Principles-based standards and judgement Ian Dennis Business School Oxford Brookes University Abstract Although there is considerable support for the idea that a financial reporting system should be based upon ‘principles-based’ standards, progress in achieving this end has been slow. This paper argues that one of the reasons for the lack of progress is the vagueness of the idea of standards being ‘principles-based’. The characteristics of such standards are identified through a conceptual enquiry into how standard setters, regulators and academics explain their nature. Superficial agreement on these characteristics masks disagreement about the reasons why these characteristics are thought to be desirable. These depend upon underlying assumptions about the nature of prescriptions in standards and about the purpose of providing implementation guidance in an accounting standard. The apparent agreement that ‘principles-based’ standards are a good thing is facilitated by the fact that this concept refers to a ‘boundary object’. With such concepts common characteristics allow for communication between parties who have different underlying interests and start from different assumptions about how those interests can be achieved. The failure to agree on these assumptions manifests itself in disagreement in the application of the concept to particular standards. This means that the concept is vague. Boundary objects may be useful for certain purposes, including political ones, but are not helpful in achieving the objectives of the current project of converging accounting standards. The paper concludes that a debate about fundamental issues about standard setting and accounting standards would be facilitated if the concept of ‘principles-based’ standards was abandoned. Key words: Accounting standards; boundary objects; judgement; principles-based standards; standard setting Contact address: Dr Ian Dennis Senior Lecturer in Accounting and Finance, Oxford Brookes University Business School, Wheatley Campus, Wheatley , Oxford OX33 1HX. Tel. (01865) 485957 Email: iddennis@brookes.ac.uk 1 1. Introduction It is a truth (that ought to be) universally acknowledged1, that if there is agreement on an accounting proposition then it must be expressed in language that is vague. One small piece of evidence to support this truth is provided by the debate about ‘principles-based’ versus ‘rules-based’ standards. That ‘principles-based’ standards are fairly universally supported is well documented. The Institute of Chartered Accountants in Scotland (ICAS) state that in interviews with professional accountants they found ‘almost unanimous agreement for principles-based accounting’ (ICAS, 2007, p. 1). Both the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) and the U.S. Financial Accounting Standards Board (FASB) claim to support the idea of ‘principles-based’ standards (SEC, 2003; FASB, 2004). The International Accounting Standards Board (IASB) states that its objectives are ‘to develop, in the public interest, a single set of high quality, understandable, enforceable and globally accepted financial reporting standards based on clearly articulated principles’ (IASB, 2011, §6). Acknowledging support for the proposition that ‘principles-based’ standards are the ideal kind of standards, the ICAS seem mystified by the fact that ‘we can’t get there’ and that standard setters appear to be moving towards ‘rules-based’ accounting standards rather than embracing ‘principlesbased’ ones (ICAS, 2007, p. 1). A survey of members of ICAS in 2011 revealed that 72% of them believed that International Financial Reporting Standards (IFRS) were very rules dominated and 67% believed that IFRS were more weighted to rules than they were five years ago. They also believed that the financial crisis and the move to convergence with the U.S. would result in more, rather than fewer, rules. The apparent support for ‘principles-based’ standards is just that – apparent. Standard setters may be cynically announcing that standards of this kind are best but in practice seeking to promulgate standards that are ‘rules-based’. Standard setting is a political process and subject to intensive lobbying by pressure groups (Armstrong, 1977; Zeff, 1978; Dopuch and Sunder, 1980). The U.S. system of standard setting is seen as ‘rulesbased’ (SEC, 2003, p. 10). One reason for this is that the SEC as an ‘enforcement agency’ that leads auditors ‘to protect themselves from litigation by encouraging the setting of 1 With apologies to Jane Austen. 2 clear and detailed rules’ (Nobes, 2005, p. 26). The ‘litigious situation in the United States…means that the risk of law suits based on alleged wrong accounting is high and gives accountants a strong incentive to ask for rules they can adhere to in case of a costly law suit’ (Benston et al, 2006, p. 168). This pulls U.S. standard setters away from a commitment to the ‘principles-based’ standards that the IASB is committed to and towards ‘rules-based’ standards. This creates a problem for under the Norwalk Agreement both Boards are committed to the convergence of accounting standards (FASB/IASB, 2002) and a common goal was established by the FASB and the IASB for their accounting standards ‘to be “principles-based.”’ (FASB/IASB, 2005, p. 1). No wonder they appear to say one thing but do another. Another, more charitable, explanation for what is happening is that the expression ‘principles-based’ standards ‘still seems to mean very different things to different people’ (Cairns, 2011, p. 71). Standard setters may promulgate standards that they conceive of as ‘principles-based’ but these standards may not be perceived to be of this kind by others. The SEC acknowledges that the categories of ‘principles-based’ and ‘rules-based’ standards are ‘not well defined and, therefore, are subject to a wide variety of interpretations’ (SEC, 2003, p. 5). The concepts are vague which means ‘there is in the practice of its application, significant disagreements about what uses of it are correct’ (Baker and Hacker, 1980, p. 218). Standard setters who claim standards are ‘principlesbased’ may simply be applying the term differently from others who judge that accounting standards are not of this kind. This paper examines whether the concept of a standard being ‘principles-based’ is vague. This is to conduct a conceptual enquiry into this concept in the sense explained in the section about theoretical frameworks. The paper considers the objectives that might underlie the construction of a concept of standards that are ‘principles-based’. It then goes on to look at the explanations of this concept that are given by regulators, professional bodies and accounting academics. It considers whether apparent agreement in explanations actually masks disagreements in the application of the term to accounting standards because the explanations themselves may be variously understood. It examines 3 whether one reason for the differences in understanding might lie in the underlying assumptions that are made about accounting standards and how they are to be followed. These are identified by looking at two problems of standard setting and how underlying assumptions about how they are to be dealt with may differ. Superficial agreement on the meaning of the expression ‘principles-based’ masks underlying disagreement in the kind of things they apply to. The paper then considers whether this arises because the concepts used in the ‘principles versus rules’ debate are ‘boundary objects’. It considers whether such concepts are adopted to present the appearance of agreement in concepts where the concept is, in fact, vague. Such concepts facilitate communication between parties with different underlying interests. The paper examines the idea that the concept of ‘principles-based’ standards may be adopted for political reasons as part of a strategy in the battle for control over global standard setting and as a means of accommodating the interests of lobbyists. It concludes by asking whether a concept of standards being ‘principles-based’ actually provides a useful ‘road map’ for standard setters and whether it can support the weight of the convergence project. In place of the commitment to such standards it urges debate about the underlying assumptions about standard setting in an effort to identify the qualities of good standards. The next section of the paper sets out the theoretical framework used in the paper. 2. Theoretical frameworks: Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Language and Social Constructivism The method used in the paper is derived from the philosophical approach adopted by Wittgenstein. His philosophical method might be called conceptual enquiry (Dennis, 2008). In modern philosophy, in general, and in the philosophy of Wittgenstein in particular, the idea of a concept is generally equated with the meanings of words (Craig, 2005, p. 135). An enquiry into concepts is thus to be understood as an enquiry into the meaning of words or expressions. Wittgenstein suggests that ‘the meaning of a word is what is explained by the explanation of the meaning’ (Wittgenstein, 1953, §560). An explanation of the meaning of a word is something that gives a rule for the use of the word. (Baker and Hacker, 1980, p. 35). A conceptual enquiry thus seeks to identify the rules for the use of the word or expression that are followed by those who use it. The 4 objective of a descriptive conceptual enquiry is to determine whether those who use the word or expression follow the same rules. This is shown by whether they give the same explanations of the expression, that is whether they give the same rule in explaining its meaning, and whether they agree on the application of the expression to the same things (Baker and Hacker, 1985, p. 244). If the same explanations are given but the rules for meaning are applied differently then the concepts used are different and there is no common understanding of what it is to be a thing of this kind. Undertaking a descriptive conceptual enquiry into the concept of being ‘principles-based’ involves