1 Value Conflict, Dialogical Pluralism, and the Idea of Wisdom1 Peter Jonkers (Tilburg University, the Netherlands) 1. Introduction In this paper, I want to analyze a specific kind of value conflict, which seems to preclude consensus, and which is nevertheless characteristic of our current situation of radical cultural diversity. This type of value conflicts is not only the subject of fierce discussions in philosophy and political theory, but are also the gist of quite a lot of propaganda wars and, unfortunately, even real wars. One could even say that the main issue of many ongoing conflicts in the world is not anymore chiefly about gaining territory or economic dominance, but about fundamental diversities in values, especially insofar as these are reflected and concretized in cultures and civilizations. In this respect, Samuel Huntington already predicted in 1993 that “the great divisions among humankind and the dominating source of conflict will be cultural,” leading to a “clash of civilizations”.2 What constitutes the identity of a civilization is a common history, language, culture, tradition, and religion. These elements result in shared ideas about the human person, the relation between the individual and the group, between the citizen and the state, parents and children, husband and wife, as well as about the relative importance of rights and responsibilities, liberty and authority, equality and hierarchy.3 All these ideas, and the practices resulting from them, are concrete manifestations of a limited number of fundamental values, some of which may be universal. But what really defines the identity of a culture is not so much the abstract level of fundamental values, but the way in which they are realized in specific spatio-temporal settings, i.e. in concrete civilizations. Through education, institution, religion and ideology, legislation, cultural practices, etc. every society aims at realizing certain fundamental values in its daily life, and tries to solve the conflicts between some different groups of values. And because civilizations differ greatly due to differences in history, location, language, etc., there is also an enormous diversity in the ways in which fundamental values are realized and value conflicts are being solved. Without going as far as to say that these concrete manifestations of cultural diversity will result in a clash of civilizations, it is obvious that they are the cause of many conflicts and even wars. In order to introduce the topic of this paper, I start, in the next section, with a concrete example of conflicting values in the field of human rights. In particular, I will outline the differences in values, which underlie the three groups of human rights, namely the individual freedom rights, the basic social rights, and the cultural rights. In my view, these differences result in, basically two different kinds of value conflicts: conflicts being fought out in a homogeneous playing field, resulting, ideally, in consensus, and conflicts being fought out in a heterogeneous field, which often precludes the possibility of consensus. The reason that this second category of value conflicts is so difficult to solve is the lack of a common ground 1 Full text of a paper, presented at the international conference on ‘Value Conflict and Consensus in the Cultural Diversity, organized by the Marxism College and Research Center for Socialism with Chinese Characteristics of Liaoning University, on Dec. 22, 2014. 2 Samuel P. Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations. In: Foreign Affairs, Summer 1993, 1 3 Ibid., 2. 2 of, phrased positively, the importance of cultural individuality. In the third section, I will give a short philosophical analysis of what defines value conflicts in a homogeneous and a heterogeneous playing field, respectively, and the implications for reaching consensus. In the final section, I try to develop a solution to the problem of value conflict in a heterogeneous or non-consensual space by making use of the ideas of dialogical pluralism and practical wisdom. 2. Conflicting human rights and the (im)possibility of consensus It is not my intention to give an extensive historical account of the specific contexts, in which the various groups of human rights came up, or to analyze how they have been constitutionalized in various political regimes, and even less to play off one group of human rights against the other. In this respect, I fully agree with the organizers of this conference that it is unjust and counterproductive to participate in a discussion about value conflict from an attitude of superiority regarding one’s own culture. In this respect, it is worthwhile to emphasize that the most fundamental value, which is to be respected universally and unconditionally, is the equal human dignity of all human beings. Actually, the idea of human dignity is the ultimate foundation in order to attribute rights at all to people. But since humans are basically cultural beings, the universal respect for human dignity also applies to civilizations, countries, and nations, as well as to the values they try to realize, because these values define their identity and, hence, their dignity. However, if the respect for cultural identity applies unconditionally, it serves as a discussion stopper, putting an end to any critical discussion about human rights; moreover, on the level of international politics, such an argument would serve as an excuse for every country to stave off any critique of its internal human rights policy, let alone an armed intervention by the international community of a barbarous regime. Against this background, I want to use the example of the fundamental tensions between the above mentioned three groups of human rights in order to illustrate the enormous complexity, which surrounds the concept of value conflict, and which seems to jeopardize consensus about cultural values in particular. 