1 Relational Malpractice RELATIONAL MALPRACTICE AND THE TRANSFORMATION OF HEALTHCARE LAW Sagit Mor and Orna Rabinovich-Einy Abstract: Legal scholarship in recent decades has devoted considerable attention to the "malpractice crisis." However, the vast majority of this literature has overlooked the essence of the problem. Mainstream legal writing on malpractice has tended to frame the problem as either an insurance crisis or a litigation crisis. In this article, we offer an alternative understanding of the nature of the current malpractice predicament: the decline of the doctor-patient relationship. We highlight the fact that contemporary doctor-patient interactions resemble a battle zone: a majority of physicians view "every patient as a potential malpractice lawsuit," while patients complain that their physicians are driven by financial incentives, treat them insensitively and fail to provide honest and full information. We find that these dynamics have colored the entire doctor-patient relationship, extending well beyond the discrete instances in which a medical error has occurred. The framing of the problem in terms of relationships paves the way for a paradigm shift in the medico-legal analysis of malpractice specifically and of healthcare law more generally through the adoption of a relational approach. On one level this paper offers a fresh approach to malpractice reform highlighting the limitations of current approaches, which have failed to frame the problem and solution in terms of a relationship crisis. Therefore, in order to improve doctor-patient relations we need to do away with the malpractice system and the negligence regime on which it is based, by adopting a No Fault based liability scheme. Past proposals for the adoption of a no-fault regime have failed to garner the requisite political support and have neglected the potential of such reform to rebuild relationships. We offer a new justification for the shift to no fault: the transformation of doctor-patient relations, and, consequently, the reduction of medical errors and enhancement of patient safety. We delineate the contours of such an alternative and the required conditions for its success in improving the overall quality of healthcare. With the new healthcare reform legislation which mandates pilot projects along these lines, we believe the time is ripe for states to experiment with such regimes. On a deeper level, the article uncovers a fundamental organizing principle for healthcare law more generally—the centrality of relationships, most notably the doctor-patient relationship. As we show, the theme of relationships cuts across various controversies and debates that dominate the field and is central to the medical profession’s own understanding of high quality medical care. Nevertheless, legal writing has largely neglected the role of relationships in healthcare law. The suggested relational approach to healthcare law contributes to the current effort to characterize the field and draw its boundaries, and allows for imaginative solutions for pressing problems to emerge. Assistant Professor, University of Haifa, Law Faculty. LL.B. Tel Aviv University, LL.M. New York University, J.S.D. New York University. Director of the Law and Health LL.M. Program at the Haifa Law Faculty. Assistant Professor, University of Haifa, Law Faculty. LL.B. Tel Aviv University, LL.M. Columbia University, J.S.D. Columbia University. Guest editor of the 2011 Law & Contemporary Problems' volume on ADR in healthcare. Director of the Law and Technology LL.M. Program at the Haifa Law Faculty. [ADD THANKS] 2 Relational Malpractice Contents: I. II. Introduction Relational Healthcare Law A. Situating Malpractice Within Healthcare Law B. The Search for Coherence in Healthcare Law C. Adopting a Relational Approach to Healthcare Law III. The Centrality of the Doctor-Patient Relationship under a Relational Approach A. The Nature of the Doctor-Patient Relationship B. The Benefits of a Collaborative Doctor-Patient Relationship Model C. The Law as a Barrier to a Collaborative Doctor-Patient Relationship IV. Doctor-Patient Relationship in the Shadow of Malpractice A. Consumed by Malpractice: Doctor-Patient Interactions as a Battle Zone B. The Sources of Current Tensions in Doctor-Patient Relations C. Partial Measures for Improving Doctor-Patient Interaction V. No Fault as a Means for Transforming the Doctor-Patient Relationship A. The History of the No Fault Alternative: From Compensation to Learning B. Relationships as a New Justification for No Fault C. Designing An Alternative with Relationships in Mind VI. I. Conclusion Introduction Legal scholarship in recent decades has devoted considerable attention to the "malpractice crisis." However, the vast majority of this literature has overlooked the essence of the problem. So far, mainstream legal writing on malpractice has tended to frame the problem as either an insurance crisis or a litigation crisis.1 The insurance crisis claim focuses on the rise in professional insurance premiums as a result of exceptionally high awards, while the problem of litigation stems from the ills of the court system—its high costs, unpredictability and the distorted incentives it provides. In this article, we offer an 1 In the last decade a third approach has emerged, emphasizing safety and error prevention. This approach has emerged from the medical setting and has permeated the writing on medical errors which focuses on public policy and institutional responses. However, it has yet to infiltrate mainstream legal scholarship. For a discussion of this approach, see infra Part IV.A. 3 Relational Malpractice alternative understanding of the true nature of the malpractice predicament: the decline of the doctor-patient relationship. The framing of the problem in terms of relationships paves the way for a paradigm shift in the medico-legal analysis of malpractice specifically and of healthcare law more generally through the adoption of a relational approach. On one level this paper offers a fresh approach to malpractice reform highlighting the limitations of current approaches, which have failed to frame the problem and the solution in terms of a relationship crisis. On a deeper level, the article uncovers a fundamental organizing principle for healthcare law more generally—the centrality of relationships, most notably the doctor-patient relationship. As we show, the theme of relationships cuts across various controversies and debates that dominate the field, such as bioethical dilemmas, informed consent and managed care, and has played a central role in the medical profession’s own understanding of what lies at the core of high quality medical services. The relational approach we adopt can contribute to the current efforts to characterize the field of healthcare law and draw its boundaries. So far, however, legal writing on healthcare law has largely neglected the role of relationships, focusing on other complementary themes, such as trust, that have historically characterized the field.2 While legal scholarship has rightly contributed to the disenchantment with old style professional medical paternalism, it has also been active in hampering the development of a viable alternative. We offer a relational understanding of malpractice, which highlights the fact that contemporary doctor-patient interactions resemble a battle zone: Most physicians view "every patient as a potential malpractice lawsuit,"3 while patients complain that their physicians are driven by financial incentives,4 treat them brusquely and fail to provide honest and full information.5 Our findings reveal that these dynamics have colored the 2 See infra Part II.B. See Michelle Mello et al., Caring for Patients in a Malpractice Crisis: Physician Satisfaction and Quality of Care, 23(4) Health Affairs, 42, 49 (2004). 3 4 See Jonathan Todres, Toward Healing and Restoration for All: Reframing Medical Malpractice Reform, 39 CONN. L. REV. 669, 689 (2006) (citing research findings according to which “82% of respondents believed that medical care had become a big business and that the industry put profits ahead of patients.”) 5 Indeed, litigation by patients in the aftermath of a medical error is often triggered by the failure of the healthcare team to provide information on the occurrence, and is pursued in the hope that such litigation will drive healthcare providers to transmit such information. See infra note 187-191 and accompanying text. Todres has described these dynamics as fostering “an ‘us vs. them’ environment that pits doctors against patients and the community” (see Todres, supra note 4, at 691). 4 Relational Malpractice entire doctor-patient relationship, extending well beyond those discrete instances in which a medical error has occurred. While physician communication patterns have typically been tied to longstanding professional and organizational cultures, our research uncovers the role the law has played in cutting off communication channels between providers and patients. These developments have permeated the entire web of relations in the healthcare arena, but most notably the doctor-patient relationship, the major relational axis in this context. Our relational approach draws on the existing medical literature, which has long acknowledged the importance of the doctor-patient relationship as a fundamental component in the provision of healthcare services. Such literature has recognized the malpractice context, acknowledging the links among relationships, errors, and quality, and underscored the significance of a collaborative doctor-patient relationship for the quality of medical services delivered. We define a “collaborative relationship” as one that is premised on a mutual, open and cooperative discourse. Such a mode of interaction has been linked with enhanced physician ability to draw relevant medical information from patients, greater motivation by patients to seek treatment and to adhere to treatment, and increased patient satisfaction. Despite these findings, the dominant model of doctor-patient relations has been a defensive, hierarchical and closed mode of communication, which we refer to as "oppositional." Current research on the doctor-patient relationship proves that the existing malpractice regime does not allow for a collaborative relationship to evolve. To the contrary, it harms the doctor-patient relationship by providing disincentives for open, free flowing communication by breeding distrust, conflict and defensiveness. Specifically, these studies have disclosed the manner in which torts law has shaped doctor-patient communication in the aftermath of an error: Doctors are driven to cut off communication following an adverse event, failing to supply patients and family members with basic information and emotional support. Paradoxically, this has actually motivated patients to sue their doctors, as research findings show that patients' decisions to sue are connected to their interaction with their healthcare providers rather than the pursuit of monetary compensation.6 Our research uncovers the deeper and more elusive nature of the impact of torts law on the doctor patient relationship, extending well beyond the moment of error and resulting in an 6 For extensive research supporting this point, see infra note 155 and accompanying text. 5 Relational Malpractice overall relationship crisis. Such crisis has hampered doctor-patient communication along the entire continuum of care and has reduced the quality of healthcare services. Based on the above findings, this article advances the view that the law governing medical errors should adopt a relational perspective. The implications of such an approach are twofold. First, adopting a relational approach would entail examining the impact legal arrangements have on the doctor-patient relationship and the web of relations that surround it. Second, a legal regime concerned with relationships would promote a collaborative model of doctor-patient relationships. Efforts to transform the malpractice regime have taken the following principal forms: piecemeal tort reform, contractual liability, apology laws and disclosure conversations, and no fault liability schemes. In our article, we explain why none of the first three options can be expected to bring about a real transformation in the doctor-patient relationship and opt for the adoption of a no fault administrative regime. While the no fault alternative is by no means new, former proposals have sought to advance different goals. Earlier proposals focused on just compensation based on the larger pool of claimants and a better screening process for just complaints. Over time, a different justification has emerged focusing on error prevention and patient safety through systemic learning about the sources of errors. Learning would be facilitated by the removal of individual blame. A principal problem with these proposals was that they were unsuccessful in garnering the requisite political support. However, the recent Healthcare Reform grants project, which calls for the development of alternative liability schemes, may alter the political economic climate, generating a broader support-base for such reform and setting the stage for states to experiment with such regimes. No less important in our view is the fact that existing calls for adopting no fault schemes have failed to address the broader connection between medical errors and the doctor-patient relationship. Consequently, they have also failed to spot the root-cause of the crisis as well as the opportunity to address it effectively. Our relational approach brings to the fore a new justification for the shift to no fault: the transformation of doctor-patient relations and a corresponding reduction in medical errors and enhancement of patient safety. This alternative assigns weight to the empirical findings on the connection between the doctor-patient relationship and quality of healthcare. Such reform would require setting the cultivation of collaborative relations as a goal, expanding the pool of disputes handled systematically, and establishing broad criteria for learning that cover the domain of relationships. This would allow for a more 6 Relational Malpractice open and rigorous inquiry into the causes of medical errors, as well as lower conflict levels that are often a diversion for healthcare providers and serve to reduce patient trust. The significance of the new justification stems from the following: (1) it highlights the fact that the harm created by the current malpractice regime extends beyond the occurrence of medical mistakes infiltrating a broad range of physician-patient interactions, (2) it provides a more comprehensive explanation for the ways in which a no fault alternative can enhance prevention of medical errors, and (3) it more effectively addresses some of the critiques voiced against the no fault alternative in light of the cost savings and enhanced learning that will emerge from the study of a broader dispute base. We therefore argue that a transformation in the nature of doctor-patient relations can only be achieved by displacing the current malpractice regime and adopting a no-fault based solution centered on relationships. The paper proceeds to examine its principal theses as follows: Part II situates malpractice within the broader framework of healthcare law and delineates the contours of a relational approach to healthcare law-related issues. In Part III we establish the doctor-patient relationship as a central theme in healthcare law in general and in the malpractice area in particular. Part IV portrays the current state of doctor-patient relations as a battle zone, and underscores some of the historical sources that have contributed to the combative nature of the interaction between healthcare professionals and patients. We show that targeted efforts to transform such interaction have had a limited effect at best. In Part V we present the no fault alternative, highlighting the novelty of the relational justification presented in this article for choosing this particular regime: the need to do away with the malpractice system in order to improve doctor-patient relations. We then explain why the adoption of a no fault system for compensating victims of medical errors would not only be a better avenue for redressing such patients and preventing future mistakes, but also for bringing about a deep change in doctor-patient interaction. We conclude with some thoughts on the potential of a relational approach to malpractice to serve as a blueprint for a more radical transformation of the way we think about the field of healthcare law. 7 Relational Malpractice II. Relational Healthcare Law A. Situating Malpractice Within Healthcare Law The literature on malpractice has tended to either address the issue in an isolated manner or to locate it within the area of torts law.7 It is our contention, however, that malpractice should be situated within the context of healthcare law.8 Healthcare law is a rapidly growing field that governs the provision of medical services by individual and institutional healthcare providers in various contexts and the receipt of such services by individuals and communities. Healthcare law encompasses a wide array of issues, including access to health care and scope of coverage (from health insurance to demographic disparities), managed care and the operation of HMOs, medical malpractice, informed consent rules, bioethical dilemmas (from beginning to end of life), genetics and technology, and more.9 These issues cut across legal subject matters, including torts, contracts, antitrust, family, labor and corporate law.10 By confining the discussion on medical errors to the realm of torts, the issue has been understood as yet another instance of professional negligence. The broader healthcare law perspective is necessary in order to fully understand the problems associated with the current malpractice regime and the ramifications of reform proposals. However, the implications of recognizing healthcare law as a field extend beyond malpractice, creating a conceptual bridge across diverse areas of law, often treated, like malpractice, as isolated issues. 7 M. Gregg Bloche, The Emergent Logic of Health Law, 82 S. CAL. L. REV. 389, 394, 416-417 (2009). 8 For similar views, see Bloche, id., at 462-470; Mark A. Hall, The History and Future of Health Care Law: An Essentialist View, 41WAKE FOREST L. REV. 347, 361 (2006) (noting that “the core of academic health care law consists of those aspects of law for which the unique features of medicine are central to the analysis of inquiry, rather than medicine simply being an incident of generic law’s subject matter”); Todres, supra note 4, at 669. Todres also addresses the unique nature of the doctor-patient relationship distinguishing it from “other interactions governed by tort law” (id., at 733). 9 See, e.g., Hall, Essentialist View, supra note 8, at 348-354 (reviewing the evolution and expansion of the field in terms of subjects of interest). 10 Einer R. Elhauge, Can Health Law Become a Coherent Field of Law? 41 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 365, 368, 371-372 (2006).. 8 Relational Malpractice B. The Search for Coherence in Healthcare Law The question of whether healthcare law constitutes a coherent field is far from settled. While some authors have underscored the field’s chaotic nature, emphasizing its lack of coherence or shared structures, others have searched for a single unifying theme for the field.11 In our view, the growing literature searching for overarching themes in this area and the vibrant debates that surround it indicate substantial support for the position that there is a “there” there.12 Specifically, four primary paradigms for the field are commonly discussed: market, professional, moral and political frameworks.13 These themes represent the prevalent understandings of the field in recent decades and the forces that drive its evolution. The professional paradigm is the traditional framework that gave absolute primacy to the medical profession's views and practices in decision making regarding individual treatment and general policy.14 This "doctor knows best" paradigm was rooted in an authoritarian hierarchical style of doctor-patient relationships, usually described today as paternalistic (sometimes mentioned as “priestly” or “parental”15). Under this paradigm the law willfully withdrew from the medical sphere, leaving it to self regulation by the profession which 11 Bloche, supra note 7, at 397-416 (2009); Mark A. Hall, Law, Medicine, and Trust, 55 STAN. L. REV. 463, 464-466 (2002-2003); Einer Elhauge, Allocating Health Care Morally, 82 CAL. L. REV. 1449, 14521544 (1994). For a view that fully rejects the attempt to find coherence in the field, see Henry T. Greely, Some Thoughts on Academic Health Law, 41 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 391 (2006). See Mark A. Hall & Carl E. Schneider, Where is the “There” in Health Law? Can it Become a Coherent Field?, 14 HEALTH MATRIX 101 (2004); Elhauge, supra note 10; Bloche, supra note 7; Hall, Essentialist View, supra note 8, at 354-356 (2006); George J. Annas, Health Law at the Turn of the Century: From White Dwarf to Red Giant, 21 CONN. L. REV. 551 (1989). One reason to acknowledge that there is such a legal field as health law is the concern about the consequences of not doing so. As Bloche has persuasively argued: “With no comprehensive health policy to guide them, judges tended to pursue doctrinal integrity within disparate areas of law. In so doing, they not only sacrificed the goal of system wide rationality in the health sphere; they added to the national health-policy disarray” (M. Gregg Bloche, The Invention of Health Law, 91 CAL L. REV. 247, 250 (2003) (cited in Hall, supra note 11, at 465 & n.5). 