looking at the explanations of the meaning of this expression and determining whether there is an agreed understanding of what constitutes a ‘principles-based’ standard. The explanations of the term that given by regulators, standard setters and academics are examined. Where there is evidence that the same explanations do not result in the application of the term to the same things then further examination of the expressions used in the explanation may be undertaken. Explanations of the meaning of expressions are given in language by using other expressions (Baker and Hacker, 1980, p. 32) and the rules for the use of these other expressions may not be agreed. This may account for the apparent agreement in meaning of the original expression but, in fact, conceals differences in understanding it. It is worth considering why differences in understanding of expressions arise. Wittgenstein adopted, what has been called, a ‘naturalistic’ view of language. This is the idea that language ‘develops over millennia to fit our needs. As something arises that we need to mark off, so we develop, by a linguistic reflex, as it were…to mark distinctions that it seemed important to us to make’. It follows that ‘to understand the meaning of any term is to understand those human interests, needs and practices in the context of which it arose and into which it fits’ (Lyas, 1993, p. 163). Concepts are created and do not just happen. To understand why a concept has been created, why a certain meaning or rule for the use of the expression has been established, it is important to grasp the objectives or desires that prompted it creation. This is a key assumption that is also made in the literature on social construction. The underlying idea is that the concepts we use are 5 shaped by us and not found in nature (Young, 2006, p. 581). Where there are different explanations of the meaning of expressions or where the explanations are understood differently this may be because the underlying ‘interests, needs and practices’ that prompt the development of the concept are different. A conceptual enquiry into ‘principlesbased’ standards tries to understand why the concept may be understood differently by different parties to the ‘principles versus rules’ debate. Before the detailed explanations of the concept of ‘principles-based’ standards are examined it is worth briefly reviewing the context in which the idea of a kind of standard is constructed. 3. Why construct the concept of standards that are ‘principles-based’? Accounting standards are promulgated in order to help to achieve the objectives of financial reporting. These objectives are realized by producing information that meets the objectives of financial reporting and has certain qualitative characteristics set out in the conceptual framework (CF). These include the fundamental qualitative characteristics of relevance and faithful representation and enhancing characteristics such as comparability, verifiability, timeliness and understandability (IASB, 2010). The concept of a kind of standard, that is one that is ‘principles-based’, is useful if it assists in producing useful financial information that achieves the objectives and characteristics. Identifying the ideal standard is meant to assist in the promulgation of useful standards. As a result of scandals such as Enron it was believed by some interested parties that part of cause of the collapse of the company was that accounting standards were not useful. Instead of the ideal kind of standard ‘rules-based’ standards predominated. This did not achieve the objectives and qualitative characteristics of useful financial information. The SEC was mandated by the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 to conduct a study into the approach to standard setting adopted in the U.S. The conclusion of this study was that ‘principles-based’ or ‘objectives-oriented’ standards are better than ‘rules-based’ or ‘principles-only’ standards (SEC, 2003, p. 4-5). 6 ‘Rules-based’ standards are sometimes favoured because it is suggested that they help to achieve the qualitative characteristic of comparability in financial reporting. Others argue that they do not and argue, as an example, that the ‘bright line’ tests that distinguish circumstances where pooling of interests was possible and those where it was not result in very different financial reporting for two circumstances which are basically the same (SEC, 2003, p. 18). As Schipper points out ‘the desire to achieve comparability and its over-time counterpart, consistency, is the reason to have reporting standards. That is…similar things are accounted for the same way’ (Schipper, 2003, p. 62). At least one objective of inventing a concept of ‘principles-based’ standards, then, is to create a kind of standard that will better achieve comparability. The characteristics of standards that achieve comparability are used in the definition of ‘principles-based’ standards. Comparability is one of the ‘interests’ that underpin the construction of the concept. Other arguments in favour or against different kinds of standards begin with a desire to achieve other qualitative characteristics of useful financial information such as relevance or faithful representation. It has been argued that ‘principles-based’ standards do not help to achieve these other characteristics even if they do improve comparability (Alexander and Jermakowicz, 2006; Wüstemann and Wüstemann, 2010). This may lead to questioning whether the concept of a particular kind of standard is actually useful in so far as it may not be able to meet all of the desires that prompt its development. Before any analysis of whether a concept of a kind of standard is useful the characteristics of such standards need to be examined. To this end a review of the explanations of ‘principles-based’ standards will be undertaken. 4. A descriptive conceptual enquiry into the concept of ‘principles-based’ standards One influential explanation of the ‘principles-based’ approach to standard setting is provided by the report of the Principles versus Rules Working Group set up by ICAS. It states that ‘principles-based’ accounting standards are based on a conceptual framework (ICAS 2006, p. 1). They go on to say that such standards ‘require a clear hierarchy of overarching concepts, principles that reflect the overarching concepts and limited further guidance’ (ICAS, 2006, p. 7). They define a principle as ‘a general statement, with 7 widespread support, which is intended to support truth and fairness and acts as a guide to action.’ They go on to say that ‘principles cannot be replaced by mechanical rules’ (ICAS, 2006, p. 4). This explanation of the nature of ‘principles-based’ standards is deficient in a number of ways. The characteristics that are meant to identify such standards flow seamlessly between those that identify standards that are ‘based on principles’ and standards that express ‘principles’. These are two distinct concepts of being ‘principles-based’. One involves the idea of standards which are derived from a standard setting process that starts by considering ‘principles’ of the kind expressed in a CF. Another concept involves the idea that standards have certain qualities, that is they express prescriptions that might be called ‘principles’ (Dennis, 2008). Standards can be ‘principles-based’ in that they are ‘based on principles’ but still not be ‘principles-based’ in that they do not have other characteristics that define such standards (Schipper, 2003, p. 62). The desire for standards ‘based on principles’ in a CF might be related to the objective of consistency. The FASB originally described the idea of a CF as ‘a coherent system of interrelated objectives and fundamentals that can lead to consistent standards and that prescribes the nature, function, and limits of financial accounting and financial statements’ (FASB, 1976, p. 2). In order to achieve this the fundamental concepts in the CF ‘need to constitute a framework that is sound, comprehensive, and internally consistent’ (FASB/IASB, 2005, Revisiting the Concepts, p. 1). It has been suggested that there are two kinds of consistency that are recognized in the accounting literature. The first is the ‘internal consistency of accounting standards’ which is the idea that any individual standards should be consistent with the existing system of standards. The second is the ‘consistency in the application of those standards’ which means that the standards are applied in the same way from period to period in a single entity or between entities (Wüstemann and Wüstemann, 2010, p. 2). The requirement to base standards on a CF appears to aim for the first kind of consistency. If a CF justifies two particular standards and it is not possible to follow both of them in the same circumstances then the CF is inconsistent. The consistency of a CF is thus conceptually related to the consistency 8 of the standards derived from it. If one has a consistent CF this means that one has a CF from which only consistent standards can be derived. This idea of the consistency of a CF makes sense if a CF is used in a deductive system. In such a system standards are derived by a deductive argument from ‘principles’ in the CF. With deductive arguments ‘given two valid deductions with incompatible conclusions, their premises must also be compatible’ (Salmon, 1992, p. 26). If the principles in a CF enable the deduction of standards that are incompatible, inconsistent in the first sense, then so must the ‘principles’ be inconsistent. Standards have to be consistent if deduced from a CF which is consistent since a CF being consistent simply means enabling the deduction of consistent standards. A lot can be said against such a picture of a CF and there is no space to consider all of the arguments here. The ideal of a CF as something to be used in a deductive system, which appears to be implied by the FASB characterization above has been seen as an important one in the development of CFs (Power, 1993). Against this picture is the idea that the ‘principles’ in a CF are not to be used