INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Ethical Systems QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHERS ASK: “WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?” “HOW DO YOU PHILOSOPHIZE?” “WHAT IS REAL?” “HOW DO YOU KNOW WHAT YOU KNOW?” “HOW SHOULD YOU LIVE?” “WHAT OUGHT WE TO DO?” THE LAST TWO ARE QUESTIONS OF ETHICS, A CATEGORY OF PHILOSOPHY THAT IS DISTINCTLY DIFFERENT FROM ALL THE PREVIOUS CATEGORIES (METHODOLOGY, LOGIC, METAPHYSICS, EPISTEMOLOGY). ALL OF THE REST DEAL WITH THE HEAD (MOSTLY). ETHICS IS NOT PRIMARILY A MATTER OF THE HEAD, BUT OF THE HEART, NOT OF THE INTELLECT BUT OF THE WILL. Still, philosophy seeks to find rational concepts to guide us in moral decision-making. In doing so, it has done one of two things, historically: 1. CONSIDER RELIGIOUS BELIEFS 2. EXCLUDE RELIGIOUS BELIEFS FROM CONSIDERATION These two stances have been procedural positions, adopted for practical reasons. Ethical systems are either RELIGIOUSLY BASED, OR SECULARLY BASED Systems based (partially or totally) on religious beliefs include: A. DIVINE COMMAND ETHICS B. NATURAL LAW THEORY Systems based on beliefs which exclude religion include: A. EGOISM B. UTILITARIANISM C. KANTIANISM D. EMOTIVISM E. CULTURAL RELATIVISM Professor Christopher Ullman 1 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY DIVINE COMMAND ETHICS SYSTEMS An act is right and moral because God says it is so. An act is wrong or immoral because God says it is so. MEMORY IMAGE: THE BOOK Far and away, this is the most commonly followed system, throughout history. Plato knew of it, and tried to show it was irrational by posing the following dilemma in his dialogue Euthyphro: 1. Is something right because God commands it? 2. Or does God command it because it is right? 1. If you said, "Because God commands it," does that mean that God could command you to lie to your neighbor, and that would make it right? This renders the moral law arbitrary, "right" just because God said so, and perhaps God could change his mind. If you object, "Oh, but he wouldn't! God is moral," you are agreeing with the second position. 2. If you said, "God commands it because it is right," then this means that God is not allpowerful but must limit his choices to that which reason shows is moral. Is God the only one who has reason? Can we not also use our reason to discover what is moral? If so, of what use is the idea of divine command, when it comes to making moral decisions? Plato's crucial assumption: "The Nature of God" and "Moral Standards for Actions" are two separate categories. The Nature of Moral Standards God for Actions Therefore, when God considers whether a given Act X is moral, he must use reason to compare the attributes of Act X to the attributes of Morality: The Nature of Moral Standards God for Actions Act X If this assumption is true, then we have the classic unanswerable dilemma: Which came first, the chicken or the egg? However, Plato, and the many ethicists who have agreed with him, have committed a fatal mistake in logic: The Strawman Fallacy. (This occurs when you distort or exaggerate a person's argument for the purpose of more easily destroying it. It's easier to kill a strawman than a real Professor Christopher Ullman 2 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY man.) Do all the world's great religions teach that the nature of God and moral standards of action are actually separate categories? NO. Instead, throughout the literature that comprises the beliefs of the great religions, it is easy to show that the prevailing belief is that morality is one of the key facets of God's nature: The Nature of God Morality & occur simultaneously Action X The question is now, "Which came first, the chicken or the chicken?" Thus, there is no dilemma for the believer, if s/he believes that God cannot violate his own nature, and this is a near universal belief for theists. Q. How can something religious qualify as a system? A.1. By furnishing the basis of moral obligation Theonomy Not Autonomy Not Heteronomy A.2. By referring to a publicly available body of ethical writings containing what are believed to be divine commands that are authoritative and normative. Incomplete list of examples: The Bible (Christianity) The Torah (Judaism) The Koran (Islam) The Granth (Sikhism) The Code of Manu (Hinduism) The Pali Sermons (Buddhism) The Analects (Confucianism) Tao Te Ching (Taoism) How does a divine command system work? 1. Categorize the situation: what kind of ethical decision needs to be made? 2. Search the scriptures, looking for: a) outright specific commands b) general commands c) underlying principles 3. Then, look for a conflicting command or principle. To what does it apply? 4. Resolve the difficulty (if any) rationally 5. Follow the command 6. In doubt or indecision? Consult a religious leader, and/or pray for understanding Objections and responses 1. “The separation of church and state make religious ethical decisions illegitimate, or at best subjective.” The U.S. Constitution's First Amendment does not mandate the elimination of religious beliefs from ethical decision-making. It says, "Congress shall make no law respecting an Professor Christopher Ullman 3 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof." It is a simple matter to research the original intent of both Thomas Jefferson, the one who coined the term "wall of separation between church and state," and of the framers of the Constitution, to see that religious beliefs are not only not excluded as a basis for moral and legal justification but that religious beliefs literally saturate their writings, even on the role of government. 