Dislocation of the West/July 2014 DRAFT Asian Theory and European Humanity - On the Question of Anthropological Difference -1 Naoki Sakai Cornell University If not a completely oxymoronic, the pairing of theory and Asia, as in Asian Theory for instance, may strike many readers as a sort of quirk or a defamiliarizing trick. At best it can have the effect of exposing the presumption often taken for granted in fields dealing with some aspects of what we understand in the name of Asia, namely that theory is something we normally do not expect of Asia. Precisely because this sense of oddity that is invoked when theory is associated with Asia is no more than a certain presumptive or conditional reflex, neither theory nor Asia receives rigorous scrutiny, and both are by and large left rather vague in conceptual articulation in this instance. Rarely have we asked ourselves why we do not feel unsettled about this feeling of incongruity, where this discomfort derives from, or how one could possibly explicate reasons for our taking this underlying presumption for granted. As long as it remains presumptive and refuses to be further articulated conceptually, I suspect that it turns into something one might well call a ‘civilizational spell,’ 1 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 and it will continue to cast a curse on us. In other words, we will remain haunted by this presumption about theory and Asia. In this chapter you will find a brief meditation on how we might disentangle from this spell. So, why do we feel odd about the unexpected combination of theory and Asia in the first place? Or, with more emphasis on our analytical attentiveness, how can we manage to evade a sense of oddity about the fact that we are accustomed to feeling strange about the combination of theory and Asia? It must be said that there have been some attempts to explicate why theory and Asia do not go hand in hand; quite a few writers have attempted to offer some reasons or justification for it even though, since the end of Second World War, only a comparatively small number of openly conservative or reactionary thinkers have dared to justify why Asians or non-Europeans are disqualified to speak or conceptualize theoretically. Yet, as the common sense prevalent in academic institutions in the North Atlantic as well as Asia holds it, it has been widely upheld that what is called “theory” is somewhat proper to Europe, and later, as the United States assumed its global stature, to North America as well. In the early twentieth century, a number of prominent intellectuals addressed the question of Europe’s commitment to theory. Immediately Paul Valéry and Edmund Husserl come to mind. For example, Husserl argued that Indian or Chinese philosophy could hardly be regarded as authentically ‘philosophical’ because the life attitude that Indian and Chinese philosophers 2 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 embodied was not genuinely ‘theoretical.’2 For Husserl, Europe was not merely a geographic category; the geographic territory ascribed to it is far from adequate to define it. Unlike ‘empirical anthropological types’ such as the Chinese, Indian, Eskimos, or even the Gypsies roaming around territorial Europe, he continued, Europe is a historical unity of peoples who shares a certain kinship or a certain modality of being human, a European humanity, which distinguishes them from humanity in general. And it is absolutely impossible to conceive of this European ‘man’ without his commitment to theory, which has been handed down in the name of philosophy from the ancient Greeks through to the 20th century. Of course, here is an archetypical declaration of anthropological difference, without which the idea of European humanity would not be intelligible. For Valéry and Husserl, theory was undoubtedly something that characterized the European Spirit or the spiritual shape of Europe. They both referred to the crisis of theoretical or philosophical reason on the grounds that the Europeans cannot fashion themselves as such without a commitment to theory. What they perceived in the 1920’s and 30’s was a crisis of the European man, the wide-spread reality all over Europe that Europeans were ceasing to be European in this specific regard. In other words, they were horrified that the Europeans were getting less and less distinguishable from such anthropological types such as the Chinese and the Indians. To my knowledge, the statement that we normally do not expect theory from Asia has been put forth on a number of occasions, and some people – 3 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Valéry and Husserl included – have wanted to raise this issue as part of their assessment of the contemporary world. What is significant about the historical mission of European humanity for Husserl, for instance, is that, in his late works, notably his posthumous work collected and compiled under the title of the Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, the entire venture of his phenomenology was reformulated as a historical movement of the European spirit, as a teleological project that was at the same time the recourse to the past origin of European humanity on the one hand and the infinite ecstatic self-overcoming in the future on the other. Clearly just before his death and under the extreme political adversity, Husserl wanted to present his phenomenology as a historical embodiment of the mission for European humanity, and attempted to speak as the ultimate representative of the spiritual shape of Europe. Yet, his Eurocentric mission seems plagued with a number of political and philosophical contradictions, which I would like to explore in order to indicate the issues involved in this book, Dislocation of the West. Let me start by offering a brief historical assessment of Husserl’s ambiguity about racism and the international background of the early 1930’s. We cannot overlook that he wrote about the crisis of European humanity in the political climate of fascism. It is more than probable that he offered his diagnosis of the crisis of European Sciences as a condemnation of fascisms in Europe. 