in deductive arguments to accounting standards but that some other kind of argument, perhaps involving ‘practical reasoning’ (Dennis, 2010) or ‘instrumental’ reasoning (Mattessich, 1995), is used to derive, rather than deduce, standards from such a framework. Practical reasoning is similar to inductive reasoning, and unlike deductive reasoning, in that it is not the case that incompatible conclusions must have incompatible premises (Salmon, 1992, p. 25). One problem in understanding the arguments about the nature of the derivation of standards from principles in a CF is that in the explanations of deductive reasoning the ‘consistency’ of premises is understood in terms of truth. The incompatibility of the conclusions of two deductive arguments is understood as the fact that both cannot be true. This suggests incompatibility of the premises also means that both cannot be true. In the context of accounting standards if it is standards that are deduced then they are not true or false. Prescriptions are not the kind of things that can be true or false. Prescriptions are inconsistent if they cannot both be followed. Is the idea of the inconsistency of principles in a CF also to be understood in similar terms? This means that the principles in a CF 9 cannot both be followed. This raises the question of what it is to ‘follow’ a principle. Are principles, like standards, some kind of prescription? Is this how principles in a CF are to be understood though? They might be understood as objectives or desires that financial reporting is meant to fulfil. The history of the search for ‘principles’ in the twentieth century shows equivocation between viewing principles as prescriptions and as expressions of desire. It is no wonder that little help was derived from looking back at the ‘principles and postulates’ debate of the 1960s and 1970s (ICAS, 2006, p. 4). This has a knock-on effect in trying to understand what it means to say that standards are ‘based on’ principles. The derivation of standards from ‘principles’ can be understood as the deduction of standards, understood as specific prescriptions, from general prescriptions or as the derivation of standards from considerations of what is wanted from financial reporting using practical or instrumental reasoning. The ICAS should perhaps have learned the lesson of history and avoided entanglement with ‘principles’. Their own definition is so vague that the nature of ‘principles’ is scarcely indicated. The ICAS definition does not explain what kind of ‘general statement’ a ‘principle’ is supposed to be. It could mean a general prescription of what is to be done or else a general desire that is wanted all or most of the time. The fact that a ‘principle’ is a ‘guide to action’ does not distinguish the sense in which prescriptions guide actions from the sense in which desires guide actions. How prescriptions ‘support truth and fairness’ is not clear. Does this mean that by following the prescriptions, doing what is required, truth and fairness in financial reporting results? Are the ‘principles’ supposed to guide the standard setter in producing prescriptions that, if followed, result in truth and fairness? The same equivocation between prescriptions and desires is evident in Alexander’s description of different types of criteria used in approaches to determining the adequacy of financial statements (Alexander, 1999). It is not clear whether ‘Type A’ criteria, that is ‘a generally expressed all-pervasive fundamental concept’ (Alexander, 1999, p. 240), are prescriptions or desires. Nobes equates these, and also ‘Type B’ criteria, that is ‘a set of rules, conventions or ways of thinking which are to be consistently applied to situations both familiar or unfamiliar’ (Alexander, 1999, p. 240), with ‘principles’ (Nobes, 2005, p. 10 26). This is mysterious since ‘concepts’ would appear to be a rather different kind of thing to ‘rules’ or ‘conventions’. The FASB calls their CF ‘statements of financial accounting concepts’. The UK Accounting Standards Board calls their CF a ‘statement of principles’. Both are unclear as to what kind of thing their statements’ state. This has a knock-on effect in understanding of what it means to say that standards are ‘based on’ principles. There is also a more general question of whether ‘principles’ in standards are meant to be the same kind of thing as ‘principles’ in CFs. A ‘principles-based’ standard might be one that sets out desires of the kind that are included in CFs or it might be one that includes prescriptions of a certain kind. It is not clear whether CFs also include prescriptions. The shift between these two meanings in discussion of ‘principles’ both in standards and in CFs results in a lack of clarity and difficulty in understanding whether someone using the term is talking about one or the other kind of thing when referring to ‘principles’ in the CF or in standards. The ICAS pamphlet rather hurries on to the question of the characteristics of the prescriptions that appear in accounting. Two kinds of prescription are identified which are called, respectively, ‘rules’ and ‘principles’. Most of the study relates to a discussion of the relative merits of these two kinds of prescription. The views of those interviewed for the study are solicited about the relative merits of each but there is little detailed exploration of what the interviewees actually mean by the word ‘principle’. This undermines the message derived from the interviews. The interviewees were largely supportive of the idea that standards should include ‘principles’ rather than ‘rules’ but it is not clear exactly what they had in mind in giving such support. Despite the problems in understanding the nature of principles and what it means for standards to be ‘based on’ them there considerable support for idea that standards should be based on principles. The alternative of promulgating ‘ad hoc’ standards or standards ‘based on’ the political interests of various lobbying groups is not attractive. Most would agree that any reasonable accounting standard should, in some sense, have this characteristic. This suggests that being ‘based on’ a CF is not a characteristic that 11 differentiates one kind of standard from another in any other sense than that it differentiates ‘ad hoc’ from reasoned standards. The characteristics that differentiate prescriptions in standards between ‘rules’ and ‘principles’ are implied by the characterization of ‘principles-based’ standards set out in the SEC Study. They attempt to rectify the problem of vagueness in the terms they acknowledge by defining a ‘principles-based’ standard as one that: i) includes a ‘concise’ statement of ‘substantive accounting principle’ that ‘incorporates’ the ‘accounting objective’ ii) includes few, if any ‘exceptions or internal inconsistencies’ iii) provides an ‘appropriate amount of implementation guidance’ iv) is devoid of ‘bright-line tests’ v) is ‘consistent with, and derived from, a coherent conceptual framework’ (SEC, 2003, p. 12). The implication of this characterisation is that ‘principles-based’ standards are those that are ‘based on principles’ in a CF, include a statement of the objective of the standard and include prescriptions that have the characteristics set out in ii) to iv). To the characteristics identified by the SEC might be added another that is identified by ICAS, namely that ‘principles-based’ standards should: vi) allow for the exercise of judgement (ICAS, 2006, p.1) This final characteristic has support elsewhere (Schipper, 2003, p. 61; FASB, 2002). This explanation of ‘principles-based’ standards also suffers from the problem of understanding the sense in which standards are ‘derived from’ a CF and understanding the nature of ‘principles’. Other issues are also raised by the SEC’s explanation. What is meant by the words ‘few’ or ‘appropriate’ in the expression of the characteristics? It is 12 not clear whether all of these characteristics have to be present if a standard is to be said to be ‘principles-based’ (Dennis, 2008, p. 266). The SEC recognizes that some standards might be called ‘principles-based’ even if they do not have all of the characteristics of being ‘principles-based’. These characteristics are thus not necessary conditions for a standard to be ‘principles-based’. The SEC refer to this concept as an ‘ideal variant’ which means that standards of this kind may have most but not all of the characteristics. They recognize that standards may only ‘approach’ the ideal (SEC, 2003, p. 24). It has been suggested that the concepts of being ‘principles-based’ and ‘rules-based’ form ‘a continuum’ (AAA, 2003, p. 74). A similar problem exists in the area of Law. These concepts have been described as ‘crude’ (Cunningham, 2007, p. 1413) and ‘imperfect’ (Cunningham, 2007, p. 1492). It is suggested that ‘accounting systems, like corporate law and securities regulation, defy tidy classification as rules-based or principles-based’ (Cunningham, 2007, p. 1460). Given that these characteristics are not necessary conditions, standards can be called ‘principles-based’ if they have only some of the characteristics. The perception of the relative importance of these characteristics may vary. Standards that are ‘principles-based’ can have different collections of such characteristics and one group of standard setters and professional using this expression can have a different collection in mind when they refer to a standard as ‘principles-based’ than another group. There is no ‘checklist’ of characteristics that has to be ticked before a standard can be termed ‘principles-based’. If there are different practices in using the expression amongst different people the term is vague. This does not necessarily mean that the concept is not useful for some purposes. The characteristics identified by the SEC for ‘principles-based’ standards may be ‘a sensible and desirable list of characteristics and admonitions’ that amounts to something of a ‘wish list’ (Benston et al., 2006, p. 170). No standard has to have all of these characteristics to count as ‘principles-based’. The problem is that different people may have a different ‘wish list’ in mind when they consider whether or not a standard is ‘principles-based’. This can become important. Standard setters who are trying to converge their accounting standards, as the IASB and the FASB are attempting at the present time, may find difficulty in achieving convergence if there is no common ‘wish 13 list’ of characteristics. A particular standard with a particular set of characteristics may be acceptable to one and not to another. The problem of agreeing on the characteristics of ‘principles-based’ standards results from different assumptions that are made in dealing with problems of standard setting. These will now be explored. 