2.1 Conflicting human rights in a homogeneous playing field From a historical perspective, the oldest declarations of human rights are exemplifications of the principle of individual freedom, stressing the natural, inalienable rights of each individual. The oldest example of such a declaration is the Magna Carta from 1215, in which the English king guarantees certain rights and liberties to the Church of England, the nobility, and citizens of the cities, and promises to respect the old liberties and free customs. The ‘jura et libertates’, which these treatises contained, are meant to define the relations between the sovereign and his subjects. They express the fundamental political-ethical principle of the regulation of power, aimed at protecting the subjects against possible arbitrariness and injustice of the sovereign. This regulation makes up the backbone of the so-called Habeas Corpus rights, which have a central place in the whole tradition of human rights, expressing the crucial value of the inviolability of the person, which means that citizens are protected against arbitrary capture and torture, and have the guarantee of a fair jurisdiction. Originally, these rights were no human rights in the strict sense, because they lacked the universal and unconditional character of the latter, but were rather privileges, 3 exception rights. They were attributed to certain groups or estates, who had enough power to exact these rights from the sovereign and have them respected by him. Moreover, all these rights and privileges were concretizations of a classical idea of the relation between the state and its subjects, in the sense that rights are attributed to individuals, because they are part of a community. This means that these rights are conceptualized as exemplifications of the most fundamental value, namely the common good or bonum commune. The principle of the common good expresses another fundamental value, namely that the community exists naturally and necessarily, and, hence, has priority over the individuals. The Aristotelian principle of distributive justice defines the relation between the community and its members, which is defined as a geometric relation (A : B = C : D) between the whole and its parts. From this perspective, the rights of individuals are attributed to him or her as a part of the common good. However, ultimately, not the individual citizens, but only the sovereign political authority decides about the content and the requirements of the common good. Hence, the rights of individuals limit and stipulate the political authority, but only insofar as the common good requires the attribution of these rights. This implies that no individual can claim exclusive rights against the power of the state. In sum, the two fundamental values, underlying this pre-modern idea of human rights are the inviolability of the human person and the idea of the common good, which subordinates the rights of the individual to those of the community. Only since the beginning of modernity, one can speak of human rights in the full sense of the world. They are meant to limit the power of the sovereign state as a whole over the individuals. Moreover, these rights are no longer privileges of certain groups, but inalienable rights of all humans without exception; they can be claimed by all citizens, simply because they are humans. That is why these rights are inalienable and natural, which means that they are prior to each form of government and societal order. As the second article of the Déclaration des droits de l’homme et du citoyen of 1789, drafted in the wake of the French Revolution, runs, it is even so that “the aim of every political association is the preservation of the natural and inalienable rights of man; these rights are liberty, property, security, and resistance to oppression.”4 The right to liberty and property deserve special attention, because they have obtained a central place in the societal and political organizations of the West: “Liberty consists of the power to do whatever is not injurious to others”; and “property is a sacred and inviolable right, and no one may be deprived thereof unless a legally established public necessity obviously requires it, and upon a condition of a just and previous indemnity.”5 The way in which these two rights are stipulated shows that human rights are pre-state rights, which have to be safeguarded by the societal and political structures through the creation of a state-free zone, which is nowadays called the civil society. In other words, the state does not have the right to interfere in the private and parts of the public lives of its citizens. People have the freedom, among others, to uphold certain values, to express them in public and share them with others, and to put them into practice and pass on to their children. It goes without saying that the state may limit this freedom in specific cases for the sake of common interest. Hence, the fundamental values, underlying the modern, liberal declaration of human rights are, first, the inviolability of the human person, just as in the pre-modern conception. But 4 5 Walter Laqueur and Barry Rubin (ed.), The Human Rights Reader. New York: Meridian, 1979, p. 118. Ibid., p. 119f. 4 unlike the pre-modern conception of rights and freedoms, the idea of the person on which the modern human rights rests is the free, autonomous individual, separated from other individuals and the community. That is why these rights are typically called ‘individual freedom rights.’ The state’s prime task is to protect the freedom of the individual, and this explicitly includes his private property. Hence, besides the inviolability of the person, the modern idea of human rights expresses a second fundamental value, namely that of individualism. The societal whole and the common good no longer have priority over the individual, as was the case in the pre-modern period, but the sovereign individual with its natural right to free self-disposal precedes every community, and even serves as the ultimate justification of the final goal of every polity. Against this background, Marx’s famous critique of the French declaration of human rights deserves to be mentioned, because it uncovers some problematic presuppositions of the values that underlie them. He shows that this declaration is unable to fulfill one of the three principles of the French Revolution, namely fraternity – besides liberty and (juridical) equality – , although it was drafted in the wake of it. In his view, “the so-called rights of man, the droits de l’homme […], are nothing but the rights of a member of civil society – i.e. the rights of egoistic man, of man separated from other men and from the community.” 6 Herewith, he rejects the individualistic character of the values of the liberal idea of human rights, accusing the French declaration of promoting selfishness: other humans are not considered as my fellows, but as possible intruders of my privacy. It goes without saying that this liberal declaration is completely at odds with the principle of fraternity. For Marx, the fact that the liberal idea of human rights actually promotes selfishness comes to the fore most explicitly in the rights of liberty and property: “The right of man to liberty,” being the right to do everything that harms no one else, “is based not on the association of man with man, but on the separation of man from man. It is the right of this separation, the right of the restricted individual, withdrawn into himself.”7 What this human right means in practice becomes manifest in the right to private property. Marx even thinks that all the articles of the declaration of human rights serve no other goal than to sanctify private property. “The right of man to private property is, therefore, the right to enjoy one’s property and to dispose of it at one’s discretion (à son gré), without regard to other men, independently of society, the right of self-interest.”8 As a result of Marx’s critique of the liberal or, as he calls it, egoistic character of the human rights declaration of the French revolution and, moreover, as the outcome of the struggle of the worker’s movement for social justice during the second half of the 19 th and the first half of the 20th century, a new group of human rights emerged, the so-called basic social rights. Together with the individual freedom rights, these basic social rights constitute the core of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of the United Nations of 1948. The latter group of rights is not so much meant to give individuals the freedom to lead their lives as they wish, but rather to enable them to participate and to be a full member of society; this group comprises the right to education in a school, to paid work, to social security, to health care, to housing, etc. 6 Karl Marx, On the Jewish Question, 11f. (Marx, “Zur Judenfrage”, MEW I, 364). Karl Marx, On the Jewish Question, 12. (Marx, “Zur Judenfrage”, MEW I, 364). 8 Karl Marx, On the Jewish Question, 12. (Marx, “Zur Judenfrage”, MEW I, 365). 7 5 As becomes apparent from Marx’s critique, the values underlying these basic social rights are fraternity, solidarity, and, more in general, participation in society. They emphasize the idea that humans are not only free, autonomous, individual beings, but also need to live in a social environment that guarantees the fulfillment of their basic material and spiritual needs: without proper schooling, the right to freedom of expression remains an empty box, depriving someone from basic food supply and health care obviously jeopardizes his autonomy, making someone homeless is ruinous for his self-esteem and, hence, for his human dignity. In sum, from a socialist perspective, basic social rights are primarily meant to ensure people’s right to participate in and contribute to shaping the total political, economic, societal and cultural life. Just as the individual freedom rights the basic social rights are essential exemplifications of the fundamental value of human dignity, because they are vital for the humanization of the human being. In the course of history, the obvious tensions between the individual freedom rights and the basic social rights have given rise to numerous conflicts: is the right to property of the happy few prior to the fulfillment of basic material needs of the deprived majority?; is it more important that a highly-educated minority has the unlimited freedom to speak English or should society protect local languages, which are predominantly spoken by people who only have primary education?; is freedom of religion an absolute right, even if certain religions are brainwashing their adherents? These examples illustrate more fundamental value conflicts, most of which come down to conflicts between the value of individual freedom and that of social and political equality. As is common knowledge, these value conflicts are inevitable, and all societies have to deal with them, trying to solve them on the basis of their political regime, their tradition, their economic possibilities etc. In this context, I want to stress that these value conflicts between the individual freedom rights and the basic social rights occur within a homogeneous playing field. In spite of their focus on different aspects of human dignity, these two groups of rights are both universal. Their universality concerns, first, the fact that the overall majority of the countries in the world has signed the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which includes both these groups of human rights, and constitutionalized it, even though quite a number of them does not always respect it. Second, there is an almost universal consensus that these two groups of rights and their underpinning values indeed constitute the essence of what it means to be human, in other words of the idea of human dignity. This twofold universality creates a common ground, which makes that the inevitable value conflicts between the two groups, and even the value conflicts within each of these groups of human rights, occur on a homogeneous playing field. Even though people may give priority to different values, and solve value conflicts between these two groups of human rights in quite different ways, the idea of human dignity, which includes both groups of human rights, has become globally recognized. Moreover, the kind of arguments they use in underpinning their choices can, in principle, be understood by the other party. Hence, people are fighting out their value conflicts on the basis of a shared understanding of and sensitivity to the idea of human dignity as well as some fundamental rules and principles, and this defines the homogeneous character of the playing field. In sum, the idea of human dignity, as well as those of reasonableness and reciprocity, serve as a common ground or common frame of reference for how the conflicts between individual freedom rights and basic social rights are to be solved. 