I affirm the resolution I value morality as ought implies a moral obligation Moral reasoning can be understood as either explanatory or explicatory. SORAN READER explains the distinction A second distinction emerges when we ask what is the point of describing ethics as natural in either sense? Some take it that showing how ethics is natural enables us to explain and even justify it. We can call these 'explanatory' approaches. Others take it that showing how ethics is natural simply explicates it? no external explanation, justification or 'grounding' is required; and seeking one involves a misunderstanding. We can call these 'explicatory' approaches.5 However any attempt at ethical reasoning will require ethics to be explicatory. Reader 2 explains What is the alternative? To understand ethics in its own terms. This deprives us of explanatory naturalism . We can't without error expect to understand ethics in any terms but ethical. This has seemed to many philosophers to be unduly The problem of displaying the rationality of ethics in a com pelling way is real. But it is also general. It is the same as the problem of displaying the rationality of all the other things we do: playing games, conducting scientific enquiry, writing philosophy papers. We might be able to make connections between activities using an analogy with another game, say, to illuminate the game of chess for someone. But all we will ever be able to lay our hands on in the activity of explaining, is more of the same: parts of our life. The idea of our being able to use 'the world as it is in itself to explain any of our activities is practically contradictory. And the idea that rationality supernature, rather than first nature can be used to explain ethics in this way, involves a similar error. The way we think acquire beliefs, deliberate, justify ourselves is also part of our life. It is as 'fundamental' in that life as ethics is, but no more so, no more knowable 'in itself , as Aristotle, in the grip of a similar error to our own, would have put it, than it is 'to us', here and now, living as we live. So explanatory accounts of ethics, whether they invoke first-nature or super natural reason, are mistaken. Explicatory naturalism is as far as we can go. And as far as we need to go. restrictive, and to threaten relativism.8 But in fact it does not lead to these difficulties ? or, more accurately, it doesn't exac erbate them. I will contend that virtue ethics alone supplies us with the qualities to achieve an explicatory system of ethics. First Barnard Mayo explains the core issues between virtue ethics and other theories. If we wish to enquire about Aristotle’s moral views, it is no use looking for a set of principles. Of course we can find some principles to which he must have subscribed—for instance, that one ought not to commit adultery. But what we find much more prominently is a set of character-traits, a list of certain types of person—the courageous man, the niggardly man, the boaster, the lavish spender, and so on. The basic moral question, for Aristotle, is not, What shall I do? But, what shall I be? The question of what we shall be however alone can be a truly explicatory system of ethics. First virtue ethics alone provides an ideal to which we can attempt to appeal to. This is necessary to be able to identify and say this is how we ought to act. Mayo 2 explains Imitation can be amore or less successful. And this suggests another defect of the ethics of principles. It has no room for ideals, except the ideal of a perfect set of principles (which, as a matter of fact, is intelligible only in terms of an ideal character or way of life), and the ideal of perfect conscientiousness (which is itself a character-trait). This results, of course, from the “black-or-white” nature of moral verdicts based on rules. There are no degrees by which we approach or recede from the attainment of a certain quality or virtue; if there were not, the word “ideal” would have no meaning. Heroes and saints are not people whom we try to be just like, since we know that it’s impossible. It is precisely because it is impossible for ordinary human beings to achieve the same quality as the saints, and in the same degree, that we do set them apart from the rest of humanity. It is enough if we try to be a little like them. This basis for a moral ideal is key to creating a system of ethics non explanatory but explicatory Reader 3 explains Virtue is a free disposition to act in certain ways under certain conditions. Virtue ethics claims that what is to count as a good action or what is a good outcome is conceptually dependent on claims about the virtue of an agent. How is this dependence supposed to work? Where those after an explanatory account seek a conceptual connection with something like a normative 'in itself, virtue ethicists instead explore the concrete dependence of moral activity on the possibility of learning from already virtuous agents. They hold that the key to moral rationality is found in moral education. Ethics begins with the apprentice moral agent: the child, or the foreigner, or the damaged person in rehabilitation are all examples. These beginner-agents learn from the experienced, wise moral agent by copying, by mimicking in their actions the actions of the virtuous agent. This mimicking, or 'going on in the same way', does not presuppose that the learner agent acquires any representations of how the world is (i.e., beliefs), nor that they acquire the ability to report on or provide justifications for what they do. Virtue is learned by cottoning on to virtuous ways of doing things, going on to do the same, then going on to do the same in new ways, once they have mastered the skill. 