12 13 These four themes were originally identified by Elhauge in his 1994 piece (Elhauge, supra note 11, at 1542-1544). The four themes were further developed in Elhauge’s subsequent work (Elhauge, supra note 10) and were adopted by other scholars (see Bloche, supra note 7, at 408-415; Meir Katz, Towards a New Moral Paradigm in Health Care Delivery: Accounting for Individuals, 36 AM. J. L. & MED. 78, 84 (2010). Parallel to those four paradigms we find the four groups of concerns in health law: quality, autonomy, access, and cost (Hall, Essentialist, supra note 8, at 353). Obviously, there are other overarching themes of the field. One example is the social justice framework (Hall, supra note 11, at 465). 14 Elhauge, supra note 10, at 372-377, 382-383. Ezekiel J. Emanuel & Linda L. Emanuel, Four Models of the Physician-Patient Relationship, 267 JAMA 2221, 2221 (1992). 15 9 Relational Malpractice meant surrendering legal judgment to medical expertise, with pockets of interventions in such cases as mental health law.16 The moral paradigm promoted the insertion of modern moral values into medical discourse.17 The growing interest in moral philosophy was related to the flourishing of bioethics following World War II. The values that were promoted along the years were autonomy and related principles, including liberty, privacy, and consent, voice and human dignity.18 Later on, access to healthcare became a second realm of interest, encompassing issues such as social justice, human dignity, egalitarianism, and the right to health.19 The moral paradigm granted power to philosophers and the imagined moral community.20 It allowed more space for the individual patient, her experience and wishes, thereby undermining the omnipotent image of the doctor and the primacy of scientific medical knowledge. This development was supported by the rise of the patients' rights movement and transformed the field of medical ethics and areas such as informed consent, informational privacy, abortion policy and the right to die. The law was a major instrument in the hands of those supporting the change and their efforts to place limits on the powers of individual healthcare providers and on medical institutions. The market paradigm evolved during the 1970s with the introduction of the economic prism to the field of healthcare.21 The economic logic is based on a cost-benefit analysis in the provision of medical services, thereby contributing to the erosion of the primacy of "pure" medical knowledge and considerations. This development also shifted the status of the patient as the center of treatment as questions of cost, efficiency, and affordability took center stage. At the same time it enhanced the image of the patient as a rational, autonomous and fully informed player who is capable of promoting his or her own self interest, thereby empowering her in a new way, which focuses on agency and free choice. 16 Elhauge, supra note 10, at 372. In the realm of malpractice this was evidenced in the adoption of professional standards as the basis for assessing reasonable conduct. Id., at 371-372. 17 Elhauge, supra note 11, at 1458. 18 Elhauge, id. (focusing on autonomy and consent); Katz, supra note 13, at 108-109 (emphasizing voice and human dignity); Hall, supra note 11, at 464 & n.3 19 Elhauge, id.; Katz, id.; JAY KATZ, THE SILENT WORLD OF DOCTOR AND PATIENT (1984); GEORGE J. ANNAS, THE RIGHTS OF PATIENTS (3rd Ed. 2004). 20 Elhauge, id., at 1458. 21 Bloche, The Invention, supra note 12 (providing a detailed review of the rise of the market paradigm and its impact on the field as well as a comprehensive critique of the dominance of the economic logic in healthcare law); Elhauge, supra note 10, at 382. 10 Relational Malpractice Under the market approach the patient becomes a consumer and health services become a commodity, a good to be exchanged between buyers and sellers. The rise of the market paradigm made resource allocation a central issue in healthcare and presented the troubling tension between cost and quality, at times placing physicians in a conflict of interest. Over the years, the market paradigm has become the dominant framework governing healthcare law.22 The political paradigm emerged as a response to the supremacy of the market paradigm. State and federal political organs began taking a more active role in the healthcare arena following the growing resistance of providers and patients to the centralized nature of managed care organizations’ decision-making and to the dominance of economic considerations.23 The political paradigm assumes that a collective decision-making process is the best way to govern the realm of healthcare.24 The rise of the political paradigm can be seen in the adoption of legislation which constrains managed care decision-making authority on such matters as hospital discharge of certain patients,25 and the inclusion of “gag orders” in their contracts with providers.26 The political avenue was envisioned as a solution to the deficiencies of the market paradigm, but has come with its own set of weaknesses, most notably a slow and cumbersome pace, and the power and knowledge disparities that exist among the various actors and interest groups who are involved in and affected by the political process.27 In recent years, the writing on the essence of healthcare law has changed. Some scholars have moved away from the search for a unifying theme, looking instead for a common method that would allow for the various themes to compete with one another, sustaining Bloche, supra note 7, at 408; Bloche, The Invention, supra note 12, at 253-254; Peter D. Jacobson, Soniya Keskar Mathur, Health Law 2010: It's Not All About The Money, 36 AM. J.L. & MED. 389 (2010). But see Elhauge, supra note 10, at 372-378 (arguing that the market paradigm has failed to gain dominance and that the professional approach continues to rule). 22 Elizabeth Price Foley, The Evolution of Health Care Decision-Making: The Political Paradigm and Beyond, 65 TENN. L. REV. 619, 646 (1998). 23 24 Elhauge, supra note 10, at 384-385. 25 Foley, supra note 23, at 626-628. 26 Id., at 628-630. 27 Elhauge, supra note 10, at 384. This is perhaps most evident in the unsuccessful efforts to substitute the current negligence-based malpractice regime with a no fault alternative. See detailed discussion in infra Part IV.A. 11 Relational Malpractice the field’s vibrant nature.28 One such proposal by Einer Elhauge has suggested a “comparative method” that mandates the consideration of specific healthcare law issues through multiple perspectives, while assigning each theme the appropriate weight in light of the context at hand, without being a priori committed to any of these themes.29 Most recently, another proposal by Gregg Bloche has described the logic of healthcare law as that of an emergent system – “a system with a design that arises from ongoing feedback among [its] scattered deciders.”30 Under this view, the contradictions that currently characterize healthcare law are not perceived as a weakness but rather as an “opportunity for mutual feedback among component systems that constitute health law.”31 The immediate implication of adopting such a view would be “a shift from linear pursuit of specific policy objectives to a quest for evolutionary pathways toward reformers' [quest for] ultimate efficiency, equity, and other goals.”32 At the same time, scholars have also offered the concept of “relationships” as a possible organizing principle for the field, drawing on the centrality of the doctor-patient relationship and the complex web of relations within which it is situated.33 This line of literature draws on relationships both for explaining the connections that exist between the topics that fall under such heading and for justifying healthcare law’s very labeling as a “field.”34 In 2004 Hall & Schneider proposed “an analytical framework that views health 28 See Hall, supra note 8, at 357 (describing this development, but rejecting it as a pragmatic method that is not unique to healthcare law). Elhauge, supra note 10 (arguing that “what matters is not so much the conclusions one would draw from using such a comparative paradigm methodology, but, rather, that this would provide some common methodology for discussing and disputing health law issues.” Id., at 379). 29 30 Bloche, supra note 7, at 422. Bloche contends that “the law of health care provision and the health care system itself are best understood and acted on as emergent systems. This understanding comes to terms with health law's seeming chaos—its emanation from disconnected regulatory and judicial decision makers, and from myriad, separate doctrinal spheres. As with all emergent systems, these many inputs interact in unpredictable ways, clashing with, reinforcing, and reacting to each other. No one actor is in position to sort out these influences. No one actor takes a grand overview. There is no center of command and control. The health care policy this system produces is the sum total of these inputs and of mutual adjustments by stakeholders and decisionmakers.” Id., at 396. 31 id., at 424. 32 Id., at 397. 33 The roots of the turn to relationships can already be found in 1985, when the American Society of Law and Medicine Task Force on Health Law Curricula developed an alternative thematic structure for Health Law textbooks, one which emphasizes “relationships in health care between and among patients, physicians, institutions, and government.” (see Hall, supra note 8, at 353). However, this development did not result in a substantial change in the “standard conception” of the field. (id.) 34 Elhauge, supra note 10, at 369-371; Hall & Schneider, supra note 12, at 103. 12 Relational Malpractice care law as a law of relational webs rather than a law of transactions.”35 The transactional perspective was criticized for taking “the atomistic view that each medical encounter is a discrete event rather than part of an on-going web of relationships.”36 It was contrasted with a relational perspective, which “views medical encounters more holistically, as part of a larger context formed by the parties' interactions with each other and their relationships with other individuals and institutions.”37 Following Hall & Schneider, Elhauge has contended that what makes healthcare law a legal field is that it “address[es] the legal treatment of a distinct set of relations,” which he described as the “unique set of relations among persons involved in the treatment of health problems.”38 The question remains how such recognition of the importance of relationships in healthcare law translates into legal analysis of healthcare related issues. For Elhauge it seems that the question of relationships remains merely conceptual with no practical implications that affect his analysis of a particular problem.39 Hall took a different path, advancing trust as a new overarching theme for the entire field and arguing that “without trust medical relationships never form or are entirely dysfunctional”40 and that “trust is the core, defining characteristic of the doctor-patient relationship – the ‘glue’ that holds the relationship together and makes it possible.”41 Hall contends that trust is a concept that is relevant to the entire field of healthcare law42 and illustrates this through detailed examples. Although Hall acknowledges the embedded tension between trust and “old-style paternalism,”43 his work is still open to criticism for his understanding of trust, which is based on patients’ absolute faith in the system. As one commentator has argued, such an 35 id. 36 Id. 37 Id. Elhauge, supra note 10, at 369 (concluding later that modern health law is in fact the “complex web of relations that affect our health” (Id., at 370), and suggesting that those relations extend beyond the classic doctor-patient relationships and include “the relations of patients to hospitals, insurers, employers, and the government, as well as a complex web of relations between all those and physicians” (Id). 38 39 Id., specifically at 370. 40 Hall, supra note 11, at 470. Id. Our work focuses on the doctor-patient relationship but departs from Hall’s focus on trust in several respects, as this article shows. Most importantly, we focus on communication as the fundamental component of the doctor-patient relationship and advance a particular model of doctor-patient relationship, which is the collaborative model. 41 42 Id., at 466. 43 Id., at 469. 13 Relational Malpractice approach encourages patients to be compliant and docile rather than sophisticated rightsbearing consumers.44 Our approach reflects an understanding of healthcare law as a complex, multifaceted area. We share the view that a holistic integrative approach which combines the various themes that appear in the literature and which allows for contradictions to coexist, correctly captures the essence of the field. At the same time, we draw on the literature that has singled out relationships as a principal theme for the field, and elaborate on the contours of a relational approach to healthcare law.45 C. Adopting a Relational Approach to Healthcare Law The relational understanding of healthcare law that we advance in this article carries two related implications: It emphasizes the centrality of relationships in the operation of healthcare law, and calls for a contextual and relational analysis. The first aspect of the two comports with relational theory of law in that it places relationships at the core, and seeks to nurture and protect them by instilling an “ethics of care” and such values as connectedness, interdependence, responsibility, and solidarity.46 The emphasis on relationships and related values is contrasted with the law’s tendency to produce atomistic social relations in which every actor advances her own interest and eventually becomes a “lone rights bearer,”47 stifling opportunities for meaningful interaction.48 44 Robert Gatter, Faith, Confidence, and Health Care: Fostering Trust in Medicine through Law, 39 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 395, 397 (2004). See also Elhauge, supra note 10, at 375-377. 45 Of course, we do not view relationships as the exclusive organizing theme of the field. For a similar approach that views relationships as one of several essential components of health care law, see Hall, supra note 8, at 358. 46 The notion "ethics of care" was introduced and developed in Carol Gilligan’s renowned work: CAROL GILLIGAN, IN A DIFFERENT VOICE: PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY AND WOMEN’S DEVELOPMENT (1982). Gilligan’s argument was later expanded to additional realms, including law and moral philosophy. See Robin West, Jurisprudence and Gender, 55 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1 (1988) (stating that “[w]omen’s concept of value revolves not around the axis of autonomy, individuality, justice and rights, … but instead around the axis of intimacy, nurturance, community, responsibility, and care,” id., at 28); SHEILA BENHABIB, SITUATING THE SELF: GENDER, COMMUNITY AND POSTMODERNISM IN CONTEMPORARY ETHICS (1992). Chapter 5 in Benhabib’s book, entitled The Generalized and the Concrete Other: The Kohlberg-Giligan Controversy and Feminist Theory, in which she explains that “[i]n treating you in accordance with the norms of friendship, love, and care, I confirm not only your humanity but your human individuality. The moral categories that accompany such interactions are those of responsibility, bonding, and sharing. The corresponding moral feelings are those of love, care, sympathy, and solidarity,” id., at 159). For a more comprehensive approach to the implementation of relational theory in law, see MARTHA MINOW, MAKING ALL THE DIFFERENCE: INCLUSION, EXCLUSION, AND AMERICAN LAW (1990). 47 MARY ANN GLENDON, RIGHTS TALK: THE IMPOVERISHMENT OF POLITICAL DISCOURSE 47-75 (1991). See, also CHARLES TAYLOR, THE ETHICS OF AUTHENTICITY 58-59 (1992) (discussing the concept of social atomism 14 Relational Malpractice Relational theory was initially developed and introduced to law by feminist legal scholars and by communitarians. Relational feminists urge the need to attend to women’s experience and to the alternative worldview that women wish to promote, based on their life experience and the moral ethics that such a worldview entails.49 For relational feminists, the protected human connection that is the basis for the entire theory is the mother-child relationship, which serves as a model for other social ties and extends to broader categories of human relations.50 Eventually, it has been extended even more broadly to a moral and political vision that benefits women and men alike by not only safeguarding individual rights and self-interest, but also by fostering care, mutuality, and human connectedness, as essential moral values.51 Communitarians have sought to revive the place of culture and community in political theory, emphasizing the aspects of collective identity that are inherent for human beings to flourish and which are essential for maintaining a meaningful social and cultural life.52 Communitarians draw on the role that cultural, religious, and national ties play in the formation of every person’s identity, arguing that society should cherish and enhance these relations generally, and that specifically it should protect and promote the group rights and cultural rights of culturally oppressed minorities.53 Our work seeks to highlight another type of social interaction that merits protection: the doctor-patient relationship. We find that the doctor-patient relationship is particularly illsuited for the atomistic culture that traditionally characterizes legal interventions. Instead of supporting these relations, the atomistic legal culture actually harms this relationship and its impact on identity formation processes); West, supra note 46, 5-9 (showing that underlying liberal theory is the assumption that the human condition is based on separateness). 48 This image is even more extreme in the context of torts, where strangers are brought together by an injurious event. 49 GILLIGAN, supra note 46; West, supra note 46; NANCY CHODOROW, THE REPRODUCTION OF MOTHERING (1978). 50 GILIIGAN, supra note 46; West, supra note 46, at 2-3, 14-17. 51 West, supra note 46, at 70-72; BENHABIB, supra note 46 (asking: “Are we not all ‘concrete others’?” (id., at 164) and arguing for “a moral theory [that] allows us to recognize the dignity of the generalized other through an acknowledgment of the moral identity of the concrete other,” id., at 164). 52 For representative works that promote this line of argument, see TAYLOR, supra note 47; MICHAEL J. SANDEL, LIBERALISM AND THE LIMITS OF JUSTICE (2nd ed., 1998). 53 WILL KYMLICKA, MULTICULTURAL CITIZENSHIP: A LIBERAL THEORY OF MINORITY RIGHTS (1995); Charles Taylor, The Politics of Recognition, in Multiculturalism 25 (Amy Gutmann Ed., 2001); WILL KYMLICKA, ED., THE RIGHTS OF MINORITY CULTURES (1995). For “cultural oppression”, see IRIS YOUNG, JUSTICE AND THE POLITICS OF DIFFERENCE (1990). 15 Relational Malpractice and fails to capture the essence of the broader context of healthcare law, of which it is a part. The centrality of the doctor-patient relationship and the need for a relational understanding of healthcare law has received only peripheral attention in legal scholarship. Where legal scholarship has addressed the topic, it has assumed that the doctor-patient relationship is premised either on separateness54 or on complete dependency.55 By contrast, the medical literature has recognized the doctor-patient relationship as the dominant relationship in the healthcare setting.56 As we shall see, while the doctor-patient relationship is a central concern in the medical arena, its meaning is still contested. Over the years, different models of doctor-patient relationships have emerged, leading not only to different interactional patterns but also resulting in disparate clinical outcomes. As we describe in further detail below, we find that one such model—the collaborative model—comports with a relational worldview and therefore we actively advocate its adoption, through legal and medical channels. The second aspect of a relational approach is the adoption of a relational-contextual method for analyzing healthcare-related issues. Such contextual understanding of healthcare operates on two complementary levels. The first focuses on the particular features of an interaction, such as personality, medical history, and professional experience of the parties. The second recognizes that broader forces play an important role in shaping what seem to be individual interactions, such as the identity of the parties (race, gender, class, disability), the institutional setting within which they interact (organizational culture, professional norms, economic incentives), and the legal arrangements that govern their relationship.57 The example of length of doctor-patient office visits can illustrate the ways in which context and relationships play out in the medical setting. Office visits are a major arena in which the doctor-patient relationship is shaped. A relational-contextual method would therefore examine the occurrence of brief 54 Such understanding underlies the literature that is within the framework of the moral or market paradigms (see supra notes 17-22 and accompanying text), which contributed to the rise of the consumerist and default types of doctor-patient relationship, as described above (see, infra note 63-66 and accompanying text). 