Harriet Johnson 76946 1 ‘It is...deeply disturbing to find the defenders of faith by reason offering proofs for God’s existence which presuppose that the divine nature can be understood on the model of spatiotemporal phenomena, as if God were a physical entity (however special a kind).’ (Stephen Mulhall, Faith and Reason 21) What do these defenders of faith miss about the nature of religious belief? Discuss with reference to two authors we studied in the course Defenders of faith in the tradition of natural theology attempt to justify belief in God’s existence via rational argument or the production of evidence. However these proofs seem to lack relevance to the nature of religious belief as it is actually experienced by the believer. Ones belief is something one trusts in and depends on beyond just the use of reason. This is not necessarily to say that the rational faculty is not involved in religious belief but it does not exhaust it. There are also emotional, imaginal and experiential components, and it is this further dimension that engenders and nurtures the believer’s relationship with the divine. Further to this, it can be argued that any attempt to justify and explain the transcendental via concepts and reasoned argument will be frustrated by our limitations as subjective human beings and the language we are bound by, which prevents us from conceptualising the non-rational. Attempts to assess the validity of religious belief, prior to attending to the emotional experience that characterises it, inevitably miss a vitally important element of the religious life as lived by the believer. Rudolf Otto begins The Idea of the Holy1 with a discussion of the rational and the non-rational. Christianity characterises God by employing concepts such as good-will and supreme power, allowing that they are analogous to the same attributes in human nature but thought of as absolute and unqualified, thereby admitting the possibility of knowledge of God by way of rational thought. However these so called rational attributes do not exhaustively describe the essence of deity. Otto terms them ‘synthetic essential attributes’2, as while they describe the idea of a deity in some 1 R. Otto, The Idea of the Holy: An Enquiry into the Non-rational Factor in the Idea of the Divine and its relation to the Rational, trans. John W. Harvey, (London: Oxford University Press, 1923) 2 Otto, The Idea of the Holy, p. 2. Harriet Johnson 76946 2 sense, in a deeper sense they are only a finger pointing at the moon3, and the essence of God eludes them. The rational attributes Otto describes, are concepts which natural theologians apply to God in an attempt to rationalise faith, but these concepts belong to human understanding and language and we cannot expect that by magnifying them to perfection or their absolute we will begin to encounter the essence of the divine. As Stephen Mulhall suggests, they presuppose that God can be understood on a model of spatio-temporal phenomena. Otto does not deny the place of this rational side of religion but wishes to avoid an excessively intellectualistic interpretation. Instead of a reasoned analysis of the nature of God and faith, Otto continues to explore the different ‘moments’ that characterise religious belief in order to illuminate the uniquely non-rational essence of religion. His method is to evoke or awaken the numinous, a term he coined to describe the holy stripped of its associations with mere moral goodness, through the exploration of human feelingresponses rather than rational demonstration or explanation. It is precisely this quality of experience that defenders of faith via reason fail to grasp. When one abandons theorising in favour of knowledge through intimate experience by recollection of deeply-felt religious experience, one encounters what Otto terms ‘creature-feeling’. It is a feeling similar to one of religious dependence, encountered when one is overwhelmed by their sense of nothingness in the face of an overpowering absolute might of some kind. This creature-feeling, different from just an experience of dependence, is not self-referential, rather it is the effect of another feeling which has immediate primary reference to an object outside of the self. This object is the ‘numinous’. The nature of the numinous is such that it can only be suggested in the way in which it grips and stirs the human mind. What is felt in the experience of the numinous, Otto terms ‘mysterium 3 A traditional image in Zen Buddhism entreating practitioners not to mistake the means of expression (the finger) for the actual experience or truth of the matter (the moon). Harriet Johnson 76946 3 tremendum’ and identifies five elements to this experience which each communicate something about the numinous.4 In Otto’s assertion that the nature of the numinous can only be suggested by the way in which it is reflected in the mind; the emotional experience itself points to the nature of an external object. For example, Otto describes a sense of awe stirring when the mysterious is looming before the mind in all its uncanniness; a feeling of fear and dread in the face of the numinous wrath of God; a feeling of religious humility arising out of the aweful majesty and overpoweringness of the numinous. So from the encounter with ones emotional experience of the divine, we learn of it’s mystery, it’s uncanniness, it’s numinous wrath. In this way, Otto indicates how the defenders of faith via