16 The way virtue and character is supposed to be basic here is simply displayed in the analogy: there is and can be nothing 'behind' the expertise of the phronimos which can explain or jus tify it (any more than there is anything 'behind' the expertise of the doctor or the navigator, to use Aristotle's examples at NE 1104b7-l 1). Of course, plenty more can be said about it, and shortcuts can be found to aid the learn ing of those who have already mastered other skills (so competent rule-fol lowers can learn from being given rules, just as competent grammarians can learn a new language from the grammar). But we should not confuse what it is possible to say about the skill of being moral, with what constitutes it. Second Virtue ethics alone supplies a coherent approach explicatory approach to ethics. Mayo 3 explains the fundamental moral question is just “what ought I to do?” And according to the philosophy of moral principles, the answer (which must be an imperative “Do this”) must be derived from a conjunction of premises consisting (in the simplest case) firstly of a rule, or universal imperative, enjoining (or forbidding) all actions of a certain type in situations of a certain type, and , secondly, a statement to the effect that this is a situation of that type, falling under the rule . IN practice the No doubt emphasis may be on simply only one of these premises, the other being assumed or taken for granted: one may answer the question “what ought I [I]f I am in doubt whether to tell the truth about his condition to a dying man, my doubt may be resolved by showing that the case comes under a rule about the avoidance of unnecessary suffering, which I am assumed to accept. But if the case is without precedent in my moral career, my problem may be a soluble only by adopting a new principle about what I am to do now and the future about cases of this kind. This second possibility offer a connection with moral ideas. Suppose my perplexity is not merely an unprecedented situation which I could cope with by adopting a new rule. Suppose the new rule is thoroughly inconsistent with my existing moral code. This may happen, for instance, if the moral code is one to which I only pay lip-service, if… its authority is not yet internalized, or if its final rejection awaits a moral crisis such as we are assuming to occur. What I now need is not a rule for deciding how to act in this situation and other of its kind. I need a whole set of rules. A complete morality, new principle to live by. Now, according to the philosophy of moral character, there is another way of answering the fundamental question “what ought I to do?” instead of quoting a rule, we quote a quality of character, a virtue: we say “be brave,” or “be patient” or “Be lenient.” We may even say “be a man”: if I am in doubt, say, to do?” either by quoting a rule which I am to adopt, or by showing that my case is legislated for by a rule which I do adopt… whether to take are risk, and someone says “Be a man,” meaning a morally sound man, in this case a man of sufficient courage. (compare the very different ideal invoked in “be a gentleman.” I shall not discuss whether this is a Moral ideal.) Here, too, we have the extreme cases, where a man’s moral perplexity extends not merely to a particular situations but to his whole way of living. And now the question “what ought I to do?” turns into the question “What ought I to be?”—as, indeed, it was treated in the first place. (“be brave.”) It is answered, not by quoting a rule or a set of rules, but by describing a quality of character of a type of person. And here the ethics of character gains a practical simplicity which offsets the greater logical simplicity of the ethics of principles. We do not have to give a list of characteristics or virtues, as we might list a set of principles we can give a unity to our answer. Of course we can in theory give a unity to our principles: this is implied by speaking of a set of principles. But if such a set is to be a system and not merely aggregate, the unity we are looking is a logical one, namely the possibility that some principles are deductible from others, and the ultimately from one. But the attempt to construct a deductive moral system is notoriously difficult, and in any case ill-founded. Why should we expect that all rules of conduct should be ultimately reducible to a few? we can readily give a unity to our answer, though not a logical unity. It is the unity of character. A person’s character is not merely a list of dispositions; it has the organic unity of something that is more than the sum of its parts. And we can say, in answer to our morally perplexed questioner, not only “be this” and “be that,” but also “be like so and so”—where so-and-so is either an ideal type of character, or else an actual person taken as representative of the ideal, as exemplar. Examples of the first are Plato’s “just man” in