55 Such understanding underlies the professional paradigm that is usually characterized by paternalistic doctor-patient relationship (see supra notes 14-16, infra note 60, and accompanying texts). It is also evident in the new yearning to professional authority. See for example the debate surrounding the role of trust in healthcare law, supra notes 40-44 and accompanying text. 56 See infra Part II.C. For a more detailed discussionon the role of context in legal theory and practice, see Martha L. Minow & Elizabeth Spelman, In Context, 63 SOUTH. CAL. L. REV. 1597 (1990). 57 16 Relational Malpractice doctor-patient office visits, for instance, through both particular and structural prisms. A focus on the particular characteristics of patients and physicians would steer us away from a “one size fits all” standard for length of office visits, recognizing that a mixture of personality traits and the impetus for seeking treatment will influence the meeting time. At the same time, the contextual-relational method recognizes that length of visits results not only from personal characteristics, but also from structural forces. Under such a view, curt and brief encounters should also be attributed to an environment that fails to compensate physicians for time spent with patients. When physicians are evaluated according to the number of patients they see and measured according to prescriptions and clinical tests, it is difficult to expect that they foster a caring and engaged relationship with their patients. While office visits are not usually viewed as being subject to legal regulation and scrutiny, the law plays an indirect role in shaping them by providing (or neglecting to provide) a standard of care against which physicians are measured. To summarize, in our proposed relational analysis, we introduce the insights that have emerged from medical writing on the doctor-patient relationship into legal scholarship through a relational prism. We view the doctor-patient relationship in a mutualcollaborative manner.58 Our approach visualizes the doctor and the patient as sharing a universe in which the physician is dependent on the patient’s input and collaboration for accurate diagnosis and effective treatment, while the patient’s need for professional care does not relegate her to a state of inferiority. As opposed to an atomistic approach, which devalues the state of dependency, a relational analysis offers a different view that emphasizes interdependence.59 Such a view considers the wellbeing of both patients and physicians, and promises mutual benefits in terms of satisfaction and quality of care. In addition, a relational approach would situate the doctor-patient relationship within a broader web of relations, i.e., between physicians and institutions, between institutions and patients, and within the healthcare team. Clearly, a better doctor-patient relationship promotes better interaction between patients and healthcare organizations, such as hospitals and HMOs. At the same time, it is obvious that policies promulgated by healthcare organizations concerning patients and participating physicians penetrate the doctor-patient relationship and shape its character. This web of relationships does not operate in a vacuum; it is located within an even broader context of social, political, 58 See infra Part II.C.1. GILLIGAN, supra note 46; EVA FEDER KITTAY, LOVE’S LABOR: ESSAYS DEPENDENCY (1999). 59 ON WOMEN EQUALITY AND 17 Relational Malpractice economic, and legal forces. Within this framework our analysis focuses on the role legal regimes play in shaping relationships in healthcare by uncovering the ways in which particular legal arrangements have impacted the doctor-patient relationship and their surrounding environment. In the following sections we introduce the medical literature that has described the different models of the doctor-patient relationship and advocate the inculcation of one specific model, that of a collaborative relationship between doctors and patients. While this model has been linked with positive medical outcomes it has yet to become a prevailing practice. We link this state of affairs to the existing legal climate which not only ignores the impact of legal arrangements governing healthcare on relationships, but has ultimately had a destructive impact on the fabric of doctor-patient relations and the quality of medical services. III. The Centrality of the Doctor-Patient Relationship under a Relational Approach A. The Nature of the Doctor-Patient Relationship The doctor-patient relationship has always been a central component of the practice of medicine. In the past, the doctor-patient relationship tended to be paternalistic and hierarchical and idealized patient submissiveness as a key for the therapeutic relationship.60 Over the years, increased competition and marketing efforts by healthcare providers together with changes in patient mentality resulting from the rise of patient rights and consumerism in healthcare have placed patient autonomy and satisfaction at the fore.61 These developments have generated competing models of doctor-patient relationships, which have attracted scholarly attention in an attempt to identify ideal types of doctor-patient relationships.62 A powerful typology was developed by Roter and Hall, distinguishing between paternalistic, consumerist, default and mutual prototypes of the doctor-patient relationship. Under the “consumerist” model, patients are described as having gained ultimate control over medical 60 DEBRA L. ROTER & JUDITH HALL, DOCTORS TALKING WITH PATIENTS 5 (1993). 61 See infra Part IV.B. 62 See e.g., Emanuel & Emanuel, supra note 15. 18 Relational Malpractice decision-making.63 This has been driven by the rise of a market paradigm for healthcare.64 At the same time, such an environment has been experienced by physicians as a challenge to their professional authority and power to exercise their professional judgment.65 The “default” model is another consequence of the weakening of the medical profession together with the growing legal recognition of patient rights and autonomy. Under this model, the disempowered physician and the emboldened patient reach a stalemate, leaving both with very little control over the course of medical decision-making.66 Both the consumerist and default models represent extreme consequences of the shift in the power dynamics between doctors and patients, neither of which seems to result in positive interactions between them. A more productive mode of interaction can be found in what has been termed a “mutual” model of doctor-patient interaction under which patient involvement in decision-making processes has been viewed as cardinal to medical care while acknowledging medical professional expertise and authority.67 Under this view “[e]ach of the participants brings strengths and resources to the relationship, as well as a commitment to work through disagreements in a mutually respectful manner.”68 The above typology can be grouped under two major modes of communication between doctors and patients: an oppositional vs. a collaborative mode of communication. The paternalistic, consumerist and default models, which are characterized by an oppositional mode of communication, envisage an interaction that is closed and hierarchical, and therefore deteriorates either into confrontation or withdrawal. Under all three models, patients and doctors are adversaries with conflicting interests. Even the consumerist model, which challenges the physician’s traditional superiority and seeks to empower patients, produces an arm wrestling environment that stifles communication. The mutual 63 ROTER 64 & HALL, supra note 60, at 28. See supra notes 21-22 and accompanying text. 65 See, Timothy Hall, Bargaining with Hippocrates: managed Care and the Doctor-Patient Relationship, 54 S. C. L. REV. 689 (2003); Arnold S. Relman, The Impact of Market Forces on the PhysicianPatient Relationship, 87 J. ROYAL SOC’Y OF MED. 22, 22 (1994); Barringer et al., Administrative Compensation of Medical Injuries: A Hardy Perennial Blooms Again, 33 J. of Health Politics, Pol'y and Law 725, 727-728 (2008). 66 ROTER & HALL, supra note 60, at 33. 67 Roter & Hall, id., at 32-33 68 Id., at. 32. 19 Relational Malpractice model, on the other hand, opens the door to a different kind of interaction between physicians and patients, one that is premised on collaboration.69 A collaborative doctor-patient mode of communication recognizes that the doctor and patient interact within a unique power structure under which each possesses different types of knowledge and expertise. While the physician has the medical proficiency, the patient is familiar with her body, her preferences and her needs. Communication therefore needs to be open, mutual and interactive.70 The collaborative model further recognizes that doctor-patient interactions may change across contexts, according to individual preferences and character traits while remaining committed to an ongoing negotiation over patient wishes. As we demonstrate below, such an interactive dialogue is a key not only to patient satisfaction and well-being, but also to physicians’ functioning and professionalism.71 B. The Benefits of a Collaborative Doctor-Patient Relationship Model Medical research and professional training have recognized the significance of open and effective communication between doctors and patients.72 Various empirical studies conducted in the medical arena have substantiated the connection between such factors as relationship, communication and trust on the one hand to improved medical results on the other. These findings show that a collaborative mode of communication could improve the quality of medical treatment in the following ways. 69 The mutual model is not the only model that is based on collaborative elements. (see Emanuel & Emanuel, supra note 15 (describing four archetypes of the doctor-patient relationship); M. Robin DiMatteo, The Physician-Patient Relationship: Effects on the Quality of Healthcare, 37 Clinical Obstetrics and Gynecology 149 (1994) (advocating for what he terms "collaborative informed choice"); Ezekiel J. Emanuel & Nancy Neveloff Dubler, Preserving the Physician-Patient Relationship in the Era of Managed Care, 273 JAMA, 323, 324 (1995). 70 It also needs to address information that may not seem purely medical and encompass nonverbal cues and body language, which can play an important role in terms of understanding the matter at hand and for establishing trust between the parties. Research has shown that doctors tend to use jargon, are poor listeners and tend to provide information which they deem important but does not necessarily comport with what patients would like to be discussed (DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 152). Collaboration, however, does not imply "that the patient tells the physician what to do or is in unilateral control of the medical decision-making process... but rather [the patient] works with the physician to try to achieve the chosen health-outcome goals" (id., at 155). 71 See infra Part IV.A. 72 See DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 154 (stating that "[t]he most effective relationships between physicians and patients are those in which power and control of health care decisions are shared. In practice, this sharing requires open, honest and forthright conversation between physician and patient…"). 20 Relational Malpractice First, it is widely accepted that the quality of care depends on the providers' ability to obtain all relevant information regarding the patient's condition.73 While physician training places an emphasis on the acquisition of interviewing skills, experience on the ground demonstrates that the effectiveness of these techniques varies widely, hampered by an authoritarian professional culture and the reality of time pressure and exhaustion. Indeed, research has shown that patients tend to disclose different information on their condition to the various providers they encounter while being treated.74 This state of affairs is further exacerbated by cognitive biases, which drive physicians to assume what is relevant and what is not prior to asking questions, and to interpret the answers they receive as strengthening their preexisting assumptions on the state of the patient.75 Studies have shown that open-ended questions allow the physician to draw a richer, sometimes surprising, account of the patient's condition without consuming significantly more time.76 A related link between relationships and quality of medicine lies in the physician's ability to diagnose the condition correctly. Here also heuristics play a role, and the ability of the physician to explore the patient's perspective depends on her information gathering capabilities.77 Another line of research illustrates the significance of a collaborative doctor-patient relationship for the patient's motivation to both seek treatment to begin with,78 and to 73 Id., at 150 (stating that "[e]ffective communication is essential for the diagnosis and full understanding of the problem a patient brings to the clinical encounter"). Id., at 157 (stating that "[m]ore effective physician-patient communication is also associated with more adequate histories given by patients"). 74 75 On the role of heuristics in physicians' diagnoses, see Pat Croskerry, The Importance of Cognitive Errors in Diagnosis and Strategies to Minimize Them, 78 Academic Medicine 775 (2003); Donald Redermeier, The Cognitive Psychology of Missed Diagnoses, 142 Annals of Internal Medicine 115 (2005). 76 See Miriam Divinsky, Stories for Life: Introduction to Narrative Medicine, 53 Canadian Family Physician 203, 204 (2007) (stating that research has estimated that the time it takes patients' to describe their condition ranges from six seconds to seven minutes); DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 150 (stating that patients will rarely tell their story for more than two and a half minutes and that if interrupted, patients will typically reiterate their concerns at the end of the visit so that no real time saving is achieved by silencing them early on). But see Roter & Hall, supra note 60, at 79-92, 114 (stating that doctors are very bad at asking open-ended questions, the skills needed in order to draw out patients' stories). 77 Divinsky, supra note 76, at 204 (describing how only when she truly listened to patients was she able to decipher what stopped them from quitting smoking or addressing obesity); Rita Charon, Narrative and Medicine, 350 N. ENGL. J. MED. 862, 863 (2004) (stating that "narrative competence gives the doctor not only the means to understand the patient, but fresh means to understand the disease itself"). 78 Todres, supra note 4, at 691. 21 Relational Malpractice follow the prescribed treatment.79 Physicians' willingness to provide patients with full information, in an open and engaging manner, has proven a critical component in patients' adherence to a medical regimen and in their ongoing commitment to keeping medical appointments.80 Studies have shown that, on average, approximately 40% of patients fail to follow short and long-term treatments, a statistic that cuts across all socioeconomic and educational levels.81 One study found that approximately one-third of patients who received prescriptions were taking the medication in a manner that “posed a serious threat to their health.”82 One explanation for this finding lies in other research which has found that physicians who prescribe medication tend to conduct shorter visits, in fact using the prescription to avoid open and elaborate communication with their patients.83 Finally, we find that physicians do very little in terms of communicating with their patients about changes in lifestyle habits that are strongly connected to health and disease prevention (e.g., smoking and weight-related diseases), even though studies have found that physician communication on these issues can have a real effect on patients’ habits.84 The connection between these findings and the quality of healthcare seems evident when we view the breadth of healthcare services as indicative of a high quality healthcare system and understand the physician's obligations as extending beyond the diagnosis phase. In addition, some research has found a correlation between doctor-patient communication patterns and health outcomes for patients. In answering the question of why such a correlation should exist, one study found that “[b]eyond the obvious—the transfer of information patients need to manage their disease effectively—the communication between physicians and patients can be a source of motivation, incentive, reassurance, and support as well as an opportunity for revision of expectations of both patient and 79 DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 156 (stating that "[i]n the area of adherence, such awareness and recognition [of the need for effective communication] have proven invaluable"); Hall, supra note 11, at 578. But see Gatter’s critique of the implied support in the submissiveness of patients entailed in this argument, Gatter, supra note 44, at 397. 80 DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 157 (stating that "[w]hen physicians offer more information, as well as more positive talk, less negative talk, and more questions about adherence, their patients are more likely to follow the chosen treatment. Physicians' interpersonal manner and nonverbal communication have important effects on patients' subsequent health behaviors and on their keeping of appointments"); Roter & Hall, supra note 60, at 140-144. 81 DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 150. 82 ROTER & HALL, supra note 60, at 140. 83 Id., at 143. 84 Id., at 143-144. 22 Relational Malpractice physician.”85 Other studies have emphasized the connection between collaborative communication and "improved recovery from surgery, decreased use of pain medication, and shortened hospital stays, as well as improved physiological changes in blood pressure and blood sugar, improvement of symptoms and better management of chronic conditions.86 While there is no obvious explanation for the connection between communication and outcomes, the various studies conducted since the 1960s seem to provide strong substantiation for the link between the two. Furthermore, research has shown that patient satisfaction is dependent on effective communication with the physician and on the nature of their relationship. Indeed, perhaps surprisingly, factors relating to the quality of communication physicians had with their patients and their ability to exhibit empathy towards their patients and provide them adequate information have been shown to be the dominant factors in evaluating the quality of care they received, more so than such elements as the scope of tests ordered by physicians or the quality of their documentation.87 Specifically, patient satisfaction has been tied to physicians' mode of communication and the social climate during their meeting with the patient. A strong connection has been found to exist between patient satisfaction on the one hand and patient-centered communication in which the patient’s perspective is actively sought and facilitated through non-judgmental and open communication, the use of positive-toned statements by physicians and their well developed non-verbal skills (both in terms of deciphering patients’ feelings and needs and in generating a warm and open atmosphere) on the other hand.88 Some studies have established a connection between patients' own evaluation of the treatment they received and physicians’ performance in medical tasks.89 While patients’ ability to evaluate quality of medical services is obviously limited,90 it is a significant factor in shaping their trust in 85 Sherrie H. Kaplan et al., Assessing the Effects of Physician-Patient Interactions on the Outcomes of Chronic Disease, 27 Medical Care Supp. 110, 112 (1989). See the various studies cited in DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 158; ROTER & HALL, supra note 60, at 146-148. 86 87 http://clinicalcompetency.blogspot.com/2010/02/physician-patient-relationship.htm; Gerald B. Hickson et al., Development of an early Identification and Response Model of Malpractice Prevention, 60 L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 7, 9-12 (1997). 88 ROTER & HALL, supra note 60, at 136-138. 89 Id., at 133. 90 Id., at 134. 