6 The homogeneity of this playing field makes it possible that these value conflicts, ideally, result in a ‘reasonable overlapping consensus’. According to Rawls, this means that all people who are defending diverging values on the basis of different comprehensive doctrines, e.g. a liberal and a socialist one, “support a political conception of justice underwriting a constitutional democratic society whose principles, ideals, and standards satisfy the criterion of reciprocity.”9 This consensus is more than a pragmatic modus vivendi, since “first, the object of consensus, the political concept of justice, is itself a moral conception. And second, it is affirmed on moral grounds, that is, it includes conceptions of society and of citizens as persons, as well as principles of justice, and an account of the political virtues through which those principles are embodied in human character and expressed in public life.”10 In sum, this kind of value conflicts appears in a homogeneous playing field, in which there is a global recognition of the fundamental principle of human dignity, as well as of the rules of constitutional democracy and reciprocity are shared by all, and in which reason is accepted by all parties involved as a neutral judge. 2.2 Conflicting human rights in a heterogeneous playing field However, with the rise of a third group of human rights, the so-called cultural rights, since the sixties of the previous century, a new and different kind of value conflicts has emerged, which jeopardizes the very idea of consensus and of global justice. In the wake of the painful decolonization process many countries that had only recently become independent, wanted to get rid of the culture of their former colonizers, and started to affirm their own, specific cultural identity. In a vehement reaction against the former colonizer’s culture, they rather emphasized and sometimes even exaggerated the differences between the ‘externally imposed’ and the ‘native’ culture than looking for the values they had in common with other cultures. Meanwhile, this stress on cultural individuality and, hence, on diversity has also permeated in most Western civilizations, depriving traditional reference points for social cohesion of their plausibility. Several factors have contributed to this change in the public consciousness: a) the modern (virtual) media have confronted Western civilizations with a wide variety of cultures and their underpinning values; b) migration streams of people looking for better life conditions have resulted in a growing impact of cultural diversity upon Western societies; c) the rise of expressive individualism in many Western countries has contributed to promoting an ideal of personal and cultural authenticity.11 Consequently, the conviction that not only countries and nations, but also individual regions have a specific cultural identity and uphold specific values, diverging from all the other ones, has gained a lot of popularity. At the same time, all of them want this identity to be recognized and respected on equal terms with mainstream cultures and their values.12 In sum, the global recognition of the value of human dignity as fundamental, as analyzed in the previous 9 John Rawls, The Idea of Public Reason Revisited. In: Idem, Political Liberalism. Expanded Edition. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993, pp. 482f. 10 Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 147. 11 Cfr. a.o. Jürgen Habermas, Die Revitalisierung der Weltreligionen – Herausforderung für ein säkulares Selbstverständnis der Moderne. In: Idem, Philosophische Texte. Band 5: Kritik der Vernunft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009, pp. 392-394. 12 Odo Marquard also points to the intriguing combination of social harmonization and universalization versus pluralization. However, I do not agree with his thesis that these two trends compensate each other. Cfr. Odo Marquard, Einheit und Vielheit. In: Idem, Zukunft braucht Herkunft. Philosophische Essays. Stuttgart: Reclam, 2003, 210f. 7 section, paradoxically goes hand in hand with the growing awareness of the local nature of cultures and their values. Obviously, the current situation of cultural diversity has led to new value conflicts between cultures and subcultures. Examples of them abound, some of them quite innocent, other ones far more problematic. It is essential for the identity of a culture that its members can express themselves in their mother tongue, not only in private, but also in public (e.g. in school, in the media, in court, etc.). Because speaking one’s mother tongue is a fundamental value, cultures claim the right to speak it, if need be against the linguistic majority. In many Western countries with an extensive legislation on animal rights, the Muslim minority claims the right to slaughter sheep according to the rite of the Islam, that is without anaesthesia. Some Arab countries consider it to run counter to cultural, that is Islamic, identity if women drive a car, and in a few of them, their cultural identity forbids girls to receive school education. Some African cultures claim the right to female circumcision, arguing that