Brandom 9/2/09 Sellars Intro Plan On the 20 anniversary of his death in 1989 th 1. Claim: Wilfrid Sellars is the greatest American philosopher of the 20th century. Put this way, Brits are out of contention (Russell etc.), as are Germans and Austrians (Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Carnap). Competitors might be: a) Dewey b) Quine c) Davidson d) Kripke e) David Lewis f) Rawls 2. Q: Why? A: a) He was essentially alone in his generation (and among the contestants above) in his deep knowledge of and the importance he attached to the history of philosophy. The worldspirit is moving his way. b) He was essentially alone in his generation (and among the contestants above) in his systematic ambitions (“the synoptic vision”). Davidson and Lewis ended up being systematic philosophers, but it was a surprise to them that things evolved that way. (The same could be said of Searle, and maybe Quine.) Again, there is at least hope that Sellars was ahead of his time in this respect. c) His aim was, he said, “to move analytic philosophy from its Humean into its Kantian phase.” This is a move beyond empiricism and naturalism (as it were, from logical empiricism to logical kantianism). Rawls, too, with Strawson, contributed greatly to the reappropriation of Kant by the analytic tradition. It is easy to forget that Kant was anathema to the founders of the analytic movement. To Russell and Moore, not to mention later folks like Ayer and Quine, he was where the idealist rot set in. (Kripke is an interesting exception—but he’s never written about Kant, and it’s a good question what he understands of him.) They saw, I think correctly, that one could not open the door wide enough to let Kant in, and shut it quickly enough to keep Hegel out. Sellars is officially, and in fact, on the Kant side of the Kant/Hegel divide, but has serious Hegelian sympathies. Rorty describes me as aiming to move analytic philosophy from its incipient Kantian to its inevitable Hegelian phase. d) It is above all Sellars’s appreciation of Kant’s lesson about the essentially normative character of intentionality—of mind, meaning, and rationality—that sets him apart from his (20th century) cohort. [Tell my Kant story in brief, from first Woodbridge lecture (in RiP).] Wittgenstein, too, appreciated this point, as Sellars acknowledges. The transition to a “Kantian phase of analytic philosophy” is the replacement of a cartesian framework with a 1 Document1 Brandom kantian one, from certainty to necessity, from mind/body problem to prescription/description or norm/fact problem 3. Aim of the course: to try to see how Sellars views, in the largest sense of the term, hang together, in the largest sense of the term. 4. I want to address this issue by putting trying to characterize Sellars’s views in the context of an understanding of the classical project of analytic philosophy, and of its principal core programs (from BSD): a) Classical project of analytic philosophy: to understand the meanings expressed by potentially problematic target vocabularies in terms of presumptively unproblematic base vocabularies. The desired relations between them have been variously construed: analysis, definition, translation, paraphrase, reduction of various kinds, supervenience, truth-making…to name just a few. b) Core programs: i) Empiricism ii) Naturalism iii) Functionalism (a late comer). c) So the large shape of the question is: what is Sellars’s attitude towards these core programs? What distinctive transformation of our understanding of them does he aim at and accomplish? 5. Picture 1: Here is a story about the large structure of Sellars’s views. He was pulled in two directions: a) Against empiricism. Slogan (space of reasons passage): “In characterizing an episode or state as that of knowing, we are not giving an empirical description of that episode or state; we are placing it in the logical space of reasons, of justifying and being able to justify what one says,” [EPM 36]. b) For naturalism. Slogan (scientia mensura): “In the dimension of describing and explaining, science is the measure of all things: of those that are, that they are, and of those that are not, that they are not.” So: Allying himself with the Neurath, rather than the Schlick wing of the Vienna Circle. c) He is also the one who introduces functionalism (though hardly anyone notices): in semantics, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, and ontology (his treatment of universals). 6. The question is, how these views “hang together.” a) Besides the notion of the Myth of the Given, Sellars is perhaps best known for his distinction, in “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man,” between the scientific image, and the manifest image, with his claim that it is the principal, defining job of 2 Document1 Brandom philosophy (at least modern philosophy) to explain the relations between them. [Explain in general terms the distinction.] There are two worries about how things stand with his own approach: b) First, there is the worry that he ends up replacing one dualism (the cartesian dualism of mind and body) with another (the kantian dualism of fact and norm). As I use the term, a distinction becomes a dualism when it is drawn in such a way as to make the relations between the distinguished items unintelligible. What is, in the end, his