the Republic; Aristotle’s man of practical wisdom, in the Nicomachean Ethics; Augustine’s citizen of the City of God; the good community; the America way of life (which is a collective expression for a type of character). Examples of the second kind, the exemplar, are Socrates, Christ, Buddha, St. Francis, the heroes of epic writers and of novelists. Indeed the idea of the Hero, as well as the idea of the Saint, are very much the expression of this attitude to morality. Heroes and saints are not merely people who did things. They are people whom we are expected, and expect ourselves, to imitate. And imitating But when we are asked “what shall I be?” them means not merely doing what they did; it means bring like them. Their status is not in the least like that of legislators whose laws we admire; for the character of the legislator is irrelevant to our judgment about his legislation. The heroes an saints did not merely give us principles to live by (though some of the did that as well): they gave us examples to follow. Thus ethics of principles can never provide an expletory of how to act in situations without precedence except by already attaching a principle of explanatory properties to your ethical theories while the ethics of virtue avoids this problem. Thus the standard is bringing out individual virtuous character. I contend that only by treating juvenile as adults can we return to a world where we provide juveniles the status necessary to ensure developed moral agency Sub point a is the uniqueness. Children have lost their picture of innocence. Marie Winn1 explains In their everyday demeanor, the language they use, the things they know and above all in their relations with the adult world, children have changed. This was confirmed in almost every one of hundreds of interviews with fourth, fifth, sixth and seventh graders . The ease and aplomb these children demonstrated in their talks with an interviewer were quite as indicative of change as anything they actually said, although some of their testimony about marijuana, sex and pornographic movies on cable television would have deeply shocked parents a decade or two ago. The reticence and shyness once associated with childhood have clearly gone the way of curtsies and pinafores. As a Denver fourth-grade teacher reports, ''Kids are a lot freer now. Even in the 10 years I've been at this school, there's been a change. The other day, a very innocent-looking little boy came up to me and casually asked me whether a certain sexual act was 'for real.' He used a crude word for it. I asked him to whisper in my ear what he thought the word meant. Well, he knew more details than I myself knew until about five years ago.'' The greatest change of all, however, is not that children have lost their innocence. (An article on that subject, ''What Became of Childhood Innocence?'' by Marie Winn, appeared in this magazine Jan. 25, 1981.) It is a change in our conception of childhood itself . We have seen, in an amazingly short span a transformation of society's most fundamental attitudes toward children. Where parents once felt obliged to shelter their children from life's vicissitudes, today, great numbers of them have come to operate according to a new belief: that children must be exposed early to adult experience in order to survive in an increasingly uncontrollable world. The Age of Protection has ended. An Age of Preparation has set in. And children have suffered a loss. As they are integrated at a young age into the adult world, in every way their lives have become more difficult, more confusing - in short, more like adult lives. We are beginning to hear a bitter reaction from that first generation of children to grow up in the new era - today's young adults. In a recent issue of a newsmagazine, a college student writes: ''We are the kids who were 'so adult.' ... Our parents expected us to understand their problems and frustrations ... . What we missed was the chance to be childish, immature and unafraid to admit we didn't have it all together.'' of time, This is caused by the social discord created when juveniles commit violent felonies. Titus explains commentators argue that children are increasingly “without childhood” (Winn, 1983) and suggest the passing of childhood’s innocence (Elkind, 1981; Postman, 1982; Suransky, 1982). Although juveniles are primarily victims, not perpetrators of vio- lence (Snyder & Sickmund, 1999), intense media scrutiny has skewed the public perception of delinquency and youth violence (Acland, 1995; Baer & Chambliss, 1997; Glassner, 1999; Modern Parker, Miller, Donegan, & Gilliam, 2001; Schissel, 1997; Shepherd, 1998). Despite a proliferation of official statistical reports showing that 1 THE LOSS OF CHILDHOOD [Author of the book. Children without Childhood. Bronx H.S. of Science, Radcliffe College, Columbia U] . May 8, 1983. New York Times Magazine. Online. http://www.nytimes.com/1983/05/08/magazine/the-loss-of-childhood.html. juvenile crime is at its lowest level in 25 years (Federal Interagency Forum on Child and Family Statistics, 2003), the vast majority of the public believes that violent juvenile crime is on the rise (Dorfman & Schiraldi, 2001; Guzman, Lippman, Moore, & O’Hare, 2003). Researchers have linked such misperceptions to the news media’s distorted coverage