it is an inherent part of their cultural identity. Obviously, especially the last examples of cultural identity run completely counter to what is considered by most Western countries to belong to the essence of human dignity, namely the universal equality between men and women, the universal right to education, and the inviolability of the human body. The above examples show that cultural value conflicts, generated by claims to cultural rights differ qualitatively from the traditional ones: whereas the individual freedom rights and the basic social rights are universal, the cultural rights lack this universality, because they are inherent to a specific culture. First, although there is an almost universal consensus that cultural identity is a basic value, the specific, individual cultural values and the rights resulting from them have to be negotiated one by one and are certainly not universally recognized by an international body, such as the United Nations. Second, people who are not a member of this or that specific culture can hardly understand why some cultural values matter so much, and sometimes are even fiercely opposed to their recognition in their own culture; on the contrary, they consider some of them as outright violations of the universal of value of human dignity. The fact that the specific cultural values obviously lack universality implies that the playing field, on which cultural conflicts are being fought out, is not homogeneous, but fundamentally heterogeneous: there is no common ground, because cultural values are by definition culture specific, and, even more importantly, because the individuality of every culture even extends – to a certain extent – to the kind of rationality that is supposed to substantiate these values. There is a gap separating the predominantly procedural rationality of modern societies, which is focused on developing just procedures to reach consensus in case of a value conflict, from the more substantial rationality of more traditional cultures, which focuses on the content of these values. The above examples have made clear that, when it comes to the substantial rationality of individual cultures, outsiders often do not share the presuppositions of the people who defend cultural values. Hence, in a cultural value conflict people often don’t understand each other’s arguments, let alone sensitivities. Nevertheless, it would be a sign of disrespect to accuse ‘the others’ of simply being irrational. Hence, when cultural value conflicts are at stake, the procedural kind of rationality, which underlies most contemporary political philosophies, is no longer accepted as a universal, neutral judge. This explains why it has become so difficult or even impossible to reach reasonable consensus when conflicting cultural values are at stake. In sum, the rise of a kind of radical cultural diversity since the 8 sixties of the previous century confronts us with a heterogeneous playing field, which seems to preclude consensus.13 3. A philosophical analysis of value conflicts The work of Jürgen Habermas and John Rawls, two of the most prominent contemporary Western political philosophers, is focused on the value conflicts in a homogeneous field. Standing in the tradition of modernity, they recognize that reasonable pluralism is the normal result of a democratic culture of free institutions.14 This means that, in their eyes, cultural diversity is a fundamental reality of all modern, democratic societies. But at the same time they are convinced that the value conflicts, which result from this diversity, are fought out in a homogeneous playing field, which makes that these conflicts can, in principle, be settled through a reasonable, overlapping consensus.15 Moreover, they consider human rights as a homogeneous point of reference, which orientates the solution of all value conflicts.16 Hence, in their theory of political liberalism, they do not take into account adequately the fact that, as a consequence of the emergence of a radical cultural diversity, the homogeneous playing field of modernity, in which procedural rationality is the final judge, is gradually and partly being replaced by the heterogeneous field of postmodernity. Richard Rorty, by contrast, offers a philosophical analysis of value conflicts in a heterogeneous field, which enables him to understand and appreciate the reality of a radical cultural diversity, which is part and parcel of Western societies, these days. He interprets all grand cultural narratives, such as the great ideals of the French revolution, liberalism, Marxism, Christianity, and even reason as a universal common ground, as contingent ‘final vocabularies’, whose truth can only be demonstrated by means of circular arguments. This means that notions like consensus and truth only function within, but not outside a given vocabulary, so that they cannot serve as a common ground between various vocabularies. This does not mean that Rorty opts for a kind of relativism, according to which every belief would be as good as any other or that ‘true’ would be an equivocal term. But it does imply “the ethnocentric view that there is nothing to be said about either truth or rationality apart from descriptions of the familiar procedures of justification which a given society – ours – uses on one or another area of inquiry.”17 Hence, one can only reach consensus between the persons or local communities, who use the same final vocabulary. Because all vocabularies 13 Wolfgang Welsch makes a similar distinction between a horizontal and a vertical dimension of the plurality of the cultural world. Cfr. Wolfgang Welsch, “Weisheit in einer Welt der Pluralität,” W. Oelmüller (Hrsg.), Philosophie und Weisheit. Paderborn, München, Wien, Zürich: Ferdinand Schöningh, 1989, p. 236. 14 Rawls defines reasonable pluralism as “the fact that a plurality of conflicting reasonable comprehensive doctrines, religious, philosophical, and moral, is the normal result of its culture of free institutions,” See John Rawls, The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, p. 441. 