5. Problems of standard setting i) Problem 1: exceptions The first problem to be considered is what to do when the standard setter realizes that following a standard will not always meet the objectives of the standards, that is the objectives set out in the CF that are meant to be achieved by the promulgation of accounting standards. Some standard setters may think that such a problem does not arise because standards are only promulgated when they will achieve these objectives on every occasion when they are to be followed. No solution is required to the problem because there is no problem. This kind of claim appears to be made by the SEC who argue that ‘it is…precisely the role of the standard setter to define the class of transactions included within the economic arrangement and then to establish the appropriate accounting for that class of transactions. While not everyone will agree with the standards setter’s conclusions, making the determination of the underlying economics of an arrangement and the appropriate accounting for that arrangement are integral to the standard setter’s role’ (SEC, 2003, p. 32). The ‘underlying economics of the arrangement’ is, presumably, what would be shown if financial statements are ‘representationally faithful’. What is being argued is that the standard setter sets standards that result in financial information that is representationally faithful and, hence, meets one of the fundamental qualitative characteristics of useful information in the CF. There is a problem if the belief that standard setters are clever enough to avoid the problem of standards that will not always meet the objectives is rejected. The belief that following accounting standards can result in portraying ‘economic arrangements in a way that omits nothing of relevance to investors, creditors and other users, and can specify and effectively deal with how these 14 should be accounted for’ has been called an ‘impossible dream’ (Benston et al., 2006, p. 177). There is also the problem that different accounting standards may require conflicting accounting treatment in certain circumstances. Those following such standards cannot do both. It was suggested above that a ‘consistent’ CF is not an answer to this problem. Inconsistencies may still arise where the reasoning to promulgating standards is not deductive. A solution to both problems is to include exceptions in a standard. These exceptions exclude from the requirements in a standard those circumstances where following them will not achieve the characteristics or where meeting the requirements of a standard conflict with meeting the requirements of another standard that would require different treatment. In order to adopt this approach the standard setter would need to be able to predict the circumstances where either of these problems will occur. Against this solution it can be argued that including exceptions creates further problems. It may result in ‘inconsistencies in accounting treatment of transactions and events with similar economic substance’ (SEC, 2003, p. 11). If including exceptions meets the characteristics of relevance and representational faithfulness, including exceptions may undermine the characteristic of consistency. The CF is supposed to have an answer to this problem. Standard setters need to look for relevant information first, then consider whether following the standard will result in faithful representation (IASB, 2010, QC18). If so then they consider whether comparability enhances these fundamental characteristics. This makes it look like an ‘on/off’ switch for relevance and faithful representation. What if a standard will not always result in relevant information that is a faithful representation but mostly does so? Are standard setters meant to look for another solution where this does not happen? What if there is no other solution, that is, there is no standard that will always meet these characteristics? Promulgating a standard which will mostly meet these characteristics but on occasion will not might be a better standard than any other one. The standard setter may simply accept the failure to meet the characteristics on all occasions and not worry about it. However, this solution undermines the commitment to meeting the qualitative characteristics if this is understood as meeting them on all occasion where standards are followed. Is there another solution? 15 There is a solution that starts with acceptance of the need to meet the qualitative characteristics whenever a standard is followed but does not include exceptions but instead allows those who follow the standard to override it where following the requirements will not achieve the objectives of the standard or where there are conflicting standards. This solution invites them to decide on whether or not to override the standard, that is, to allow them to exercise judgement. In this context ‘judgement’ is understood along the lines of the report Professional Judgment in Financial Reporting. ‘Judgement’ is defined as ‘the process of making a choice, a decision, leading to action’ (CICA, 1988, p. 4). This seems a reasonable description of what is going on in the decision as to whether or not to override the standard. The characteristics of exercising judgement are used to identify standards as ‘principles- based’ according to ICAS and others. Including exceptions is to give the job of exercising judgement to standard setters. The link between the override and a ‘principles-based’ approach has been made in the academic literature (Alexander and Jermakowicz, 2006; Benston et al., 2006, p. 167). It has been observed that ‘the suggestion by many commentators…that the IRFS regime is principles- rather than rule-based…gives reason to imagine that such a distinction is underpinned by the qualitative criterion, ‘true and fair view’ (or its equivalent) legal or professional override’ (Dean and Clarke, 2005, p. 1). The possibility of a solution of allowing the override depends upon the jurisdiction in which the standard is followed. This, in turn, depends upon the particular conception of the prescriptions in standards that is adopted in that jurisdiction. One issue that lies behind this adoption is whether or not those who follow the standards can be trusted to implement the override and whether their judgements are or are not open to challenge in the courts or by regulators. Different standard setters may have different attitudes to both of these matters. Whether or not an override is allowed depends upon the conception of prescriptions adopted in a jurisdiction (Dennis, 2010). Rawls identified two conceptions that might apply. With prescriptions, or as Rawls refers to them ‘rules’, that are ‘rules of thumb’ ‘each person is in principle always entitled to reconsider the correctness of a rule and to question whether or not it is proper to follow it in a particular case’ (Rawls, 1955, p. 16 161). In other words, an override is allowed. With prescriptions on the ‘practice’ conception accepting the prescription ‘necessarily involves the abdication of full liberty to act on utilitarian and prudential grounds’ (Rawls 1955, p. 162). In other words, the prescription is to be followed whether or not, in particular circumstances, it will fulfilled the objectives that prompt its promulgation. The rule is not to be overridden. Some prescriptions fit one conception while some fit the other. What kind of prescription is included in accounting standards? In the UK the requirement of the Companies Acts allows companies to override the rules in standards where following them will not result in a true and fair view (TFV). The UK conceives prescriptions as ‘rules of thumb’. In the U.S. listed companies are required to ‘present fairly’ their results and financial position and the auditors report includes the statement that the financial statements ‘presents fairly’. Zeff (1990) argues that the idea of a TFV is not the same as the U.S. ‘presents fairly’ in the auditor report. The words ‘presents fairly’ never stand alone but are always seen in conjunction with ‘generally accepted accounting principles’. For this reason the ‘TFV legal requirement with its override implications has not been adopted in the U.S. regulatory system’ (Alexander & Jermakowicz, 2006, p. 144). Rule 203 of the AICPA Code of Professional Conduct allows departure from GAAP in ‘unusual circumstances’ and says that it ‘is a matter of professional judgment’ to determine what circumstances warrant such a departure (Alexander & Jermakowicz, 2006, p. 145). However, van Hulle noted that ‘the representative of the SEC argued that – although there is an override test in the auditing standards in the US – no registrant with the SEC had ever applied the override in its financial statements’ (van Hulle, 1997, p. 718). In effect, there is no override of accounting standards in the U.S. Rules are conceived on the ‘practice’ conception. The move to a ‘principles-based’ in the U.S. does not appear to be proceeding by changing the conception of prescriptions from those on the ‘practice’ conception to those conceived of as ‘rules of thumb’. The SEC rejects the view that ‘a necessary component of principles-based standards is the inclusion of a “true and fair override”’ (SEC, 2003, p. 32). This contradicts the view of some academic commentators who argue for a connection between the override and ‘principles-based’ standards. 