account of the relation between the norms that articulate the manifest image and the regularities or laws that articulate the scientific image? c) Alternatively, there is the worry that his “scientific realism,” epitomized in the scientia mensura, ends up committing him to a reductive naturalism, according to which the manifest image is ultimately mistaken, and must eventually be replaced by successor concepts within the scientific image. This is the lesson his student Paul Churchland explicitly draws. This suspicion is reinforced by Sellars’s (relatively late) obsession with “sensa”, that is, with the issue of what the successor in a “Peircean” scientific framework of sensations conceived of as of continuous colors: the infamous pink icecube. He endorses some truly astonishing conclusions in this vicinity. Again, his discussion of “picturing” (in “Naming and Saying,” and in Chapter 4 of Science and Metaphysics, “Truth and Picturing”) and in general his account of how matter-of-factual regularities track norms raises the worry that he thinks that it is concepts of these that will be the successor concepts of the normative concepts of the manifest image, in a “Peircean” eventual scientific image. His student Ruth Millikan draws the inspiration for her naturalistic program in semantics (see her Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories) from Sellars’s “Some Reflections on Language Games.” On this reading, Sellars’s scientific realism drives him to a reductive naturalism that puts him in the same box with Quine or Fodor. 7. The result of these worries has been a sociological division among Sellars’s admirers: a) “Right-wing” Sellarsians (Rorty’s terminology), such as Rosenberg, Churchland, and Millikan see his scientific realism, epitomized in the scientia mensura and PSIM (where he talks about the “primacy of the scientific image,” as the axial commitment, and privilege his naturalism over his rejection of empiricism. b) “Left-wing” Sellarsians, such as Rorty, Brandom, Williams, and McDowell, see his normative Kantian insight, epitomized in the “space of reasons” passage in EPM, as the core insight. We see the scientific realism as a throwback—a “pre-Sellarsian remnant” as I called it, to Sellars’s irritation—to commitments Sellars inherited from his father Roy Wood Sellars, without ever realizing that the semantic and epistemological insights of EPM were incompatible with them. c) Our hope, of course, is that the disagreements between right- and left-wing Sellarsians can be worked out more amicably than those between right- and left-wing 3 Document1 Brandom Hegelians, which were settled only after an intensive years-long seminar called the battle of Stalingrad. 8. Picture 2: Besides his appreciating and adapting Kant’s insight into the normative character of concepts and concept-use, he also takes from Kant a transcendental perspective, transposing it into a (meta-)linguistic key. Here the key point they share is a realization that there are essential features of the framework that makes empirical description and explanation possible that are expressed in kinds of vocabulary whose principal office is not empirical description or explanation. Their role is rather, in a broad (and confusingly elastic) sense, metalinguistic. (Cf. Kant on categories, pure concepts, paradigmatically modal ones.) Sellars talks about the “tendency to assimilate all discourse to describing” as principally “responsible for the prevalence in the empiricist tradition of 'nothing-but-ism' in its various forms (emotivism, philosophical behaviorism, phenomenalism)” [CDCM §103] 9. On this picture, at the core of Sellars’s thought, in addition to the normative insight that informs his distinction of the two images, is i) his nonrelational, functionalist semantics, and ii) his view that every vocabulary of philosophical interest—modal, normative, semantic, intentional, logical, and ontological—is to be understood in terms of its functionalist, metalinguistic expressive role. a) Sellars is an empirical naturalist (the scientia mensura), but a transcendental nonnaturalist (cf. Kant's empirical realism and transcendental idealism). His empirical naturalism is what he (and following him, others such as Rosenberg) call his “scientific realism”. b) His transcendental non-naturalism is a matter of his appreciation of the normative character of semantics (and so epistemology) and intentionality. c) That normative character is what, in turn, underwrites the distinction between the two “images”. The scientific image is non-normative; the manifest image comes with the norms in. d) This bifurcation provides the twist that he puts on the analytic core programs of both naturalism and empiricism. e) As pointed out in (6) above, there is a danger at this point of replacing a cartesian dualism with a kantian one: the dualism of mind and body with that of norm and empirical descriptive fact. To be entitled to the distinction without its becoming a dualism, he has to have an intelligible story about the relation between the 'images'. f) This is the point at which Sellars's other master idea is wheeled in. This is the idea that normativity, modality, semantics, intentionality, logic, and universals and abstract entities [which Sellars puts in a box, though it is not clear that they should be assimilated]— basically