15 Jürgen Habermas, The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of Its Voices. In: Idem, Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 1996, pp. 139-146. 16 Jürgen Habermas, Pre-political Foundations of a Democratic State. In: Jürgen Habermas and Joseph Ratzinger, The Dialectics of Secularization: On Reason and Religion. San Francisco: Ignatius, 2006, p. 33; Rawls, Political Liberalism, 411. 17 Richard Rorty, Science as Solidarity. In: John S. Nelson, Allan Megill, Donald N. McCloskey (eds.), The Rhetoric of the Human Sciences: Language and Arguments in Scholarship and Public Affairs. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987, p. 42. 9 are local and incommensurable, there is no neutral meta-vocabulary, which could serve as a common ground for all final vocabularies. Unlike modernity, which lived on the belief that all specific final vocabularies were to justify themselves before the tribunal of reason, which served as a kind of impartial judge, people living in the postmodern condition have lost this conviction. Nowadays, the dominant idea is that all value systems are nothing but contingent social constructions, available only on the local market. This explains why, in this fundamentally heterogeneous field, there is no common ground on the basis of which a consensus between different value systems could be found. It is therefore no surprise that, many post-modern individuals so often don’t feel at home in any vocabulary, and run the risk of completely losing their identity: they are constantly in doubt as to whether they haven’t been raised in the ‘wrong’ vocabulary, and inclined to give it up in favour of another, because they utterly lack the possibility to discuss and compare these vocabularies on reasonable grounds.18 In reaction to the rise of this unreflective pluralism and the doubts it generates, some people feel the need to affirm their individual and collective cultural identities as (exclusive) singularities. This shows that, paradoxically, for postmodern people, the threatening feeling of losing their identity amidst a plurality of alternatives, which all seem equally attractive, but also equally contingent, and the longing to unreflectively affirm the identity with which they feel most familiar, often in an exclusivist way, are not opposite attitudes, but just two sides of the same coin. 4. Dialogical pluralism as an alternative for consensus in value conflicts In the previous sections it has become clear that, against the background of today’s radical cultural diversity, philosophical reason has been forced to give up its claim to neutrality, and, consequently, to a homogeneous, neutral public square, in which value conflicts could be discussed. This has undermined political liberalism’s most fundamental condition for reaching reasonable consensus in case of conflicting values. Hence, it is necessary to develop an alternative way of dealing with value conflicts, which takes into account the reality of radical cultural diversity and, consequently, of a heterogeneous playing field. I propose to call this alternative approach ‘dialogical pluralism’ and try to give an outline of it. Dialogical pluralism can be defined as a conscious, well-organized critical dialogue between people who are living conflicting values in a heterogeneous field.19 The pluralist character of this dialogue implies the recognition that values are mostly part of specific cultures or traditions, which stand more or less on their own, and, hence, cannot be translated into the language of neutral reason. This means that the differences between values can be compared with each other, but not fully comprehended by outsiders. As a Westerner, I have a first person’s experience of my own, Western culture and its values, but only a third person’s knowledge of non-Western cultures and their values. Through (cultural) empathy, I can perhaps even sympathize with the values of others, but, as a Westerner, I can never experience fully what it would mean to live by non-Western values.20 This is all the more so, when it comes to specific, cultural values, generating specific practices and insights, because these cannot be 18 Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism and Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991, p. 203. Henk Vroom, Walking in a Widening World. Understanding Religious Diversity. Amsterdam: VU University Press, 2013, pp. 265f. 20 Thomas Nagel makes a similar point in the case of the subjective character of experience. Cfr. Thomas Nagel, What is it Like to Be a Bat? In: Idem, Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980. 19 10 integrated in a higher, universal value system. Dialogical pluralism does not require that one has to downplay or translate one’s own specific, cultural values for the sake of finding some common ground. By dropping this requirement, it wants to do justice to the reality of a heterogeneous playing field in the case of conflicting cultural values. But although we don’t have a first person’s experience of radically different cultural values, we can learn from the values of others, mostly by contrasting them with ours. In other words, traditions, of which cultural values are part, are not closed wholes, which cannot be understood by others, but rather configurations of insights, stories, rituals and organizations, which develop and change continuously in interaction with their broader cultural milieu.21 Especially in our times of cultural globalization, this interaction is becoming ever more important, and we can see the effects of this development in the ways in which most traditions have, indeed, become players in a global field. Although this field is still heterogeneous, the fact that there is interaction makes that cultural traditions have to become more self-reflective about their own identity and their correspondence and differences with other traditions. This self-reflexivity creates room for mutual understanding between different cultural values, even though the fact that this self-reflexivity is bound to a specific cultural perspective precludes that these value traditions would be prepared to enter a neutral or homogeneous playing field. In sum, in the case of conflicting cultural values, dialogical pluralism aims at avoiding a complete deadlock, which would be the inevitable consequence of holding on to the idea of a complete incommensurability between heterogeneous values, by requiring the participants in this dialogue to be open minded to the values of others while at the same time remaining attached to their own values. 