17 The position with respect to international accounting standards and to jurisdictions applying them in the European Union (EU) is not so clear cut. Although there is a similar override in the Fourth Directive of the EU and an override is allowed in IAS 1 it is not clear whether this is interpreted as similar to the UK’s override or closer to the U.S. position. It has been suggested that it is likely to be differently interpreted in different jurisdictions within the EU and who follow international accounting standards (Evans, 2003). It is thus unclear whether accounting standards as conceived by the IASB and adopted by the EU include prescriptions that are ‘rules of thumb’ or conceived on the ‘practice’ conception and consequently on the kind of judgement that may be exercised. It appears rather strange that the project to converge accounting standards could proceed without agreement on the fundamental question of the conception of prescriptions in standards. How can there be agreement on the characteristics of the ideal standards without agreement on this underlying assumption about prescriptions contained in them? If a standard setter promulgates a standard for jurisdictions where there is an override and where they think of standards as ‘rules of thumb’ they may agree that standards require few, if any exceptions. One standard setter may think that ‘principles-based’ standards require an override and for this reason no exceptions are needed for standards of this kind. If another standard setter promulgates a prescription for a jurisdiction where there is no override and they think of standards as on the ‘practice’ conception but they believe that they are clever enough to promulgate standards where there are no circumstances where following the standard will not meet the objectives or that, if there are, then they do not matter then they too will agree that standards require few, if any exceptions. Their conception of ‘principles-based’ standards may not imply the need for an override. There can be still be agreement that a standard is of the ‘principles-based’ in that it requires few, if any exceptions without thinking that such standards must allow an override. The problem is that this agreement on standards of the kind that do not need exceptions can break down when a new standard is proposed where it is not possible to promulgate a standard that meets the objectives on all occasions and where this matters or on whether standards can be ‘crafted so that they exclude contradictions’ (Benston et al., 2006, p. 18 177). It may be difficult to obtain agreement on how to revise existing standards which contain exceptions. In such circumstances the second standard setter may well feel that exceptions are needed whereas the first standard setter may not. The apparent consensus breaks down. The reason for this is that the underlying assumptions about standards are different. True convergence may not be possible without convergence on these underlying assumptions about the nature of prescriptions in standards. ii) Problem 2: implementation guidance As with the previous characteristic of ‘principles-based’ standards of including few exceptions, the reasons for thinking that such standards should provide an appropriate amount of implementation guidance and should be devoid of ‘bright-line tests’ need to be grasped. Accounting standards are expressed in language. If there is to be agreement in understanding what the standard requires accountants to do then there must be agreement about the meaning of the expressions used to communicate the requirements, that is, about what is in accord with the prescription (Baker and Hacker, 1985, Ch. 111). Expressions must not be vague. Where there is evidence that the rule is explained differently or where the rule is followed differently then this may be overcome by the inclusion of implementation guidance in the standard. Guidance of this kind explains the meaning of the expressions used to express the requirement in the standard and should result in different parties meeting the requirement by doing the same thing. If the language used in a standard is not vague then no guidance is required. The appropriate’ amount of implementation guidance would be none. There is an argument in the accounting literature that all language is vague (Brown et al., 1993). The origin of this idea is said to be in the philosophy of Wittgenstein. In fact, this has been referred to as a ‘caricature’ of the ideas in Wittgenstein’s later work and ‘radically misconceived’ (Baker and Hacker, 1980, pp. 215-217). Although he did not deny that some language is vague he did not insist that all language is vague. Actual vagueness arises where there are actual disagreements in the practice of explaining or using language. This is not always the case. As Wittgenstein puts it ‘the sign-post is in order – if, under normal circumstances, it fulfils its purpose’ (Wittgenstein, 1953, §87). 19 Wittgenstein’s actual argument is that no language is immune from possible vagueness. Possible vagueness arises where it is possible that there will, in some circumstances where it is used, be disagreements in explanations or in using the language. What he was suggesting was that no language has ‘determinacy of sense’. If an expression has ‘determinacy of sense’ then an explanation of the expression would enable someone to determine whether or not the expression applies to any particular object or state of affairs (Baker and Hacker, 1980, p. 210). In the context of accounting standards this would mean that someone who understood the language used to express a requirement would know what is in accord with the requirement in any circumstance. This has been claimed to be one of the objectives of a ‘rules-based approach’ to formulating accounting standards. The implementation guidance has as it objective to ‘minimize (and in certain instances to trivialize) the judgmental component of accounting practice through the establishment of complicated, finely articulated rules that attempt to foresee all possible application challenges’ (SEC, 2003, p. 15). It is designed to eliminate possible vagueness and to achieve ‘determinacy of sense’. The SEC appears to accept that, as Wittgenstein suggests, no language has ‘determinacy of sense’. They argue that ‘it is simply impossible to fully eliminate professional judgment in the application of accounting standards’ (SEC, 2003, p. 16). Interestingly, it is sometimes thought that the use of ‘bright-line tests’ can achieve this ideal. Requirements that include such tests involve numbers and it is thought that these have ‘determinacy of sense’. If the objective of standard setters is to eliminate possible vagueness then the use of ‘bright-line tests’ is understandable. The problem with such tests is that they undermine comparability. Very similar circumstances are treated differently if they fall on different sides of the ‘bright-line’ (SEC, 2003, p. 18). It looks as though a choice has to be made between the objective of ‘determinacy of sense’ and comparability. ‘Rules-based’ standards give more weight to determinacy of sense whereas ‘principles-based’ standards give more weight to comparability. 20 The underlying issue that should be debated in order to obtain agreement about the nature of standards is the objective of including implementation guidance in an accounting standard. If the objective of such guidance is to eliminate possible vagueness, that is, to achieve ‘determinacy of sense’, then it is not surprising that voluminous amount of implementation guidance is needed. In fact, no amount of guidance will achieve this end. If the objective is to eliminate actual vagueness then less guidance is required. In some cases, none at all is appropriate if there is no actual vagueness in the expressions used to set out the requirements of the standard. There is another possible objective in the provision of implementation guidance. It may be designed to eliminate probable vagueness, that is, where expressions are not actually used in different ways but it is possible to see that they would be in certain foreseeable circumstances. Different amounts of guidance may be appropriate given these different objectives. No agreement on the characteristics of different types of standard can be reached without agreement on the underlying assumption about the objective of implementation guidance. No one would argue against the idea that implementation guidance should be of an ‘appropriate amount’. The real argument is about the objective of such guidance. There is another underlying assumption that also needs to be debated in relation to standards. It is important to agree on how vagueness, of whatever kind, is to be tackled. It does not follow that including implementation guidance is the only solution. Another way of dealing with vagueness is to leave it to the judgement of those meeting the requirements of a standard to determine how the requirements in the standard are to be interpreted in the circumstances where the prescription is to be applied. Interpreting a standard means attributing a meaning to the expressions used to formulate the requirements in the standard. In effect this means determining what the prescription actually is. This does not mean that any meaning can be given to expressions. The meaning of an expression is determined by the practice of using expressions and this cannot be completely ignored. Much depends upon judgements as to whether or not the circumstances in which the prescription is to be applied are similar to those where it is actually applied, that is where there is a practice of applying it. This means that some decision or choices will be required in determining what is in accord with the prescription 21 in the standard. It has been argued that the U.S. system of standard setting does not wish to allow those who follow standards to have such choices. One reason for this has been said to be the existence of the SEC as an ‘enforcement agency’ that leads auditors ‘to protect themselves from litigation by encouraging