Realism, Nominalism, Resemblance Theory, and Contested Cases Howard Benjamin Shaeffer Assistant Professor of Philosophy Humboldt State University 1 Harpst St. Arcata, CA 95521 hbs1@humboldt.edu 707-826-5755 Abstract: According to Renford Bambrough, Wittgenstein’s family resemblance account of universals –which is at odds with both realism and nominalism -- solves the problem of universals. After rehearsing Wittgenstein’s arguments against both nominalism and realism, I argue that Wittgenstein’s view does not do an adequate job explaining how we resolve the problem of universals for important, contested cases, such as art, justice, and science. I conclude that we are, in those cases, driven back to nominalism. 2991 words. 1 Did Wittgenstein solve the problem of universals? According to Renford Bambrough1, he did. On Bambrough’s interpretation (which I think is basically correct), Wittgenstein’s resemblance theory of universals holds simply that what all games, for instance, have in common, are that they are games. Wittgenstein is thereby at odds with both realism and nominalism. The realist thinks that what all games (for example) have in common is that they have the essential characteristics of games. The nominalist, on the other hand, says that the only thing all games have in common is that they are called “games”. Suppose we disagree over whether tossing a ball against a wall and catching it constitutes a game. The realist’s position implies that our disagreement could in principle be settled on objective grounds: that there is a real definition of “game” that exists independently of human agreement and against which our judgments about what constitutes a game can be judged right or wrong. The nominalist’s position implies that there is no such real definition, and that our disagreement cannot be settled on principled grounds. What makes it the case that tossing a ball against a wall and catching is a game, if it is a game, is simply that we decide to call it one. Wittgenstein held that the meaning of a person’s speech is its use in human activity. An analysis of the meaning of “game” will be a matter of describing the various ways in which the word functions in the different contexts where it has a home, as it were. When we do, we find that there is nothing that all the things we call “game” have in common: Consider, for example, the proceedings that we call “games”. I mean board-games, card-games, ball-games, Olympic games, and so on. What is common to them all? Don’t say: “There must be something common, or they would not be called ‘games’” – but look and see whether there is anything common to all. For if you look at them you will not see something that is common to all, but similarities, relationships, and a whole series of them at that. To repeat: don’t think, but look! …And the result of this examination is: we see a complicated network of similarities Renford Bambrough, “Universals and Family Resemblances”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. LXI (1960-61), pp. 207-222. 1 2 overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes overall similarities, sometimes similarities of detail. (PI 66). Although there are a number of features that figure in something’s being a game, there is no one of these features that all games have in common. But the games form a family in that some combination of these features is always present, though no one combination is always present. It is obvious that Wittgenstein’s view has more affinities with nominalism than with realism, insofar as they both have it that it is our saying that x is a game, ultimately, that makes it the case that x is a game. But as Bambrough points out, the nominalist cannot explain how it is a person is able to learn applications of terms like ‘chair’ to new cases. Suppose, he says, that we invent a term (call it “alpha”) that refers to whatever we say it refers to, in accord with the nominalist’s theory of how general terms work. Then it follows that we will have applied the term arbitrarily to the things we label as alphas. But if that is so, then it will be impossible for someone to learn the term such that he or she will know how to apply it in the future; and furthermore, any such applications will necessarily be wrong, because those future items will not be things that we have called “alpha”. So the nominalist cannot explain two important aspects of concept possession, namely, our ability to learn how to apply concepts beyond the particular examples we are given, and, perhaps more importantly, the capacity to do so correctly. The resemblance account, however, can explain both how one learns to apply terms to novel cases and what makes it correct to do so. When one sees that the novel case sufficiently resembles paradigm cases of alphas – cases that everyone more or less takes to count as alphas -- then it is correct to apply the term alpha. Resemblance theory avoids realism without making meaning arbitrary. 3 The realist assumes we need a rule or criterion that, when applied to any test case, will determine whether we are or are not dealing with a game. If we lack such a criterion, then we have no justification for applying the word to new contexts, and in that case, the realist speaks, we speak gibberish whenever we use the word. But if Wittgenstein is right and the word’s meaning is in its use, we have no reason to expect that our definition will be able to cover any logically possible case, and no need for it to do so: I say “There is a chair”. What if I go up to it, meaning to fetch it, and it suddenly disappears from sight? “So it wasn’t a chair, but some kind of illusion”. – But in a few moments we see it again and are able to touch it and so on. …Have you rules ready for such cases – rules saying whether one may use the word “chair” to include this kind of thing? But