4 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 As soon as the Nazi Party dominated the Reichstag of Germany in March 1933, it passed a number of legislations including the Law for the Restoration of the Professional Civil Service. These were measures in Germany aimed at excluding anti-Nazi and non-Aryan elements from public institutions such as universities, schools, the judiciary, and the civil service. These Nazi policies were in accordance with the populist outcry of “Europe for the Europeans,” that was spreading all over Europe around that time. Indeed the life of Edmund Husserl, an internationally renowned philosopher at Freiburg University, was deeply affected even though he had already been in retirement from 1928 from the position of professor in philosophy, a position inherited by his equally renowned student, Martin Heidegger, himself a Nazi Party member. Being a Jew born in Moravia in the Austro-Hungarian Empire, Husserl was denied access to university libraries and was no longer allowed to publish in Germany as a result of the newly-implemented Nazi policies. The rise of National Socialism in Germany, or more generally of Fascism in many European countries, Latin America, and Japan, provoked a widespread fear, not only within Europe and the Americas, but also in East Asia. As I have discussed elsewhere,3 in Japan, for instance, a nation-wide anti-Fascist movement was organized against the dismissal of Takigawa Yukitori, only two months after the Nazi ascendency to the national state. Minister of Education Hatoyama Ichirô – grandfather of Hatoyama Yukio, a recent prime minister of Japan (2009-10) – dismissed Professor Takigawa Yukitori from the Faculty of Law at the Kyoto 5 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Imperial University for his alleged sympathy with Marxist scholarship and for his supposedly critical attitude toward family morality. In the same month of the same year - May 1933 - Heidegger’s Rektoratsrede, rector’s address, was broadly covered in Japanese mass media, and leading intellectuals of the day, Tanabe Hajime, Miki Kiyoshi, Tosaka Jun, Shinmei Masamichi and others wrote alarmingly about the rise of Fascism in Europe. It is easy to detect the sense of urgency with which Japanese intellectuals received the news of a Fascist resurgence - around this time ‘fassho’ was first coined in the Japanese vernacular and began to be used to denote the contemporary global trends towards ultranationalism and the theories of racial purity - and, for the rest of the 1930’s, the topic of Fascism continued to dominate Japanese mass media. The public debates about Fascism continued until the Japanese State officially endorsed the leading regimes of Fascist ideologies, Germany and Italy, when it signed the Axis Pact in September, 1940, and a few months later other countries including those of the so-called Clerical Fascism – Hungary, Romania, Slovenia, Bulgaria, and Croatia – joined this Pact, although the Japanese leadership was hesitant to openly endorse the ethnic nationalism and racist doctrines prevalent, particularly in National Socialism. Even during the war, Japanese intellectuals and reformminded bureaucrats - except for a few ethnic nationalists such as Watsuji Tetsurô and Nishitani Keiji, whose presence was particularly significant in the history of postwar Japan - remained critical of the racial policies of Nazi Germany and the anti-Semitism of Clerical Fascism. Of course, Nazi’s outright disdain for the 6 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 yellow race made it hard for the Japanese to accept Nazism. But, more importantly, many Japanese intellectuals could not accept the basic tenets of National Socialism because they were concerned about the multi-ethnic imperial order that Japan was creating in Greater East Asia; they advocated the ideas of the East Asian Community - and later the Greater East Asian Co-prosperity Sphere - by claiming that it was Japan’s mission to liberate Asian peoples from the shackles of white supremacy. In May and November of 1935, Edmund Husserl was invited to give lectures in Vienna and Prague. According to Ludwig Landgrebe, Walter Biemel and others involved in the deciphering and compilation of stenographic manuscripts and notes left behind by Husserl, these lectures marked the beginning of the unfinished work we now know as the Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. One may well recognize in this set of manuscripts a further elaboration of the themes Husserl had already discussed in Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology based upon the lectures, which he delivered in Paris in 1929. What distinguished the Vienna and Prague lectures from his ones in Paris was his open confrontation with the political climate of the time. In Cartesian Meditations, Husserl addressed the question of modernity in philosophy, while in the Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, he reorganized his discussion of a set of topics concerning philosophy’s historicity under a new directive or problematic that he summarized as ‘the crisis of European humanity.’ 