly states that human ethical activity “does not happen of necessity(ουδέν εξ’ ανάγκης,Rhetoric,1357a26), Aristotle stresses here that «a human being is a principle(αρχή), begetting actions(γεννητήν των πράξεων) as he begets children.”22 Having discussed the difference between voluntary and involuntary actions in ch1, ascribing the latter to force or ignorance,and having given a very nuanced account of intention which includes prognosis, he concludes his discussion by showing that virtuous and vicious actions, indeed virtue and vice are both voluntary and up to us. Aristotle defines virtue as “the habit of choosing(έξις προαιρετική)” 23 thus reiterating the more general point he made in the Metaphysics about rational beings as being able both for the good and its opposite. Here Aristotle differs from Kant for whom, as we have seen, a rational will can be only good, and it is rather the desiring part of the soul that is to blame if the agent misses the mark. Unlike Kant, for whom the ‘freedom’ of the autonomous will seems problematic since the outcome of its exercise is a given, reasoning always to the good, for Aristotle it is not the desiring part which is failing but the whole soul of a rational being which can be both miss and hit the mark, making the outcome contingent on her choice. I would claim that by his account of practical action, Aristotle has made at least three major contributions to ethics: his division of virtues into ethical and intellectual ones, his distinction of practical from theoretical truth and his conception of a human agent as a desiring nous that is responsible for her choices for either the good or the bad. The first consists in two interrelated claims: first, virtues include neither just intellectual, nor just ethical ‘habits’ but both: “There are two kinds of virtue, ethical and dianoetic, since we praise not only just people but also intelligent and wise men.”24 21 J.O.Urmson, Aristotle’s Ethics, Blackwell, Oxford, 1988,p.59. Aristotle, NE 1113b18-19. NE 1107a1. 24 Eudemian Ethics, II,1220a5. 22 23 11 and also, “Virtue, then, is of two sorts, virtue of thought and virtue of character. Virtue of thought arises and grows mostly from teaching; that is why it needs experience and time. Virtue of character results from habit; hence its name ethical.”25 Second, far from one dominating the other, the two kinds of virtue should and do cooperate and strive to harmonize in the virtuous human being: “As assertion and desire are to thought, so pursuit and avoidance are to desire.Now virtue of character is a state that decides; and decision is a deliberative desire. If, then, the decision is excellent, the reason must be true and the desire correct, so that.”26 In making these two interrelated claims, of course, Aristotle moves decisively away from a Platonic conception of virtue which equates it with truth. If this conceptualization of ethical activity as comprising not only reasoning, cannot be emphasized enough, it is of crucial importance to realize that at the same time that Aristotle insists on the independence of the virtues of character, he also stresses that no character can be a virtuous character unless she has developed the virtue of practical reasoning, which belongs to the dianoetic part of the soul and therefore its aim, its ergon, its function is the achievement of truth. Aristotle does not equate goodness with practical rationality or truth but makes a certain conception of truth necessary, albeit not sufficient, for goodness. And this leads us to his second major contribution to ethics, his theory of practical knowledge, and his conception of practical truth as distinct from theoretical truth, as what Heidegger famously designated as ‘being in truth(In-der-Warheit-sein)’. Aristotle insists that “truth is the function of whatever thinks”27 and therefore the function of both parts of the rational soul is the achievement of truth, although each part seeks for truth in a distinct way: “Previously, then, we said that there are two parts of the soul, one that has reason and one nonrational. Now we should divide in the same way the part that has reason. Let us assume there are two parts that have reason: with one we study NE 1103a15-18. NE 1139a22-25. 27 NE 1139a29. 25 26 12 beings whose principles do not admit of being otherwise than they are and with the other we study beings whose principles admit of being otherwise.” 28 Theoretical truth, f.e. geometry, according to Aristotle, is founded on principles that are universal and necessary, that is they do not admit of being otherwise. True conclusions reached on the basis of universals are ‘self-sufficient’, and ‘independent’ of any emotional participation of the practitioner of this kind of truth, since they correspond to the end point of thought. Practical truth, on the contrary, leads to the making of a choice and to an action, is not self sufficient and involves some measure of emotional participation of the agent, since the reaching of a conclusion is not sufficient to lead to a choice because the nonrational, the desiring part of the soul participates in the choice. As Carlo Natali states, “For Aristotle, since the characteristic of practical knowledge is to have action and good as its end, it is not sufficient for one who acts to know the principles, as instead happens in geometry, where whoever knows the principles is immediately a geometer. In practical knowledge one is good only if one knows the principles and acts in accordance with them.” 29 It is for this reason that practical knowledge requires time, experience and learning, unlike theoretical truth in which even a young person can excel. But although universals are not sufficient for practical truth, Aristotle insists that they are necessary as there can be no thinking without universal concepts and axioms. In this way Kantian universalizable maxims, or say something like the Golden Rule, unlike what is sometimes asserted, have a very important place in Aristotelian ethics, since to think in a practical way requires them, as any kind of thought does: “Whereas young people become accomplished in geometry and mathematics, and wise within these limits, prudent young people do not seem to be found. The reason is that prudence is concerned with particulars as well as with universals, and particulars become known from experience, but a young person lacks experience..”30 Indeed universalizable maxims operate better within an Aristotelian account of ethics since they operate only as ‘regulative’ principles of action rather than as ‘constitutive’, coming closer to the Kant of the third critique NE 1139a6-8. Carlo Natali, The Wisdom of Aristotle, State University of New York Press, New York, 2001, p.12. 