the setting of clear and detailed rules’ (Nobes, 2005, p. 26). It has been suggested that ‘the litigious situation in the United States…means that the risk of law suits based on alleged wrong accounting is high and gives accountant a strong incentive to ask for rules they can adhere to in case of a costly law suit’ (Benston et al, 2006, p. 168). Leaving decisions or choices to the preparer and auditor, that is leaving them to exercise judgement about what to do in following a standard, opens the possibility of legal challenges to such judgement. It makes it difficult to produce accounting standards with one of the characteristics of ‘principles-based’ standards. This kind of decision is similar to promulgating a standard. In prescribing standards standard setters have to consider the objectives of the standard. Those who follow the standard have to use objectives to do decide on the prescription adopted. There is some room for choice given the expressions and the objectives and this is why interpreting the expressions in a standard counts as an exercise of judgement, albeit constrained. Where judgement in interpretation is allowed then it makes sense, as it did with standards where an override is allowed, to include a ‘concise’ statement of ‘substantive accounting principle’ that ‘incorporates’ the ‘accounting objective’ to guide this interpretation. One can begin to see how the characteristics used to identify ‘principles-based’ standards are relevant to solving this problem. However different underlying assumptions about the problem and its solution may result in different attitudes towards the amount of implementation guidance required as well as the kind of language that is to be used in accounting standards. Agreement on the underlying assumptions is required if there is to be agreement on using this characteristic to promulgate standards. Although all parties in a convergence project may agree that the amount of implementation guide should be appropriate exactly how much should be provided when faced with a standard setting situation will depend upon the underlying assumptions about language and the objectives 22 of providing implementation guidance. Once again, true convergence will not be attained without convergence on the underlying assumptions. Where the characteristics of ‘principles-based’ standards are detached from the underlying reasons for using them then agreement on applying the characteristics to standards is difficult. 6. Detaching characteristics In explaining the override it was stated that those who follow standards have to exercise judgement in deciding not to follow the standard where doing so on a particular occasion will not meet the objectives of the standard. One problem with the idea of exercising judgement is that the explanation of judgement set out by CICA, talking as it does about decisions relating to courses of action, is itself vague. It can be interpreted in different ways given that there are a number of different decisions relating to courses of action that may need to be taken when following the requirements of standards. Two exercises have already been considered in this paper, that is, decisions about an override and decisions about how to interpret the expressions used in a standard. Other decisions may also have to be made in following certain standards. If there is a requirement to make predictions about future cash flows then, in order to follow such a requirement, inductive reasoning may have to be exercised whereby generalizations are used in conjunction with facts about the current circumstances to derive a conclusion about future cash flows. With inductive reasoning the conclusion does not follow necessarily from the premises. Various decisions have to be made about how strong the conclusion has to be and hence how strong the generalizations in inductive reasoning have to be. Deciding whether or not there are other generalizations and facts that undermine the conclusion also involve decisions. These can all be called exercises of judgement. Any kind of standard may requires that such decisions to be made and hence involve an exercise of judgement. This characteristic does not differentiate one kind of standard from another. If such a characteristic is taken to define ‘principles-based’ standards then any standard that requires some kind of exercise of judgement might have some grounds for being referred 23 to as ‘principles-based’. Different people may nonetheless have different kinds of exercise of judgement in mind in so characterizing a standard as ‘principles-based’. A similar kind of argument applies to the other characteristic of ‘principles-based’ standards as those that express the objective of the standard. In the discussion of the underlying assumptions it was suggested that including an objective in a standard is useful where such objectives are used in exercising judgement about the override or interpreting the standard. However, stating an objective can be divorced from these underlying assumptions. Any standard that expresses a requirement to do something can be re-phrased as a requirement to do something to bring about an objective. The ability to re-phrase requirements follows from the fact that requirements are prescriptions to someone to undertake an intentional action. Intentional actions are those actions that are done for reasons which include the desire to bring about a certain end (Anscombe, 1957, §5). An example from auditing standards will make this clear. ISA 500 requires the auditor to obtain sufficient appropriate audit evidence to be able to draw reasonable conclusions on which to base the auditor’s opinion. Auditors must do something that brings it about that they have sufficient appropriate audit evidence. What is brought about might be called the objective of the action. Such a requirement is ‘objectives-oriented’. This can be used to re-state the requirement in terms of an objective. In ISA 500 the objective is stated as ‘the objective of the auditor is to design and perform audit procedures in such a way as to enable the auditor to obtain sufficient appropriate audit evidence to be able to draw reasonable conclusions on which to base the auditor’s opinion’ (IAASB, 2010, ISA 500). There appears to be a fudge going on here. Objectives, at least as expressed in a CF, are things that are desired to be brought about by the actions of financial reporting. The manoeuvre of re-stating a requirement for action enables an objective to be stated. This was observed at the time that auditing standards were being revised as part of the Clarity Project. An objection was made during the due process of developing new auditing standards that the objectives of the standard were nothing more that requirements re-stated (Dennis, 2010, p. 298). Anyone could agree that standards should state objectives in this sense in so far as they agree that 24 standards should express requirements. Given that any standard expresses requirements this characteristic does not distinguish one kind of standard from another. 7. The problem of explaining ‘principles-based’ standard in terms of characteristics The reasons for choosing some of the characteristics may depend upon the underlying assumptions that are made about accounting standards and what it is to follow them. If it is assumed that standards express prescriptions that are ‘rules of thumb’ then no exceptions are required as an override is possible. Where a standard setter assumes that the problem of failure to meet the objectives will not arise because either the standard setter will only promulgate standards that if followed will achieve the objectives in all applications and where they assume that in setting standards they can avoid inconsistent standards, that is, standards which result in contradictory requirements for actions in following them, they too may agree that exceptions are not required. The same characteristic of standards may be thought to be useful in identifying ‘good’ standards but for very different reasons. The consensus may break down where the assumptions become untenable and may result in a desire to promulgate standards that do not have such a characteristic. A similar argument can be made for agreement on characteristics such as there being ‘appropriate’ amounts of implementation guidance where there may be very different assumptions about the objective of such guidance and as to whether or not language is vague in some sense. It might be simply accepted that in such circumstances standards will not have such a characteristic and, hence, that such standards will not be ‘principles-based’. The problem is that these standards may still have other characteristics that are used to identify ‘principles-based’ standards. They may contain little in the way of implementation guidance. They may include objectives, particularly where the nature of objectives is vague. The standard may, as all useful standards are thought to be, ‘based on’ a CF. If there is discretion as to which and how many of the characteristics of ‘principles-based’ standards such standards have to have then there can be different views on whether or not standards that are promulgated are ‘principles-based’ or not. It may be, as Cairns suggests, that the term ‘still seems to mean very different things to different people’. How 25 can apparently unwavering support for promulgating standards of this kind go hand in hand with lack of agreement as to what is being supported? A superficial agreement on a concept despite underlying disagreements in what is wanted in inventing such a concept is characteristic of concepts that refer to ‘boundary objects’. The idea of a ‘boundary object’ will now be explored. 