1 (They did caution that the federal government should not make a specific denomination the official religion of the United States, however.) 2. “Which religion? They are each so different from one another.” Similarities in ethical standards among the world religions are very apparent. Differences in the basic moralities are very minor. The biggest areas of difference between the world's religions are not ethical, but theological.2 3. Religion is neither rational nor philosophical.” Philosophy was born among highly religious people, and flowered among highly religious cultures. 4. “Does this mean I can’t be ethical if I’m not religious?” No. It means you can be ethical if you are. Divine command ethicists agree that atheists can and often are very moral individuals, but they reason that it is because they have discovered what God says is right without acknowledging that God is the source of morality and of sound moral decisions. This inscription is attributed to Mother Teresa. It is a plaque on the wall of her home for children in Calcutta. People are often unreasonable, illogical, and self-centered; Forgive them anyway. If you are kind, people may accuse you of selfish, ulterior motives; Be kind anyway. If you are successful, you will win some false friends and some true enemies; Succeed anyway. If you are honest and frank, people may cheat you; Be honest and frank anyway. 1 For example, the Founders quoted heavily from the Bible, and from authors such as John Locke (who wrote, among other things, A Rational Defense of Christianity) and Charles Montesquieu (who based his three-part government structure of separate judicial, legislative and executive branches on two Biblical verses: Isaiah 33:22 and Jeremiah 17:9). 2 For an enlightening illustration of this amazing agreement throughout history on ethical standards, see the Appendix of C. S. Lewis's The Abolition of Man. Professor Christopher Ullman 4 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY What you spend years building, someone could destroy overnight; Build anyway. If you find serenity and happiness, they may be jealous; Be happy anyway. The good you do today, people will often forget tomorrow; Do good anyway. Give the world the best you have, and it may never be enough; Give the world the best you've got anyway. You see, in the final analysis, it is between you and God; It was never between you and them anyway. 3 THE BASIS OF OBLIGATION THAT SOMETHING IS OR WILL BE DOES NOT IMPLY THAT WE OUGHT TO SEEK IT. OBLIGATION IS SELF-IMPOSED (AUTONOMOUS) OTHER-IMPOSED (HETERONOMOUS) GOD-IMPOSED (THEONOMOUS) IF OBLIGATION IS SELF-IMPOSED, I AM ABSOLUTELY FREE TO DO WHATEVER I FEEL I OUGHT TO DO. PROBLEM: -VALUE MAY ARISE FROM A GOLDEN-RULE, ‘RECIPROCITY’ UNDERSTANDING OF THE VALUE OF ME. BUT WHAT GIVES ME SUCH A VALUE? IF OBLIGATION IS OTHER-IMPOSED, I OUGHT TO DO WHAT THE GROUP TELLS ME I OUGHT TO DO. PROBLEMS: -WHICH GROUP? -DOES ALL THAT THIS GROUP COMMAND BECOME AN OBLIGATION? -IF AT ANY POINT I OBJECT, ON WHAT GROUNDS MAY I OBJECT? 3 http://www.ot-mp.net/mother_teresa.html Accessed on September 18, 2008 Professor Christopher Ullman 5 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY IF OBLIGATION IS GOD-IMPOSED, I OUGHT TO DO WHAT GOD SAYS I OUGHT TO DO. PROBLEMS: -WHICH GOD? -IS AN ACT RIGHT BECAUSE GOD SAID IT IS RIGHT, OR DOES GOD SAY IT IS RIGHT BECAUSE THE ACT IS RIGHT? (THE SECOND PROBLEM ARISES FROM AN UNDERSTANDING THAT GOD IS ONE ENTITY, AND MORALITY IS SOMETHING OUTSIDE OF GOD. THE PROBLEM VANISHES WHEN ONE ASSUMES GOD TO BE THE SOURCE AND GROUND OF ALL MORALITY.) WE CAN DEMONSTRATE THAT EACH BASIS REQUIRES FAITH, AND EACH REQUIRES SINGLE-MINDED, WHOLE-HEARTED DEVOTION. IN SUMMARY, EACH BASIS OF OBLIGATION RELIES UPON SOME ASSUMPTIONS. BASIS ASSUMPTIONS AUTO- “THE VALUE OF ME IS THE REASON FOR ETHICS.” NOMOUS “THE VALUE OF ME IS REAL & IN NO NEED OF OUTSIDE SUPPORT.” “I CAN LOOK TO MYSELF AS THE ULTIMATE MORAL AUTHORITY.” HETERONOMOUS “THERE ARE GROUPS WITH MORAL STANDARDS I CAN KNOW AND FOLLOW.” “I WILL CHOOSE A GROUP.” “ONCE I CHOOSE A GROUP, I CAN LOOK TO IT AS THE ULTIMATE MORAL AUTHORITY.” THEONOMOUS “THERE IS A GOD, AND THIS BEING HAS MORAL STANDARDS I CAN KNOW AND FOLLOW.” “ONCE I CHOOSE TO FOLLOW GOD, I CAN LOOK TO GOD AS THE ULTIMATE MORAL AUTHORITY.” Professor Christopher Ullman 6 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY NATURAL LAW ETHICS There is a natural order in the world that humans can discover. This natural order is good. An act is right and moral when it is in agreement with the natural order. An act is wrong and immoral when it violates that natural order. MEMORY IMAGE: A GARDEN Formative influences: Aristotle’s view of categories The Stoic philosophy of order Aquinas’ Christian filter 1. Individual things are of different kinds 2. Each kind of thing functions in ways determined by its nature 3. The nature of each thing is to function in the way it was designed by the Creator to function 4. Natural laws can be deduced from this fact 5. Even without the knowledge of God, humans have reason, which is the essence of our nature, and therefore humans can discover the laws necessary for human flourishing 6. “Good” is that to which a thing is naturally inclined to do, considering the purpose for which it was made. 7. “Evil” is any thing contrary to a thing’s nature 8. Humans are created beings with a unique nature to serve and enjoy fellowship with the Creator Some principles of Aquinas’ version of natural law theory: 1. Double effect (hinges on intention) a) Act must be no worse than morally neutral b) Bad effect must not be the means to achieve the good effect c) Intention must be to achieve the good effect