of youth and its skewed reports on juvenile justice policy debates (Alequin, Florence, Medoza, Ware, & Vazquez, 2001; Dorfman & Schiraldi, 2001; Males, 1999; O’Hare, 2003; Parker et al., 2001; Soler, 2001; We Interrupt This Message, 2001). By the early 1990s, there was a fermenting body of opinion that juvenile justice (and penal liberalism) had gone too far (Soler, 2001). A “moral panic” (Cohen, 1972, pp. 1-15) was constructed through a public “discourse of fear” (Altheide, 1997, p. 648) that portrayed atypical and extraordinary cases as expressions of the dangerous lawlessness of children. Although only a small number of crimes committed by juveniles are classified as violent (Snyder, 2003, p. 4), such crimes tend to emerge sensationalized. The media described a “mounting terror of the anarchy and uncontrollability of unfettered youth” (Pilkington, 1994, ¶ 6), and experts predicted that because these young offenders were “distinctively malevolent” (Zimring, 1998, p. 7), we are “facing a potential bloodbath of teenage violence in the years ahead” (Ellis, 1996, p. 97). Conceptions of youth became equated with notions of criminality, and a dangerous and threatening character was taken to be their inherent ano- mie (Males, 1999). Young people were more than just dangerous, they were “full of mur- derous rage” and “brutality” (Philips, 1993, ¶ 7, 8) and were described as “turning feral” (Jeffs & Smith, 1996, p. 1). The panic that ensued from this “dramatization of evil” (Tannenbaum, 1938, p. 19) was a moral one, in that there was The public responses of fear, hostility, and condemnation became heightened when the perpetrating “folk devils” (Cohen, 1972) were identified as young, morally weak, and dabbling in evil. Rhetorical framing of juvenile offenders as “super-predators” (DiIulio, 1995, p. 23) characterized their actions as intentional, sinister, and lacking (childish) innocence, and attributed their crimes to primal dark forces intrinsic to a perceived threat to values held sacred by society, a destabilizing “threat to the social order itself” (Thompson, 1998, p. 8). them. “[T]he Child has never been seen as such a menacing enemy as today. Never before have children been so saturated with all the power of pro- jected monstrousness to excite repulsion—and even terror” (Warner, 1994, p. 56). When confronted with (innocent) children and (evil) horrific crimes defying conven- tional categorization, society repositions the accused as an outsider, an “Other,” “distanced, yet inseparable, from the social order” (Acland, 1995, p. 19). In the essentializing news media reports of child murderers, a particularly demonic image of childhood was constructed. Statistically, child murderers are rare, with juveniles involved in 10% of murder arrests (Snyder, 2003, p. 1), and of those juveniles arrested for murder, only 12% are under age 15 (Snyder, 2003, p. 3). Such rarity itself declares the aberrant status of a child mur- derer, and the effect is magnified through their distorted presence in the media discourse (Kunkel, 1994) and reports of an “unprecedented epidemic” of killer children (Cook & Laub, 1998, p. 27). The rhetorical framing of juveniles as evil delineates them as distinctly sacrificable, through a conversion of their status as “Other.” This creation of the “Other” is integral to a notion of “little monsters” (Warner, 1994, p. 43) and the “politics of spectacle” (Acland, 1995, p. 20) within which their monstrousness emerges. Media dwell on the bru- tality of the crimes, and the public views the child’s presumed monstrosity to be confirmed by the character and rarity of the very offences they are accused of having committed. The increasing public disquiet over violent children contributed to the institutionalization in law and policy of offending children’s symbolic expurgation as folk devils. Aspects of this process were displayed when a murder in the United Kingdom of a 2year-old boy by two 10-year-old boys unleashed a moral outrage. Young (1996) has shown how the media set the concept of good, innocent childhood against the aberration of the kill- ing. The victim, James Bulger, represented the quintessential child, exemplifying child- hood ideals (e.g., small, trusting, affectionate, vulnerable), an allegory for the innocence of childhood. Juxtaposed, his killers personified the oppositional categories of evil and dan- gerousness. Hay (1995) explains that we were “confronted by the implications of the real- ization that those formerly confirmed a belief that “children may look like angels but still be devils underneath” (Warner, 1994, p. 57). Having betrayed an conceived of as innocent victims might pose a profound threat in and of themselves” (p. 201). They abstract myth about proper childlikeness, the murderers’ trial and media coverage “revealed a brutal absence of pity for them as children” Headlines announced the “death of inno- cence” (Bedell, 1993, p. 23), and reporters accused the boys of having “killed not just a child but the idea of childhood” (Warner, 1994, p. 45). (Morrison, 1997, ¶ 1). The conjoined descriptions of the “embryo-angel” and “infant fiend” that expressed parents’ feelings about their children in the 17th century (Greven, 1977, p. 28) are reflected in our contemporary dual imagery of the angel-monster child. According