8. ‘Principles-based’ standards as ‘boundary objects’ The concept of a boundary object was developed in sociology. It was recognized that science requires cooperation and this involves the creation of ‘common understandings’. There is also a ‘‘central tension’ in science between divergent viewpoints and the need for generalizable findings’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 387). Against the myth that scientific cooperation requires a ‘consensus imposed by nature’ it is argued that there is no such consensus and it is not necessary for cooperation in scientific endeavours. On the other hand communication must be possible between actors if there is to be some cooperation (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 388). The creation of ‘boundary objects’ is a means of achieving communication despite the different interests and viewpoints of those who cooperate in scientific endeavours. Such objects ‘come to form a common boundary between worlds by inhabiting them both simultaneously’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 412). Objects of this kind ‘are both plastic enough to adapt to local needs and the constraints of the several parties employing them, yet robust enough to maintain a common identity across sites…They have different meanings in different social worlds but their structure is common enough to more than one world to make them recognizable, a means of translation. The creation and management of boundary objects is a key process in developing and maintaining coherence across intersecting social worlds’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 393). In natural history work of the kind described by Star and Griesemer ‘boundary objects are produced when sponsors, theorists and amateurs collaborate to produce representations of nature’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 408). In such collective work ‘people coming together from different social worlds frequently have the experience of addressing an object that has a different meaning for each of them’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 412). 26 The idea of a ‘boundary object’ is useful in understanding how different parties involved in setting and following accounting standards can cooperate by using the ‘boundary object’ of ‘principles-based’ standards. Instead of ‘scientific endeavours’ the activity involved is standard setting. The analysis above suggests that these parties may start with ‘divergent viewpoints’ about the nature of accounting standards and the kind of prescriptions included therein as well as about the exercises of judgement that is allowed in following them. The project to converge accounting standards requires cooperation between these parties. The ‘boundary object’ of ‘principles-based’ standards is not something that exists ‘out there’ in nature but is created to facilitate cooperation given divergent views about accounting standards. The idea of ‘coherence across intersecting social worlds’ is understood as coherence amongst parties to the convergence project who inhabit different worlds where what is wanted from standards and what is believed to achieve these desires is not common to all parties. ‘Boundary objects’ are said to have ‘different meanings in different social worlds’ and can be ‘abstract or concrete’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 393). Elsewhere they are referred to as ‘artefacts’ (Kimble et al. 2010, p. 438). Referring to them as ‘artefacts’ and ‘concrete’ suggests that they are physical objects. The suggestion that boundary objects can be ‘abstract’ and have ‘meanings’ suggests, on the contrary, that they are part of a language. One way of bringing these two together is to say that a boundary object is the referent of a particular kind of concept or expression. Something is a ‘boundary object’ if it is referred to by a concept or expression that has a particular kind of meaning. It might be more accurate to say that ‘boundary objects’ are what are referred to by boundary concepts. This follows from the kind of approach in philosophy undertaken by Wittgenstein. He did not see philosophical enquiries as a form of scientific exploration of objects (Baker and Hacker, 1980, Ch. XIII). The focus of philosophical enquiries is on getting clear about the meaning of expressions that denote the kind of objects that science investigates. Ontology, that is the investigation of the kind of things that exist (Craig, 2005, p. 756), is only ‘a shadow in the Platonic Cave’ (Hacker, 1990, p. 261). The objects that exist are shadows cast by the meaning of expressions used to denote them. This throws light on the idea of the ‘social construction of reality’. What is constructed are 27 meanings and objects come into being, are constructed and have reality, as the shadows cast by meaning. The need for communication where different parties in an activity give different meanings to expressions used to denote ‘boundary objects’ creates a problem of managing such objects. Star and Griesemer suggest a number of ways in which ‘problems posed by conflicting views’ can be managed, some of which are evident in the context of adopting a ‘principles-based’ approach to developing accounting standards. One way is to develop the concept of a ‘principles-based’ standard ‘via a ‘lowest common denominator’ which satisfies the minimal demands of each world by capturing properties that fall within the minimum acceptable range of all concerned worlds’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 404). The property of ‘being consistent with, and derived from, a coherent conceptual framework’ would appear to be of this kind. All parties agree on this characteristic as providing a ‘minimum acceptable’ criterion of a standard being ‘principles-based’. Another management device is ‘the use of versatile, plastic, reconfigurable (programmable) objects that each world can mould to its purposes locally’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 404). The kind of vague generalized definition of a ‘principle’ given by ICAS and the lack of clarity about what being ‘based on’ a principle so defined might be taken as a device to facilitate communication about ‘principlesbased’ standards that enables various parties to mould to their own ends. Yet another device is to enable ‘each participating world can abstract or simplify the object to suit its demands; that is, ‘extraneous’ properties can be deleted or ignored’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 404). The SEC identification of various characteristics of ‘principles-based’ standards that do not all have to be met by standards to come under this concept. The suggestion made above that this concept may be understood as a ‘family resemblance’ concept facilitates its use as a device of this kind. The characteristics themselves are acceptable as a ‘lowest common denominators’ such as the characteristics of including ‘an appropriate amount of implementation guidance’ or the characteristic of requiring the exercise of judgement. This characteristics and that of having minimum exceptions may be an example of a ‘plastic’ criterion that masks different ‘purposes’ in so far as parties 28 may adopt them from different underlying assumptions. The literature on ‘boundary objects’ identifies political motives in their use that is relevant to the accounting context. 9. The politics of language It is suggested that ‘the selection of the boundary object can be a political act directed towards maintaining or redefining the direction of the group’s activities’ (Kimble et al., 2010, p. 442). There are two objectives of this direction. One objective is to further collective goals and the other to choose ‘boundary objects’ to defend a position. Both of these objectives are evident in the debate over ‘principles-based’ standards. The idea of standards of this kind is used to further the collective goal of standard setters to achieve agreement on accounting standards. The development of the classification of standards as ‘principles-based’ may also be prompted by the political motives of defending the authority of particular standard setters. The ‘international accounting promulgators promote their product as principles-based against US GAAP, which they rebuke as rulesbased, to gain leadership in establishing the global accounting system’ (Cunningham, 2007, p. 1416). As McSweeney suggests ‘representations, accounting and other, are not disinterested characterizations of the world but rather are arguably created in order to act on and master it’ (McSweeney, 1997, p. 708). The ‘boundary object’ of ‘principlesbased’ standards has assisted in achieving this end. Indeed, the use of boundary concepts in accounting is often responsible for the ‘unbearable ambiguity of accounting’ (McSweeney, 1997) whereby the appearance of agreement is possible only by the use of ambiguous concepts. The IASB appear to have won in the first ‘game’ to establish leadership and ‘mastery’ of the world of standard setting. However, while both parties appear to agree on the characteristics of ‘principles-based’ standards and in the commitment to converge on such standards they do so from very different starting positions. The Convergence Project was made possible only by using the ‘boundary object’ of ‘principles-based’ standards. These different starting positions, that is different underlying assumptions about prescriptions, may result in differences that emerge in determining the standards upon which the Boards converge. Political wrangling can still take place under the umbrella of 29 apparent agreement on the nature of standards. A boundary object like a ‘principlesbased’ standard acceptable precisely because ‘it is fairly vague; it serves as a means of communicating and cooperating symbolically - a ‘good enough’ road map for all parties’ (Star and Griesemer, 1989, p. 410). There is a lot of talk about ‘road maps’ in the U.S. in connection with the convergence project and with the move towards ‘principles-based’ IFRSs. The question is whether the ‘road map’ provided by the concept of ‘principles-based’ standards is going to assist this convergence or not. The failure to agree on the underlying assumptions about prescriptions is useful in so far as it allows the appearance of convergence on a kind of standard without the necessity to achieve convergence on the underlying assumptions. However, as the problems considered above show this superficial agreement