23 Relational Malpractice the particular physician who treated them, as well as in the healthcare system more generally.91 Finally, research has established a link between physician wellbeing and measures of high quality medical care. Physician wellbeing and satisfaction are tied to several domains, one of which is the quality of their relationship with their patients, and have been found to increase physician attentiveness and decrease such phenomena as risky prescribing practices.92 These above research findings underscore the importance of communication skills and relationships building capacities for the assurance of high quality healthcare. They thus challenge the perceived distinction between relevant and irrelevant information, as well as between medical-clinical skills on the one hand and relationships and communication skills on the other, positioning both as central to high quality professional care. Unlike the collaborative model, the oppositional model still perceives relationships and communication as very much peripheral to the clinical treatment, and often as a luxury the system cannot afford, or as a symptom of the patient’s struggle to gain power over physicians. Instead, it views technical measures that relate to clinical knowledge and skills as primary indicators of quality.93 The problems with such a distinction are twofold. First, the notion of a clear divide between clinical and non-clinical medical skills and competencies is questionable. This is due to the interdependence that exists between clinical performance and communication skills. and between the perception of the quality 91 However, people tend to rate their own doctors higher than healthcare in general, a tendency that is attributed to cognitive biases. See Roter & Hall, supra note 60, at 135. 92 Mello supra note 3, at 43. The recognition that a fresh approach to the doctor-patient relationship holds promise for increased physician wellbeing is what has driven the emergence of the narrative medicine movement. See infra notes 94-97 and accompanying text. 93 See DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 149 (stating that "[t]he role of communication in the physicianpatient relationship, however, is sometimes trivialized. It may seem natural to achieve therapeutic success by placing great emphasis on physical examinations, blood tests, x-rays, sonograms, medications, and surgeries. However, available information suggests that when this is done to the exclusion of a meaningful exchange of information and ideas… several critical elements of care are adversely affected"). This is also fostered by the fact that the system reimburses physicians for procedures done to patients and not for talking to them (id., at 153) and is evident in the prominent definitions of quality of care in the field. Avedis Donabedian, in an article mapping the prevailing approaches to the measurement of quality of medical intervention, describes three dominant approaches: (1) outcome of medical services (recovery, post-treatment functioning and survival rates); (2) process of care (appropriateness and completeness of information obtained through examinations, diagnostic tests and physicians' technical competence in performing medical intervention), and (3) structure (examining the adequacy and qualification associated with the setting in which treatment was rendered) Avedis Donabedian, Evaluating the Quality of Medical Care, 83 Milbank Quarterly 691, 692-695 (2005). 24 Relational Malpractice of care provided and how patients are treated. Second, even where the distinction between the two spheres seems correct, the hierarchy between them is flawed because it assumes the inherent inferiority of relational aspects, which are considered peripheral capabilities needed merely to ensure patient satisfaction and to assuage complaints. Despite the proven significance of relationships to quality of care, research has shown that the oppositional mode of communication constitutes the norm and attention has remained focused on physicians' clinical skills and expertise. Within the medical profession certain schools have recognized the benefits of what would fall under the definition of collaborative communication and the need for a deep structural change in the profession's understanding of the doctor-patient relationship. These strands of thought are important because among other things they express the physician's perspective and the benefits that such a shift holds for the medical profession. A prominent example is the emergence of narrative medicine.94 Narrative medicine promises to "enrich the doctor-patient relationship, improve patient care, and enhance doctors' sense of satisfaction with work" by learning to listen, to reflect and to understand the narrative conveyed by the patient, as well as by demonstrating emotion and more effectively communicating information to the patient.95 While physicians have traditionally been taught and trained to disconnect from their patients, narrative medicine advocates that doctors stay in touch with their emotions,96 thereby dismissing the common justifications in support of emotional detachment such as lack of time or the emotional burden associated with attachment.97 Another example can be found in the writing on ethics of care and their implications for the practice of medicine and for medical ethics.98 Such writing has sought to infuse a new set of principles and values into classical medical ethics, such as "human connection, responsibility, care, and context".99 94 Interest in the area has grown with over half of the medical schools in North America including such courses in their core curriculum, and a leading medical school such as Columbia offering a specialized degree in narrative medicine. 95 Divinsky, supra note 76, at 203. 96 Id., at 203. 97 Id. 98 Amy Freedman, The Physician-Patient Relationship and the Ethic of Care, 148 CAN. MED. ASSOC. J. 1037, 1037 (1993); Rosemarie Tong, The Ethics of Care: A Feminist Virtue Ethics of Care for Healthcare Practitioners, 23 J. Med. Philos. 131 (1998); D. F. CATES & P. LAURITZEN, (EDS.) MEDICINE AND THE ETHICS OF CARE (2001). 99 Freedman, supra note 98, at 1037. 25 Relational Malpractice Both movements draw on (and reinforce) the findings described above and move the debate to a higher level of abstraction by offering a normative justification for the centrality of relationships in the medical arena. At the same time, these strands have remained peripheral in the medical landscape, and have failed to garner the requisite support to bring about real change.100 One explanation could be that they have remained focused on the internal-professional front while neglecting the dynamic role of law in shaping doctorpatient relationships. C. The Law as a Barrier to a Collaborative Doctor-Patient Relationship The role of law in shaping the different types of doctor-patient relationships has changed over time. In the past, the law tended to defer to professional practices and judgment, leaving the field of what is now “healthcare law” to self regulation. As of the second half of the twentieth century the law became a central player in the power struggles between physicians, patients and other stakeholders over control and authority in decision making. At times the law seemed to reflect the old paternalistic power structure, while in other instances it served as a tool in the hands of reformers who wished to redefine these hierarchical relations through the empowerment of patients and by curbing the authority and discretion granted to physicians. In its various roles, the law has rarely singled out the doctor-patient relationship (as regards relationships more generally) as an important component of healthcare law that merits legal attention. This neglect has not meant that the law has been absent. To the contrary, the design of legal arrangements has typically placed significant barriers to the adoption of a collaborative model. As evidenced in the following examples, we find that where the law is not explicitly committed to the promotion of a collaborative doctor-patient mode of communication, it inevitably gives rise to the oppositional model, thereby cutting off opportunities for an alternative discourse to emerge. One example is the concept of "informed consent." This legal category is a relatively late development that emerged from the growing legal recognition of patients' rights in the 100 Many current medical services still lack "narrative competence," which not only detracts from "the quality of patient care, but it contributes to an ailing health care system, with dissatisfaction and frustration felt by health care consumers and those who care for them" (see www.narrativemedicine.org/announcement-1.doc (last visited on September 27, 2010). 26 Relational Malpractice latter half of the twentieth century.101 Originally, protection of patient autonomy was achieved through tort based assault claims against physicians.102 However, the categorization of unauthorized medical intervention as an assault on the patient, seemed inappropriate in a context centered on healing and care, and was therefore later situated within the realm of negligence.103 But the new legal concept of informed consent has also proven challenging. Patients are asked to sign long legal documents before undergoing procedures. Very much like uniform contracts in other contexts, the patient and her family members sign a document that states that they are aware of the nature of the procedure and the associated dangers and complications, without carefully reading the document, if at all. When asked to sign the informed consent form, they are preoccupied with the upcoming procedures, and agree to the procedure without real choice.104 We see how legal intervention, seemingly aimed at enhancing communication between doctor and patients to ensure that patients are knowledgeable about their options and are empowered to make informed decisions, defeats its purpose. In fact, this issue illustrates the consumerist model, and the ways in which legal intervention has given rise to an oppositional mode of communication. A legal regime that takes the doctor-patient relationship seriously and seeks to engender collaboration would emphasize the conditions under which information is transmitted and the manner in which understanding is verified, rather than simply providing an avenue for unilateral information transmission. Another example is the area of bioethical dilemmas and disputes. Many U.S. hospitals have established ethics committees that address and resolve conflicts over bioethical issues that arise in the course of medical treatment. Issues such as a patient's refusing life sustaining treatment are typically decided by a committee comprised of various institutional representatives. Even though the law has not mandated the adoption of ethics committees, courts have played an important role in motivating hospitals to establish such committees, and, in recent years, have come to view the decisions of such 101 Peter P. Murray, The History of Informed Consent, 10 IOWA ORTHOPEDIC JOURNAL 104 (1990). 102 Id., at 104. KATZ, supra note 19, at 68-69; Linda Farber Post, et al, Pain: ethics, Culture and Informed Consent to Relief, 24 J. L. MED. & ETHICS 348, 351 (1996). 103 104 DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 155 (stating that "[t]oo often… the obtaining of the patient's signature under considerable social and normative pressure on both parties shortly before the performance of a procedure is substituted for truly informed consent about the management of the patient's entire medical condition"). 27 Relational Malpractice committees as carrying legal weight.105 While case consultation is only one of several functions performed by ethics committees (in addition to policy formation and education), 106 it is considered controversial107 and fraught with conflict.108 The establishment of ethics committees, endorsed by the law, has failed to generate decision making that incorporates a variety of viewpoints and is responsive to patient and family needs and concerns. Despite being driven by the same trends that have given rise to informed consent, the mode of communication and interaction that surrounds ethics committee decision-making is often unilateral, confrontational and defensive (both vis-à-vis patients and family members, and within the committee).109 An alternative approach that envisions a collaborative mode of communication between physicians and patients as well as within the committee can be found in the bioethics mediation model developed by Nancy Dubler and Carol Liebman.110 Bioethics mediation provides a “neutral turf,” in which discussions on the manner in which bioethical dilemmas should be addressed can take place in an effort to reach consensus, referred to as “principled resolution.” 111 The mediation involves various members of the care team – physicians, students, nurses, social workers and consultants, while allowing patients’ and families’ voices to be heard.112 A primary advantage of bioethics mediation is therefore the fact that “it permits a problem to be characterized and analyzed by a greater number of trained professionals, thereby collecting experience and facilitating multidisciplinary discussion,” while including the patient’s own perspective, needs and views in the decision-making process.113 We see how an approach that is attuned to relationships and the preferences of the patient can generate a more effective avenue for addressing conflict in this context. However, bioethics mediation has yet to become widespread, and the vast majority of hospitals still ascribe to the unilateral, non-inclusive alternative of decision-making by ethics committees. 105 Anne Griswold Peirce, Some Considerations about Decisions and Decision-Makers in Hospital Ethics Committees, available at http://www.ojhe.org/index.php/ojhe/article/viewArticle/14/17. 106 Gregory P. Gramelspacher, Institutional Ethics Committee and Case Consultation: Is There a Role? 7 ISSUES. L. & MED. 73 (1991-1992). 107 Id. 108 NANCY N. DUBLER & CAROL B. LIEBMAN, BIOETHICS MEDIATION: A GUIDE xiv-xvi (2004). 109 DUBLER & LIEBMAN, Id.; Gramelspacher, supra note 106. 110 DUBLER & LIEBMAN, id. 111 Id., at 10. 112 Id., at xiv. 113 Id., at 12. TO SHAPING SHARED SOLUTIONS 28 Relational Malpractice A third example has to do with the allocation of decision making power between physicians and managed care organizations. In recent decades, we have witnessed a dramatic change in the structure of healthcare services, with the rise of managed care and the market paradigm.114 These new structures have challenged the traditional doctor-patient relationship by introducing another actor into the decision-making equation. Physicians are required to choose diagnostic procedures and medication from pre-approved lists or to obtain approval for exceptional treatment in advance. This state of affairs represents a major shift from past reality under which physicians enjoyed sole discretion over diagnosis and course of treatment. In the new market for medical services physician autonomy is threatened, and physicians may find themselves in a position of conflict of interest between what they perceive to be the best course of treatment for their patient and what their carrier agrees to cover. These conditions might distort incentives for open communication between physicians and patients, rendering some of the information patients could disclose to their physician irrelevant and making some of the physician’s considerations confidential. A legal framework seeking to encourage collaborative communication would favor an alternative structure for supporting the delivery of medical services, one that would allow for meaningful patient and physician participation in decision making over medical treatment. Despite some efforts by the law to remove barriers to communication stemming from the rise of managed care,115 legal intervention in many instances endorses general policies and specific decisions of managed care organizations at the expense of direct, open and mutual patient-physician interaction.116 As we can see, in all three contexts legal arrangements have ignored the significance of the doctor-patient relationship and the need for a proactive commitment to the collaborative model, resulting in tension, conflict of interest, sometimes undermining the very goals legal initiatives were designed to achieve. In some cases, bottom up efforts to transform this environment have emerged, but have achieved limited pockets of success. We believe that the injection of the collaborative model of relationships into the design of legal arrangements would generate better outcomes in terms of quality of healthcare, patient satisfaction and doctors' performance. We therefore contend that the law should adopt a 114 Timothy Hall, supra note 65. 115 See supra note 26 and accompanying text. 116 Bloche, supra note 7, at 413-414. 29 Relational Malpractice relational approach to healthcare related issues. Such an approach would provide fertile ground for the emergence of a mutual doctor-patient relationship, giving rise to a collaborative mode of communication. As we demonstrate below, the law governing the realm of medical malpractice similarly endorses the oppositional model and does not allow for a collaborative mode of communication to evolve. Within healthcare law, malpractice provides the arena in which the need for considering the doctor-patient relationship in the design of a legal framework in the field of healthcare is most pressing.117 We claim that by neglecting the doctorpatient relationship in that context, the law has driven physicians to minimize risk of liability instead of the risk of harm. These incentives for minimizing risk have penetrated both the conduct of physicians (the practice of defensive medicine) and their communication with patients (the adoption of an oppositional mode of communication). We argue that the oppositional mode of communication stems not only from professional culture, but also from physicians' desire to shield themselves from legal liability. Such a mode of communication also breeds an environment that is fraught with conflict and distrust, where both healthcare providers and the system beneficiaries are dissatisfied and frustrated. Consequently, doctor-patient relations in many instances are broken, communication is ineffective or non-existent and both sides are distrustful of one another. The following sections explore this reality, its origins and consequences, as well as the limited efforts taken to transform the existing state of affairs. IV. The Doctor-Patient Relationship in the Shadow of Malpractice A. Consumed by Malpractice: Doctor-Patient Interactions as a Battle Zone Medical malpractice has been described as the single most significant phenomenon in the healthcare arena, shaping such factors as insurance for practitioners and enterprises, professional standards and training, and the scope and nature of medical care given in particular instances.118 While early medical malpractice claims appeared around 1840 in 117 Malpractice constitutes a major area of interest in healthcare law, see Hall, supra note 8, at 350. 118 Todres, supra note 4, at 679-693. 30 Relational Malpractice the U.S.,119 malpractice litigation as we know it today is very much related to developments that took place in the mid twentieth century.120 Over time, the legal rules governing malpractice have expanded, creating a complex framework that is unpredictable, cumbersome and costly. Specifically, a medical malpractice claim must meet the basic requirements for proving that the injury resulted from a negligent act by establishing a duty of care, its breach, causation and harm. Proving these is no easy task, given the ongoing evolution of medical knowledge and standards of practice,121 the knowledge gap between healthcare providers and patients,122 and the delays and costs associated with the backlogged court system.123 Consequently, litigation results are often described as arbitrary, with justified claims not being pursued while frivolous suits may result in substantial awards.124 On the one hand, researchers have estimated that approximately 10% of potential claimants do not bring a malpractice claim precisely because of these difficulties,125 suggesting that the granting of very high awards in extreme cases obfuscates the fact that many of those injured remain undercompensated.126 On the other hand, the system enables those with financial and emotional stamina to pursue borderline claims,127 and has been critiqued for generating 119 James C. Mohr, American Medical Malpractice Litigation in Historical Perspective, 283 JAMA 1731 (2000). 120 See infra Part III.C. 121 See David. R. Riemer, Follow the Money: The Impact of Consumer Choice and Economic Incentives on Conflict Resolution in Health Care, 29 HAMLINE J. PUB. L. & POL'Y 423, 423-424 (2008) (stating that medicine "is inherently imprecise. Uncertainty, probability, and risk permeate many, if not most, of the decisions that doctors make"). 122 Paul C. Weiler, The Case for No-Fault Medical Liability, 52 MD. L. REV. 908, 926 (1993); Marlynn Wei, Doctors, Apologies and the Law: An Analysis and Critique of Apology Laws, 40 J. OF HEALTH L. 107, 153 (2007). This general knowledge gap is made even more extreme by the prevailing physician communication patterns. Oftentimes patients do not understand much of what they are being told by their physicians who tend to use professional jargon, leave little room for questions and hold very different beliefs than patients about what constitutes adequate disclosure. See DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 152. 123 Todres, supra note 4, at 681, 686. 124 Weiler, supra note 122, at 912-914; Todres, supra note 4, at 679-682;. 125 T. A. Brennan et al., Incidence of Adverse Events and Negligence in Hospitalized Patients: Results of the Harvard Medical Practice Study I, 324 NEW ENG. J. MED. 370, 371-372 (1991). 126 See Weiler, supra note 122, at 918-919; Todres, supra note 4, at 680, 682. 