7 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 It is not hard to understand why Husserl had to shift his emphasis between his lectures in Paris and those in Vienna. They took place in the midst of the period ‘Austorofascism’ (1934-1938). Fascist fervor broke out not only in Italy and Germany but also in many parts of Europe - Portugal and Austria - which would be followed by Romania, Greece, Croatia, Spain and France. In Portugal, Antonio Salazar became prime minister and introduced an anti-parliamentarian and authoritarian constitution in 1932. In May 1934, Engelbert Dollfuss, then Chancellor, suspended parliamentary government in Austria eight days before Adolf Hitler did the same thing in Germany, and in the following year Dollfuss succeeded in replacing liberal parliamentary democracy with the doctrine of a Christian German corporate state. In July 1936, a civil war broke out between the Republicans who received support from the Soviet Union and Mexico and the Nationalists led by Francisco Franco, supported by Fascist Italy, Nazi Germany and Portugal, and Austria’s Second Republican government. Eventually Spain would be seized under what historians call Clerical Fascism. Countries such Slovenia, Croatia, and Romania would follow suit, and violent anti-Semitism spread all over Europe. On 10 June 1936, a month before the Spanish Civil War started, Moritz Schlick, known as the founding father of Logical Positivism and the Vienna Circle, was assassinated for his affiliation with Jewish intellectuals by a deranged student. This was a year after Husserl’s lecture in that city. A Catholic national newspaper Schönere Zukunft responded to the Schlick assassination, by insisting: “The Jews should be allowed their Jewish philosophy 8 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 in their own Jewish cultural institute! But in the chairs of philosophy in the Viennese university in Christian-German Austria, there belong Christian philosophers.”4 It was under such a political climate that Husserl delivered his lectures in Prague and Vienna. Husserl was a victim of the populist demand for “Europe for the Europeans,” but he did not hesitate to endorse the rhetoric of Eurocentric exclusionism when it was an issue of the spirit of European Humanity.5 Before involving ourselves in the reading of these attempts, however, we ought to return to the statement in order to clarify the sense of oddity radiating from the presumption contained in it. That we normally do not expect theory of a person if he or she is of Asia is in fact a negative corollary of another statement: theory is something that we normally expect of a person if he or she is of the West or Europe,6 and the relationship between the first and second statements is generally called contraposition in logic. Let us note that the first statement implied in this presumption – we normally do not expect theory if the speaker, thinker or knower is from Asia, a native of Asia, or a resident in Asia – is not thematically or primarily about Asia. It is no more than a derivative of the general statement about the West or Europe rather than about Asia. ***** 9 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 However, as a matter of fact, the derivative character of the first statement in relation to the second is inherent in the designation ‘Asia’ itself. As Takeuchi Yoshimi, a sinologist specializing in modern Chinese literature, observed more than half a century ago, the East – Tôyô, the Chinese compound for the Orient as opposed to Seiyô, the Occident - which he more or less assumed to be the representative of the Rest of the world, arrived at its selfconsciousness as a consequence of its defeat by the West or Europe.7 Spending his college days in Japan in the 1930’s, Takeuchi was immersed in the various readings about Hegel available then; these ranged from the Marxian reading, arguably best represented by Lukacs, the Kyoto School readings (Tanabe Hajime, Miki Kiyoshi, and other philosophers of World History), through to modernization Hegelianism in Maruyama Masao, four years junior to Takeuchi, who published during the war but would become a leading figure, of the intellectual world after Japan’s surrender. It is no surprise that he viewed the historical destiny of Asia in Hegelian terms. Negativity, without which reflectivity – not reflex, which illustrates a lack of reflectivity which is essential for self-consciousness to be accomplished – never originated in the East, and the absence of reflectivity was certainly implied in Takeuchi’s word ‘defeat (haiboku).’ He claimed that the East could never be conscious of itself before it was invaded by Europe. Asia came to its selfconsciousness through its defeat. Only through the acknowledgment of its lost autonomy, of its dependence upon and subjugation to the West - or only in the 10 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 mirror of the West, so to say8 - could the Rest reflectively acquire its civilizational, cultural, ethnic, and national identities. Historically the moment of defeat was actualized in the colonization of Asia, and it is in this respect that the modernity in Asia is unavoidably a colonial modernity. Takeuchi observed that, only when Asia was defeated, invaded, penetrated, and subjugated, could she wake up in modernity, so that, in Asia and for Asia, it is impossible to conceive of modernity without reference to colonial humiliation. However, because of his uncompromising faith in the Enlightenment values of modernity, which could only be concretized in the institutions of the nation-state, Takeuchi could not envision the future of Asia - and by implication, the future of the Rest of the world - along a historical trajectory other than that of historicism. Like many intellectuals of Asia and Europe who had their formative years in the 1930s, Takeuchi had internalized modern historicism to such an extent that, for him, an effective struggle against the colonizing forces of the West could not bypass the creation of national subjectivity. His furtive loyalty to Hegel prevented him from conceiving any other historical trajectories than that of historicism in which the actualization and appropriation of modern values must first require a radical negation of external forces as well as of its internal heritage of a feudal past. Therefore, to be modern for Asia meant to appropriate the essence of Western modernity by resisting the West without, and overcoming the reactionary heritage within. In other words, Asia must modernize itself by negating its own past as well as the West. Without no resistance to, or negation 11 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 of the West, there was no prospect of modernity for the Rest of the world. Where else, he would ask, if not in the midst of a struggle against colonial powers and the oppressive remnants of the past, could one possibly actualize the concrete and practical senses of liberty, equality, and fraternity? He diagnosed Japan’s modern history as a case where a genuine negativity was absent. This perhaps explains his excessive idealization of China. He thought that, unlike Japan which had imitated the West to the extent of reproducing its imperialism, China would actualize a truly authentic modernity by negating not only the West’s intervention but also the remnants of its own past, such as Confucianism. Yet the dialectic, which he anticipated to lead historical conflicts forward, could not have made sense unless the externality of what Asia should resist had been postulated. For peoples in the Rest, then, modernity was considered a sort of historical movement which spatially consolidated the unity and substantiality of a political grouping called ‘the nation’, by negating external forces, while at the same time temporally constituting itself as a subject, as an agent of self-determination, by continually overcoming its own past. This is why the dichotomy of ‘development from within (naihatsu)’ and ‘imposition from without (gaihatsu)’ was the ultimate criterion for Takeuchi’s evaluation of modernity.9 In a schematization such as the one operating in his discussion of modernity, the unity of the nation depended upon the externality of what had to be resisted, which was more often than not mapped onto the cartographic plane. 12 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Just as with the Japanese invasion of China, that which must be resisted must come from the ‘outside’ of the presumed integrity of the nation. A nation of Asia, such as China, was located within the reach of the West, but the West itself was external to it. The externality of what had to be resisted was thus comprehended in terms of the geographic distance between Western Europe and Asia. For Takeuchi, therefore, the West was postulated as an entity external to Asia, and the possibility that the West could be inherent in the Rest of the world was deliberately foreclosed. Perhaps, more importantly, we must note the other aspect of this foreclosure: deliberately excluded from consideration is the feasibility that the Rest is inherent in the West, the Third world immanent in the First World. Takeuchi was determined to view the relationship between the West and the Rest of the world as one of geographic externality, of a border separating two entities; even though he acknowledged the designation of Asia as an instance of colonial defeat, nonetheless he refused to comprehend it as a relation of mutual self-reflectivity, or mirroring. What he was totally blind to was the truism that so many of those self-fashioned Westerners cannot discard their premodernity or non-European features. The binary of the West and the Rest is often a matter of class difference and of cultural capital. The differential in the social positionality most often results from factors such as social class, education, and cultural capital, the distinction of the West and the Rest is in fact far from stable. Precisely because of the inherent instability of civilizational identity, the supposedly fixed characteristic of individual’s physiognomy, linguistic accent or 13 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 