d) Bad effect must not outweigh the good effect 2. Totality (hinges on stewardship or custodianship) a) Each of the body’s organs was created with the purpose of contributing to the function of the whole body b) Wholeness is to be preserved c) Actions which threaten wholeness must be necessary to be moral d) Always treat your body as something entrusted to you Objections and responses: Professor Christopher Ullman 7 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY 1. “Maybe we weren’t put here for a purpose.” Response: There is plenty of evidence we were. For example, the Second Law of Thermodynamics teaches that every closed system goes from order to randomness, from usefulness to uselessness, from information to confusion. This is confirmed by experimentation, and by everyday experience. Where did the initial high level of organization come from, if not from an Intelligent Designer? The evidence supporting the Anthropic Principle is significant. 2. “‘Function’ and ‘nature’ are imprecise terms.” Response: Empirical observation can clear them up. Faith can aid understanding 3. “What humanity affirms solely on the basis of inherent instincts and philosophical reasoning lacks normative force. Once God’s authority as lawgiver is used to support a particular law or principle offered by a natural law, the question becomes, ‘How then does this differ from divine command ethics?’” Response: There are so many principles for humans that are so essential for ethics. The rational person cannot not know them. For example, to plead ignorance of the principle that one ought not to harm another is absurd, even if the person has no belief in God. By following natural law, cross-cultural accountability is possible, without invoking a particular passage of sacred scripture. Professor Christopher Ullman 8 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY EGOISM Psychological egoism is the view that human beings always act from a single motive: self-love. Ethical egoism is the moral theory that we ought to act only from self-love. Image: A Big Number Five things to know about egoism: 1. Egoism teaches that everyone should always act in his/her own self-interest, regardless of the interests of others, unless their interests also serve his or hers. 2. This was taught by the ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus (341-270 B.C.), Friedrich Nietzsche (18441900), and by the contemporary American philosopher Ayn Rand (1905-1982). 3. It’s easy to determine self-interest, as opposed to the difficulty in determining what is in the interest of others, and then doing it. 4. Once you have determined your own self-interest, take responsibility for your actions (no more dependence upon someone else’s instructions). 5. Egoism works best for people living in isolation (e.g., Grizzly Adams), and for those who are financially self-sufficient (e.g., a Fortune 500 CEO). Objections and responses: 1. “What do you do when conflicts arise between selves?” -Egoists believe that the carefully considered self-interests of rational people will never conflict. 2. “Egoism works best when you keep it a secret. What another self ought to do is not something you can openly encourage in most cases.” -If it is in the egoist’s best interest to conceal motives, nothing should stop him/her from doing so. 3. “Egoism is antagonistic to most of the tasks of the helping professions (nurse, physician, teacher, etc.) Who wants to change a bedpan, or tell a person he has cancer, or fail a hard-working student?” -There are enough non-egoists in the world to take care of those tasks, for some misconceived higher good. It is in my interest as an egoist to let them carry on. 4. “Egoism is where we begin, as moral agents. (‘MINE!’ ‘NO!’ ‘I DON’T WANT TO!’) It’s why we need ethics in the first place!” -You need “ethics” because you haven’t the courage to pursue your self-interests unswervingly. An egoist does not need ethics as you have described them. 5. “Egoism is actually self-defeating. Unrestrained pursuit and indulgence of wants creates a world which it is in nobody’s best interests in inhabiting.” -We egoists will lose often enough to keep it interesting. Professor Christopher Ullman 9 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY UTILITARIANISM (a.k.a. “consequentialism” or “teleological ethics”) Originators: Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill (19th century) MEMORY IMAGE: A SET OF SCALES Key terms: utility, goal, consequences, prediction The principle of utility: 1. We will choose to do what is most useful (has the most utility) in reaching our goal 2. This is impossible to prove, but it is axiomatic, unquestionable, and unavoidable The goal: 1. The most famous utilitarian goals are either a) Maximize pleasure/minimize pain (Bentham) b) Bring about the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people (Mill) 1) Both goals beg the following questions a) For how long? b) By whose definition? c) At what cost? d) By what measure? Consequences – that which results from the action you decided to take or the rule you chose to follow Prediction – what the utilitarian must do, in every instance 1. Will the consequences of the chosen action or rule be the most useful possible consequences for achieving the chosen goal? 2. If the answer is yes, the action or rule is moral 3. If the answer is no, the action or rule is immoral “Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do . . . They govern us in all we do, all we say, in all we think . . .” -Jeremy Bentham, “The Principle of Utility,” from The Principles of Morals and Legislation, 1789. Ways to measure the value of a pleasure (Bentham’s