127 Weiler, supra note 122, at 918-919; Todres, supra note 4, at 680. 31 Relational Malpractice arbitrary and unpredictable outcomes.128 The result is a complex picture in which courts provide distorted incentives for parties.129 Even where litigation is merited, the trial typically lasts several years, during which time claimants are preoccupied with the lawsuit and find it difficult to heal and move on with their lives. Physicians, on their end, are deeply concerned with the harmful impact such litigation can have on their reputation and professional status, as well as the financial implications in terms of insurance premiums.130 In addition, they are often consumed by feelings of guilt and isolation,131 even depression.132 This state of affairs has proven taxing for healthcare providers, patients and the healthcare system at large. Malpractice litigation in the U.S. is constantly rising133 with many more potential claims being settled even before a lawsuit has been filed.134 Although malpractice claims have been more frequent in particular areas of practice,135 the reality of large scale medical malpractice claims has colored doctor-patient relations in all fields. A prominent development has been the adoption of defensive measures by the medical team in an attempt to reduce their exposure to legal liability.136 Fear of malpractice liability has also served as a real barrier to communication between the medical team and patients (and their family members) in the aftermath of a medical mistake. While patients and their 128 See Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 740 (stating that in response to the Harvard Medical Practice Study on malpractice claiming “the lawyers asserted that the study demonstrated that too many instances of malpractice went under-compensated; physicians argued that it highlighted the litigation system’s arbitrary nature and inability to distinguish negligent from non-negligent injuries”). Physicians, who predictably have very little trust in the system, typically believe that the outcome of litigation has more to do with the extent of the injury than to the existence of negligence. See Todres, supra note 4, at 684. 129 Weiler, supra note 122, 911-919; David A. Hyman, Medical Malpractice and the Tort System: What Do We Know and What (If Anything) Should We Do About It?, 80 TEX. L. REV. 1639, 1645 (2002). 130 Charity Scott, Therapeutic Approaches to ADR in Health Care Settings, 21 GA. ST. U.L. REV. 797, 798 (2005); Samuel R. Gross & Kent D. Syverud, Getting to No: A Study of Settlement Negotiations and the Selection of Cases for Trial, 90 MICH. L. REV. 319, 360-367 (1991). 131 Tom Delbanco & Bell K. Sigall, Guilty, Afraid and Alone – Struggling With Medical Error, 357 NEW. ENGL. J. OF MED. 1682, 1682 (2007). 132 See infra note 149. 133 Weiler, supra note 122, at 912 (showing that within three decades claims have rose "from approximately one claim per 100 doctors a year in the late 1950s to more than ten claims per 100 doctors in the early 1990s"). 134 Delbanco & Sigall, supra note 131. 135 See Hickson et al., supra note 87, at 7. 136 See Todres, supra note 4, at 684-685. 32 Relational Malpractice families seek an apology and information on the circumstances that gave rise to the mistake as well as its consequences, doctors often disclose as little information as possible,137 refrain from communicating with such patients altogether, and do not apologize.138 As a result, patients and family members may sue precisely because the silence and evasion by the healthcare team has generated feelings of resentment and distrust on their end and in the hope that they will obtain more information about the circumstances of the adverse event they or their loved ones experienced.139 But the reach of the fear of malpractice liability has extended beyond those instances where mistakes have actually taken place, contaminating the entire sphere of doctorpatient relations and infiltrating such interaction from the outset.140 This is very different from the idyllic portrayal of the doctor-patient relationship in some of the legal scholarship dealing with malpractice. Such relations are sometimes described as healing relationships: Relationships that are centered on physicians' desire (and duty) to relieve suffering and provide optimal treatment with "care being the foundational principle and healing being the primary objective."141 While these relations have been likened to family ties in their level of intimacy and trust,142 others have shown that the rhetoric of healing can be misleading in light of prevailing modes of professional training and treatment protocols, which are centered on physical symptoms and suffering.143 In fact, as we have shown, the 137 See Carol B. Liebman & Chris Stern Hyman, A Mediation Skills Model to Manage Disclosure of Errors and Adverse Events to Patients, 23 HEALTH AFFAIRS 22, 24, 30 (2004); Todres, supra note 4, at 685. 138 See Jay L. Hoecker, Guess who is not Coming to Dinner: Where are the Physicians at the Healthcare Mediation Table?, 29 HAMLINE J. PUB. L. & POL'Y 249, 258 & footnotes 18-21 (2008); Jonathan R. Cohen, Advising Clients to Apologize, 72 S. CAL. L. REV. 1009, 1061-1065 (1999). This reality has been somewhat softened by the adoption of "Apology Laws" aimed at encouraging physicians to provide patients and their families with information on medical errors by excluding the admission at trial of any statements of sympathy made by physicians during such disclosure (see http://www.sorryworks.net/laws.phtml (last visited on September 25, 2010)). Critics have claimed, however, that apology laws have been unsuccessful in overcoming other barriers that discourage physicians from disclosure of errors (see Wei, supra note 122). In addition, some states have adopted "mandatory disclosure laws," which have in effect forced providers to conduct conversations with patients and families in the aftermath of "serious events" (Liebman & Hyman, supra note 137, at 23). Here, like in the apology context, it is insufficient to allow for (or even mandate) such conversations to take place. For these talks to be fruitful and responsive to patient needs, they need to be conducted in accordance with patient expectations regarding provider demeanor and information provision in the course of the conversation (id., at 23-24). 139 See Delbanco & Sigall, supra note 131, at 1683; see also infra note 155 and accompanying text. 140 See the view conveyed in the following article: Wei, supra note 122, at 126. 141 Todres, supra note 4, at 675. 142 Hall, supra note 11. 143 Todres, supra note 4, at 675. 33 Relational Malpractice traditional model of doctor-patient relationships, which reflects the perception of the doctor as a powerful healer, is actually in tension with the ideal healing paradigm. This is not surprising considering the fact that physicians’ training emphasizes perfection and clinical skills over empathy and attentiveness.144 The idyllic portrayal of doctor-patient relations is further eroded when we think of the reality of delivery of medical services in many hospital departments. Long shifts in often under-staffed and under-budgeted departments have made it difficult for physicians to treat patients in accordance with their expectations by communicating with them in a timely and attentive manner.145 When patients seek medical care, in particular urgent care, they not only feel physical pain, but they (and their family members) are often under extreme emotional pressure, experiencing fear and anxiety in the face of complex, bureaucratic surroundings.146 But patients are not the only ones in pain. Such indicators as a high rate of dissatisfaction with the practice of medicine,147 physicians ceasing to practice,148 and clinical signs of depression among physicians (both those who have been sued and those who have not been sued for malpractice),149 are indicative of the breadth of the impact the malpractice crisis is having on doctor-patient interactions. Indeed, in one study, 75% of specialists agreed with the statement "[b]ecause of concerns about malpractice liability, I view every patient as a potential malpractice lawsuit."150 In this environment, the authors deduce 144 Id., at 687-688; Wei, supra note 122, at 147-149. Orna Rabinovich-Einy, Escaping the Shadow of Malpractice Law, 74 L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. (forthcoming, 2011). 145 146 See Hall, supra note 11, at 470-472. 147 See Mello et al., supra note 3, at 45. 148 Id., at 44; Allan Kachalia et at., Physician Responses to the Malpractice Crisis: From Defense to Offense, 33 J. L. MED. & ETHICS 416 (2005). See Sara C, Charles et al., Sued and Nonsued Physicians’ Self-Reported Reactions to Malpractice Litigation, 142 AM. J. PSYCHIATRY 437, 440 (1985) (stating that “[a] surprising finding was that the groups [of sued and non-sued physicians] reported a similar degree of the cluster of symptoms that might be associated with major depressive disorder … it is possible that the nonsued respondents in general had a greater vulnerability to stress, especially that related to potential litigation”). In another article, malpractice litigation is found to generate feelings of uneasiness, vulnerability, frustration and anger. This impact is related to the allegation of malpractice, not to the outcome of the litigation and therefore, being cleared of the allegations may do little to alleviate these feelings. Wei, supra note 122, at 139-140 and the references therein. 149 150 Mello et al., supra note 3, at 49. 34 Relational Malpractice that "[a]n atmosphere of high liability risk and costs may affect the physician-patient relationship, precluding mutual trust and hampering communication (relationships)."151 Indeed, research has found that physicians tend to adopt a defensive mode of communication – one that is hierarchical, distant and confrontational or is based on avoidance and withdrawal.152 Under such oppositional modes of communication there is very little engagement, limited listening and reduced understanding. The consequences of poor communication between physicians and patients can be grave. Obviously, a mode of communication driven by distrust on both sides is bound to engender frequent conflicts, which range from small scale conflicts stemming from long waits to actual malpractice allegations. In such a setting, incentives and instincts go in opposite directions: Physicians will seek to communicate as little as possible so as to minimize risk while the patients and family members will want as much information as possible so as to allow them to feel safe and to trust their doctor.153 Patients are bound to feel they are being treated in a curt and disrespectful manner. Therefore, the long waits with little proactive attention and few updates can be expected to generate angry responses. Such a loud environment, in turn, is hardly conducive to high quality healthcare services. The harm produced by frequent clashes in the corridor can be expected to expand beyond discomfort by affecting concentration and morale, potentially impacting clinical decision making. But the connection between communication and malpractice runs even deeper than the potential impact of background noise on the quality of treatment provided; high quality medical care depends on the existence of effective communication between physicians and patients (as well as within the care team). As we have shown, the ability to communicate effectively with patients and establishing trust is a key for physicians to solicit all necessary information on patient history and current symptoms, as well as to ensure that patients adhere to the treatment ascribed by their physician.154 The need for a collaborative mode of communication with patients for administering high quality medical 151 Id., at 44. 152 Rabinovich-Einy, supra note 145. This phenomenon has received wide attention in the context of doctor-patient communication in the aftermath of a medical error (see Thomas Gallagher et al., Choosing Your Words Carefully: How Physicians Would Disclose Harmful Medical Errors to Patients, 166 Arch. Intern. Med. 1585 (2006)), but has also been found to infiltrate such communications throughout treatment, even before an error has occurred (see generally Rabinovich-Einy, supra note 145). 153 154 See supra Part II.C. 35 Relational Malpractice services is in tension with physicians' incentives to minimize such contact, so as to protect themselves, should their encounter evolve into a dispute involving a malpractice allegation. Paradoxically, their desire to minimize risk, which translates into an oppositional mode of communication, actually increases the likelihood of their making a mistake, as well as that of being sued.155 Fear of liability, resulting from the current malpractice system, extends beyond the individual level, infiltrating the doctor-patient relationship and interactions on a structural level. This is evident in physicians’ reluctance to disclose information relating to errors and near misses, which not only harms individual patients, but also hinders the ability to learn from past errors and prevent future ones through open discussion.156 Effective doctor-patient communication and mutual relations between the two groups are therefore important not only for enhancing the wellbeing of both doctors and patients,157 but, as we have shown, also for improving the quality of medical services.158 To better understand the source of the difficulties in doctor-patient relations described above, in the following section we examine some of the historic developments that have shaped the doctor-patient relationship in the malpractice context in recent decades, revealing the centrality of communication in conflict between doctors and physicians as well as the role of communication as a potential source for prevention and resolution of malpractice-related conflicts. 155 Many articles tie patients’ motivation to sue and their physicians’ communication patterns over disclosure of errors. Specifically, major driving forces for suing physicians are the desire for information about the circumstances under which the error occurred, as well as the physicians demeanor and seeking an apology. See Kathleen M. Mazor et al., Communicating With Patients About Medical Errors: A Review of the Literature, 164 ARCH. INTERN. MED. 1690 (2004); Bernard B. Virshup et al., Strategic Risk Management: Reducing Malpractice Claims through More Effective Patient-Doctor Communication, 14 AM. J. MED. QUALITY, 153 (1999); Wendy Levinson et al., Physician-Patient Communication: The Relationship with Malpractice Claims Among Primary Care Physicians and Surgeons, 277 JAMA 553 (1997); Christine M. Duclos et al., Patient Perspectives of Patient-Provider Communication After Adverse Events, 17 INT'L J. FOR QUALITY IN HEALTHCARE 479 (2005); Hickson et al., supra note 87. See also DiMatteo, supra note 69, at 151 (stating that "[e]ffective communication can reduce the risk of malpractice litigation significantly by enhancing the physician's capacity to determine the patient's expectations for treatment outcomes, thereby reducing misunderstanding between physician and patient."). In addition, when medical decisions are a product of collaborative communication, patients are less likely to blame their physicians for the outcome (id., at 157). 156 See Todres, supra note 4, at 688. This reluctance also extends to errors made by others, promoting “a culture of protecting other doctors’ actions” (id., at 691). 157 Divinsky, supra note 76, at 203 (stating that better communication could provide “a remedy for the burnout, exhaustion and disillusionment many… physicians are feeling”). 158 See supra Part II.C.; Michelle Mello et al., supra note 3, at 43 (tying the “culture of mistrust” that develops under a malpractice regime to the quality of care delivered); Todres, supra note 4, at 687 (stating that “[t]he current malpractice liability system deters open dialogue and information exchange to the detriment of patient care as well as the emotional well-being of both patients and healthcare providers"). 36 Relational Malpractice B. The Sources of Current Tensions in Doctor-Patient Relations The history of doctor-patient relations in recent decades can shed some light on the contentious nature of these interactions in the malpractice context. Over the years, physician-patient relations have changed with patients gaining increased power vis-à-vis doctors and the medical establishment, while physicians have lost some of their authority and have had to accept a heightened degree of scrutiny by their patients. These changes can be attributed to several factors, among them legal recognition of individual patient rights (associated with the "moral paradigm")159 and the rise of consumer rights (i.e., rights in healthcare as opposed to the right to healthcare),160 developments that have been strengthened by the healthcare industry's own commercial interests (as portrayed by the "market paradigm").161 In terms of patient rights, a deep change took place in the 1970s, as a series of court decisions did away with traditional paternalism in doctor-patient relations and made way for a new approach enshrining patients' right to make informed medical decisions and to view and correct their medical records, and delineating the care team's duty to obtain patients' informed consent for medical procedures, to keep full medical records, and to maintain confidentiality of such records.162 The concept of patient informed consent, and related rights, such as the right to refuse treatment, were further developed by the courts and in the literature in the 1980s.163 While patients have gained increased power, the medical profession has experienced an all time low on the personal, professional and organizational levels with a general decline,164 a 159 Supra notes 17-19 and accompanying text. 160 For this distinction, see George J. Annas, A National Bill of Patients' Rights, 338 N. ENGL. J. MED. 695 (1998) 161 Supra notes 21-22 and accompanying text. Marc A. Rodwin, Patient Accountability and the Quality of Care: Lessons from Medical Consumerism and the Patients' Rights, Women's Health and Disability Rights Movements, 20 AM. J. L. & MED. 147, 150-151 (1994) (hereinafter "Patient Accountability"); Annas, supra note 19, at 695-696. 162 163 See Rodwin, supra note 162, at 152-153. 164 Marion Crain, The Transformation of the Professional Workforce, 79 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 543, 564571 (2004); George Ritzer & David Walczak, Rationalization and the Deprofessionalization of Physicians, 67 SOCIAL FORCES 1 (1988-1989); Herbert Kritzer, The Professions Are Dead, Long Live the Professions: Legal Practice in a Post-Professional World, 33 L. & SOC'Y REV. 713 (1999). 37 Relational Malpractice drain in medical staff in particular fields of medicine165 and extreme financial crises at public and community hospitals.166 Availability of medical information has made patients more informed,167 while developments in technology have made it ever more difficult for doctors to know all that they are expected to know.168 The close of the twentieth century and the beginning of the twenty-first have been accompanied by extensive writing on the decline of the "professions." In a well-known article, Herbert Kritzer describes the decline of the medical and legal professions due to a combination of factors, mainly the rise of digital media and the wide availability of information formerly monopolized by the professions coupled with increased specialization and compartmentalization of the work into routine, simple and repetitive tasks some of which can now be handled quite effectively by low-skill workers at much lower costs.169 These developments have pierced doctors' authority over patients and have transformed the doctor-patient relationship quite dramatically. While in the past, patients acceded to their doctor's advice, nowadays the generalist family doctor has given way to a series of specialists whose authority is often questioned by patients and their families, in light of information that is freely available online, competing experts' opinions, and constantly evolving technologies that challenge existing conceptions.170 Challenges to the authority of medical experts have been voiced not only in terms of treatment of individual patients, but have also served to uncover patterns of treatment to specified groups of patients, such as women and people with disabilities, exposing the biases expressed by medical professionals, the existence of alternative avenues for treatment and the limits of expert opinion.171 These changes have allowed patients to more frequently contest the course of 165 Florence Yee, Mandatory Mediation: The Extra Dose Needed to Cure the Medical Malpractice Crisis, 7 CARDOZO J. CONFLICT RESOL. 393, 399-400 (2006). 166 See John D. Blum, Beyond the Bylaws Hospital-Physician Relationships, Economics and Conflicting Agendas, 53 BUFF. L. REV. 459, 463 (2005-06); Sara Rosenbaum et al., EMATALA and the Hospital "Community Engagement": The Search for a Rational Policy, 53 BUFF. L. REV. 499, 499 (2005-06). 167 P. Greg Gulick, E-health and the Future of Medicine: The Economic, Legal, Regulatory, Cultural and Organizational Obstacles Facing Telemedicine and Cybermedicine Programs, 12 ALB. L.J. SCI. & TECH. 351, 373 (2001-02). 168 Riemer, supra note 121, at 425. 169 Kritzer, supra note 164. 