Language and reality: The constitution of what is human Maturana, Humberto. (1989). Lenguaje y realidad: El origen de lo humano. Arch. Bio. Med. Exp. 22: 77-81. Translated into English by Cristina Magro, Revised by Cristina Magro and Julie Tetel Abstract The author proposes that: 1. a lineage of living systems is constituted by the reproductive conservation of a manner of living under the form of an ontogenic phenotype. 2. language is a manner of living in recurrent consensual coordinations of consensual coordinations of actions. 3. the human manner of living entails among other things, a braiding of languaging and emotioning that we call conversation. 4. human beings arise in the history of bipedal primates with the origin of language and the constitution of a lineage defined by the conservation of an ontogenic phenotype that includes conversations as part of it. 5. the magnitude of the involvement of the brain and anatomy of the larynx and face in speech as our main manner of languaging indicates that language cannot have arisen more recently than two or three million years ago. 6. rationality pertains to the operational coherences of languaging and that different rational domains are constituted by different basic notions that are accepted a priori. That is, on preference. 7. responsibility and freedom are a function of our awareness of the participation of our emotions (preferences) in the constitution of the rational domains in which we operate. The human emerges, in the evolutionary history of the hominid lineage to which we belong, when language emerges. In the biological realm, a species is or system of lineages constituted as such when a particular manner of living is conserved transgenerationally in the reproductive history of a series of organisms. Insofar as every living being exists as a dynamic system in ongoing structural change, the manner of living that defines a species, a lineage, or a system of lineages occurs as a dynamic configuration of relations between living being and medium that extends in the course of its ontogeny from conception until death. Jorge Mpodozis and I call this manner of living or dynamic configuration of ontogenic relations between living being and medium ontogenic phenotype which, insofar as it is conserved transgenerationally in a reproductive succession of organisms, constitutes and defines the identity of a system of lineages. The ontogenic phenotype is not genetically determined because, as a manner of living that develops during ontogeny, i.e. the individual history of every organism, it is a phenotype, and as a phenotype it occurs in this individual history necessarily as a present moment that is generated one moment after the other in an epigenetic process. What the genetic constitution of an organism determines in the moment of conception is a 2 domain of possible , one of which the organism’s history of interactions with the medium will realize in an epigenetic process. Because of that, when a system of lineages is constituted, the genotype, i.e. the genetic constitution of the organisms that constitute this system, remains free and may vary insofar as such variations do not interfere with the conservation of the ontogenic phenotype that defines the system of lineages. For this reason, if at any given moment in the reproductive history that constitutes a lineage the conserved ontogenic phenotype changes, from then on the identity of the lineage changes or a new lineage appears as a new form or kind of organisms parallel to the antecedent lineage. In these circumstances, in order to understand what happens in the history of evolutionary change of any class of organisms, it is necessary to locate the ontogenic phenotype that is conserved in a particular class and within whose limits such changes are produced. Thus, in order to understand the evolutionary history that gives rise to the human, it is necessary first to look at the manner of living that, insofar as it is conserved in the system of hominid lineages, makes possible the origin of language, and then to look at the new manner of living that appears with language which, insofar as it is conserved, establishes a particular lineage to which we modern human beings belong. Let us consider this for a moment: a) The origin of language, which is a domain of consensual coordinations of behavior, requires a history of recurrent relationships of mutual acceptation sufficiently intense and prolonged (Maturana, 1978 and 1991). b) What we know about our ancestors that lived in Africa three and a half million years ago, indicate that they had a manner of living centered around the harvesting and the sharing of food, the collaboration of males and females in the upbringing of the progeny, sensual coexistence and face to face sexuality, and a realm of small groups formed by few young adults and children. c) The manner of living indicated in (b), which we still basically conserve, offers all that is necessary to: i) the origin of language; ii) together with the appearance of language, the constitution of conversing as the intercrossing of languaging and emotioning (Maturana, 1991); and iii) along with the addition of conversing as another element to be conserved in the manner of living of hominids, the constitution of a particular ontogenic phenotype which defines the system of lineages to which we modern human beings belong. d) The fact that current chimpanzees and gorillas, whose brain is comparable in size with that of our ancestors, can be incorporated in language through coexistence in Ameslan (American Sign Language), suggests that the brain of our ancestors three million years ago must have been already adequate for language. What distinguishes the hominid lineage from other lineages of primates is a manner of living in which the sharing of food, with all that it implies of proximity, mutual acceptance and coordinations of actions in passing things to one another, plays a central role. It is the hominid manner of living that makes language possible, and it is love, as the emotion that constitutes the domain of actions in which the hominid manner of living occurs, that is the central emotion in the evolutionary history that gives rise to us. This is apparent in the fact that the largest part of human illnesses, either somatic or psychic, belong to the domain of interference with love. The manner of living properly human, nevertheless, constitutes itself, as I have already said, when conversing is added to the hominid manner of living, and the intercrossing of languaging with emotioning becomes conserved as part of the ontogenic phenotype that defines us. When the manner of living properly human emerges, conversing as action belongs to the emotional realm in which language emerges as a way 3 of being in the coordinations of actions that arise through the intimacy of sensual and sexual coexistence. That this is so is apparent in several ways: a) in the tactile images we use when referring to what occurs to us with voices during speech, such that we say that a voice can be smooth, caressing or rough; b) in the physiological and hormonal changes, for example, that we trigger in each other with speech; and c) in the pleasure we have in conversing and in flowing through languaging. When did languaging and conversing start in our evolutionary history? The enormous structural compromise of our present nervous system, of our larynx, of our face as well as of other aspects of our body with speech as our most fundamental way of being in language, indicates that vocal languaging has to have started several million years ago; I think that it was between two and three. Realities Human existence in language configures many domains of reality, each one of them constituted as a domain of explanatory operational coherences. These different domains of reality are also domains of activities that we generate in coexistence with others, and that, as networks of conversations (networks of coordinations of actions and emotions), constitute all domains, ways and systems (institutions) of human existence. In these circumstances reality in any domain is an explanatory proposition of human experience. Emotions What we distinguish when we talk about emotions is the domain of actions in which the observed organism moves. Accordingly, I say that emotions correspond to body dispositions that specify the domain of actions in which an organism moves. I also say that different human actions are defined by the emotion that supports them and that everything we do, we do departing from an emotion. Because of that, even if what is human emerges in the evolutionary history to which we belong when language emerges, the human constitutes itself, in fact, in the conservation of a particular manner of living in which the sharing of food, the cooperation of male and female in the upbringing of children, and individualized and sensual recurrent relationships occur in the interbraiding of languaging and emotioning that is conversing. In other words, all human activities occur in conversing, and whatever in the ongoing existence of human beings that does not happen in conversing is not a human activity. Accordingly, at the same time, since all human activities occur departing from an emotion, nothing that is human happens outside of the interbraiding of languaging and emotioning, and, therefore, the human is lived always departing from an emotion, even the most sublime and purest reasoning. Finally, the emotioning in whose conservation the human is constituted when language emerges is centered around the enjoyment of coexistence, in the acceptance of the other together with oneself, that is, in love, which is the emotion that constitutes the domain of actions in which we accept the other. That love is the emotion that, in the origin of the human, stablishes the enjoyment of conversing that characterizes us, has as consequence that both our welfare as well as our suffering depend on our conversing, and are originated and ended in. 4 Rationality In daily experience, reason or rationality appears as a constitutive property of human consciousness. Nevertheless, in human evolutionary history, reasoning appears with language in its operational regularities. Because of that, human reason or rationality is a distinction made by an observer about the flow of discoursive coherences in language, when he or she can say that this discourse occurs without confusing domains. It follows that every domain or rational system is a system of coherences in language that constitutes itself from basic premises accepted as valid a priori. It also follows that: a) an argument is rationally valid only in the rational domain constituted by the basic premises that support it; b) those who accept an argument as rationally valid accept implicitly or explicitly the basic premises that constitute the rational domain in which such an argument is valid; c) insofar as the basic premises that define a domain or rational system are accepted a priori, they are accepted depending on the preferences of the one who accepts them, and d) the rational domain