Hedonistic Calculus) 1. its intensity 2. its duration 3. its certainty or uncertainty 4. its nearness or remoteness 5. its fecundity, or its ability to create more pleasure 6. its purity, or the absence of pain with it 7. its extent, or the number of persons enjoying it at the same time “By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure.” -John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, 1863 Objections and responses to utilitarianism: 1. “What about minority concerns, if the greatest good for the greatest number of people is the chosen goal?” – Enlightened societies know that minorities cannot be ignored without harm to the overall society. Professor Christopher Ullman 10 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY 2. “Utilitarianism encourages people to ignore or rationalize away their deepest intuitive moral feelings, at times” – Careful consideration of goals will point out which moral feelings have utility. Pay attention to those. 3. “How can we accurately predict the consequences of our actions?” – No one has a crystal ball; do the best you can with what you’ve got. 4. “What keeps utilitarians from breaking their word, or from breaking the law, to accomplish their goals?” 5. “Is this really a situation-specific ethical system? Do absolutes get smuggled in somewhere?” - _________ Professor Christopher Ullman 11 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY KANTIAN ABSOLUTISM Kant felt that the consequences were not the important thing. Principles ought to win out. His system has been called a deontological system, because it emphasizes duty, not goals. MEMORY IMAGE: A LIGHTHOUSE Five basic things to know about Kant: 1. Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) – lived all his life in the university town of Konigsberg, Prussia. Began as a rationalist, was awakened from his “dogmatic slumbers” by the radical empiricist David Hume, and then brought about a remarkable fusion of the two. 2. The Categorical Imperative: “Act only on that maxim which you can will to be a universal law.” Universalizability 3. The Humanitarian Principle: Always treat persons as ends in themselves, not merely as a means to some other end. Inherent worth vs. Lifeboat Game values 4. What is absolutely good? A good will Altruism 5. What drives our ideas of right and wrong? Duty, not goals. Four points from Kant on ethics: 1. It’s always wrong to lie 2. You must always treat each person as an end in him/herself. Never treat a person merely as a means to get something else. 3. An action is right when it satisfies the Categorical Imperative 4. Some duties are unavoidable (“perfect duties”). Some duties are optional (“imperfect duties”). Rights are rooted in perfect duties, freedom is rooted in the concept of imperfect duties. Objections and responses 1. Conflicting duties arise. How do you resolve the conflicts, if every duty is based on the Categorical Imperative? 2. There is no logical limit to the number of maxims to be formulated. 3. The Humanitarian Principle depends upon the definition of a person: personhood from conception? From birth? Only upon demonstrating you can function as a person? 4. The Good Will may be wishful thinking. Does anybody have an autonomous selfregulating will? Kant’s responses generally included an appeal to the amazing rational abilities of humankind. “Upon analysis and reflection, the answers to these can be found.” His answers are at times enigmatic, and the objections are still being debated. Professor Christopher Ullman 12 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY EMOTIVISM The Boo-Hurrah Theory Core ideas of emotivism 1. When we say some action or person is morally “good” or “bad”, we are doing nothing more than expressing an emotion about the action or person. 2. Ethical statements are merely emotional responses, in the same class as other interjections such as “Ouch!” and “Ahhhhh!” 3. Making a moral judgment is just venting a feeling. How do the following verses relate to the core ideas of emotivist ethics? Matthew 27:22-23 Psalm 37:12 Ephesians 4:31 What is good about emotions that come with our ethical evaluations and decisions? What triggers emotions? List some causes. Can we control the way we feel about an action, person, or idea? What does it mean to say that all facts are theory-laden? What makes consequences of an action (for example, capital punishment) “good” or “bad?” What do these verses mean in the context of our considerations of emotions and ethics? Isaiah 29:13 - The Lord says: "These people come near to me with their mouth and honor me with their lips, but their hearts are far from me. Proverbs 26:23-24 - Like a coating of glaze over earthenware are fervent lips with an evil heart. A malicious man disguises himself with his lips, but in his heart he harbors deceit. Ephes. 6:6 - Obey them not only to win their favor when their eye is on you, but like slaves of Christ, doing the will of God from your heart. Can you think of other passages that link emotions and ethics in some way? Professor Christopher Ullman 13 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY RIGHT OR WRONG? “IT ALL DEPENDS . . .” OR DOES IT? CULTURAL RELATIVISM 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. Flowing out of anthropological studies comes the idea that people think that what is right is what the culture says is right. It is defended by the anthropologists Ruth Benedict and Graham Sumner, and has been considered in various forms by philosophers Thomas Hobbes, William James, John Dewey and Melville Herskovits. Five things to know about relativism: It teaches that the folkways (the customs, mores, and traditions of each society) are so ingrained in its members that they naturally come to think of them as objectively ‘right’ and ‘good.’ In America, relativism is frequently expressed in platitudes, such as “Nothing is right or wrong in itself.” “Things are right or wrong, depending on the ________________.” (fill in ‘person,’‘culture,’ ‘situation,’ ‘administration,’ etc.) “To each his own.” “Different strokes for different folks.” Relativism is closely tied to post-modernism, which teaches that nothing is objectively “true.” Relativism is similar to secular existentialism, which teaches There is no such thing as a ‘given,’ no such thing as ‘human nature.’ Nothing is prescribed. You are utterly free, and condemned to be free. You create your own meaning in life by your choice of a life project. You are utterly responsible for your own choices. Relativism teaches that there are no absolute values, and that all values are relative to time, place, person and/or situation. Professor Christopher Ullman 14 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Objections 1. By cutting oneself off from absolutes, how does one know what something is relative to? Relativism risks being self-referentially incoherent. In other words, without looking outside of the system, it is nearly or actually impossible to make sense of moral judgments, upon analysis. Relativists may depend upon an intuitive, unspoken consensus that there are some absolutes, but by definition they cannot admit it. 2. Relativism supports actions such as female circumcision, slavery, child labor, etc., which receive a nearly universal response of moral revulsion. (Why do we respond with a shudder and outrage when we hear of rape, or abuse of infants, or bestiality, or necrophilia, or terrorism?) 3. No relativist can tell you that relativism is the best of all ethical systems. 4. Cultural relativists must grant legitimacy to any system of values: Hitler’s values are no better than Jesus’s values. “It just depends on what society you come from.” 5. The practicality of living itself requires us to qualify relativism and state some guidelines or limits within which we all must behave if we are to survive as a race. Where do these limits come from? Three Kinds of Relativism (but only two of them tell us what to do) Kind of relativism “SOCIETY DOES” Core belief Each society has morals that are different from other societies Implication Attribute There can’t be any Descriptive only absolutes, and there can’t be any objective moral standards There aren’t any absolutes You should do what your Descriptive and “SOCIETY SAYS” or objective moral society says is right, and Prescriptive (Cultural Moral standards that will be the right thing Relativism) to do There is nothing more I should do what I Descriptive and “I SAY” authoritative than each privately believe to be Prescriptive (Subjective Moral person’s private opinions right. You should do what Relativism) you privately believe to be right. It’s relatively easy to conclude that one kind of relativism inevitably leads to another, and then to another. Professor Christopher Ullman 15 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY FIVE REASONS WHY CULTURAL DIVERSITY DOES NOT WARRANT MORAL RELATIVISM4 There are many different cultures. This fact is called the diversity thesis. Moral relativists teach that the diversity thesis is proof that there should be many different moralities, each one dependent on the culture in which one finds oneself. This belief is called the dependency thesis. Moral relativists teach that what is right for one society, group or individual may be wrong for another society, group or individual, even if the two parties are similarly situated. If this is to be accepted as correct, moral relativists must be able to show that the same act could be both right for one society, group or individual and at the same time wrong for another society, group or individual. 1. Frequently, the act that is condoned by one is not the same act that is condemned by the other. This means the moral relativists’ requirement has not been met, in these cases. 2. Even when the same act is being compared, for that act to be right for a society, group or individual to do, it must be possible for that party to be able to discern the act as right. However, frequently it is the case that the party could not have arrived at the same judgments that we think are morally right. This means the moral relativists’ requirement has not been met, in these additional cases. 3. Moral relativists frequently fail to indicate what a moral judgment is supposed to be relative to. For cultural relativism, a group that is the continuing point of reference must be specified. However, very frequently this information is not offered by moral relativists. This means the dependency thesis is undecipherable, when the reference group has not been identified. 4. Even when a reference group has been specified, the means of determining the moral judgments of the group, which are then to be related to specific acts in question, are highly problematic. Voting, polling, and other means of arriving at a consensus on a value or an act require the individuals to make judgments without the help of the group as a whole. After all, at some point prior to the vote or poll the group theoretically has no opinion. By what means is that first consensus reached? Apparently by some sort of non-relativist means. If so, moral relativists have failed in making their case. 5. Moral relativists claim to be stating a truth about morality that is true for all times and places. In other words, its truth is not relative to being a member of any particular society or group, nor is it relative to living in a certain time or place. But if truth is not relativistic, why should morality be relativistic? Moral relativists fail to provide an adequate answer to this question. In so doing, they demonstrate their belief to be self-referentially incoherent. A summary of James Sterba’s Contemporary Social and Political Philosophy (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1995), pp. 97-99. 