30 NE 1142 a12-15. 28 29 13 rather than the second. Another way to express this is by claiming that unlike Kant, for whom ‘schematism’ takes place only within the bounds of theoretical reason but not in practical reason, for Aristotle the ‘schematism’ operates in practical reason as well taking its terminus a quo, its point of departure, human finitude. Moreover, as Natali has observed for Aristotelian practical reasoning minor premises are more important than major premises regarding the concrete situation, in order “to reach an individual decision here and now, rather than know[ing] only the principles in a universal and abstract way.” 31 But practical truth, while combining universals and particulars, and unlike theoretical truth, is not self-sufficient and requires some participation of the emotional, nonrational part of the soul in order to reach its conclusion which is action. This is the third major contribution that he has made to ethics, his conception of a human being as a desiring nous, a contribution unsurpassed in its novelty and its influence: “Thought by itself moves nothing; what moves us is goal directed thought concerned with action…decision is either understanding combined with desire or desire combined with thought; and this is the sort of principle(αρχή) that a human being is.”32 Although practical wisdom is an intellectual virtue, for Aristotle, it cannot reach its aim which is ‘truthful’,i.e. good action(in his words truth agreeing with correct desire33) unless it is complemented by desire and what he calls prohairesis, that is, a decision or choice, reached by the cooperation of character and the intellect. Thought as he says, moves nothing. But is neither desire which leads to good action by itself according to Aristotle. It is prohairesis, which he defines as a desiring nous and he states that this is the principle a human being is. We need to be careful here because Aristotle is clear that it is not desire itself which is the principle of action, the source of motion, but prohairesis, and as we have seen, “the principle of prohairesis is desire and goal directed reason”. It is the whole self therefore that makes choices and decides about the goodness of a course of action and not desire by itself. And it is this insistence on the agent as a whole which distinguishes Aristotle’s Carlo Natali, op.cit., p.22. NE, 1139a36-1139b5. 33 NE, 1139a30. 31 32 account of ethics both from a Platonist, 14 intellectualist account and from a voluntaristic conception is which desire or inclinations or a fantom faculty of the will makes choices and wills in a criterionless way. Very importantly, though, if my reading is here correct, Aristotle makes a strong claim against any voluntaristic account of human action. For him desire might “be of the end(του τέλους εστί)” and practical reasoning “towards the end” (which has been very unfortunately translated as end versus means), but desire by itself does not lead to a choice of action. All ethical choices in other words are conscious, rational choices to a greater or lesser, of course, degree, whether an agent recognizes it or not. In other words, it is not only bare thought but also bare desire that do not lead to action for Aristotle but is always the combination of the two and the resultant choices that do34. In this I disagree with Natali and a host of other scholars who take “desire to be the only proximate cause of human action.”35 As I have just argued, for Aristotle, it is rational choice(prohairesis) in accord with desire that is the most proximate cause of human action and not desire by itself. In this reading of Aristotle then prohairesis, choice is the modern equivalent of the will and is always a human will which combines both rational and nonrational elements in its willing. One important challenge that Aristotle seems to extend to his readers and interlocutors is to resist an either intellectualist or voluntaristic account of ethical decision making. Unlike Kant he stresses the contribution of desires and emotions to a good will. But, interestingly, he shares with Kant a major insight into human nature which was the major issue of contention in the famous 1929 Davos debate between Cassirer and Heidegger. For Aristotle, as for Kant there is no such thing as ‘bare’ existence, as ‘throwness into the world(geworvenheit)’, as the ontic as such. Instead human existence is always, already ontological, Dasein is never ontic, is only insofar as it is ontological and in this Aristotle is in agreement with Heidegger who has learned this basic insight from Kant. But as Cassirer was arguing against Heidegger the way that a human being exists ontologically, its being-in-the-world, is always through symbols and concepts: See here NE, 1178a 15-16:”Prudence is inseparable from virtue of character, and virtue of character from prudence.” 35 Carlo Natali,op.cit., p. 12. 34 15 “I believe there is no other way from Dasein to Dasein than through this world of forms. There is this factum. Should this not be so, then I would not know how there could be something like self understanding. Knowing, too, is just a basic instant of this assertion..” 36 In Aristotle’s insistence that any ethical, rational, choice links the world of desire with the world of nous, we might be able to search for this intermingling of finitude and infinitude that constitutes a finite human being, not only in theoretical contemplation, but in practical activity also. A being which as a finite, desiring creature is striving, even if always failing, to use her desiring nous in ways transcending finitude. And in this aspiration, ultimately Aristotle is not too far away from Kant, although for the former, practical reason, in its tendency to transcend the limitations of finitude, does not transcend desires and emotions but works with them. Cited in Peter E. Gordon, The Continental Divide:Heidegger, Cassirer, Davos, Harvard University Press, Cambridge Massachusetts, 2010, p.205. 36