to the “myth of pure evil,” people identify with the good of innocent victims against the evil of perpetrating others (Baumeister, 1996, p. 60). Baumeister (1996) argues that this way of constructing evil is persuasive because it provides us with some certainty about our own goodness, as well as a scapegoat Such a good-evil dualism allows groups to vent their moral panic by providing the ability to categorize, judge, and express the revulsion that proves their social power to control the threat. on which to blame perceived disruptions in the social fabric. B is the link Only by treating juveniles as adults are we able to undue this construction of children as losing their innocence Because Treating children like adults in the criminal justice system is a way of saying that these children are inconsistent with our normal conception of childhood, serving to actually reinforce the conception of childhood innocence that we hold. Allison James and Chris Jenks2 write, Within these quotations two kinds of 'Otherness' can be identified: (a) the child possessed of an inherently evil nature; and (b) the composite creature, the 'adult-child'. Both are highly transgressive images, at once wilful, bizarre and demonic. In that these images[is an] instance acute fracture from the commonplace idea of 'the child' as it is understood within western society, they both constitute a powerful, and volatile, ambiguity in public accounts of childhood. Anthropological work on social classication enables us to understand such a response as one emitting from a people whose cosmologies are under the identification of anomalies, whether in the form of people, plants or animals, is integral to the establishment of social order. Anomalies are, in essence, the byproducts of systems of ordering. Through their remarked differences, ironically, they work to firm up the boundaries which give form and substance to the conceptual categories from which they are excluded. In this sense, by refusing children who commit acts of violence acceptance within the category of child, the public was reaffirming to itself the essence of what children are. That is, it was a way to restore the primary image of the innate goodness of children through relegating some would-be children (those who commit acts of violence) to another category essentialized through images of evil or pathology. threat. As Mary Douglas (1970) has shown, Secondly the act of expelling the violent juveniles and separating them from others by making them adults is key to returning conceptions of childhood to a status quo of innocence. Titus further explains The operation of exclusivity allowed for Bulger’s killers to be cast out from child- hood. The killers’ “Otherness” was their media-ascribed nonhumanness; they were referred to as animals, beasts, freaks of nature, savages, and monsters. There was a strong display of associating the killers with Christian ideas of evil. They were “from hell,” “products of the devil,” who had the “Satan bug inside them” and the “Mark of the Beast” on them; indeed, “Demons had invaded the innocents” (Haydon & Scraton, 2000, p. 425). The judge de- clared that the boys were “cunning and wicked” and had perpetrated “an act of unparalleled evil and barbarity” (Pilkington, 1993, ¶ 3). Their anomaly served not only to allow for their segregation from other Allison James and Chris Jenks, “Public Perceptions of Childhood Criminality,” The British Journal of Sociology Vol. 47, No. 2 (Jun., 1996), pp. 315-331, http://www.jstor.org/stable/591729 2 children, but also for a viewing public to demand to “kill them,” and “hang them” (Pilkington, 1993, ¶ 16). The child who kills becomes devalued and made a “monstrous double” (Girard, 1972/ 1977, p. 272) for the innocents they imitate. The sacrificial victim who is significantly different ensures that the public is less likely to sympathetically identify with that “monster” (Girard, 1972/1977, p. 270). Subsequent institutional responses sought to reaffirm a tradi- tional construct of childhood’s innocence whereby (good) children are protected and evil youth who are disruptive of the social order are sacrificed for the beneficial effects of their surrogacy. By virtue of their dehumanization and monstrousness, child criminals then can be exposed to the violence of law without fear of reprisal because their sacrifice will not entail any act of vengeance. C is the impact Retaining the juveniles image of innocence generally is key to reforming and developing their character. Its important to associate children with innocence. Society when it expects children to not be children and instead to lose their innocence and gain maturity ends up causing great harm to children. Marie Winn3 explains. ''innocence, once considered the right of children, may be seen as simply the absence of weight and burden. Maturity, meanwhile, may be defined as the capacity to carry a burden successfully. But if you are given the heavy burden of knowledge before you have the capacity to deal with it -and knowledge is burdensome, because it requires mental and psychological work to deal with it - the results may be those distressing signs parents and teachers are observing among children today: confusion, fear, feelings of incompetence. Children grow up not really able to deal with difficulties, and