Kyle Sutliff Philosophy of Law Page |1 A Positivist Response to Criticism In Law’s Empire Ronald Dworkin puts forth a compelling criticism of H.L.A. Hart’s theory of Legal Positivism. This criticism is based on the rigidity of Hart’s “Rule of Recognition” and its inability to account for theoretical disagreements. In this paper I intend to prove that though Dworkin’s argument is logically valid, a further analysis that expands his conclusion, results in a contradiction. This is because such a rigid interpretation of the rule of recognition eliminates not only the possibility of theoretical disagreements but also empirical disagreements and the need for a rule of change. Since Hart’s theory provides for the possibility of both, Dworkin’s criticism must be flawed. The first two premises of Dworkin’s argument are simply definitions of terms. He claims that a theoretical disagreement arises when legal officials “disagree about whether statute books and judicial decisions exhaust the pertinent grounds of law.”(Dworkin 5) In other words disagreement is not about historical facts of law but about whether these facts thoroughly identify with a specific case. This distinction is important because Dworkin would have Hart claim that such disagreements are non-existent; that for such cases that the historical facts are insufficient to resolve a situation, the legal officials simply make new law. This claim is based on Dworkin’s second premise which is a definition of a semantic theory. Such a theory “suppose[s] that lawyers and judges use mainly the same criteria in deciding when propositions of law are true or false; They suppose that lawyers actually agree about the grounds of law.”(Dworkin 33) This is important because if legal officials use the same criteria for deciding the grounds of law then they must agree when they are exhausted by historical facts. What this does for Dworkin is prove that if a theory is semantic then it must deny the existence of theoretical disagreements. As his third premise Dworkin proves the existence of Kyle Sutliff Philosophy of Law Page |2 theoretical disagreements through the example of real cases. This generates the conclusion that semantic theories must be flawed, since they cannot account for reality. The only step that remains is to prove that positivism is a semantic theory. To do this Dworkin points to the rule of recognition. According to Hart the rule of recognition acts to “specify some feature or features possession of which by a suggested rule is taken as a conclusive affirmative indication that it is a rule of the group to be supported by the social pressure it exerts.”(Hart 94) In this definition Dworkin takes the suggested rule to be the law or proposition of law in question. The features such a proposition must possess, to affirm it as law, become the grounds of law. Based on Dworkin’s definition, taking the grounds of law to be “circumstances in which particular laws should be taken to be sound or true,”(Dworkin 110) this interpretation of the rule of recognition is, at worst, plausible. It is remarkable how similar Hart’s term “features” is to Dworkin’s “circumstances” and how “affirmative indication” matches “taken to be sound” in meaning. Given this, Dworkin has proven legal positivism to be a semantic theory and thus completing his argument disproving the validity of legal positivism. So far, this argument seems to be, not only valid but perfectly sound. However, let us follow Dworkin’s reasoning further and consider the validity of the resulting conclusions. The main strength of the argument is its proving that the rigidity, caused by the assumption of mutual agreement that is required for the rule of recognition to function, cannot account for reality. Keeping that in mind, consider a case in which a previous decision was overturned as being unconstitutional. If we thought that all legal officials agreed upon the grounds of law when making the first ruling how is it that they could then rule in an opposite direction at a later time? This question highlights the problem of how law ever changes in a semantic theory. Based on the current definition of a semantic theory it is impossible to ever change or eliminate Kyle Sutliff Philosophy of Law Page |3 law. This inability exists because the assumption of the mutual knowledge and common sense required for mutual agreement, on the grounds of law, creates a requirement for a sudden unanimous revelation of circumstance in order to change current law. Imagine a society in which all members possessed almost identical knowledge and thought in the same rational manner(shared common sense). What would it take for this society to change its mind on a rule that was unanimously agreed upon? It seems like nothing short of a revelation of previously unattainable information would suffice. It is completely implausible, for it to be true, that for every overturned legal proposition a sudden, unexpected change in circumstance appeared to the shock and awe of all legal officials. This would seem to be another problem for the positivist, except for the blaring contradiction created by the existence of the rule of change. Hart defines this rule as “that which empowers an individual or body of persons to introduce new primary rules…and to eliminate old rules.”(Hart 95) It would seem odd, given the information we have already divined from Dworkin’s argument, that Hart would bother to define such a rule. Yet, within his theory Hart identifies not only the existence, but necessity, of such a rule as a counter to the problem of a static legislature. Since we have already shown the impossibility of meeting the circumstances required to eliminate a law, the existence of the rule of change is a contradiction amidst our argument. Since this contradiction is the result of an expansion of Dworkin’s argument it implies the existence of a flaw inherent within. Dworkin can respond to this implication in two ways. The first way would be to attack the premise stating that positivism doesn’t allow for legal change. This approach would be ineffective in that to adequately attack the premise Dworkin would have to dispute the rigidity of the rule of recognition, an assumption upon which his initial argument is dependent. The second Kyle Sutliff Philosophy of Law Page |4 option available to Dworkin would be to continue to promote the rigidity inherent in the rule of recognition and claim that the existence of an elimination function within the rule of change is a mistake. This argument is reminiscent of his portrayal of the standard positivist defense to his argument. Dworkin portrays the first positivist response to his original argument as a denial of the existence of theoretical disagreements. He disproves this denial through showing us examples in which legal officials believe they are interpreting existing law. We can also demonstrate examples of judges overturning law and of Hart explaining this ability in the rule of change. Dworkin could attempt to deny the existence to a further extent by trying to prove Hart as mistaken, confused or even communicating on a different level than us, but this type of argument would be subject to his own counterargument of the semantic sting. Dworkin eliminated any defense he could make to the claim that elimination actually exists, within the rule of change, when he presented arguments to defend his claim that theoretical disagreements actually exist. He also cannot deny the rigidity of the rule of recognition because this premise is one upon which his argument is dependent. Therefore since this rigidity creates a contradiction within Hart’s theory, Dworkin’s argument must be flawed. This is true despite its original appearance as sound because the extrapolation of his premises have led to a contradiction. Overall Dworkin’s argument does require us to consider the existence of theoretical disagreements and how Hart could address them, but due to this flaw, it does not provide us with a good reason to abandon legal positivism. Kyle Sutliff Philosophy of Law Bibliography Dworkin, Ronald. Law's Empire. Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1986. Print. Hart, H. L. A. The Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1997. Print. Page |5