reason miss what it feels like to confront the idea of the divine in our own experience. Although the terms Otto uses could be considered to be quite loaded concepts, layered with meanings, Otto uses them in a very specific way in an attempt to capture a unique feeling-response, whilst acknowledging the finitude of their ability to encapsulate the numinous essence. Kierkegaard also challenged the systematic thought of philosophers in the tradition of natural theology, who attempted to reinforce the idea that Christianity is a rational religion whose truth could be objectively demonstrated. He appealed to the subjectivity of experience, especially with regard to the personal nature of relationship with the divine, to subvert the rationalistic tendencies of Christian philosophy and reveal a more authentic form of faith. Hegel wanted to construct a self-grounding allencompassing philosophical system, but Kierkegaard opposed his methods and asserted that a human being has an inner life, which he termed inwardness, that can’t be assimilated into a system in this manner. This inwardness cannot be rationalised in such a way, and perhaps cannot even be articulated, so for Kierkegaard it is this inward sphere that Hegel’s philosophy doesn’t do justice to. 4 Otto, The Idea of the Holy pp.8-42 Harriet Johnson 76946 4 For Kierkegaard, “Truth is Subjectivity”. This is not a complete rejection of objective truth, but an insistence on placing the human being at the centre of the enquiry. Objective truth is about what is known; subjective truth is about how one appropriates that truth and lives by it. Kierkegaard rejects the whole idea of scientific objectivity as a guide to how we should believe and act in all matters that concern our personal lives. In objectivity, one tends to lose the infinite personal interestedness in passion, which is the condition of faith. For Kierkegaard, those who attempt to justify belief in God by rational means are not authentic, and not inspired. When the question is treated in an objective manner it becomes impossible for the subject to face the decision with passion, and it lessens ones engagement with their relationship to the enquiry. The uncertainty that comes with a lack of objectivity increases the tension of that infinite passion which constitutes his inwardness. Inwardness becomes intensified by embracing this objective uncertainty with the passion of the infinite. Kierkegaard gave the counter-example of a mathematical proposition, in which the objectivity is given, but for this very reason it is an indifferent truth, as it is not experiential or lived.5 Kierkegaard has been accused of irrationalism because of his definition of truth as “an objective uncertainty, held fast through appropriation with the most passionate inwardness”6, but this is a misinterpretation. Like Otto, he wants to unsettle the comfortable, uncommitted, cultural mode of Christianity; It is not a rejection of the rational faculty, but for these two thinkers, faith and religion are much more of an existential task to be participated in; according to Kierkegaard one must be continually engaged in and committed to faith. Kierkegaard rejects reason conceived of as a superior faculty, he instead emphasises the reasoning capacity of historically embedded human beings, whilst appreciating the limits of human reason. This emphasis is connected with Otto’s view of our ‘creatureliness’, in that we are not entitled to occupy a god-like, birds-eye position. We each of us are living temporal beings, engaging in philosophy from the perspective of the existing individual. There 5 S. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. D. F. Swenson and W. Lowrie, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974) p.182 6 S. Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, p.182 Harriet Johnson 76946 5 are elements to our existence from this perspective that we cannot know or understand. If Kierkegaard were committed to irrationalism, he would not be able to discriminate between objects of faith; but he definitely commends the Christian faith above all others, precisely because he views it as a rational religion, grounded in its objective, empirical reality; the reality that God revealed himself in a human form in Christ.7 So Kierkegaard is not committed to irrationalism, rather he appears to be an anti-rationalist, in that he does not deny the value of reason in his project but maintains that there is a tendency to excessively emphasise abstract impersonal forms of thought thereby losing contact with equally important alternative sources of wisdom. There is a continuum extending from different formulations of rationalism, including evidentialist and cosmological arguments, to irrationalism, or fideism, the view that religious belief by its very nature is opposed to reason and should be adopted on the basis of faith alone. As we have seen, Otto and Kierkegaard argue for a position in between these two. Otto believes that his account can begin to offer us a better understanding of religious belief than proposed by natural theology because it accounts for both experience and practice. The kind of understanding that Otto describes does not necessarily fall within the traditional epistemic boundaries however he is contacting the experiential component of religious belief by plunging into the depths of its nonrational element; depths which are inaccessible to those who attempt to provide proofs