SARTRE ON THE “PLEDGE” When freedom becomes common praxis and grounds the permanence of the group by producing its own inertia through itself and in mediated reciprocity, this new statute is called the pledge…. It goes without saying that pledges can take very different forms, from the explicit act of swearing an oath…to the implicit assumption of a pledge as the already existing reality of the group (for example, by those who are born into the group and who grow up among its members). In other words, the historical act of making a pledge in common, though it is universal and always corresponds to a surviving group's resistance to the divisive tendency of (spatio-temporal) distance and differentiation, is not the only possible form of the common pledge, in so far as the pledge is a guarantee against the future, inertia produced in immanence and by freedom, and the foundation of all differentiation. If we examine it in its explicit reality as a historical act…this is only because this posits itself as such and shows its structures more clearly. A pledge is mediated reciprocity. All its derivative forms for example a witness's oath in law, an individual swearing on the Bible, etc. - derive their meaning from this basic form of pledge. But we must be careful not to confuse this with a social contract. We are not trying to describe the basis of particular societies - which, as we shall see, would be absurd; we are trying to explain the necessary transition from an immediate form of group which is in danger of dissolution to another form, which is reflexive but permanent. A pledge is a practical device. It cannot be presented as a possibility for the individual, unless it is assumed that the possibility is social and that it appears only on the basis of groups which are already bound by a pledge. As we have seen, the abstract experience of the practical organism, in so far as its praxis is a constituent dialectic, can give us only the translucidity of an action which is defined by its objective and which exhausts itself in its objectification. But, in so far as it is the group itself as praxis, this invention is the negation of some exterior circumstance which defines it negatively…. In other words, it is the affirmation by the third party of the permanence of the group as the negation of its exterior negation. And exterior negation must not be confused with the danger of extermination by the enemy (or by a cataclysm); it only involves the possibility that certain tasks involve the re-emergence of the multiplicity of alterity or of exteriority, and this re-emergence does not directly imply the annihilation of the individuals as such. In this sense, the pledge is an inert determination of the future: that is to say, this inertia is above all a negation of dialectic inside the dialectic. Regardless of subsequent developments of praxis, of the event, or of the developing totalisation (up to and including the level of historical totalisation), one element will remain non-dialectical: every member's common membership of the group. The group will enter into new dialectical combinations which will transform it as such, but this will not affect its common unity, that is to say, its interior statute as a group. The act of swearing an oath therefore consists in freely presenting the dispersal of the group in the future as an inert possibility (as a permanent negation of certain possibilities within the field of possibilities) and, conversely, in bringing the future group to the present community as the limit to all possible transcendence. Here again we encounter the dialectical law which we met at the beginning of this investigation: the re-exteriorisation of inorganic inertia is the basis of instrumentality, that is, of the struggle against the inertia of matter within the practical field. The group tries to make itself its own tool against the seriality which threatens to dissolve it; it creates a factitious inertia to protect it against the threats of the practico-inert. The device itself, that is to say, behaviour as immediate praxis, appears in the schema of intelligibility elucidated earlier. There is mediated reciprocity; whether or not it is spoken, the order: 'swear' certainly represents the invention as the regulatory action of the third party in the existing group. But it should be observed that in the milieu of the same, the third party fears dispersive dissolution in the other third party as much as in himself: the possibility of his being isolated may come to him from the third party, but only to the extent that it can come to the third party from him, or even, to the extent that it can come to him through himself. This negative possibility is therefore in everyone and here the same, and the reverse of the praxis of the fused group as ubiquity. And it is the possibility in everyone of becoming other through the other third party, and for him, through himself and for himself. Thus, in the order: 'Let us swear', he claims an objective guarantee from the other third party that he will never become Other: whoever gives me this guarantee thereby protects me, as far as he is concerned, from the danger that Being-Other may come to me from the Other. But equally, if he were to swear alone (or if everyone swore except me), then I alone would thereby take responsibility for bringing alterity to the group. But in fact the act of making a pledge cannot be anything but common: the order is 'Let us swear'. This means that I also make myself, both in and for him, a guarantee that alterity cannot come to him through me (either directly, as would happen if I were to abandon him in the middle of a joint action on behalf of the group, or through the mediation of all, as would happen if, within the majority, I abandoned the struggle with them and fled or surrendered). This reciprocity is mediated: I give my pledge to all the third parties, as forming the group of which I am a member, and it is the group which enables everyone to guarantee the statute of permanence to everyone. A given third party can pledge the permanence of the group against alterity only in so far as this permanence depends on him, that is to say, in so far as the other third parties have assured him, on their account, of future unchangingness. For how could he guarantee that he will never be the Other, if he does not begin with the assurance that alterity will not come to him from outside and in spite of him (or unknown to him)? Indeed, it is characteristic of alterity to come to everyone through the Other. Thus my pledge