4 Professor Christopher Ullman 16 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY The Blind Men and the Elephant by John Godfrey Saxe5 It was six men of Indostan To learning much inclined, Who went to see the Elephant (Though all of them were blind), That each by observation Might satisfy his mind The Sixth no sooner had begun About the beast to grope, Than, seizing on the swinging tail That fell within his scope, “I see,” quoth he, “the Elephant Is very like a rope!” And so these men of Indostan Disputed loud and long, Each in his own opinion Exceeding stiff and strong, Though each was partly in the right, And all were in the wrong! The First approached the Elephant, And happening to fall Against his broad and sturdy side, At once began to bawl: “God bless me! but the Elephant Is very like a wall!” Moral: So oft in theologic wars, The disputants, I ween, Rail on in utter ignorance Of what each other mean, And prate about an Elephant Not one of them has seen! The Second, feeling of the tusk, Cried, “Ho! what have we here So very round and smooth and sharp? To me ’tis mighty clear This wonder of an Elephant Is very like a spear!” The Third approached the animal, And happening to take The squirming trunk within his hands, Thus boldly up and spake: “I see,” quoth he, “the Elephant Is very like a snake!” The Fourth reached out an eager hand, And felt about the knee. “What most this wondrous beast is like Is mighty plain,” quoth he; “ ‘Tis clear enough the Elephant Is very like a tree!” The Fifth, who chanced to touch the ear, Said: “Even the blindest man Can tell what this resembles most; Deny the fact who can This marvel of an Elephant Is very like a fan!” Question #1 for Mr. Saxe: Who does see the elephant as it really is? Question #2: What gives him this privileged perspective? And now a question for the student of ethics: What does this poem have to do with moral relativism? 5 American poet John Godfrey Saxe (1816-1887) based the following poem on a fable which was told in India many years ago. Professor Christopher Ullman 17 ETHICS RELATIVISM’S SEVEN FATAL FLAWS 1. Relativists can’t accuse others of wrongdoing. 2. Relativists can’t complain about the “Problem of Evil.” 3. Relativists can’t place blame or accept praise. 4. Relativists can’t make charges of unfairness or injustice. 5. Relativists can’t improve their morality. 6. Relativists can’t hold meaningful moral discussions. 7. Relativists can’t promote the obligation of tolerance. Beckwith, Francis J. and Gregory Koukl, Relativism: Feet Firmly Planted in Mid-Air (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Books, 1998), p. 61-69. Christopher Ullman, Instructor 18 ETHICS Virtue Ethics Until now we have been looking at action-based ethics: what a person ought to do. Virtue ethics is a different stream of thought entirely, for it focuses on how a person ought to be. Contrasts ACTION-BASED What to do Derivative Conduct Rules Outwardly manifested Overt behaviors Temporary VIRTUE-BASED How to be Fundamental Character Traits Inwardly developed Inner states Enduring Some famous lists of virtues: BUDDHA PLATO Enlightenment Courage Right views Temperance Right intention Wisdom Right speech Justice Right conduct Right occupation Right willpower Right awareness Right concentration ARISTOTLE Courage Temperance Liberality Magnificence Pride Friendliness Justice PAUL Faith Hope Love (Agape’) Joy Peace Patience Kindness Goodness Faithfulness BOY SCOUTS Trustworthy Loyal Helpful Friendly Courteous Kind Obedient Cheerful Thrifty Brave Clean Reverent SOCRATES (PLATO) ON VIRTUE Socrates taught that there are some things more important than life itself, such as being true to your principles. TO THINE OWN SELF BE TRUE, and THE UNEXAMINED LIFE IS NOT WORTH LIVING. For Socrates, the GOOD LIFE is not a pleasant life in which we seek gratification for the sake of having a good time. The GOOD LIFE is strenuous, but gratifying in its own way because one knows that one seeks and sees the Truth, and one is in control of oneself. THE ROLE OF REASON, IN THE GREEK IDEA OF THE GOOD LIFE We can’t hope to attain virtue without the use of our reason. A person who does something unjust to others is either ignorant or sick. If he knew better, he wouldn’t have done it. His problem is that his appetites (the needs and wants of humans) rule him, and they must be controlled to achieve a good life. A person ruled by his appetites does not have a good life. Christopher Ullman, Instructor 19 ETHICS IN HUMANS THERE ARE THREE POWERS AT WORK REASON Reason and spirit SPIRIT APPETITES will keep the body healthy and the soul balanced. Reason is the name of the charioteer. Spirit (willpower, ambition) is the name of the well-behaved horse. Appetites is the name of the wild, unruly horse. The charioteer must make both horses work together; he can’t just untie the wild horse and let it go. His strategy is to make the well-behaved horse control the wild, unruly horse and subdue it. When REASON rules, the person is WISE (virtue of the intellect). When SPIRIT controls the APPETITES, that person is also BRAVE (virtue of the spirit). When the APPETITES are completely controlled, that person is TEMPERATE (virtue of the appetites). Such a person is well balanced and would