all the phenomena that philosophers have traditionally been concerned to address—are fundamentally metalinguistic phenomena, whose surface grammar invites 4 Document1 Brandom g) h) i) j) k) l) m) n) o) us to assimilate them to the bits of discourse that describe and explain empirical descriptive facts. His idea is that rather than describing or explaining, what these transcendental discourses do is functionally classify discursive (linguistic-conceptual) expressions and their use. This is his way of working out the Kantian insight (cf. (1) above) that some bits of discourse do not describe or explain empirical matters of fact, but rather express (make explicit) essential features of the discursive framework that makes describing and explaining possible. “Transcendental grammar” (I think “semantics” might be a better term) is the discipline that studies those essentially metalinguistic tropes. It is WS's version of philosophy. This is his specific metaphilosophy: philosophy as doing transcendental grammar, examing the use of expressions that play the metalinguistic expressive role of making explicit essential features of the framework of describing and explaining (cf the scientia mensura) that are not themselves descriptive or explanatory. So for Sellars (cf. (a)), there are at root only two things one can do, cognitively: science, and philosophy. That is, empirically describing and explaining natural, non-normative phenomena, on the one hand, and examining the functioning of bits of discourse that make explicit essential elements of the discursive framework within which describing and explaining are possible in the first place. The dualism that threatens (cf. (e)) is thus manifested also in the danger of a science/philosophy dualism. Sellars's response to that threat is not the Quinean naturalistic one that assimilates philosophy to science. One move is to expand the notion of philosophy to a second level: it comprises not only transcendental grammar, but also the relation between transcendental grammar and the empirical scientific enterprise of describing and explaining. (Cf the “fusion of the images”.) His theory of the metalinguistic—an elastic, catch-all category—sees it as generically a matter of functional classification. And that fact provides the next twist: functional classification is itself a normative concept. In functionally classifying linguistic expressions, one is not describing or explaining how things empirically are. One is doing something else. Among the expressions whose use one can systematically functionally classify are those whose office or functional role is describing and explaining. In this sense, philosophy is the more capacious enterprise, and science the less capacious. Thinking normatively about what subjects do is the necessary framework for thinking about the objects they (we) describe and explain. In this sense, Sellars belongs in a box with the later Wittgenstein and the early Heidegger, and is a conceptual idealist in the sense I have given to that term in thinking about Hegel's idealism. This is what distinguishes his way of thinking about the science/philosophy distinction (and keeping it from being a dualism) from Quine's naturalistic reductionism. (Cf (k).) 5 Document1 Brandom p) This fact about the overall shape of Sellars's view has been masked by his “scientific realist” (cf (a) and (o): Sellars's scientific realism is compatible with conceptual idealism, with transcendental non-naturalism) approach to sensa. This is his engagement with a version of what Chalmers calls “the hard problem” of (sensuous) consciousness: the “location problem” (Jackson) with respect to phenomenological properties of sensory consciousness, what red things look like to us. Here it looks as though Sellars is being a naturalist in Quine's sense: what is real (but: in the narrow sense) is what empirical natural science can tell us (all) about. If sensory consciousness is real (in the narrow sense), then it must have an ultimately empirical natural-scientific successor concept (cf. Sellars's concern with conceptual change and progressive development). But, I claim, the key thing to realize here is that this is an issue of sentience, not of sapience. Sensa are in the causal order, postulated as things that trigger sapient responses, namely perceptual judgments. They are not the sapient responses themselves. Sellars is not a “scientific realist” (naturalist) about the use of normative or (therefore) 'metalinguistic' expressions. He does not envisage the absorption of the manifest in to the scientific image, nor its replacement by the scientific image. That is not the context in which he speculates about the scientific successor concepts of sensa. q) The other piece of Sellars that invites the reductive Quinean reading of his “scientific realism” [perhaps I should also mention, to begin with, misreading the scientia mensura passage by ignoring its protasis] is his story about picturing: about how norms can be reflected by regularities that track them, and so form a non-normatively characterizable 'shadow' of them within the realm of the narrowly natural. My ultimate view about this is that it belongs in a box with account of sensa. Picturing is not meant as a reductive account of what norms are or why they matter, not part of a scientific account of them. It