5. Practical wisdom Against this background, I want to examine whether the idea of practical wisdom could be helpful to develop the idea of dialogical pluralism further. In particular, the question is whether this kind of wisdom presents a possible way to deal with value conflicts in a context of radical cultural diversity. The reasons for drawing such a parallel with dialogical pluralism are, first, that the idea of wisdom does not uphold either the idea of a neutral public space, but tries to establish a shared space. Moreover, in both cases this shared space rests less on a procedural than on a substantial kind of rationality. Finally, just as dialogical pluralism, practical wisdom has a close relation to cultural values, including the implicit, fragmented, and local ones. To my mind, the idea of wisdom may be making a comeback, after it has been associated for a long time with old people, tradition and conservative caution in a culture of youth, modernisation, innovation and risky exploration. The revival of wisdom is especially evident in areas where knowledge and (technical) know-how come up against questions of ethics and, above all, values.22 Any wisdom needs to take seriously the desire for some sense of overall meaning and connectedness, and also for guidance in discernment in specific 21 Vroom, Walking in a Widening World, 260f. David Ford, Christian Wisdom. Desiring God and Learning in Love. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007, p. 1. 22 11 situations.23 This means that wisdom requires an objective as well as a subjective integration or connectedness, and, hence, has an aspect of theoretical learning as well as of practical virtue: someone who has a vast knowledge about values, but who lives foolishly himself, would not be termed wise.24 Since striving for wisdom is an inherent element in all religious and secular value systems, wisdom can be qualified as having a trans-cultural, universally human character,25 which is founded on the fact that all humans have to deal with value issues. A concrete example of how the idea of practical wisdom offers a concretization of dialogical pluralism is cultural value reasoning. This approach stems from the tradition of interreligious dialogue, which, under the name of ‘scriptural reasoning’, is aimed at solving conflicts between religions in a peaceful way.26 Because of the major similarities between religious conflicts and cultural value conflicts, what I will do in this section is to examine whether this approach can be rephrased in such a way that it can be applied to cultural value conflicts as well. It has to be noted that ‘value reasoning’ refrains from a theorizing about values, but concentrates on how people with diverging values can dialogue with each other about concrete, practical value issues.27 First of all, all participants engaged in cultural value reasoning have to acknowledge the fundamental character of the others’ values to them (without having to acknowledge their authority for oneself), as well as to recognize that they do not exclusively ‘own’ the values of their cultural tradition, which means that they are not the only experts on its final meaning.28 By taking this approach, cultural value reasoning aims at stimulating a self-reflective attitude among the people who participate in such a dialogue, without requiring them to give up the fundamental character of their values to them. Cultural value reasoning starts with recognizing that cultural values are at the heart of the identity of a culture, as has been pointed out in the introduction of this paper. However, cultural values are not just abstract principles or strange practices, but result from long chains of reasoning about the good life, thus constituting the essence of a cultural identity. So, cultural value reasoning prevents these values from being reduced to contingent social constructions. In order to show how these values can orientate the lives of people today they have to be made public. Value reasoning fulfils this task by bringing together the views of the good life, their interpretation by philosophical reasoning, and ‘public issue’ questions. As is common knowledge, each of these value systems can also be used to frame the identity of a culture in a problematic way, e.g., by opposing it to other identities, legitimatizing violence, claiming superiority, pronouncing blanket condemnations, etc.29 This refers to the pitfall of exclusivism, i.e. the tendency that one value system strives for exclusive recognition. In order to avoid this and other pitfalls, cultural value reasoning stimulates that 23 John Kekes, Wisdom. In: American Philosophical Quarterly, 1983, 277-286. Robert Nozick, What is Wisdom and Why do Philosophers Love it so? In: Idem, The examined Life. Philosophical Meditations. New York: Touchstone Press, 1989, p. 273. 25 Andreas Speer, Weisheit. In: Joachim Ritter, Karlfried Gründer, and Gottfried Gabriel (eds.), Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 2004, p. 371. 26 For an analysis of scriptural reasoning and references to other literature about this issue see: Peter Jonkers, From Rational Doctrine to Christian Wisdom. In: Staf Hellemans and Peter Jonkers (eds.), A Catholic Minority Church in a World of Seekers. Washington: The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy, 2015. 