not dream of being unjust to anybody. Therefore, JUSTICE is the virtue that describes the WELL-BALANCED PERSON (virtue of the harmony of reason, spirit and the appetites). Virtue takes on meaning when we consider the non-virtues or anti-virtues (known as vices). Paul mentions his list of virtues (he calls them fruits of the Spirit) after listing a variety of vices (he calls them works of the flesh): sexual immorality, impurity, idolatry, witchcraft, hatred, selfish ambition, fits of rage, envy, drunkenness, orgies. Aristotle draws attention to the middle traits or virtues (he called them means) by describing the excesses and deficiencies. ARISTOTLE ON VIRTUE The virtues are the ways we attain the highest goal of humanity: HAPPINESS. Why happiness? Why not honor, or pleasure, or intelligence, or good health, or wealth, or power? Because each one of the latter are things which we strive to attain partly for themselves, and partly because they make us happy. But happiness is never sought to make us honorable, or intelligent, or healthy. So it alone is the final end. This happiness is not something that you can attain in a moment or in an afternoon or over the summer vacation. It takes a lifetime. Happiness is more than an emotional state: it is a state of complete being, balance and harmony. Christopher Ullman, Instructor 20 ETHICS It is a state of character or soul. Aristotle’s three practical rules for good conduct: 1. Keep away from that extreme which is more contrary to the mean. 2. Know your own weaknesses. 3. Guard yourselves especially against pleasure and pleasant things, because we are not impartial judges of pleasure. A fourth rule to remember: the mean is not merely the halfway point between extremes of excess and deficiency. It is the optimal way to be. BERNARD MAYO ON MORAL CHARACTER VS MORAL PRINCIPLES Aristotle will not tell you what to do, but he will tell you what to be. If I am ruled by an ethical system of moral principles, my decision making will have to go like this: 1. What kind of situation is this? 2. What kinds of rules govern actions in a situation like this? 3. If there is no rule, I will have to discover a new rule which will work in situations like this in the future. If I am ruled by an ethical system of moral character, my decision making will look like this: 1. What ought I to be, in this situation? So there is a simplicity to character morality that cannot be found in principle morality. Character can not be summed up by a list of dispositions or rules. It has an organic unity that is greater than the sum of its parts. In times of perplexity, we can ask not only “What shall I be?” but also “Who shall I be like?” Plato’s answer: the ‘just man’ Aristotle’s answer: the man of practical wisdom Augustine’s answer: the citizen of the City of God Marx’s or Lenin’s or Mao’s answer: the good Communist John Wayne’s answer: the gunslinging, strong, quiet cowboy Sometimes a particular role model is held up to be imitated: Socrates, Buddha, Christ, St. Francis, Mohammed, Mike. The Hero and the Saint are very much the expression of this approach to moral decision making. Heroes and saints are not merely people who did things; they are people to be imitated in the way they were. We should not only act as they acted, in specific situations; we should be like they were. Their lives became examples for us to follow. Kant predictably said that this idea of emulation was fatal to morality. The exemplar is useful only to render visible an instance of the moral principle. Should we say that principles are less important than personalities? No, since we identify role models by the principles they follow. Yet, the person is not nothing, when you are struggling to decide how to be moral. The morality of character gives room for ideals, and more importantly, it appeals not only to the reason but also to the psyche. Heroes and saints embolden us by their example in ways that mere principles cannot. They can win our hearts and our heads. ALISDAIR MACINTYRE ON VIRTUE I best understand my life when I see it as a story, with episodes in which I acted out a certain role. I am the subject of a narrative that runs from birth to death. My life furthermore is a part of the story of your life and your life and your life and your life, and in each I have a certain role. I can only answer the question, “What am I to do?” if I have already answered the question, “Of what story or stories do I find myself a part?” We learn what a child or a parent is through the stories we are told, as we are developing as moral agents. Deprive children of stories, and your leave them unscripted, “anxious stutterers in their actions as in their words.” Mythology is essential for teaching virtues. Since each one of us is the star character of the narrative which is our individual life, we are accountable for what we do, if our life is to be narratable. The story of your life is supposed to make sense, but if you can’t give any reasons for the way you acted in a situation, it doesn’t make any sense. Since I am also a character in the narrative of someone else’s life, I can ask them to give account of their actions as well. Asking what you did and why, saying what I did and why, are the essential elements in all narratives. Without this, the narrative becomes unintelligible. In what does the unity of an individual life consist? The unity of a narrative in a single life. What is the good for me? It is the best way to live out the story and bring it to completion. Christopher Ullman, Instructor 21 ETHICS What is the good for humanity? It is what all answers to the former question have in common. This commonality has different