170 Id. at 725-731. These developments are typical of the Israeli healthcare arena as well. See Ran Belitzer, The Revolution Of Information And The Impact On Doctor Patient Relationship, 749 HAREFUA 143(10) (2004). 171 See Rodwin, supra note 162, at 157-166; PAUL STARR, THE SOCIAL TRANSFORMATION MEDICINE 388-389 (1982). OF AMERICAN 38 Relational Malpractice treatment recommended by the healthcare team, generating arguments in the course of treatment and malpractice accusations and claims in retrospect. Patients have gained increased power not only vis-à-vis their caregivers, but also with regard to the medical establishment. Increasingly, hospitals are being driven by competition and commercial considerations,172 seeking, on the one hand, to draw more patients (at least to certain departments and for specific procedures) and on the other, to reduce expenditures primarily by cutting hospitalization costs.173 These changes have put departments like emergency rooms under severe pressure, but have also given patients, or at least some patients suffering from certain illnesses, more power.174 Since consumers make choices and such choices are often based on their satisfaction with treatment, patients' voices and concerns have become more prominent.175 In other cases, however, dissatisfaction and conflicts have remained widespread phenomenon. Through the years, litigation over malpractice-related claims has soared,176 as have other conflicts over such matters as coverage for medical services and complaints over doctor demeanor.177 With the rise in complaints and conflicts. many physicians have come to view patients with suspicion, fearing that professional encounters could deteriorate into legal debacles in the future.178 Similarly, patients have consistently complained about physicians’ distant and cold demeanor and their reluctance to provide satisfactory explanations in a direct and comprehensible fashion.179 172 As a result of a combination of factors that have taken place since the 1970s, U.S. hospitals were transformed from "community service entities" to "healthcare delivery businesses." Blum, supra note 166, at 463. 173 id. 174 Rodwin, supra note 162, at 155-157 175 Louise G. Trubek, New Governance and Soft Law in Health Care Reform, 3 Ind. Health L. Rev. 137, 157-158 (2006). But see Rodwin, supra note 162, at 154-155 (describing the difficulties in making such decisions in light of information asymmetries as well as some of the ways these problems have been addressed). 176 Weiler, supra note 122, at 912; Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 727. 177 Indeed, in recent years many hospitals and medical groups have instituted an ombudsman or patient affairs office to handle such complaints. See Hickson, supra note 87, at 12. 178 See Supra notes 150-151 and accompanying text. 179 See supra notes 87-88 and accompanying text. 39 Relational Malpractice As we can see, the picture of doctor-patient relations that emerges from the above overview is a complex one. On the one hand, the changes that have occurred in the last few decades can be seen as a positive development enshrining patient rights and contributing to the equalization of access to important information. On the other hand, these very developments and the ensuing change of balance in doctor-patient relations have also given rise to distrust, conflict, and defensive conduct on the part of healthcare practitioners. While doctors have always been infamous for their brusque manner, the role played by fear of liability in sustaining such communication culture has received insufficient attention. As the historic overview suggests, it may very well be that the tortsbased malpractice regime is what has sustained doctors’ traditional mode of communication in the face of social pressures for change. In the following section we elaborate on some of the exceptional efforts launched by the medical and legal establishments, attempting to transform the medical communication culture, often driven by the desire to reduce malpractice claims precisely because of the empirical data substantiating the connection between communication skills and the likelihood of making an error on the one hand, as well as the tie between communication and the likelihood of patients suing for malpractice on the other hand. We also suggest why such efforts have enjoyed only limited success so far. While the measures described below represent an understanding that the doctor-patient relationship is in crisis and a new balance needs to be found so as to restore trust, these targeted avenues fail to address the root cause of the problem: the need to do away with the incentives provided by the current torts system governing malpractice disputes and to adopt instead a legal regime that allows for a collaborative doctor-patient relationship to develop. C. Partial Measures for Improving Doctor-Patient Communication There have been limited areas in which the connection between communication and malpractice has led to the adoption of important reforms and changes, as evidenced in the realm of physician communication training,180 in the institutionalization of alternative 180 See Bobbi McAdoo, Physicians: Listen Up and Take Your Communication Skills Training Seriously, 29 HAMLINE J. PUB. L. & POL’Y 287, 290-293 (2008) (describing the impressive efforts to introduce communication skills training into the curriculum of medical schools in the years since the publication of “To Err is Human”). 40 Relational Malpractice dispute resolution (ADR) avenues in hospitals for addressing doctor-patient disputes,181 in the adoption of laws requiring providers to establish "disclosure conversations" with patients and family members in the aftermath of an serious adverse event,182 and in the adoption of measures for encouraging communication between healthcare providers and patients in the aftermath of a medical error in the form of "Apology Laws" that shield doctors who apologize for a mistake from legal liability,183 and/or protocols for disclosure of medical mistakes by healthcare institutions.184 In this vein, the Department of Health and Human Services recently awarded four grants, totaling $10 million, devoted to research on the connection among patient safety, malpractice litigation and doctor-patient communication.185 Many of the above efforts, including the recent grant scheme, have been driven primarily by concern over malpractice litigation and a desire to reduce the number of errors and claims. Enhancing doctor communication skills has been seen as a preventative measure against the occurrence of mistakes based on the realization that at least some errors were a result of poor communication. The establishment of ADR channels and the adoption of the "Apology Laws" have been viewed as a means for encouraging pre-litigation resolution of malpractice disputes by satisfying the patient's and/or family members' need for information and/or for an apology.186 These developments have been based on a substantial body of research establishing that patients' decisions whether to sue in the aftermath of a medical mistake are not based on monetary considerations,187 but driven by 181 Gary A. Balcerzak & Kathryn K Leonhardt, Alternative Dispute Resolution in Healthcare: A Prescription for Increasing Disclosure and Improving Patient Safety, PATIENT SAFETY & QUALITY HEALTHCARE (2008), available at http://www.psqh.com/julaug08/resolution.html. 182 Liebman & Hyman, supra note 137. 183 Jonathan R. Cohen, Advising Clients to Apologize, 72 S. CAL. L. REV. 1009, 1061-1065 (1999); Jonathan R. Cohen, Legislating Apology: The Pros and Cons, 70 U. CIN. L. REV. 819 (2002); Liebman & Hyman, supra note 137; Carole Houk, The Internal Neutral: Why Doesn't Your Hospital Have One?, mediate.com, June 2002, http://www.mediate.com/articles/houk.cfm (last visited on August 10, 2009). 184 See Liebman & Hyman, supra note 137; See Massachusetts Coalition for the Prevention of Medical Errors, When Things Go Wrong: Responding to Adverse Events: A Consensus Statement of the Harvard Hospitals (2006) [hereinafter: When Things Go Wrong]. 185 See Carol B. Liebman, Medical Malpractice Mediation: Benefits Gained, Opportunities Lost, 74 L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. (forthcoming, 2011). 186 Dale C. Hetzler et al., Curing Conflict: A Prescription for ADR in Healthcare, 11 DISP. RESOL. MAG. 5, 6 (2004); Donald J. Cegala & Stefne Lenzmeier Broz, Physician Communication Skills Training: A Review of Theoretical Backgrounds, Objectives and Skills, 36 MED. EDUC. 1004, 1004 (2002). 187 Tamara Relis, "It's Not About the Money!": A Theory on Misconceptions of Plaintiffs' Litigation Aims , 68 U. PITT. L. REV. 701 (2007); Liebman & Hyman, supra note 137, at 30. 41 Relational Malpractice frustration over lack of communication about medical errors and mishaps.188 Consequently, numerous U.S. hospitals have adopted internal conflict management schemes189 for addressing patient complaints and malpractice disputes.190 Interestingly, while these efforts have shown real potential in addressing some of the deeprooted problems associated with malpractice,191 the various initiatives have not succeeded in bringing about real change in the communication culture between doctors and patients and have failed to significantly reduce communication problems with patients. explanation for the persistence of the 192 hierarchical, distant and curt mode The of communication in doctor-patient relations has typically focused on the traditional values and culture of the medical profession.193 While professional culture is certainly a factor in sustaining the oppositional communication style, we believe that the current legal regime governing malpractice disputes plays a significant role in cutting off communication channels between physicians and patients. This is true not only in the aftermath of a medical mistake, but in a much deeper sense, infiltrating doctor-patient relations from the outset, leading doctors to focus on “reducing risk rather than error.”194 Therefore, it is our contention that only by displacing the malpractice system in its entirety, would it be possible to escape its shadow and transform doctor-patient relations in a meaningful way. Clearly current piecemeal tort reform initiatives cannot achieve this goal. They are aimed at remedying the litigation and insurance crises surrounding 188 See supra note 155 and accompanying text. 189 Susan J. Szmania et al., Alternative Dispute Resolution in Medical Malpractice: A Survey of Emerging Trends and Practices, 26 CONFLICT RES. Q. 71, 79-80 (2008. Liebman & Hyman, supra note 137; Balcerzak & Leonhardt, supra note 181; Szmania et al., supra note 189, at 77. Charity Scott, Therapeutic Approaches to ADR in Health Care Settings, 21 GA. ST. U.L. REV. 797, 798 (2005); Sheea Sybblis, Mediation in the Health Care System: Creative Problem Solving, 6 PEPP. DISP. RESOL. L.J. 493 (2006). 190 191 Balcerzak & Leonhardt, supra note 181; Szmania et al., supra note 189, at 74-75, 77. 192 Coby Anderson & Linda D'Antonio, Empirical Insights: Understanding the Unique Culture of Health Care Conflict, 11 Disp. Resol. Mag. 15, 17 (2004) (citing a healthcare professional who described how the conflict resolution skills taught in medical school get "untaught" in the residency period). Naturally, although this could be a result of the quality of particular trainings and courses offered (see Cegala & Broz, supra note 55), the view offered in this article is that there is a deeper explanation for this failure. 193 Hoecker, supra note 138, at 252. 194 Todres, supra note 4, at 677. An additional result of this reaction is the growing practice of defensive medicine, see id., at 684-685. 42 Relational Malpractice malpractice and therefore leave intact the underlying structure of negligence based liability regime.195 Other proposals for reforming the ills of the current malpractice regime have offered a more radical change in the form of a shift to contractual liability on the one hand, or the adoption of a no fault administrative liability scheme, on the other hand. The contractual approach calls for the substitution of the traditional torts regime in the malpractice arena with a contractual arrangement between patients and either individual providers or insurers.196 This approach assumes sufficient knowledge, sophistication and information by patients to reach adequate contractual bargains. This assumption has been convincingly critiqued from both economic197 and behavioral perspectives.198 Furthermore, this approach fails to acknowledge the centrality of doctor-patient relations and therefore provides little hope for transformation on this realm. By contrast, we find that the no fault option lays the foundation for real change on the relational front. We therefore advocate a shift from a torts-based system to the adoption of a no fault administrative scheme. This proposal is by no means a new one. As we describe below, no fault reform proposals emerged as early as the 1970s. However, past proposals have been based on varying justifications ranging from improved compensation for victims to enhanced patient safety. None of those proposals put forth a justification grounded in the doctor-patient relationship and its impact on the quality of healthcare. In the following section we examine whether and under what conditions the shift to no fault would allow physicians to adopt a collaborative mode of communication and build better relationships with patients, boosting existing efforts within the medical arena to improve communication and transform the doctor-patient relationship. V. A. No-Fault as a Means for Transforming the Doctor-Patient Relationship The History of the No Fault Alternative: From Compensation to Learning Since the mid-1970s the medical and legal literature on malpractice have presented the no fault compensation scheme for injuries related to medical errors as an attractive 195 Todres, supra note 4, at 693-697. Jennifer Arlen, Contracting Over Liability: Medical Malpractice and the Cost of Choice, 158 U. PENN. L. REV. 957 (2010). 196 197 See id. Tom Baker & Timothy Lytton, Allowing Patients to Waive the Right to Sue for Medical Malpractice: A Response to Thaler and Sunstein, 104 NW. U. L. REV. (forthcoming 2010). 198 43 Relational Malpractice alternative to the existing tort-based system.199 The interest in no fault has been driven by the emergence of such systems in other countries, with New Zealand and Sweden being the leading models.200 The developments abroad permeated the U.S. legal system in the late 1980s, in a somewhat different format. The U.S. experiment introduced pockets of no fault systems in two states – Virginia and Florida,201 but the calls for a more comprehensive reform of the medical malpractice system have yet to be embraced. The interest in the no fault alternative for medical errors in the U.S. was linked to what has been termed the "malpractice crisis." This crisis was manifested in soaring insurance rates for practitioners,202 a brain drain in certain high-risk specialties,203 and the proliferation of defensive medicine,204 all of which have resulted in rising healthcare and 199 Clark C. Havighurst & Laurence R. Tancredi, ”Medical Adversity Insurance”—A No-Fault Approach to Medical Malpractice and Quality Assurance, 51 MILBANK MEMORIAL FUND Q. 125 (1973); Jeffrey O’Connell, No-Fault Insurance for Injuries Arising from Medical Treatment: A Proposal for Elective Coverage, 24 EMORY L. J. 21 (1975); Weiler, supra note 122; Eleanor D. Kinney, Malpractice Reform in the 1990s: Past Disappointment, Future Success?, 20 J. HEALTH POLITICS, POLICY AND LAW 99, 106 (1995); Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 728. The literature on medical errors has distinguished between medical errors and adverse events with an inner distinction between preventable and unpreventable adverse events. An adverse event is defined as “an injury that was caused by medical management rather than the patient’s underlying disease. … an adverse event may or may not result from an error.” Medical errors are defined as “the failure of a planned action to be completed as intended or the use of a wrong plan to achieve an aim. Medical errors include serious errors, minor errors, and near misses … A medical error may or may not cause harm.” A preventable adverse event refers to “an injury (or complication) that results from an error or system’s failure.” An unpreventable adverse event is defined as “an injury or complication that was not due to an error or systems failure and is not always preventable at the current state of scientific knowledge.” See When Things Go Wrong, supra note 184, at 4-5. The torts system compensates claimants only for those medical errors that meet the legal requirements for negligence. No fault initiatives have expanded the scope of events covered, depending on the specific definition of the triggering event for compensation. In this paper, we use the terms medical error and adverse events in accordance with the above definition, but as we demonstrate in infra Part IV.B., our approach makes such distinction less acute than previous cases, as we advocate the adoption of a comprehensive system that provides redress (not necessarily monetary) for a broad range of adverse events. 200 See Allen Kachalia et al., Beyond Negligence: Avoidability and Medical Injury Compensation, 66 SOC. SCI. & MED. 387 (2008). 201 These systems were designed to cover specific instances of birth-related injuries, as a substitute for the general torts system. In both states, the stimulus for the shift to no fault was a severe insurance crisis because of which obstetricians were unable to obtain insurance coverage and, consequently, access to obstetric care was severely limited. See Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 738-739; Siegal et al., Adjudicating Severe Birth Injuries Claims in Florida and Virginia: The Experience of a Landmark Experiment in Personal Injury Compensation, 34 AM. J. L.& MED. 489 (2008); Maxwell J. Mehlman, Bad “Bad Baby” Bills, 20 AM. J. L. & MED 129 (1994). 202 See Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 728. See Michelle Mello et al., Effects of a Malpractice Crisis on Specialist Supply and Patient Access to Care, 242 ANNALS OF SURGERY 621 (2005). 203 204 See supra note 194 44 Relational Malpractice legal costs. The crisis was never perceived as one relating to the doctor-patient relationship even though the problem soon gave rise to the battle zone mentality described above, and proponents of no fault never set as a goal the transformation of relations between patients and physicians through legal reform. The no fault option has been hailed by its proponents for its promise of a just, simple and efficient framework in lieu of the complex, cumbersome, unpredictable and costly tort option.205 The no fault alternative is premised on the establishment of an administrative scheme that offers broad compensation that is not dependant on the question of negligence or personal blame of a healthcare provider.206 Instead, eligibility is determined based on a definition of the triggering event.207 In addition, the system provides more limited compensation to a broader class of claimants, thereby controlling some of the indeterminacies associated with the torts system.208 The thought has been that this structure would generate a more equitable, quick and inexpensive compensation scheme, independent of the overburdened and unpredictable court option.209 The global political climate which gave rise to the early no fault alternatives in the 1970s and 1980s was grounded in the meeting point between two intellectual frameworks: the then prominent social welfare paradigm210 (which was one of the sources of the moral paradigm) and the rise of a market approach to law211 (evidenced in the rise of the market paradigm in the specific context of healthcare law). As we can see, the dawn of one era and the rise of another, created an atmosphere that was receptive to the no fault alternative. 205 See David M. Studdert & Troyen A. Brennan, No-Fault Compensation for Medical Injuries, 286 JAMA 217, 220 (2001); Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 726. 206 Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 219. 207 Id. 208 Id., at 220. 209 Id., at 226. The social welfare paradigm reigned in the 20 th century, and emphasized values and principles such as solidarity, social responsibility and a high degree of government involvement in the regulation of markets and led to the strengthening of social security arrangements in various countries. The U.S. was no exception, with the adoption of Workers’ Compensation systems. The social welfare worldview comported with the adoption of a no fault alternative because such system would allow for a broader and more equitable compensation base. See Weiler, supra note 122, at 924. 210 211 See supra notes 21-22 and accompanying text. The spread of the market paradigm in torts and healthcare was indicative of a shift in the broader political climate from a social welfare to a neo-liberal ideology. Under a law and economics analysis, efficiency is the primary goal of legal arrangements. The no fault alternative was viewed by some scholars as a superior means for advancing efficiency by reducing litigation-related costs, curbing the rise in insurance premiums, better spread of harm among the various actors implicated, and better serving deterrence through improved correlation between the degree of harm caused and level of compensation awarded. 