27 For a description of the practice of scriptural reasoning see: Ford, Christian Wisdom, pp. 275-278, and Nicolas Adams, Habermas and Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006, pp. 239-243. 28 Ford, Christian Wisdom, pp. 279f. See also Adams, Habermas and Theology, p. 243. 29 Ford, Christian Wisdom, p. 274. 24 12 cultural traditions become self-reflective: in particular, its members have to acknowledge the fundamental character of the others’ values to them, but without having to acknowledge their authority for oneself. When people enter the hermeneutical circle of the public debate and, by doing so, become self-reflective, they learn to accept the idea that the values of others express a kind wisdom that can be interpreted philosophically, and, hence, offers food for thought to all participants in the public debate, even though they may not share or even reject these values. Hence, this philosophical interpretation of the wisdom that is embedded in value traditions creates a shared field for people from different cultures. But, given the heterogeneous character of this field, value reasoning is polyphonic, which implies that it is not aimed at reaching consensus. It even less can be reduced to an authoritarian monologue of one value system, distorting all the other ones. The above shows that value reasoning can mediate between divergent cultural values in a heterogeneous playing field. It realizes this aim by making deep value reasonings public so that others may learn to understand them and discover why particular trains of reasoning are reasonings, and not just particular assumptions, contingent social constructions, and why they are attractive or problematic.30 In other words, value reasoning stimulates value traditions to become self-reflective, so that they can situate themselves against a broader cultural background, and can be recognized by people who do not belong to this specific tradition, but without requiring them to accept any claim for exclusive recognition. Value reasoning is able to fulfill this task because it is a manifestation of practical wisdom, which is the fruit of a much broader kind of rationality than the rather procedural kind of rationality, which dominates the thinking of many prominent modern political philosophers. Hence, value reasoning is able to understand the values that are foundational for a culture in their own right. It is aimed at establishing a self-reflective, hermeneutical field that is shared by various value traditions. This shared field is the result of the common need for existential orientation, to which all value traditions are trying to respond. In this context, it is also important to note that the shared field, at which value reasoning aims by making the reasonings of different value systems public, is not identical with striving after consensus. As we have discussed in the previous section, consensus is only possible in a homogeneous playing field, whereas the kind of value conflicts that I am discussing in this paper take place in a heterogeneous field. Rather, the best result that can be reached is friendship, that is, the recognition of the sacred nature of each other’s values and a shared desire to study them. How, then, can value reasoning realize the recognition of the sacred character of fundamental values, while avoiding that this recognition becomes exclusive? The answer is that it only coordinates discussions between members of different value traditions without requiring a commitment to a specific culture and a specific interpretation of human rights, which often turns out to be a Western, individualist one. Participants engage in value reasoning only as members of a particular value tradition. But by doing so, they also recognize that their specific value system does not completely exhaust the very idea of human dignity, which underlies each value system. Because this recognition counts for all specific value systems, none of them can claim to have a monopoly on it. Moreover, value reasoning prepares a shared playing field, which means that the members of value traditions accept the claim that the other belongs there too, without stating further conditions as to the nature of their reasonings. This explains why value reasoning is aimed at friendship, 30 Adams, Habermas and Theology, p. 242; see also Ford, Christian Wisdom, p. 281. 13 resulting from respectfully studying religious traditions, rather than at consensus on specific issues. A final reason why value reasoning may offer a solution to the problem of value conflicts in a context of radical cultural diversity is that it does not make a strong contrast between argumentation and narrative. Because value reasoning brings together the interpretation of values, the practices of philosophical and theological reasoning, and ‘public issue’ questions, there is argumentation at every stage of it. This is so because, again, value reasoning is an expression of practical wisdom, and is practiced in a shared, not in a neutral, space. In other words, through its origin in wisdom, value reasoning manifests a broader kind of reasonableness than modern, procedural reason, and is therefore able to include argumentation and narration. 6. Conclusion Accepting dialogical pluralism and cultural value reasoning, being instances of practical wisdom, as possibly fruitful approaches to deal with conflicting cultural values in a heterogeneous field inevitably means having to accept a far greater variety as regards the substance of these values. Hence, no specific cultural value tradition, including the Western one, can legitimately claim to have the prerogative to impose its own values on other cultures or even to require that the latter have to translate their values into the procedural, secular rationality, which predominates the current public debate on these issues. The only fundamental requirement that has to be fulfilled is that all value traditions are prepared to make their values public by showing that they result from reasoning, thus stimulating a process of self-reflexivity.