do we miss them when we use the word “chair”; and are we to say that we do not really attach any meaning to this word, because we are not equipped with rules for every possible application of it? (PI 80) Furthermore, the need for an explanation of the meaning of the terms only arises in contexts in which there is a specific misunderstanding, and it is satisfied when the specific misunderstanding is resolved: Suppose I give this explanation: “I take ‘Moses’ to mean the man if, there was such a man, who led the Israelites out of Egypt, whatever he was called then and whatever he may or may not have done besides.” – But similar doubts to those about Moses are possible about the words of this explanation… --But then how does an explanation help me to understand, if after all it is not the final one? In that case the explanation is never completed, so I still don’t understand what he means, and never shall!” ‘—As though an explanation as it were hung in the air unless supported by another one. Whereas an explanation may indeed rest on another one that has been given, but none stands in need of another – unless we require it to prevent misunderstanding. (PI 87) The realist’s demand for a criterion for every term only leads to an infinitely regressive analysis, Wittgenstein thinks, and so the explanation will, ultimately, be unsupported. But that has the absurd consequence that we do not understand one another ever. It is absurd because it is contradicted by the evidence. We see language “working” every moment of every day, since it is woven into every aspect of our daily lives, in ways that are central to our success at cooperative 4 activity. There are some contexts where “Stand roughly here” is perfectly exact, depending on what we are trying to accomplish (say I want to take your picture in front of a landscape). Why should we say that because I cannot specify what precisely I mean by “here”, I am therefore not speaking meaningfully, especially if the photo comes out as we wanted? Notice, however, that Wittgenstein’s examples are examples where it is difficult to imagine much of importance being at stake in whether or not we agree to the extension of the term. It is difficult to imagine a conversation in which whether a child tossing a ball against a wall and catching it (say) constitutes a game, or whether a barstool constitutes a chair, matters. This is not to say that we cannot imagine such cases. But for the most part, it does not matter, with regard to these terms, what we say, so long as we understand one another. You may insist, and I may deny, that the child is playing a game. But if you give me your reasons for saying so (“it involves using a ball with skill”, maybe), then I can say that while I don’t agree, I can see your reasons for saying so, and as long as there are no misunderstandings when we are speaking of games in other contexts, you can call it a game if you wish. Or I may want to count a barstool as a chair because a person can sit on it, whereas you think it must be the sort of thing a person can sit in. But, again, it is as we wish, so long as we know what the other means. When nothing of importance hangs on whether the particular before us is an example of an x, the standard of reasonableness in calling it an x is correspondingly weak. But what about cases where something important is at stake? Plato, the arch-realist, was concerned not with terms like “game”, or “chair”, but with consistently contested terms that had important political and social implications, terms such as “virtue”, “justice”, “art”, or “science”. These are cases in which it is wrong to say, as Wittgenstein says of “game”, that our inability to draw a boundary never troubled us before when we used the term (PI 68). These terms do in fact 5 trouble us; they are often the basis of deep and sometimes even violent disagreement. So, yes, if the realist’s only motivation for wanting a strict criterion is a theory of meaning in which we do not speak meaningfully unless our words are supported by definitions, then Wittgenstein’s response seems persuasive. But that is not the realist’s only, or perhaps even main, motivation for wanting a strict criterion. The need for the criterion in these cases arises from the need to be able to settle important disputed cases. (It is still true that we do not need a criterion for every possible case; but we do, it might be argued, need a criterion to sort through the contested cases with which we are constantly face). Nor will it help to say, as Wittgenstein does at PI 68, that we can draw a boundary if we choose, but that this boundary is only useful for particular purposes, and needn’t be drawn at all. For the person who is concerned about whether capital punishment for child rapists is just will not want an arbitrary definition of justice, or one that simply fits the particular case (whatever that may mean). It seems, then, that Wittgenstein has not shown that the realist has no good reason for wanting a definition. What he needs to show, I think, is that that need is an empty one because it cannot, as a matter of necessity, be met. If Wittgenstein is right about meaning-as-use, then he already has an argument against the possibility of a definition at his disposal. Once we agree that the meaning of a term or phrase is its use in human practices, we are committed to saying that there can be no a priori limit on how the term will be used. Human life is organic; language games grow and change, come and go. There are always new possibilities and the closing off of previous possibilities. Thus we cannot say, once and for all, what, for instance, is a “game”, because we do not know what will constitute sufficient resemblance to other games in the future, or how the context in which games 6 are played will change. (For evidence of this, consider the fact that there is at this moment a serious debate about whether chess constitutes a sport). 