they learn that the best way to deal with problems is to escape, through drugs or drink or whatever.'' Because of the precocious knowledge, independence, assertivenesss and ''adultness'' that characterize so many children today - especially, it appears, those who have had to ''grow up faster'' because their parents have divorced or are both absorbed in their careers, it is easy to get the impression that children are also more mature these days. Moreover, Annie Hermann continues, Indeed, the child growing up under more protective, old-fashioned circumstances may seem more ''bratty,'' more ''spoiled,'' more demanding than But while a certain level of sophistication is inevitably achieved true maturity, defined by an ability to share, to sacrifice, to be generous, to love unselfishly, and to nurture and care for children of his own, may prove elusive, and in its place, attention-seeking and narcissism become the characteristics that define his adult life. While those children whose childhoods are enriched by a bounty of adult experiences end up the poorer for it, those ''poor'' protected children have received a treasure in disguise - one, however, that will reveal itself only when they have grown up. the hardy, self-sufficient child of absent parents. when a child is forced to take care of himself much of the time, it is not the same thing as maturity. As the child grows older, Second, retaining the concept of the innocent child allows adults to have the ability to understand the virtue to which they must aspire Allison James and Chris Jenks4 write, to abandon a shared category of the child is to confront a daunting paradox. If as adults we do just that, what happens to the concept of 'childhood' through which we, as adults, see ourselves and our society's past and future? If, as we have argued here, the concept of'childhood' serves to But 3 THE LOSS OF CHILDHOOD [Author of the book. Children without Childhood. Bronx H.S. of Science, Radcliffe College, Columbia U] . May 8, 1983. New York Times Magazine. Online. http://www.nytimes.com/1983/05/08/magazine/the-loss-of-childhood.html. Allison James and Chris Jenks, “Public Perceptions of Childhood Criminality,” The British Journal of Sociology Vol. 47, No. 2 (Jun., 1996), pp. 315-331, http://www.jstor.org/stable/591729 4 articulate not just the experience and status of the young within modern society but also the projections, aspirations, longings and altruism contained within the adult experience then to abandon such a conception is to erase our final point of stability and attachment to the social bond. In an historical era during which issues of identity and integration (Giddens 1991) are, perhaps, both more unstable and more fragile than at any previous time, such a loss would impact upon the everyday experience of societal members with disorienting consequences. Only by interrogating the possessive adhesion of adults to the concept of childhood in the context of postmodernity can we begin to understand the fear behind those distorted masks of hatred and retribution that disfugured the faces of the crowd outside of the courthouse in Liverpool during 1993 where two sad little boys were being charged with the murder of a third. Contention 2. Rehabilitation does not link to the framework. There are two different forms which alter how people act. The medical and the moral only ones deals with the person real character the other deals merely with states of affairs. C.S. Lewis5 explains the distinction. morality claims to be a technique for putting the human machine right, I think you would like to know how it is related to another technique which seems to make a similar claim-namely, psychoanalysis. Now you want Before I come down to details there are two more general points I should like to make. First of all, since Christian to distinguish very clearly between two things: between the actual medical theories and technique of the psychoanalysts, and the general philosophical view of the world which Freud and some others have gone on to add to this. The second thing-the philosophy of Freud-is in direct contradiction to Christianity: and also in direct contradiction to the other great psychologist, Jung. And furthermore, when Freud is talking about how to cure neurotics he is speaking as a specialist on his own subject, but when he goes on to talk general philosophy he is speaking as an amateur. It is therefore quite sensible to attend to him with respect in the one case and not in the other-and that is what I do. I am all the readier to do it because I have found that when he is talking off his own subject and on a subject I do know something about (namely, languages) he is very ignorant. But psychoanalysis itself, apart from all the philosophical additions that Freud and others have made to it, is not in the least contradictory to Christianity. Its technique overlaps with Christian morality at some points and it would not be a bad thing if every parson knew When a man makes a moral choice two things are involved. One is the act of choosing. The other is the various feelings, impulses and so on which his psychological outfit presents him with, and which are the raw material of his choice. Now this raw material may be of two kinds. Either it may be what we would call normal: it may consist of