Izaguirre Yoe Classical Rhetorics Annotated Bibliography I. Rhetoric, Ethics, and Politics Rowland, Robert C. and Deanna F. Womack. “Aristotle’s View of Ethical Rhetoric.” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 45, no. ½ (Winter – Spring 1985): 13-31, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3885793. Rowland and Womack describe the ways in which Aristotle’s conception of rhetoric operates under ethical constraints in the public sphere. The authors demonstrate how Aristotle’s ethical theory permeates rhetorical practice, particularly as rhetoric should be practiced within the context of a democratic society. Rowland and Womack, however, are careful to distinguish between the rhetorical potency and rhetorical product, the former bearing amoral dynamis to argue both sides of a contested issue whereas the latter as “action” or energeia invites moral evaluation. For the authors, it is the rhetorical product that can be evaluated for ethicality. Their distillation of the “Five Presuppositions” of Aristotle’s ethical theory, as discerned through the Rhetoric, Nicomachean Ethics, and Politics, provides a moral foundation for Aristotle’s rhetoric as social practice and will supply the student of rhetoric with a heuristic for discerning the ethical dimensions threading Aristotle’s works. II. Rhetoric and Politics Haskins, Ekaterina. “On the Term ‘Dunamis’ in Aristotle’s Definition of Rhetoric.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 46, no. 2 (2013): 234-240, Haskins proposes that Aristotle’s use of the term dunamis represents a rhetorical choice to situate rhetoric as a distinct art divorced from practical oratory. Instead, rhetoric as a dunamis is a faculty by which rhetorical causes can be discovered without necessarily delving into the world of praxis or practical matters. For Aristotle, Haskins argues, the realm of the practical belongs to the politike, which is itself, according to Haskins, an exploration into the most amenable context for the development of practical virtue. Haskins admits a divergent approach to Aristotle’s conception of rhetoric as a dunamis, namely and approach that provides an understanding of Aristotle’s view on the role of politike in shaping practical virtue that subjugates rhetoric rather than converse. The work supplies a fresh perspective on understanding Aristotle’s explication of the “ability to discern the available means of persuasion.” III. Rhetoric and Ethics Irwin, T.H. “Ethics in the Rhetoric and in the Ethics,” in Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, edited by Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, 142-74. Berkeley: University of California, 1996. Irwin draws distinctions between how the Rhetoric and Aristotle’s Ethics approach ethical qualities or “virtues.” Although Aristotle treats various virtues in both works, he does not do so with the same end. Irwin observes that the primary concern of the Rhetoric is virtue’s role in argument construction suitable to the audience. However, in Ethics, the primary concern is the discovery of the nature and expression of each virtue. Both works detail how commonly held beliefs resource rhetorical activity and ethical activity, but the difference between them lies in the argumentative end or lack thereof. Irwin’s argument merits attention, as it attempts to consider how the purposes of each book display their content differently because of their apparent function. Irwin’s chapter of the book are excellent resources for exploring Aristotle’s ethical theory through the lens of (rhetorical) purpose. 1 Izaguirre Yoe Classical Rhetorics IV. Rhetoric and Poetics Kaufmann, Charles. “Poetic as Argument.” Quarterly Journal of Speech 67 (1981): 407-415. Kaufmann contends for a rhetorical link between Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics. For the author, poetry and rhetoric share a similar goal: audience affect. The means by which both disciplines accomplish their respective goals is through argumentation, particularly the employment of an enthymematic form. During argument, the enthymeme works as a deduction from the audience’s “common beliefs” to the “rhetor’s” desired outcome. Since both rhetoric and poetry work to produce judgment from the audience, Kaufmann articulates how the enthymeme functions in both arts to accomplish each discipline’s ends. This work serves as a validation for rhetoric’s employment and criticism in other disciplines besides texts of discourses. V. Rhetorical Criticism Farrell, T. B. "Sizing Things Up: Colloquial Reflection as Practical Wisdom." Argumentation 12 (1998): 1-14. Farrell reconsiders Aristotle's conception of three poetic categories within the function of rhetoric as "making things matter." He appropriates categories from Poetics and other works (e.g., De Interpretatione) to demonstrate the ways in which rhetoric can take the vast and threatening nature of our worlds and invite the audiences to reflect on the meaning and significance of events. Farrell explicates Aristotle's concepts of contingency, magnitude, and phronésis, as rhetorically relevant categories that provide the Rhetoric with both logical and aesthetic components necessary to induce audience participation and recognition. This piece highlights the ways in the rhetorical critic can fuse Aristotle's thoughts on aesthetics and dialectics to understand rhetorical enterprises intended to emphasize particularities within contested situations, and thus, is an excellent resource for how the critic can engage in rhetorical reflection from an aesthetic perspective. 2