in which an observer operates depend on his or her emotioning when he or she moves from the acceptance of certain basic premises to others, according to his or her preferences at that moment. In daily life we move from one rational domain to another in the course of our emotioning, frequently without realizing it. Because of that, the flow of rational discourses in human interactions depends on the emotional flow of the conversings in which those interactions occur. This we do not normally see, because we are normally blind to our emotioning. In short, the validity of our rational arguments does not depend on our emotions, but on the rational domain in which we find ourselves at every moment during conversing, indeed. Conclusions To recognize that human beings exist as such in the intercrossing of many conversations in many different operational domains that configure many different domains of reality is particularly significant because it allows us to restore emotioning as a fundamental realm of human. In evolutionary history, the human is configured together with conversing when language arises as a recursion in the consensual behavioral coordinations that occur in the domain of a particular manner of living in the flow of co-emotioning of the members of a particular group of bipedal primates to which we belong. Because of that, when conversing emerges with the emergence of language in an operational domain of mutual acceptance (love) among these primates, the human remains constitutively stablished with the basic participation of emotioning and, in particular, with the participation of love. In the delusion of the patriarchal culture to which we belong in the West, and which presently seems to be expanding throughout the world, emotions have been devalued in favor of rationality as if rationality could exist independently or contrary to emotions. To recognize that the human realizes itself in conversing as the intercrossing of languaging and emotioning that emerges with language gives us the possibility of reintegrating ourselves in these two dimensions with a more complete understanding of the processes that constitute us in our daily being, as well as the possibility of respecting these two aspects of our being as legitimate. Since childhood people tell 5 us to control or deny our emotions because emotions give rise to the arbitrariness of the nonrational. Now we now that this is not so. In conversing, rationality also emerges as a way of being in the flow of the operational coherences of consensual behavioral coordinations of languaging. Nevertheless, the effectiveness of reasoning guiding the coordinations of actions in technical activity blinds us to the non-rational foundation of every rational domain, and transforms, with its pretension of non- arbitrariness, any rational claim into a demand for obedience from other people that limits our possibilities of reflection because it impedes us from seeing the emotional dynamics of conversing. This is important to the understanding of the human and of the rational because, even if it may seem to goes against the grain, by accounting for the participation of our emotions as the foundation of any rational system in the flow of conversing, we obtain the true value of reason in the understanding of the human. And this is so because now we know that we should acknowledge our emotions and know them in their flow, when we want our behavior to be, in effect, rational from the understanding of what is rational. Finally, to acknowledge the interbraiding between emotioning and languaging that is all conversing and therefore all human activity gives the foundation to the comprehension of two additional dimensions of human beings, that is, responsibility and freedom: a) we become responsible in the moment in which, in our reflection, we recognize whether we do or do not want the consequences of our actions and b) we become free in the moment in which, in our reflections about our activities, we recognize whether we do want or do not want our wanting the consequences of our actions. In being responsible and free, the course of our actions spontaneously begins to depend on our desires and on our recognizing these desires and this interdependence. In these circumstances, it is possible that the most enlightening aspect of these reflections about reality and reason is in recognizing that the rational understanding of the most fundamental aspects of the ongoing human existence, which resides in responsibility and freedom, emerges from the reflection about emotioning, which shows us the non-rational foundation of what is rational. References Maturana, H. R. (1978). Biology of Language: Epistemology of Reality. In: Miller, G. and Lenneberg, E. (eds.). Psychology and Biology of Language and Thought. New York, Academic Press. p. 27-64. Maturana, H. R. (1991) Reality: The Search for Objectivity, or the Quest for a Compelling Argument. In: Leser, N.; Seifert, J. und Plitzner, K. (eds.) Die Gedankenwelt Sir Karl Poppers. Kritischer Rationalismus im Dialog. Heidelberg, Carl Winter. Universitätsverlag. p. 282-357. See also in this volume. Maturana, H. R. & Mpodozis, J. M. (1992). Origen de las Especies por medio de la Deriva Natural o La diversificación de los linajes a través de la conservación y cambio de los fenotipos ontogénicos. Publicación ocasional del Museo Nacional de Historia Natural. Dirección de Bibliotecas, Archivos y Museos, Santiago do Chile. See also in this volume (N.T.: This work was still in preparation when the present paper was published.)