geographic place of origins is obsessively sought after to naturalize and consolidate an individual’s position in the system of classification dictated by the logic of anthropological difference. This is why, while very perceptive to the implications of Eurocentricity in so many aspects of life in Asia, Takeuchi could not detect the workings of what elsewhere I called “the civilizational transference,” a mutual constitution of desire between the West and the Rest, in nationalisms in Asia10. Although Takeuchi was unmistakably critical of the modernization theory, he could not avoid the cartographic imaginary that serves as a substratum for knowledge production, namely, the postulate of the area, upon which the modernization theory invariably relied. Therefore, his insight into colonial modernity could never go beyond a hierarchy premised upon the developmental teleology of modernization. What Takeuchi somewhat short-changed in his discussion about Asia was the self-reflective postulation of Asia. He failed to acknowledge that, essentially, Asia exists for the West’s self-recognition. For peoples living in Asia, there used to be no clear distinction of Asia from Europe. Asia had never been an immediate designation for the Asians and, therefore, Asia could not have existed for them prior to the occasion of colonial defeat, an occasion that symbolized the very moment of negativity deliberately pinpointed by Takeuchi. Since Greek antiquity, Asia always meant an ecstatic or outward orientation of Europe; it pointed to an area or people in the east of Hellenes, so 14 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 that it was not expected to designate a fixed geographic location, a closed land surface or a determinate social group; instead it was meant to serve as a directional index only from the viewpoint of the Greeks, Europeans or Westerners. However, it is important to remind ourselves that, in the genealogy of Western or European civilization, Asia played a little or no meaningful role from the end of the Roman Empire until the era of Eurocentric modernity, simply because Europe was no more than a provincial periphery to large metropolitan civilizations of Islam and Mongolia, and the Chinese and Indian Empires. In short, there was no such thing as Europe prior to the explosion of the modern international world and the rise of global capitalism. The idea of the continuity of the Western civilization itself is dubious because most of what Western Europe claims today as its heritage from Greco-Roman antiquity was handed down from Islamic civilizations of the pre-modern eras. In antiquity Asia referred to the Greeks’ geopolitical neighbours to the east: in Asia Minor or those along the Tigris and the Euphrates; then those along the Indus and the Ganges were included, and eventually as Europe expanded its system of Eurocentric international law through global capitalism and colonialisms, the notion of Asia would extend to those islands in the East Indies, peoples under the reign of the Central Kingdom – China – and even as far east as the Korean peninsula and the islands of Japan. This expansion of Asia and the term’s versatility amply illustrate the directional character of Asia, that is, moving away – ex-static, meaning a movement beyond or away from the self 15 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 from the presumed position of viewpoint. It marks something reflectively social and cosmopolitan about how Europe could possibly be identified: is it ever possible to designate Europe without reference to Africa, Asia and the Americas? Asia is an open kind of reference, indicating the directional relation of the viewing subject and the designated object. Of course, the West too is such a directional designation and, in this respect, the East – the polar opposite of the West – and Asia are often held to be interchangeable. Thus, when all the historical nuances and accidents are reduced, Asia simply signifies ‘the East of Europe.’ Asia’s referential function was based upon Europe’s self-referentiality in the sense that to refer to Asia is to indicate the position of Europe or the West self-reflectively.11 It is the very ecstatic nature of the West itself that Asia reflects upon itself. Neither the West nor the East can be a determinate location; both of them are a relative designation, so that what is determinate about this relation is the microphysics of power relations that makes the West and the East appear somewhat fixed, natural or preordained. What makes the West or the East determinate is the very conduct that takes place in these power relations at the very locale in which the West is bordered from the Rest. Nevertheless, neither of them is arbitrarily determined since, as Antonio Gramsci argued, these relations are hegemonic.12 Instead of the Gramscian term, however, I want to describe them in terms of the microphysics of power relations. Well into the nineteenth century, many in Europe knew that there were many dynasties, theocracies, traditions and peoples in Asia. It was not expected 16 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 that the Asians themselves knew they were Asians. Europeans called people in Asia Asians, but they never expected Asians to call themselves Asians. Court officials serving the Nguyên Dynasty, Samurais of the Matsudaira clan, and merchants working in the port of Ningbo, must have been aware that they were expected to recognize themselves as subjects of Emperor Gia Long, of the Tokugawa shoguns, and of the Qing emperors respectively, but it is unlikely that they were aware of being Asians. What Takeuchi called ‘defeat’ happened in Asia from the late nineteenth century to the early twentieth century, as a result of which bureaucrats in Vietnam, schoolteachers in Japan, and soldiers in China came to acknowledge that they were all Asians. ‘Defeat’ was not only a matter of competition or rivalry but of self-recognition and identification. Their identity was nothing but the consequence of an ‘imposition from without (gaihatsu).’ Furthermore, the ‘defeat’ brought about a distinction between Europe and Asia, the mutually marked positionalities of Europeans and Asians. And the reign of these mutually-defining positionalities is often called the ‘colonial power relation.’ The ‘defeat’ therefore means global modernity according to which the entire world was reorganized with respect to the modalities of self-recognition. I do not believe that Takeuchi was entirely negligent of this truth about the dialectic of self-consciousness for the Asians. He wrote, ‘The Orient essentially lacks not only the ability to understand Europe but also to understand itself. What understands the Orient, and so brings it to realization, are those European elements within Europe. What makes the Orient possible is situated in 17 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Europe. Not only does Europe become possible in Europe, the Orient also becomes possible there.’13 Nevertheless, Takeuchi stopped short of an ultimate cognition of the political reality in which the demarcation of Asia from Europe as a separate entity, region, people or civilization was not only a consequence of ‘defeat,’ but also the condition in which colonialism is preserved. An inscription of Asia as a distinct entity from Europe is far from innocent, and a people in Asia may not be able to dispel colonial power relations even if their national sovereignty is installed. On the one hand, Asia is a derivative of Europe’s selfreferentiality. On the other hand, the distinction of Asia from Europe is an effect of exclusionist and discriminatory ‘bordering’ or border inscription. Accordingly, as soon as the Asians fashion themselves as such, the structure of heteronomous referentiality has to be manifest in their identity. For the Asians, paradoxically, the desire for their autonomy requires that they be heteronomous. In this context, it is absolutely imperative for us to guard against the typical mistake committed by Husserl and many others: in the spatial configuration of Europe in relation to the Rest – Asia, Africa and Americas – Europe should never be postulated as a subject that evolves linearly along the chronological line from antiquity to the present, that transcends itself to form the successive life of its own from the past to the future, and that generates its own living tradition. The West is not an enduring entity; it is an accidental assemblage of power relations that cannot be synthesized to form an organic unity either spatially or chronologically. In this respect, it is Europe’s mythological obsession 18 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 with its ancient Greek origin that the spiritual shape of Europe came into focus as a living tradition and as a teleology with the historical mission to infinitely transcend itself by recourse to its archaic origin while distinguishing itself from its exterior. This mythological teleology of the West or Europe is involved in what I meant by the derivative character of the statement ‘we normally do not expect theory of Asia.’ Just as Asia is indicated from the implicit and self-referential position of Europe or the West, the oddity experienced about theory associated with Asia is a derivative effect of another statement, namely ‘we normally expect theory of Europe.’ What we must call into question is this ‘normalcy,’ in the presumption of which we expect theory to be of Europe or of European origin. So far I have postponed the mention of two elementary questions; this negligence may make my argument appear persuasive up to this point. As a matter of fact, however, I am endorsing neither the autonomy of Asia as an active agent nor the victimization of Asia under Eurocentrism. What I am asking is how the civilizational designations of the West, Asia, Europe, and so forth, are still possible today. The two questions at issue are as follow: I) Are ‘we’ always and by definition secondary to or derivative of ‘you’ ontologically, so that the European priority hidden in the designation ‘Asia’ is a consequence of some disastrous logical or philosophical mistake? Asia as an indexing function is nothing abnormal in its derivative and secondary nature; then what is not 19 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 normal would be the modern system of geopolitical naming according to which the West has enjoyed being the centrality of the global standard. Does the West not illustrate the inevitable performativity of indexing, namely, that the centre of the world could only be designated as the West of somebody else? Is the West therefore distinguished from such previous global centres of civilization as the