2 But what of resemblance itself, though? What justifies us in claiming that two things resemble one another? How do we know how many properties two things must have in common in order for them to sufficiently resemble one another? How do we know which are the relevant points of comparison? It is obvious that Wittgenstein would reject a realist account of resemblance. Presumably Wittgenstein will want to say that all cases of resemblance are so in virtue of their resembling paradigmatic cases of resemblance. Will we say, in teaching resemblance, “…this and other similar relationships we call ‘resemblance” (PI 61)? It is obvious that this method of teaching presupposes that the learner already knows what resemblance is. So how do we learn resemblance itself? And what makes us correct in saying that two things sufficiently resemble one another such that they can be categorized the same? The question presupposes that the child first learns what resemblance is, and then applies this knowledge to the learning of other concepts. How else could it be?, we are tempted to ask. And this, in a way, is Wittgenstein’s point as Bambrough interprets him: we do not determine that all chairs are chairs by resemblance; rather, we learn what resemblance is when we learn concepts such as “chair”. As our elders point out to us chairs, we learn to judge when we are in the presence of chairs. The resemblance account of universals is not an account of how we learn what chairs (for instance) are; it is simply a way of pointing to the fact that we learn what chairs 2 (Wittgenstein does not make this argument. Instead, he returns to the idea that no sign (of which ostensive definition is an example) is self-interpreting. Sometimes others interpret our speech in ways we expect them to; other times they do not. This shows that the rule itself always stands in need of interpretation. But then, won’t the rule for interpreting the rule itself stand in need of interpretation, and so on without end? Our perceived need for a rule that works in every conceivable context cannot be satisfied, because the rule itself always needs interpretation. But we know it is always possible to misinterpret). 7 are by being trained simply to recognize chairs. It is not that we first learn resemblance and then apply it to other concepts; we learn resemblance when we learn those other concepts. This may sound absurd, but I do not think that it is. Consider a person learning to drive a car. At some point, one has to be able to judge when it is safe to cross a highway, or to merge into traffic. And in learning this, we learn to judge the speed of the other cars, the space between the cars, etc., so that at some point we can determine when it is safe to proceed. But we do not find ourselves applying a standard of resemblance between cases. Rather, we simply use the judgment that we have honed by practicing at driving. I do not infer that it is safe to cross; I see that it is safe, just as I do not infer that the children tossing a ball are playing a game, I see that they are. It is true, perhaps, that this particular case is significantly like other cases when we crossed traffic safely. But that is not the basis on which we judge that it is now safe. Still, though, the problem that I mentioned before, namely, the problem of contested cases, remains. For it is precisely here that our judgment falters. Consider, for instance the case of art. A person might reasonably claim that Olafur Eliasson’s Your Mobile Expectations: BMW H2R Project—which essentially consists of a stripped BMW frozen in 2 tons of ice – is not really art. I say that it is. After all, it is being displayed in the San Francisco MOMA, the person who created it is a well known artist (though this begs the question), etc. Here it will not do to say that the question of whether it is art is settled by asking whether it sufficiently resembles other cases of art because, as we have said, there is no objective criterion for sufficient resemblance, and whether they sufficiently resemble one another depends, on the view we are considering, as much on whether they are artworks as vice versa. Only the judgment of those who have experience in identifying artworks will resolve the issue. And, obviously our judgment differs. 8 So where does this leave us? We have seen that there are good arguments against possibility of giving a criterion for distinguishing (for instance) art from non-art. And we have seen that the resemblance account will not help us either. Perhaps we should return to Wittgenstein’s directive that we “look and see”. When we do look and see how it actually works with regard to art, we see that all the terms of the language game of art (not to mention others) – shift and slide and are negotiated every day by art-historians, artists, critics, journalists, and other members of the artworld, so that the concept of art is always in the process of being decided. And we see furthermore that this decision is not based on principle grounds – that would be a return to realism – but rather to contingent facts about the art-institution, for instance, who is in power and what are their moral and aesthetic commitments, how do they understand the history of art and its relation to current society, etc. But now, it looks as if the nominalist is right after all; for it looks as if what determines whether something sufficiently resembles another to be considered art is, after all, a matter of our deciding that it does. This is not, as in the case of chair or game, a matter of using our judgment, for, as I have said, here our judgment gives out. Rather, if we do decide to count Olafson’s work as a work of art, it will not be for reasons that we can give to justify the choice. 9