names. In Aristotle’s thought: happiness. In Plato’s thought: justice. In the Apostle Paul’s thought: Christlikeness. In Buddha’s thought: enlightenment. In Marx’s thought: communist utopia. In Hollywood’s John Wayne mythos: the American dream. HOW IS IT THAT PEOPLE THINK THEY SEE THINGS AS THEY REALLY ARE WHEN THEY ONLY SEE A SHADOW OF REALITY? This was and is the philosopher’s burden, and the first to bear it was Plato, in “The Allegory of the Cave.” He taught that people are prisoners of an artificial idea that the physical world is all that there is. Isn’t it obvious, though, that everything in the physical realm is but a poor copy of its perfect form? Cat, chair, color, and character traits: these conjure up images, ideas, which serve as templates for what we actually sense. We compare what we see to those images, those ideals, those concepts of catness, chairness, redness, treeness, beauty, truth, justice, and judge how close to the ideal the physical approaches. We never will see a perfect copy, with our senses. Yet we can reflect and discover the perfect Form, or prototype, upon which all copies are based. There is a realm of the Forms, but it is not a physical place. It is an intellectual and psychic state, to which we are liberated at death, according to Socrates and Plato. While we stay in the flesh, we struggle with the imperfect copies, believing they are all that there is, yet knowing that perfection is yet to be attained, in every area. Yet there are some who by Reason comprehend the Forms. By training the mind, they break the chains of merely empirical observation and ascend out of the cave and its darkness into the pure light of the Form of the Good. As they grow accustomed to the real light radiated by the Good, they see things as they really are. Equipped with this vision, they gain control of their minds, spirits and appetites. By Reason their lives are transformed, and they learn to embrace the ideals and to esteem them most highly above the physical, which is illusory and shadowy. The Forms of Wisdom, Courage, Temperance, Justice, Beauty, Truth and ultimately the Good are the real meaning of life. These virtues are changeless and eternal, worth basing one’s life upon, and if need be, worth dying for. Once beheld, Plato believed, they will never be turned away from, and will continue to bring one’s life into conformity with them. The reflective mind, exhilarated by the perfection of the Forms, will never again be satisfied merely with the changeableness of the physical realm. The Forms provide landmarks which never move by which one might plot one’s course from birth to death, and a life well lived from cradle to grave, a GOOD LIFE, will result in being reborn, not in the physical realm, but in the realm of the Forms. Was Plato a religious man? Certainly. He worshipped as all Athenians did the gods of the Greek Pantheon. But obviously the real object of his devotion was the perfection of the ideal realm of the Forms, and the means by which humans can ascend out of the cave-like existence to behold the Form of the Good: REASON. DOES THIS IDEA OF IDEALS FIND EXPRESSION IN OTHER THOUGHT-SYSTEMS? HINDUS seek the perfection of awareness of the ONENESS OF ALL THINGS IN BRAHMAN. BUDDHISTS seek the end of craving and absorption into the perfect realm of NIRVANA. TAOISTS seek to enter that stream of harmony with the world in which all is recognized as being as it should be: the TAO. The great MONOTHEIST RELIGIONS seek communion and fellowship with the ONE GOD, who is perfect and unchanging, whose character embodies in one Person the purest expression of the Virtues. Even New Age religions and Earth-worshippers recognize and aspire for a perfection which transcends mere physical existence. Christopher Ullman, Instructor 22 ETHICS Are they all alike in every way? Not hardly. Are they all correct? Not hardly. The specifics of each system contain truth claims which contradict the truth claims of other systems. A non-A. Is there a great similarity they seem to share with one another? Yes. It appears to be, in one form or another, the belief in the existence of an IDEAL. A LIFE OF VIRTUE is a life well lived, the ancients all affirm: A GOOD LIFE. For PLATO, the saying “It takes a village” would be restated as “It takes a POLIS.” A Polis ruled by philosophers, in which each person had discovered and accepted his/her proper role in the society, and worked together with other citizens to attain virtue and a realization of the Form of the Good. For AUGUSTINE, a 4th century African bishop who lived in the final days of the Roman Empire, it required a MIRACULOUS REBIRTH BY THE POWER OF GOD, to become a citizen of the City of God, and to work by faith and the grace of God to bring about the kingship of God in each person’s life. For MAHAVIRA, founder of the Jainist religion, it involved a RENUNCIATION OF THE FLESH in every conceivable way, and a life of severe devotion and fasting in order to enter into that perfect realm. For CONFUCIUS, it called for a life of careful training in the PROPER WAYS OF CONDUCT AND SOCIAL LIVING, to become a superior human being whose life reflected the stability and order of the universe. TO LIVE A LIFE OF VIRTUE, THE GOOD LIFE, REQUIRES MOST OR ALL OF THE FOLLOWING: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Early discipline and a well-ordered social environment Instruction Parental modeling of virtue Peers who serve as role models of virtue Awareness of a society’s heroes and heroines and saints Continued reflection Repeated choices of virtue over vice In many systems, an awareness of the need for help from a higher power Christopher Ullman, Instructor 23