and arguments for God’s existence. For Kierkegaard too, a certain kind of thinking remains closed to us until we are ourselves thrown back into inwardness. Related to these emotional and experiential components of religious belief, is the way human beings approach and encounter God by setting up symbolic meaning in their lives through ritual, stories, the arts, and engagement with scripture. This is the imaginal component referred to in the 7 Carr, K. L., and Ivanhoe, P. J., Antirationalism in Zhuangzi and Kierkegaard, in Readings in Philosophy of Religion: East Meets West, ed. by A. Eshleman (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2008) p.134 Harriet Johnson 76946 6 introduction. Coleridge speaks of the primary and secondary imagination as the fundamental creative power of the mind, and the expression of this power in the phenomenal world. The primary imagination I hold to be the living Power and prime Agent of all human Perception, and as a repetition in the finite mind of the eternal act of creation in the infinite I Am.8 So for Coleridge, the power of the primary imagination is embodied by human beings, as we participate and re-enact God’s creativity; it is a power that provides a connection between the human being and the divine being. The operation of the imagination creates new meaning, ultimately searching for union with the divine; in this way it is a religious act, whether through creation expressed through ritual and the arts, or perception of the eternal revealed in the world. 9 Ritual can have profound meaning for a human being, communicating through symbol and archetypes to the subconscious depths of the mind. This emotional-imaginal faculty is uniquely able to connect with the elements of religious belief which are inaccessible to the conscious rational faculty. The believer’s relationship with God is the focus of religion and faith and one of the ways in which it is developed and nurtured is through engagement in ritual and imaginative connection with scripture, developing and enriching ones personal understanding of the nature of God and one’s own belief. Defenders of faith by ratiocination assume that reasoning is objective only when unaffected by personal interest and desire. Claims that God can be understood by excluding our passional nature from the process of reasoning reject the epistemically beneficial effects of exploration of the subjective experience which have been communicated by Otto, Kierkegaard and Coleridge in this essay. The complexity of religious belief as experienced by the believer, with its many emotional, experiential and imaginal dimensions is missed when approaching religious belief only via reason. Reasoning capitalises on the necessary conceptual distinctions drawn by the use of language and any attempt to conceptualise the nature of religious belief is an attempt to delimit it and put it in some 8 Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Biographia Literaria, chapter XIII, Project Gutenberg, 2004, <http://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/6081/pg6081.html> 9 Sandra M. Levy, Imagination and the Journey of Faith, (Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2008) Harriet Johnson 76946 7 sort of a framework. Attempts to defend religious belief in this way fail to account for the fact that the nature of the divine is wholly other and will not be compromised in order to fit into some pre-defined structure of knowledge. Instead we must respect the limits of our human capacity for reasoning and make use of what is accessible to us; our own individual experience of the divine, expressed by Otto as a feeling of mysterium tremendum, and Kierkegaard as our subjective relationship with God. Bibliography Carr, K. L., and Ivanhoe, P. J., Antirationalism in Zhuangzi and Kierkegaard, in Readings in Philosophy of Religion: East Meets West, ed. by A. Eshleman (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2008) Coleridge, S. T., Biographia Literaria, chapter XIII, Project Gutenberg, 2004, <http://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/6081/pg6081.html> Eshleman, A., The Rationality of Religious Belief in the Absence of Evidence, in Readings in Philosophy of Religion: East Meets West, ed. by A. Eshleman (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2008) James, W., The Reality of the Unseen from The Varieties of Religious Experience, in God (Second Edition), ed. by T. A. Robinson (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2002) James, W., The Will to Believe, in Readings in Philosophy of Religion: East Meets West, ed. by A. Eshleman (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2008) Kierkegaard, S., Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. D. F. Swenson and W. Lowrie, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974) Kierkegaard, S., Truth is Subjectivity, in Readings in Philosophy of Religion: East Meets West, ed. by A. Eshleman (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2008) Macquarrie, J., Twentieth Century Religious Thought, (London: SCM Press, 2001) Mulhall, S., Faith and Reason, (London: Duckworth, 1994) Otto, R., The Idea of the Holy: An Enquiry into the Non-rational Factor in the Idea of the Divine and its relation to the Rational, trans. John W. Harvey, (London: Oxford University Press, 1923) Wainwright, W. J., Reason and the Heart, (New York: Cornell University Press, 1995) Harriet Johnson 76946 Word Count : 2284 8