45 Relational Malpractice Nevertheless, these systems only took hold in countries with elaborate welfare systems and were fiercely critiqued in the U.S. on two major grounds – the need for individual deterrence through personal liability, and the higher costs for the public associated with scope of coverage under such systems.212 Deterrence was recognized as a major goal of the torts-based system following the spread of law and economics literature in the 1970s and 1980s. The law and economics school underscored the significance of legal incentives in shaping human behavior in a manner that maximizes aggregate welfare. By establishing individual liability, it was believed that a rational doctor would be deterred from acting negligently. As we can see, while liability is placed on an individual healthcare provider, the rationale behind such a policy is a broadsocietal one. The resistance to the no fault alternative stemmed from the position that individual blame was essential for steering physicians’ future conduct and the inculcation of safe practices by individuals.213 Ironically, it was the early law and economics literature that led to the rise of deterrence as the new goal of the torts system also justified a shift to no fault, based on the torts system’s failure to realize deterrence.214 It therefore seemed questionable to reject no fault arrangements based on the grounds of deterrence.215 Another major source of critique of no fault schemes related to the costs that operating such systems would allegedly entail. Critics claimed that these systems are prohibitively expensive due to costs associated with the larger pool of claimants.216 Proponents, on the other hand, emphasized the need to include more justified claims in the compensation scheme than the current torts system, which presents significant barriers to the pursuit of 212 Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 220. 213 Id., at 220. See also Michelle Mello & Troyen A. Brennan, Deterrence of Medical Errors; Theory and Evidence for Malpractice Reform, 80 TEX. L. REV. 1595, 1636 (2002). 214 Guido Calabresi’s seminal book The Costs of Accidents, published in 1970, played a key role in advancing the idea that a fault based regime is not an optimal vehicle for achieving efficiency and deterrence: “Fault uses the market in an extensive and unstable way to reduce fault caused accidents, while from the standpoint of market deterrence, we want to use the market in an efficient and stable way to reduce accident costs, whether they are fault-caused or not.” GUIDO CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS: A LEGAL AND ECONOMIC ANALYSIS 26 (1970) (cited in O’Connell, supra note 199, at 767). 215 Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 220; See also Mello & Brennan, supra note 213, at 1603-1606 (addressing the critiques voiced against the no fault option based on deterrence). 216 Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 748. 46 Relational Malpractice justified claims.217 Indeed, the debate could be framed as a controversy over whether the torts system was one in which there were too many or too few claims.218 In effect, the question remained which legal arrangement could deliver the goal of just compensation, at a reasonable cost, without sacrificing deterrence. The first comprehensive attempt to provide empirical data that would shed light on the debate was published in the 1990s by a group based in the Harvard School of Public Health (the “Harvard Group”). This was an extensive study of medical injury and malpractice claims in New York, which investigated the prevalence of injuries incurred during medical treatment, the incidence of malpractice, and the rate of claiming for malpractice.219 The study produced fresh data on the state of medical injury revealing that 4% of hospitalized patients experience an “adverse event,” approximately half of which are defined as “preventable.”220 Half of the preventable injuries have been found to be the result of negligence by the healthcare provider,221 but in only 10% or so of these instances claims were filed.222 Another striking discovery was that “[p]aradoxically, many claims that were filed did not appear to involve harmful negligence.” 223 Based on the above findings, the Harvard Group called for a shift to an administrative no fault regime.224 Indeed, in the years and decades that followed, members of the group became the most vocal advocates of the no fault alternative. Their New York research was extended to additional 217 Weiler, supra note 122, at 921-925. Weiler raises an additional important aspect of the costs of malpractice versus no fault, arguing that “the resulting costs will be ‘afforded’ somehow – if not by the broader community, then by the immediate victim and family.” Id., at 922. 218 Those who opposed the no fault reform proposals typically viewed the malpractice crisis (rising insurance premiums) as resulting from (and generating) over-litigiousness. Therefore, while they recognized the need for change, they endorsed reforms such as caps on non-economic damages, shortening statute of limitations, and limiting attorney fees, while leaving the torts framework in place (Todres, supra note 4, at 693-697). Others, on the other hand, focused on the need for redressing those injured in the course of medical treatment claiming that “The Crisis is Injuries, Not Liability”, Richard A. Able, The Crisis is Injuries, Not Liability, 37 NEW DIRECTIONS IN LIABILITY LAW 31 (1988). 219 Brennan et al., supra note 125; Leape, L. L., et al., The Nature of Adverse Events in Hospitalized Patients: Results of the Harvard Medical Practice Study II, 324 NEW ENG. J. MED. 377 (1991); Localio, A. R., et al., Relation between Malpractice Claims and Adverse Events Due to Negligence: Results of the Harvard Medical Practice Study III, 325 NEW ENG. J. MED. 245 (1991). 220 Brennan et al, supra note 125, at 371-372. 221 Id. 222 Barringer et al, supra note 65, at 740. 223 Id. 224 Id. 47 Relational Malpractice jurisdictions and produced an impressive body of research devoted to the topic published in leading legal and medical journals.225 The data produced by the Harvard Group generated a lively debate on the adequacy of compensation under each alternative (torts vs. no fault). However, the group failed to generate conclusive data226 on both the costs227 and deterrence228 under each alternative. Their study acknowledged the problem of costs,229 but posited that this could be controlled through adequate system design by adopting threshold measures and caps on compensation.230 Furthermore, it seems that the focus on compensation as the sole factor determining costs seems too narrow a view as it fails to address major costs associated with the current system (defensive medicine, adjudication, etc.) and the no fault alternative (administrative costs). This narrow approach may represent a pragmatic recognition that measuring a broader array of costs is a thorny task.231 Over time, the issue of deterrence became a major source of resistance to the no fault option.232 Although the original studies were not designed with deterrence in mind, the Harvard Group’s later work provides important insights into the inherent difficulties in measuring deterrence.233 More importantly, the group questioned the validity of an individual deterrence paradigm by shifting the focus from an individualistic approach to a system-based error prevention framework, and suggesting that the torts system's 225 Hyman, supra note 129, at 1641-1642 & n. 6. 226 Id., at 1646. 227 William G. Johnson et al., The Economic Consequences of Medical Injuries, 267 JAMA 2487 (1992). 228 229 Mello & Brennan, supra note 213. Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 220. 230 Id.; Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 728. The Harvard Group, however, did not address a different problem related to the role that cost play in the very definition of “preventable adverse event,” as defined in the IOM report. As one commentator rightfully claims, these definitions are not objectively determined since high prevention costs could make an event “unpreventable” and therefore noncompensable. See Maxine M Harrington, Revisting Medical Error: Five Years After the IOM Report, Have Reporting Systems Made A Measurable Difference? 15 Health Matrix 329 (2005). 231 David M. Studdert et al, Can the United States Afford a "No-Fault" System of Compensation for Medical Injury? 60 L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 1 (1997); David M. Studdert et al, Toward a Workable Model of "No-Fault' Compensation for Medical Injury in the United States, 27 AM. J. L. & MED. 225, 233-234 (2001). 232 Weiler, supra note 122, at 949 & n. 110; Todres, supra note 4, at 701 & n. 155. 233 Hyman, supra note 129, at 1646-1647. While factors such as the relationship between “tort risk” and “cost per patient” may at first blush seem indicative of a deterring effect on healthcare providers, they may also reflect added expenditures associated with defensive medicine practices. Mello & Brennan, supra note 213, at 1610; Weiler, supra note 122, at 916-917. 48 Relational Malpractice deterrence capacity is questionable at best while carefully designed no fault systems are "far better placed to [deter] than negligence-based litigation."234 Nevertheless, the proposal failed to garner the requisite support for actual policy change,235 demonstrating the limitations of the political paradigm described above.236 No fault became a limited solution for displacing narrowly defined pockets of torts litigation as in the case of the “bad baby” and vaccination laws where such crises did in fact materialize.237 The dawn of the twenty-first century brought about an important change in the understanding of the malpractice problem: It was no longer an insurance crisis, but a question of quality. The impetus for change was the publication of the provocative Institute of Medicine report “To Err is Human” in 1999.238 The report unveiled fresh data on the prevalence of medical injuries and their causes. It described medical errors as the eighth leading cause of death in the U.S., a figure higher than motor vehicle or breast cancerrelated deaths.239 In addition, the report expanded on the various costs associated with medical errors, highlighting the significance of intangible costs such as loss of trust in doctors and the healthcare system or loss of morale by healthcare providers, which have often been overlooked in previous studies.240 The report laid the foundation for the shift from an individualistic perspective focused on compensating injured patients and deterring specific healthcare providers to a systemic approach geared towards prevention 234 Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 220. 235 Undoubtedly, the inconclusive nature of the data on deterrence and costs was a major factor in sustaining the status quo. Another important factor hindering reform has been the divergence in the interests of key stakeholders. As the Harvard Group members reflect retrospectively, not only was there divergence among physicians, attorneys, insurers and consumers, but also a diversity of positions, needs and interests within each group (see Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 743-745, 747-750). Without broad political support for such a scheme, a shift to no fault was unlikely. In addition, in the 1990s there was no sense of urgency for reform because there was no so-called “malpractice crisis” at that time (id., at 742). 236 See supra notes 23-27 and accompanying text. In these specific areas there was a real crisis resulting in the case of neonatal injuries in Florida and Virginia and in the case of vaccines in a real shortage of vaccinations. See Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 735-739. 237 238 INSTITUTE OF MEDICINE, TO ERR IS HUMAN: BUILDING A SAFER HEALTH SYSTEM 1 (2001). The roots of this approach can be found already in the early 1990s, see Weiler, supra note 122, at 937-941. 239 To Err is Human, supra note 238, at 1. The reliability of the report’s findings was later critiqued, questioning the methodology and reliability of the underlying research. See Harrington, supra note 230, at 345. 240 To Err is Human, supra note 238, at 2. 49 Relational Malpractice of mistakes and learning about the sources of errors more generally.241 Errors were no longer viewed as resulting from individual mistakes, incompetence or oversight but from structural characteristics of the delivery of healthcare services. The report eloquently states: "To err is human, but errors can be prevented."242 This move echoed similar developments the aviation and auto industries that accomplished striking breakthroughs in reducing the frequency of errors. Despite recognizing the tension between the shadow of individual liability in torts and the drive for learning through rigorous ongoing analysis of errors, the IOM Report did not openly endorse large scale reform in the torts liability system. 243 Nevertheless, by reframing the issue from one relating to insurance premiums to enhancing the quality of healthcare services, the report set the stage for renewed interest in no fault systems. The appeal of no fault schemes this time around was not framed around their potential for delivering compensation to injured patients more equitably and efficiently, but because they open the door for a more inclusive and sincere analysis of errors, generating learning and enhancing patient safety.244 However, even the connection to this much-cited report failed to garner the necessary support for reforming the system. Realizing that a comprehensive regulatory reform was unlikely (and perhaps premature), the Harvard Group advocated the adoption of state-level enabling legislation that would allow for experimentation with no-fault schemes on the ground,245 which could generate learning on both the optimal design of such systems as well as the sources of errors.246 The latest 241 Barringer et al., supra note 65, at 751; Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 217; Hyman, supra note 129, at 1647 & n.28 (describing the shift as a “strategically repackag[ing]” of the issue from uneven compensations to “system based solutions to medical error.” 242 To Err is Human, supra note 238, at 5. The report makes a series of recommendations, which include the establishment of a national center for research on safety and causes of errors, the adoption of both strong mandatory reporting requirements on errors as well as voluntary efforts for analyzing errors and improving quality, the strengthening of private efforts and regulatory incentives aimed at the promotion of safety programs in healthcare, and the adoption of safe practices at the level where medical services are delivered (id., at 6-14). 243 Id., at 111. 244 Indeed, in the years following the publication of To Err is Human, the Harvard Group published a series of articles advocating the shift to a no-fault enterprise liability model, as a superior means for achieving both the broader-systemic goals of prevention and learning and the individual goal of compensation. See Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 220; Barringer et al. supra note 65, at 751; Kachalia et al., supra note 200, at 22. 245 Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 222; Mello & Brennan, supra note 213. For various critiques of a voluntary approach to no fault, see Hyman, supra note 129, at 1647-1654. 246 While the Harvard Group did not ground its proposals for these schemes in a theoretical-legal framework, they seem to comport with innovative regulatory approaches termed "new governance theories," which gained salience from the mid-1990s. 50 Relational Malpractice incarnation of the no-fault alternative was the health courts proposal advanced by members of the Harvard Group. This proposal preserves the fundamental elements of previous proposals while shifting from a pure administrative structure to a quasi-judicial one.247 As we can see, these proposals were unsuccessful in garnering the requisite political support. However, the recent Healthcare Reform grants project, which calls for the development of alternative liability schemes, may alter the political economic climate, generating a broader support-base for such reform.248 As we can see, over the years, the debate surrounding the no fault alternative has changed: from an insurance crisis to an issue of quality, from individual liability to structural causes, and from compensation and deterrence to learning and prevention. Nevertheless, we believe that the understanding of the problem is not sufficiently broad. "Quality" in both "To Err is Human" and in the Harvard Group's writing remains focused on clinical skills and medical knowledge. A broader approach would highlight the role played by doctor-patient relations in the delivery of high quality medical services, and, in particular, the effect of collaborative communication in that context.249 As we have shown, the hierarchy between clinical skills and relational aspects of medical care is questionable. Open, mutual and non-defensive communication is essential for preventing medical errors to begin with as well as allowing for deep learning to take place. In the following section we explain why the quality of the doctor-patient relationship is not only a relevant justification for the shift to a no fault regime, but also an important one meriting special attention. 247 Michelle M. Mello et al., “Health Courts” and Accountability for Patient Safety, 84 MILBANK Q. 459 (2006). 248 American Medical Association, Federal Funding to Test Medical Liability Alternatives, available at http://www.ama-assn.org/ama1/pub/upload/mm/399/mlr-federal-grants.pdf (last visited on February 1, 2011) (stating that “Congress created a separate medical liability grant program in the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010 (PPACA). Under the PPACA program , states are required to develop an alternative liability reform that: (1) allows for the resolution of disputes over injuries allegedly caused by health care providers or organizations and (2) promotes a reduction of health care errors by encouraging the collection and analysis of patient safety data.”) 249 In a similar vein, Todres has stated that the no fault alternative “may provide little or no forum for restoring the relationships that are so integral to health care” (see Todres, supra note 4, at 701). We, however, do not see this as an inherent attribute of no fault proposals, but as a consequence of system design features, which could be designed to promote the enhancement of relationships. 51 Relational Malpractice B. Relationships as a New Justification for No Fault While reform proposals advocating a shift to no fault have viewed it as a targeted solution to an isolated problem (malpractice), we believe that the debate should be situated within the broader framework of healthcare law. As we have argued, the design of legal arrangements for the healthcare arena should be informed by relational theory. We have offered an understanding of relational theory which is comprised of two major aspects – the centrality of relationships and the significance of context. While in the opening of the article we offered a sketch of the general contours of a relational approach to healthcare law in general, in what follows we focus on the specific arena of malpractice, demonstrating the ways in which relationships and context shape this field and should shape legal intervention. As we show below, the current malpractice regime and the nofault alternative as portrayed so far, present a different approach, one that is focused on clinical skills and competencies of healthcare providers, providing little room for relationships to flourish and for patient input to be taken seriously. In terms of relationships, there are three major problems with the current malpractice regime and with the traditional justification for no fault. For one, under both legal schemes, the focus is on the moment of error. The current torts regime has harmed the doctor-patient relationship in two respects. Most clearly, the torts framework makes interaction between physicians and patients in the aftermath of an adverse event combative and confrontational, rupturing their relations and hampering communication between them both in the medical setting and in court. But the torts regime has a more elusive, indirect influence on doctor-patient relations by shaping medical professionals' routine interactions with their patients during medical visits, tests, and procedures. The no fault reform proposals have the potential to reduce some of the animosity and tensions that currently characterize doctor-patient relations because of the removal of the individual blame component. Still, their contribution to the relationship aspect will in all likelihood remain limited. This is, first and foremost, because any improvement in relationships will merely be a byproduct of the system and not a goal in and of itself.250 Second, these proposals, like the torts system, remain focused on medical errors, excluding those instances in which problems in the doctor-patient relationship have not yet resulted in an adverse event. By contrast, a relationships-centered no fault alternative 250 See Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 222. 