is a supplement, to indicate that science need not have nothing to say about us, just because it cannot encompass the normative dimension of our lives. Picturing is to norms as sign-designs are to linguistic-expressions-in-use. 10. Sellars’s claim is that all philosophically interesting vocabularies are metalinguistic in character. All are part of what he sometimes calls “transcendental grammar.” Semantic, intentional, modal, normative, logical, universal-abstract, even terms like ‘time’ come in for such treatment. This claim is never made explicitly with this generality. Rather, for each vocabulary he considers, this is the form of his analysis. All of them turn out to express essential features of the framework of describing and explaining that are not themselves in the business of describing or explaining in the narrow sense. 11. Two large questions about the nature of this claim (before we start to worry about its truth, and its justification—what reasons there might be to think it is true) are these: a) What does he mean by ‘metalinguistic’ in this claim? The notion of transcendental grammar will be important to consider in this connection. This is not only a very 6 Document1 Brandom capacious notion, it is elastic, and clearly encompasses a considerable variety of substantially different offices or expressive roles. Hope: meaning-use analysis can be of help here. b) What can we say about the “wider” sense in which expressions performing these framework-expressing (explicitating), transcendental, “metalinguistic” roles can be considered as descriptive-explanatory? This question picks up the aspects of GibbardBlackburn post-Geach expressivism (which allows for a descriptive dimension to bits of discourse whose primary meaningfulness is to be understood in expressive terms) and the generalization of it that Huw Price is promoting. This issue becomes particularly acute when we look at modally rich statements of natural law, which we can only come to justify empirically, and with moral principles. But versions of it arise for all of the vocabularies that fall within the scope of the claim in (1)—Sellars’s metalinguistic master idea. 12. In keeping with the though expressed at the end of (2a), one of my projects as we go through these texts will be assess the extent to which a MUA (with accompanying MUD) can be offered of each vocabulary Sellars addresses, and to what extent the metatheoretic apparatus of BSD would need to be altered to accommodate his claims. 13. Summary: a) Sellars’s Big Idea I: Normativity of Semantics and Intentionality. This insight shapes and transforms his versions of empiricism and naturalism. b) Sellars’s Big Idea II: Empirical-Naturalistic framework of describing and explaining (cf. scientia mensura) involves many linguistic expressions that articulate features of the framework, rather than themselves describing or explaining (in the narrow sense). (Kant) Much of our discourse is actually metalinguistic. (Carnap) This includes: Semantic and (therefore) intentional discourse, (some) logical discourse, normative discourse, modal discourse, talk of universals and abstract entities, (with some waffling) talk about time… But Sellars has a protean, plastic, elastic notion of the metalinguistic, which he never properly clarifies. c) Sellars’s Big Idea III: Metalinguistic functional classification, rather than relational semantics. Inferentialism as a way of working that out. d) Sellars’s Big Idea IV (not explicit): Look at pragmatic dependences between the use of various kinds of expression, in order to underwrite claims about conceptual dependences between the meanings that they express. Paradigm: account of ‘looks’-talk. e) Sellars’s Big Idea V (not explicit): conceptual change as key to functionalist semantics and epistemology. For it provides the answer to the key question for one (like Kant himself) who makes the Kantian transcendental move—above all with respect to modality. That is: lawfulness in general might be a necessary feature of all empirical descriptive-explanatory frameworks, but the particular laws seem to be in a generic sense 7 Document1 Brandom contingent, and also a posteriori. We need to discover the laws of nature empirically, and at least the low-level ones could in some intelligible sense, have been different. That suggests that in a broad sense, they are empirical-descriptive. What can one say about how these features can be combined? Sellars’s approach to a response is in terms of an account of what happens when we change concepts. 14. Among important things that we are not going to be reading: a) Pure Pragmatics and Possible Worlds b) EPM c) Science and Metaphysics d) Two Kant essays e) Naturalism and Ontology f) “Time and the World Order” g) Linley lectures (Kansas) h) Carus lectures 15. Resources linked from website: a) Notre Dame lectures b) “Counterfactuals, Dispositions, and the Causal Modalities” (the only principal reading that is not in In the Space of Reasons) c) Chrucky central Sellars website, with bibliography d) Sellars archive at Pitt e) Recommendations for books, including recent monographs, on Sellars. f) Syllabus 16. Close by describing the tragic arc of Sellars’s career (and some of the contingent reasons why he couldn’t recover, after about 1965), as I have come to conceive and understand it. 8 Document1