to the third party receives at its source a dimension of community; it comes to touch everyone directly and through all. This common action of the third party realises itself as an objective structure of interiority and characterises the group as such. The pledge is not a subjective or merely verbal determination: it is a real modification of the group by my regulatory action. The inert negation of certain future possibilities is my bond of interiority with the sworn group to which I belong, in the sense that for everyone the same negation is conditioned by mine, in so far as it is his behaviour. Of course, it must be added that my own behaviour is itself conditioned by everyone else's. But this is not the most important point to emphasise: what appears at first, indeed, is that the guarantee of permanence provided by the oath of the Others produces itself in me as the objective impossibility 2 (in interiority) that alterity should come to me from outside; but, at the same time, it is the possibility that I should make myself Other (by betraying, fleeing, etc.) which is underlined as a possible future coming from me to the Others. Now, this possibility may realise itself in the free development of my action: I may freely decide to abandon my post or to go over to the enemy. It goes without saying that the word 'freely' - here and elsewhere in this work - refers to the dialectical development of an individual praxis, born of need and transcending material conditions towards a definite objective. Betrayal and desertion, brought about by fear and suffering, are, therefore, from this point of view, free praxes in that they are organised behaviour in response to exterior threats. It is also clear that the fear of being afraid - for example, of letting the side down, of being the one through whom the group changes through panic into an inert mass - may be important for an inexperienced young combatant. He is afraid of this fear as an irresistible impulse and, at the same time, he rejects it as a free preference for his own safety over that of all. In this sense, my pledge becomes my surety for myself in that it is me offering myself, in every third party, as everyone's guarantee of not relapsing, in my person or through my conduct, into serial alterity. Thus, in making a pledge, the first movement is to swear so as to make the Others swear, through mediated reciprocity, that is to say, so as to guarantee oneself against the possibility that they will disperse. The second moment of the operation is to swear in order to protect oneself against oneself in the Others. It should also be noted that the second moment cannot be that of the totalising action of a regulatory third party: when I make a pledge, in fact, or when I swear or perform some equivalent act, I remain in a relation of transcendenceimmanence to the group as a whole, and through my behaviour I effect a totalising synthesis which does not actually integrate me into the whole. My making the pledge thereby reveals itself as common freedom, but not as the inert negation of my possibilities. In other words, I unveil my future behaviour and its objective, which is the permanence of the group; but I unveil them in freedom, that is to say, the description expresses an untranscendability which freedom, as practical transcendence, cannot produce of itself... A pledge necessarily involves the following: (1) the characteristics of an order, of a regulatory action, whose (reflected) aim is to involve third parties: I offer myself so that they can offer themselves; the offer of my services (my life, etc.) is already the same as theirs. At this level, my commitment…is a reciprocal commitment, mediated by the third party. (2) The characteristic of a manipulation of myself: to swear is to give what one does not possess in order that the Others shall give it to you so that one can keep one's word: I define the permanence of the group as my untranscendability in a practical movement of all which, through the totalisation of pledges, must confer on me this untranscendability as a negative limit and as an absolute exigency. These two characteristics are indissolubly linked; in so far as each of them is a claim made upon the other third party or myself, through the mediation of the third party, these claims are immediately satisfied by the pledges of all the Others. In fact, although the actual giving of the pledges may be successive…and thus involve a quite formal seriality, the entire real moment of the common action is contained in the order 'Let us swear' - that is to say, in the common decision to swear. At the moment of the decision, the pledge still lies in the future, but its signification - as an immediate objective of the group and as a means of maintaining the permanence required by certain more distant objectives presents it to everyone as a common operation, or, in other words, as the group acting on itself through every member. Thus even if the pledge of one third party is given before that of others (for example, in the serial order of signing), it can never fail: it temporalises itself in an already limited temporality which contains in advance the pledges of all. In a sense, to say 'Let us swear' is to swear: the possibility of a disagreement about this is in fact normally purely formal. If the pledge is recreated, this is because objective circumstances already constitute it as the group's only reflexive means of preserving its unity. It should be defined as everyone's freedom guaranteeing the security of all so that this security can return to everyone as his other-freedom so as to ground his free, practical membership of the group as an untranscendable exigency. Indeed, after the pledge, as before, the third party makes himself a member of the group through his common praxis, and therefore in freedom: this means that his very action develops in dialectical freedom, either within a sub-group or as the common praxis of an isolated individual. The pledge is simply the coincidence, at the source of his practice, of the security of the absent third parties (which he guarantees) and of his own security (guaranteed by the third parties). Exigency and untranscendable permanence as an inert negation of possibilities reveal themselves under the influence of definite conditions (actions of the enemy, for example, such as terror, torture, or separate offers to negotiate, etc.). (Excerpted from Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, translated by Alan Sheridan-Smith [New York: Verso, 2004 (1991)], pp. 419-424.)