on a concept may be compatible with disagreements on the standards that are promulgated. Even if such disagreements are thrashed out in the standard setting process it may be a mystery to preparers and auditors as to why the resulting standards are to be referred to as ‘principles-based’ standards. There may be a perception that they are not really of this kind. 10. Conclusions The paper has considered why it might be the case that despite widespread agreement amongst standard setters, regulators and those who follow accounting standards that accounting standards should be ‘principles-based’ there is an apparent difficulty in promulgating such standards or agreeing that the standards formulated are of this kind. It is suggested that one reason for this is that the concept of a standard being ‘principlesbased’ is vague. The concept is one that expresses a ‘boundary object’ and concepts of this kind while achieving the appearance of agreement conceal underlying differences in understanding them. Although such concepts enable some kind of communication between parties with different interests they are not able to sustain the more comprehensive agreements that are required by a project such as the one to converge the accounting standards of the IASB and the FASB. One benefit of the ‘principles versus rules’ debate is that it has focused attention of important underlying issues in standard 30 setting. It is important to debate the nature of the CF that sets out reasons for promulgating accounting standards and the kind of reasoning that leads from the CF to standards. The kind of prescriptions that are included in standards needs to be considered. Are the ‘rules of thumb’ or prescriptions understood on the ‘practice’ conception. This leads on to the question of whether or not standards can be overridden where following the standards will not meet the objectives of the standard or where there the requirements in standards lead to conflicting actions when following them. The objective of implementation guidance needs to be agreed. It is important to decide whether the objective is to eliminate actual or possible vagueness. This leads on to the question of whether those who follow the standards are allowed to exercise judgement in interpreting the standard, that is in determining what the prescription in the standard actually is in certain circumstances, or whether the judgement in determining the prescription is only to be exercised by the standard setter. The paper has argued that these questions have not been fully debated in the context of the ‘principles versus rules’ debate. It is not surprising that this has not been done. Given that agreement on some of these issues is unlikely the development of a ‘boundary object’ concept of being ‘principles-based’ provides a way of achieving the appearance of convergence against a failure to converge on the underlying assumptions that are expressed in different attitudes towards these issues. Wittgenstein once observed ‘concepts lead us to make investigations; are the expression of our interest, and direct our interest (Wittgenstein, 1953, §570). The paper argues that the concept of being ‘principles-based’ does not provide clear direction of the interests of standard setters. The conclusion of the paper is that it would be better to recognize the impotence of such a concept. It is time to ‘neutralize the rhetorical and political power of the false binary’ and allow a ‘fizzling out of the vocabulary altogether’ (Cunningham, 2007, p. 1493). The idea of ‘principles-based’ standards has outlived its ‘sell by’ date and should be dumped. 31 References AAA, 2003. Evaluating Concepts-Based vs. Rules-Based Approaches to Standard Setting. Accounting Horizons Vol. 17 No. 1, 73-89. Alexander, D., 1999. A benchmark for the adequacy of published financial statements. Accounting and Business Research, Vol. 29, No. 3, 239-253. Alexander, D. and Jermakowicz, E., 2006. A True and Fair View of the Principles/Rules Debate. ABACUS Vol. 42, No. 2, 132-164. Anscombe, G.E.M., 1957. Intention. Basil Blackwell, Oxford. Armstrong, M.S., 1977. Statements in quotes The politics of establishing accounting standards. The Journal of Accountancy, February, 76-79. Baker, G. and Hacker, P., 1980. Wittgenstein Meaning and Understanding. Blackwell, Oxford. Baker, G. and Hacker, P., 1985. Wittgenstein Rules, Grammar and Necessity. Blackwell, Oxford. Benston, G.J., Bromwich, M., Wagenhofer, A., 2006. Principles- Versus Rules-Based Accounting Standards: The FASB’s Standard Setting Strategy. ABACUS 42, Issue 2, 165-188. Blackburn, S., 1994, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Brown, G.A., Collins, R., Thornton, D.B., 1993. Professional judgment and accounting standards. Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 18, No. 4, 275-289. Cairns, D., 2011. Accountancy, Vol. 148, Issue 1417, 71-71. CICA, 1988. Professional Judgment in Financial Reporting. CICA, Toronto. Craig, E., 2005, The shorter routledge encyclopedia of philosophy, edited by Craig, E., Routledge, Abingdon. Cunningham, R.A., 2007. A Prescription to Retire the Rhetoric of “Principles-Based Systems” in Corporate Law, Securities Regulation and Accounting. Vanderbilt Law Review, Vol. 60, Issue 5, 1411-1493. Dean, G. and Clarke, F., 2005. ‘True and fair’ and‘fair value’- accounting and legal willo’-the-wisps. ABACUS 41, Issue 2, 1-8. 32 Dennis, I., 2008. A conceptual enquiry into the concept of a ‘principles-based’ accounting standard. British Accounting Review, Vol. 40, No. 3, 260–71. Dennis, I., 2010. ‘Clarity’ Begins at Home: An Examination of the Conceptual Underpinnings of the IAASB’s Clarity Project. International Journal of Auditing, Vol. 14, No. 3, 294–319. Dopuch, N. and Sunder, S., 1980. FASB’s Statements on Objectives and Elements of Financial Accounting: A Review. Accounting Review, 55(1), 1-21. Evans, L., 2003. The true and fair view and the ‘fair presentation’ override of IAS 1. Accounting and Business Research, Vol. 33, No. 4, 311-325. FASB, 1976. Scope and Implications of the Conceptual Framework Project. FASB, Connecticut. FASB, 2002. Proposal: Principles-Based Approach to U.S. Standard Setting. FASB, Connecticut. FASB (2004) FASB Response to SEC Study on the adoption of a Principles-based Accounting System. FASB: Connecticut. Accessible at: http://www.fasb.org/response_sec_study_july2004.pdf [Accessed 17 January, 2012] FASB/IASB, 2002. Memorandum of Understanding “The Norwalk Agreement”. FASB, Connecticut. Accessible at: http://www.ifrs.org/NR/rdonlyres/6F81606F-6182-4D27-A2C96A6DD5D10BA4/0/Norwalk_agreement.pdf [Accessed 17 January, 2012] FASB/IASB, 2005. Revisiting the Concepts: A New Conceptual Framework Project. FASB, Connecticut. Accessible at: http://www.ifrs.org/NR/rdonlyres/E5B8A298-6179-4FAA-985A42416EB597F5/0/8_1455_0602sob04a.pdf [Accessed 12 January, 2012]. Hacker, P.M.S., 1990. Wittgenstein Meaning and Mind. Blackwell, Oxford. IAASB, 2010. Handbook of International Standards on Auditing and Quality Control. International Federation of Accountants, New York. IASB, 2010. The Conceptual Framework for Financial Reporting. IASB, London. 33 IASB, 2011. Preface to International Financial Reporting Standards. IASB, London. ICAS, 2006. Principles not rules A question of judgment. ICAS, Edinburgh. ICAS, 2007. Principles into Practice Key points from the “Too Late for Principles” conference held in October 2006. ICAS, Edinburgh. Accessible at: www.icas.org.uk/site/cms/download/PrinciplesIntoPractice.pdf [Accessed 14 November, 2011] Kimble, C., Grenier, C., and Goglio-Primard. K. (2010). ‘Innovation and Knowledge Sharing Across Professional Boundaries: Political Interplay between Boundary Objects and Brokers’. International Journal of Information Management 30 (5), 437–444. Accessible at: doi:10.1016/j.ijinfomgt.2010.02.002. [Accessed 28 September, 2011) Lyas, C.,1993. Accounting and Language in M. Mumford and K. Peasnell (edd.) Philosophical Perspectives on Accounting. Routledge, London. Mattessich, R., 1995. Conditional-Normative Accounting Methodology: Incorporating Value Judgements and Means-End Relations of an Applied Science. Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol.20 No.4, 259-284. McSweeney, B., 1997. The Unbearable Ambiguity of Accounting. Accounting, Organizations and Society, Vol. 22 No. 7, 691-712. Nobes, C., 2005. Rules-based Standards and the Lack of Principles in Accounting. Accounting Horizons Vol. 19 No. 1, 25-34. Power, M., 1993. On the idea of a conceptual framework for financial reporting in M. Mumford and K. Peasnell (edd.) Philosophical Perspectives on Accounting Routledge, London. Rawls, J., 1955. Two concepts of rules. Philosophical Review 64, reprinted in Theories of Ethics, 1967, edited by Foot in the Oxford Readings in Philosophy series, 144-170. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Salmon, W., 1992. Scientific Explanation. In Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis. Schipper, K., 2003. Principles-based accounting standards. Accounting Horizons 17 (1), 61-72. SEC, 2003. Study Report Pursuant to Section 108(d) of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002. SEC. 34 Star, S. and Griesemer, J., 1989. Institutional Ecology, ‘Translations’ and Boundary Objects: Amateurs and Professionals in Berkeley’s Museum of Vertebrate Zoology, 1907-39. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 19, No. 3, 387-420. van Hulle, K., 1997. The True and Fair override in the European Accounting Directives. European Accounting Review Vol. 6, No. 4, 711-720. Wittgenstein,L., 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Basil Blackwell, Oxford. Wüstemann, J. and Wüstemann, S., 2010. Why Consistency of Accounting Standards Matters: A Contribution to the Rules-Versus-Principles Debate in Financial Reporting. ABACUS Vol. 46, No. 1, 1-27. Young, J., 2006. Making up users. Accounting Organizations and Society 31, 579600. Zeff, S.A., 1990. The English-language equivalent of Geeft een Getrouw Beeld in Parker, R.H. and Nobes, C.W. An international view of true and fair accounting. Routledge, London. 35