the sort of feelings that are common to all men. Or else it may consist of quite unnatural feelings due to things that have gone wrong in his subconscious. Thus fear of something about it: but it does not run the same course all the way, for the two techniques are doing rather different things. things that are really dangerous would be an example of the first kind: an irrational fear of cats or spiders would be an example of the second Now what psychoanalysis undertakes to do is to remove the abnormal feelings, that is, to give the man better raw material for his acts of choice: morality is concerned with the acts of choice themselves. Put it this way. Imagine three men who go to war. One has the ordinary natural fear of danger that any man has and he subdues it by moral effort and becomes a brave man. Let us suppose that the other two have, as a result of things in their sub-consciousness, exaggerated, irrational fears, which no amount of moral effort can do anything about. Now suppose that a psychoanalyst comes along and cures these two: that is, he puts them both back in the kind. The desire of a man for a woman would be of the first kind: the perverted desire of a man for a man would be of the second. 5 Lewis, C. S. Mere Christianity. Collins, 1942. Print. position of the first man. Well it is just then that the psychoanalytical problem is over and the moral problem begins. Because, now that they are cured, these two men might take quite different lines. The first might say, "Thank goodness I've got rid of all those doodahs. Now at last I can do what I always wanted to do-my duty to the cause of freedom." But the other might say, "Well, I'm very glad that I now feel moderately cool under fire, but, of course, that doesn't alter the fact that I'm still jolly well determined to look after Number One and let the other chap do the dangerous job whenever I can. Indeed one of the good things about feeling less frightened is that I can now look after myself much more efficiently and can be much cleverer at hiding the fact from the others." Now this difference is a purely moral one and psychoanalysis cannot do anything about it. However much you improve the man's raw material, you have still got something else: the real, free choice of the man, on the material presented to him, either to put his own advantage first or to put it last And this$ free choice is the only thing that morality is concerned with. The bad psychological material is not a sin but a disease. It does not need to be repented of, but to be cured. And by the way, that is very important. Human beings judge one another by their external actions. God judges them by their moral choices. When a neurotic who has a pathological horror of cats forces himself to pick up a cat for some good reason, it is quite possible that in God's eyes he has shown more courage than a healthy man may have shown in winning the V.C . When a man who has been perverted from his youth and taught that cruelty is the right thing, does some tiny little kindness, or refrains from some cruelty he might have committed, and thereby, perhaps, risks being sneered at by his companions, he may, in God's eyes, be doing more than you and I would do if we gave up life itself for a friend. This means rehabilitative effects don’t link to the framework. Rehabilitation is not concerned with the moral qualities of a person but with the mental makeup. Instead we must foster active wills by bring up and providing an environment for moral choice not rehabilitative cure. G.K. Chesterton6 explains But the point is that a story is exciting because it has in it so strong an element of will, of what theology calls free-will. You cannot finish a sum how you like. But you can finish a story how you like. When somebody discovered the Differential Calculus there was only one Differential Calculus he could discover. But when Shakespeare killed Romeo he might have married him to Juliet's old nurse if he had felt inclined. And Christendom has excelled in the narrative romance exactly because it has insisted on the theological free-will. It is a large matter and too much to this is the real objection to that torrent of modern talk about treating crime as disease, about making a prison merely a hygienic environment like a hospital, of healing sin by slow scientific methods. The fallacy of the whole thing is that evil is a matter of active choice whereas disease is not. If you say that you are going to cure a profligate as you cure an asthmatic, my cheap and obvious answer is, "Produce the people who want to be asthmatics as many people want to be profligates." A man may lie still and be cured of a malady. But he must not lie still if he wants to be cured of a sin; on the contrary, he must get up and jump about violently. The whole point indeed is perfectly expressed in the very word which we use for a man in hospital; "patient" is in the passive mood; "sinner" is in the active. If a man is to be saved from influenza, he may be a patient. But if he is to be saved from forging, he must be not a patient but an IMPATIENT. He must be personally impatient with forgery. All moral reform must start in the active not the passive will. one side of the road to be discussed adequately here; but 6 The Project Gutenberg eBook, Orthodoxy, by G. K. Chesterton. 1908