52 Relational Malpractice envisions a collaborative doctor-patient relationship, creating an environment that cultivates ongoing collaboration on a structural level, whether an adverse event has taken place or not. Such an approach recognizes that relationships develop over time, are dynamic, contextual, and cannot be fully understood when examined as discrete events that occur at a particular point in time. It therefore seeks to detect a broad range of problems along the continuum of care based on the understanding that problems often cannot be neatly categorized into a particular type of dispute (such as "errors" vs. "complaints"), that such categorizations may change over time, and that our understanding of the circumstances which may generate errors also change and depend on our ongoing examination of complaints, problems and errors. A second way in which the current medical malpractice scheme and the no fault alternatives have misunderstood the nature of relationships in healthcare law is by focusing on the doctor-patient relationship as a standalone relationship, which provides sufficient context for understanding the circumstances that surround medical errors. As we have shown throughout this article, while the doctor-patient relationship is a (perhaps "the") central relationship in healthcare, it exists within a broader web of relationships, feeding into them and being shaped by them – relationships that exist within the healthcare team itself, between providers and managed care organizations, between patients and managed care, and the like.251 To gain a better understanding of the sources of medical errors, one must not only examine a broader range of problems and complaints than those defined as "errors," but also examine problems that arise outside the scope of the doctor-patient relationship and could shed light on the reasons for the occurrence of an error as well as the means for preventing such errors in the future. Finally, the existing torts framework and the proposed no fault alternative, by focusing on individual compensation for the injured, have remained loyal to the basic atomistic lone rights bearer paradigm, failing to offer a more satisfying alternative to patients that actually addressed their needs and interests. As we and others before us have claimed, most malpractice claimants are not after monetary compensation, certainly not as a sole and principal goal. Many of them would like to learn additional details regarding the circumstances of the injury, receive reassurance that it will not recur in the future, and 251 See supra Parts III.A. and III.B. 53 Relational Malpractice hear an apology.252 The no fault alternative brings us closer to "what plaintiffs want" by cultivating an atmosphere that allows more communication to take place between physicians and patients in the aftermath of an error and by setting prevention and learning about the sources of mistakes as a goal. Nevertheless, by limiting learning to the realm of medical errors and neglecting the need for nourishing relationships as a goal in and of itself, the no fault alternative has also been relegated to an individualistic perspective. In terms of context, the second component of a relational approach, both the torts system and the no fault options, as presented thus far, have failed to meet relational expectations. For one, both approaches fail to take into account patient input and voice, offering uniform prefixed monetary remedies through a structured process. By contrast, a relational approach would seek to offer a more pluralistic array of processes, which envisage a range of needs according to varying patient characteristics, different problems and the range of circumstances under which the problem arose.253 Second, a relational approach must recognize, alongside the particular characteristics of a given context that such circumstances are also shaped by structural factors. While the no fault alternative has moved in this direction by recognizing that medical errors often result from structural deficiencies, it has yet to recognize the impact of structural elements on the relationshiprelated aspects and the connection between clinical skills and competencies on the one hand and relational components on the other hand. In the following section, we further develop these ideas in offering a more concrete vision for the design of a no fault alternative from a relational perspective. C. Designing an Alternative with Relationships in Mind In considering how the law should address medical errors, a broad view should be employed under which the impact of legal arrangements on relationships is examined at various points along the continuum of care, independent of the occurrence of an error. A commitment to advance collaborative relations between physicians and patients would necessitate a comprehensive scheme that addresses a wide range of conflicts including, 252 See supra note 186 and accompanying text. 253 See supra Part II.C.. 54 Relational Malpractice but not limited to, those stemming from medical errors.254 Under such a scheme, a no fault regime would play an important part in dealing with adverse events, while other channels would need to be established to address additional types of conflicts, including legal (such as scope of coverage) and non-legal disputes (such as physician demeanor), as well as disputes and problems that arise in the context of the web of relationships that surround the doctor-patient relationship (such as problems among hospital employees). What sometimes seem trivial disputes could expose communication problems, thereby preventing future medical errors, in addition to improving satisfaction. Such an approach responds to the understanding that the distinction between clinical and communication skills is flawed and recognizes the need to address relationship-related conflicts. A broad approach that targets a wide range of conflicts, including those that are not categorized as "malpractice," is based on the understanding that all conflicts have an impact on quality and potentially relate to safety and prevention, rendering it difficult to discern ahead of time which of these cases would merit compensation. By addressing a broader pool of conflicts on a systematic level, the doctor-patient relationship is strengthened and broader learning is achieved. Within the framework for addressing medical errors, a no fault system that is focused on relationships is likely to generate a richer information pool. The expected increase in the information-base is a result of greater disclosure of information. The expansion in the pool of available information can be expected due to the removal of physicians' fear of personal liability which eliminates some of the strongest barriers to information gathering.255 In addition, the commitment and trust that come with a stronger relationship between physicians and patients can also be expected to enhance information sharing and disclosure. By removing the legal disincentives for information sharing and by creating positive professional incentives and a supportive climate for disclosure, physicians will divulge more errors and near misses, as well as adopting a more robust understanding of what constitutes each of these categories. Expansive information exchange and disclosure can also be expected to reinforce other proactive efforts to engender a more mutual and collaborative doctor-patient relationship (e.g. communication skills initiatives, and ADR 254 Conflicts stemming from medical errors are one type of dispute that arises in the context of the doctor-patient relationship. The potential of patient complaints to shed light on malpractice-related issues was recognized by Hickson and his co-authors who advocated the establishment of a broad dispute resolution system that would draw on patient complaints to provide advance warning on potential malpractice allegations. See Hickson et al., supra note 87. 255 See Studdert & Brennan, supra note 205, at 218. 55 Relational Malpractice schemes). It will also enable improved learning and decisions that are more just in their allocation of compensation. By expanding the information base on medical errors and related incidents, a no fault system, premised on the enhancement of relationships, is likely to be able to realize more fully the very goals that no fault proponents have advanced – compensation and learning. In terms of compensation, a richer database would make it possible to better distinguish those claimants who deserve compensation from those who do not, something the torts system has been unable to do satisfactorily. Furthermore, a system that enshrines the importance of the doctor-patient relationship can buoy physician willingness to assist patients in recognizing when a claim is merited as well as in the process of preparing and submitting such claim. While the various existing no fault systems already boast of such cooperation, we believe that it can be expected to flourish in an environment that enshrines a collaborative ethos.256 As for learning, by expanding the dispute base, we can expect richer, more rigorous data gathering that could promote learning on the sources of errors and on the effectiveness of the various means for preventing them, and could generate insights into the connection between other types of disputes and doctor-patient relations. While in the past, disputes were perceived as negative developments and were therefore dealt with grudgingly and suspiciously on an ad-hoc basis, in recent decades this view has changed with entities recognizing the positive potential of learning from disputes for evaluation and improvement.257 Disputes provide an important source of data about the quality of healthcare, professional practices, patient expectations, sources of errors, and the potential and limitations of current policies. A relationship-based no fault system would therefore commit to promoting learning that extends beyond the realm of medical errors 256 Research on no-fault systems outside the U.S. has established a link between the shift to no fault and increased physician collaboration in the claiming process. Specifically, research findings indicate that Swedish physicians are particularly helpful and cooperative in the claim filing process, with 60-80% assisting patients in the process. In fact, patients often seek the physician's advice on whether to file a claim or not, although they are not required to do so by law. Unlike Sweden, in New Zealand the statistics have been somewhat less positive, but this is tied to the former lack of “Chinese wall” between the claiming and disciplinary avenues, a situation that has since been modified with the hope of achieving a higher level of cooperation by physicians. Here, physicians' participation in the claiming process is required, with the physician filing the claim form. See Kachalia et al., supra note 200, at 399-400. TO 257 See CATHY COSTANTINO & CHRISTINA MERCHANT, DESIGNING CONFLICT MANAGEMENT SYSTEMS: A GUIDE CREATING PRODUCTIVE AND HEALTHY ORGANIZATIONS IV (1996). 56 Relational Malpractice and relates to the realm of relationships.258 In some cases, lessons drawn from non-legal complaints may shed light on sources of medical errors as well.259 Indeed, in a system that is committed to learning, definitions and categorizations can be expected to change over time.260 Such a system should therefore seek to create a rich database and be committed to ongoing analysis and evolution. A no fault system whose primary justification is grounded in the doctor-patient relationship could also prove instrumental in addressing some of the criticism voiced against no fault enterprise liability schemes. As mentioned above, one of the early criticisms raised against no fault reform proposals was that the removal of individual blame would hinder deterrence.261 The answer provided by the Harvard Group, the leading proponents of such reform, was that rather than advancing deterrence, such systems should advance error prevention and patient safety through learning about the sources of errors.262 Because of the dynamic and evolving nature of medical knowledge and clinical skills, the need for multi-disciplinary cooperation in the delivery of medical services, and the strained conditions under which medical treatment is rendered it is often difficult to discern what went wrong and how such instances could be prevented in the future. In this environment the incentives provided by the torts system are unfavorable to the type of rigorous root-cause analysis such complex environments require. As we have shown above, the shift from deterrence to learning was driven by the realization that medical errors were rooted in systemic causes and cognitive biases rather than individual For example, over time, recurring medical errors may uncover difficulties in physicians' ability to elicit certain types of information from patients, which in turn, undermines patient trust in the physician and reduces their adherence to the regimen recommended by the doctor and their inclination to return to the same physician in the future. Compensation to the injured will not address the difficulty in terms of the doctor-patient relationship. Other measures would need to be adopted, such as individual training and education of physicians as well as organizational policies that encourage the establishment of a more effective doctor-patient relationship that generates trust and encourages patients to divulge personal, intimate information that is relevant to their medical condition. 258 259 Consider, for example, repetitive complaints by patients about the intake process in the ER, which could uncover that not enough attention is given to the initial questioning of patients about their condition and symptoms. While complaints could be framed as being about long waits, rude conduct and the like, the hospital could generate important lessons on the adequacy of information gathering on patients during these crucial early stages. 260 The understanding of what constitutes an injury that is a result of medical treatment may change over time, with developments in technology and change in social values and views on these matters. For example, our understanding of what constitutes a preventable injury will undoubtedly change as globally accessible digital medical records become the norm. 261 See supra notes 232-234 and accompanying text. 262 See supra notes 238-244and accompanying text. 57 Relational Malpractice incompetence or oversight.263 Such emphasis reinforces positive incentives for improving healthcare instead of attempting to direct conduct through sanctions, the success of which has proven questionable at best. Where relationships occupy center stage, we can expect even more rigorous, richer learning and more effective prevention efforts to take place because of the broader pool of disputes and complaints such learning will be based on. This is attributable to the system's interest in different dispute types and to providers' strong sense of duty and commitment to disclose problems and take part in addressing them in a collaborative climate. Another source of criticism of no fault liability schemes is related to their cost. As we have shown, the cost calculation by both proponents and opponents has been incomplete, ignoring such components as administrative costs (courts vs. administrative schemes) and potential savings (reduction in defensive medicine practices). The new justification we offer for a no fault system reveals additional elements of potential savings. For example, the broadening of the scope of disputes addressed by the system and the focus on relationships can be expected to lower the overall rate of disputes due to prevention and early intervention.264 This, in turn, could translate into higher productivity, improve doctors’ wellbeing, and lower the rates of employee attrition providing significant savings that may offset some of the costs associated with a no fault system.265 In addition, we can expect some of the costs of the no fault compensation scheme to be offset by those cases in which patients refrain from pursuing claims altogether because they are satisfied with overall quality of care they received and the information provided regarding the error. A third compelling critique against no fault systems has been that these compensation schemes end up excluding a substantial group of eligible claimants because of their threshold requirements. As described earlier, these requirements were introduced as a necessary price paid in exchange for curbing the costs associated with a broader base of potential beneficiaries.266 Under a broad compensation scheme, these claimants will not be 263 Id. WILLIAM URY ET AL., GETTING DISPUTES RESOLVED: DESIGNING SYSTEMS TO CUT THE COSTS OF CONFLICT (1988) (the book that signifies the birth of the field of "dispute system design" and whose principal insight was that conflicts that took place in closed settings could be addressed most effectively through systemic, pre-designed avenues, thereby also play a key role in the prevention of future disputes). 264 265 DAVID B. LIPSKY ET AL., EMERGING SYSTEMS FOR MANAGING WORKPLACE CONFLICT: LESSONS FROM AMERICAN CORPORATIONS FOR MANAGERS AND DISPUTE RESOLUTION PROFESSIONALS 7 (2003). 266 See supra note 230 and accompanying text. 58 Relational Malpractice excluded, but will be referred to the relevant patient complaint unit where an investigation into their claim can be initiated and alternative remedies may be awarded. In addition, the data concerning such complaints will not be ignored and lost, but will be included in the overall database and contribute to the efforts to enhance quality of care. Ideally, hospitals and other such enterprises will implement a centralized unit that will serve as a clearinghouse, channeling appropriate claims to the no fault compensation schemes, while referring other types of disputes to parallel channels charged with redressing them. Such design would enable both addressing different types of disputes and promoting deep learning on the quality of care, broadly defined. VI. Conclusion The article uncovers the vicious cycle that drives the delivery of medical services today: The rise in malpractice litigation as a result of patient empowerment and increased legal scrutiny of medical standards has generated widespread fear of being sued among physicians, which has translated into the adoption of defensive medicine practices and a defensive mode of communication. Paradoxically, by limiting communication channels, providers have actually increased the likelihood of making an error and, where an adverse event has taken place, the likelihood of their being sued. This, in turn, reinforces physicians’ concerns over malpractice litigation. Over the years there have been attempts to break this vicious cycle. These efforts have failed to transform this cycle into a virtuous one because they have either ignored the role relationships play in the malpractice context altogether, or have attempted to transform such relations by focusing mainly on post-error interactions between physicians and patients. In our view, a virtuous cycle can emerge only if we take relationships seriously. The relational approach to malpractice that we advance identifies the harm to the doctorpatient relationship caused by the existing legal regime as the main source of the current crisis. While the law does not explicitly address relationships in healthcare, the legal arrangements that govern malpractice have had a deep impact on the type of interactions that have emerged between doctors and patients over the years, steering physicians away from a collaborative model and cultivating an oppositional mode of communication in its place. By focusing on relationships, the law is committed to examining its impact on the doctor-patient relationship and to advancing a collaborative relationship. As we have 59 Relational Malpractice shown, this would not only improve the wellbeing and satisfaction of physicians and patients alike but would also reduce errors, enhance safety and improve the quality of medical services. In order to realize the transformation to a collaborative model, the current legal regime of individual fault and blame must be displaced, and a new alternative should be designed with relationships in mind. The proposed no fault alternative, which has been advanced in this article, holds a promise for such a transformation. Its integrative impetus takes seriously both the doctor-patient relationship and the additional concerns that are typical to no fault, including compensation, cost, deterrence, safety, and learning. Finally, this article also delineates the contours of a relational approach to healthcare law related issues more generally. As the above analysis of the malpractice crisis reveals, such an approach can mitigate the destructive impact law can sometimes have on relationships, the backbone of high quality medical care and effective healthcare services. In addition, a relational approach expands the range of considerations and concerns that are addressed by healthcare law, moving beyond traditional solutions. As the field becomes increasingly complex with the introduction of new technologies, the performance of innovative procedures, and the involvement of a growing number of stakeholders and actors in healthcare, the need for addressing the human dimension and relational aspects will be come all the more pressing.