Central Kingdom that claimed itself as the centre without the regime of self-referentiality so that it could never have a positive outside, a realm outside the Central Kingdom? In this respect, the emperor of China once was literally the son of the Heaven. II) If one positively positions oneself as the origin of spontaneity, will one possibly demarcate the distinction between the self and the alternate? Regardless of whether it is in dialectics or psychoanalysis, the self is always a secondary postulate, posterior either to consciousness (in dialectics) or to the specularity of an image in the imaginary register (in psychoanalysis). In this respect, the designation ‘Asia’ behaves normally, so to say, and the problem of its derivative character, marked by the legacy of colonial ‘defeat’ derives, not inherently from the postulation of Asia, but rather from the priority granted to Europe or the West. There is no question that the mutual 20 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 determination of the West and the Rest involves power relations, but these should not be construed in terms of activity and passivity. Power relations that posit the West and Asia as designees are not governed by the causality of cause and effect, of spontaneity and receptivity; instead of the logic of causality (hatarakumono) or effectuating, they are rather organized by the logic of seeing or reflectivity (mirumono).14 For our management of analysis concerning theory and Asian humanity, we must shift our focus from Asia to Europe or the West in a sort of counter movement to Takeuchi Yoshimi’s. For this reason the questions I want to entertain are only reflectively and indirectly concerned with Asian humanity. They are these: on what ground was theory considered as being European in origin? what sort of argument tried to justify the presumption that theory is something that we expect of Europe or the West? how has this presumption managed to remain hidden until now? what would follow if the conditions no longer existed by which we normally expect theory out of Europe or the West? In other words, how can we possibly assess the disappearance of this civilizational ‘normalcy’ and disenchant ourselves with the civilizational spell? Now under the scope of theory and Asian humanity, it is possible to view a number of famous arguments that have attempted to explicate in one way or another why we somewhat presume that there ought to be some intimate link between theory – variously talked about under the headings of modern 21 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 rationality, scientific reason, commitment to the spirit of rigor whereby universal openness to knowledge production has been sustained, incessant return to the archê of the Greek origins - and Europe or the West: Max Weber’s discussion on European modernity and Protestant ethic, Paul Valéry’s insights into the crisis of the European spirit, Edmund Husserl’s inquiries concerning the crisis of European humanity, and Martin Heidegger’s attempt to rescue Western metaphysics, as well as many others. I have drawn tentative examples from the first half of the 20th century in which the term Europe was gradually replaced by the West. The first half of the 20th century is significant in many respects, since, for the first time, the West or Europe became a topic of such intense debate. Then it is in the element of crisis that Europe or the West was acknowledged globally and for the first time as a domineering centre of the world. But, as soon as it somewhat succeeded in receiving the legitimacy of the global hegemony, it began to suffer from a confusionism inherent in its identity. Who are Europeans after all? Where does the West end, and the Rest of the world start? What constitutes the very border by which the distinction of the West from the Rest can be drawn? ***** Christopher GoGwilt notes that the term Europe was called into question early in the twentieth century when the term the West gained a new rhetorical force. In reference to Heidegger’s discussion of ‘nihilism’, he shows that, in 22 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 discussing it Nietzsche never ascribed the word Western to it. Citing passages from Heidegger’s Nietzsche however, GoGwilt writes, ‘Heidegger here translates Nietzsche’s term European (‘europäish’) into the post-Nietzschean terminology ‘Western history’ (‘abendländischen Geschichte’).’15 Heidegger was lecturing on Nietzsche in Germany under National Socialism, and his terms are of course inflected in complex ways by debates of the 1930’s. Yet precisely the distance between the contested terms of Nietzsche’s Europe and those of Heidegger’s West indicates that the term Western acquired a rhetorical force between the 1890’s and the 1930’s.’16 After the emergence of such a use of the term the West which originated from the Russian Slavophile-Westerner controversy over nihilism, GoGwilt argues, Oswald Spengler could make the following claim about Europe and the West in his Introduction to The Decline of the West. The word ‘Europe’ ought to be struck out of history. There is historically no ‘European’ type .... It is thanks to this word ‘Europe’ alone, and the complex of ideas resulting from it, that our historical consciousness has come to link Russia with the West in an utterly baseless unity -- a mere abstraction derived from the reading of books -- that has led to immense real consequences.17 A half century later than Nietzsche, Heidegger’s focus was on Western metaphysics. During the interwar period, there is no doubt that the problem of theory and the West was implicated in the general question of ‘Europe for the 23 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Europeans.’ To discriminate Europeans from non-Europeans in Europe was a daunting task then. But it is also a task that an increasing number of Europeans want to engage in once again today, after a seventy-year hibernation. We must never lose sight of the fact that the opposition of the West and the Rest served then and still does now as a trope whereby to constitute ‘Europe for the Europeans.’ After the Second World War, implicitly and explicitly, the presumed center of the West moved westward across the North Atlantic, and Americans began to claim the throne of the West. Given the tremendous versatility with which the West has been determined cartographically, ethnically, culturally, politically, economically and socially, it would not be at all surprising for the West to shift elsewhere, once again in a few decades, and to the eastern shore of Eurasian Continent facing the South China Sea, for instance. However, the endless wandering and dissemination of this floating designee named the West is not subject-matter for my argument in this chapter. Instead we should concern ourselves with the question of theory and the West, with how theory can presumably be the exclusive possession of the West. ***** By inquiring into the geneaology of colonial modernity, we now begin to comprehend why theory had to be so intimately associated with the West. There is a figure of ‘man’ or humanity, yet this humanity was not ‘man’ in general. 24 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Instead it had to be modified by an adjectival, ‘European’ or ‘Western.’ Thus the geneaolgical analysis of colonial modernity exposes the participation of a certain humanism in modernity. In what underlies the possibility of talking about the modern at all, it is essential to deal with an other of the modern, the pre-modern, with reference to which modernity has also been defined in a great many instances. Unless it is contrasted with the pre-modern, the modern cannot acquire any definitive sense as a periodic adjectival. This pairing may suggest a chronological order. Yet, it must be remembered that this order has never been dissociated from the geopolitical configuration of the world. As is known very well by now, this basically nineteenth-century historical scheme provides a perspective through which to comprehend the locations and statuses of nations, cultures, traditions, and races in a systematic manner. The historico-geopolitical pairing of the premodern and the modern has been one of the major organizing apparatuses of academic discourse in which modernity, modernization, and even modernism have been discussed. The emergence in the 1980’s of the third and enigmatic term, the postmodern, possibly testified not so much to a transition from one period to another as to the shift or transformation of our discourse as a result of which the supposed indisputability of the historico-geopolitical pairing - modern and pre-modern - has become increasingly problematic and unsettling. Of course, it was not the first time the validity of this differentiation was challenged. Yet, surprisingly enough, the pre-modern – modern opposition has managed to 25 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 survive many challenges, and it would be extremely optimistic to believe it has finally been found ineffectual. Nevertheless, those who still want to presume that this historico-geopolitical pairing is somewhat ‘normal’ now suffer from a sense of insecurity. Particularly in those disciplines dealing with Asia in the West or in countries accustomed to regarding themselves as ‘modern,’ the level of anxiety has never been higher than today. Either as a set of socioeconomic conditions or as an adherence of a society to selected values, the term ‘modernity’ can never be understood without reference to this dichotomy of the pre-modern and the modern. Historically, modernity has primarily been opposed to its historical precedent; geopolitically it has been contrasted to the non-modern, or, more specifically, to the non-West. Thus the periodic dichotomy has served as a historico-geopolitical scheme according to which a historical predicate is translated into a geopolitical one and vice versa. A propositional subject is posited through the attribution of these predicates, and thanks to the function of this discursive apparatus, two kinds of areas are diacritically discerned: the modern West and the premodern non-West. As a matter of course, this does not mean either that the West was never at premodern stages or that the non-West can never be modernized: it simply excludes the possibility of the simultaneous coexistence of the premodern West and the modern non-West. A temporal differentiation is turned into a cartographic trope, so that the geographic expanse of the globe is dissected into 26 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 the stages of development, which in turn spatially represents a chronological series of World History. A cursory examination of the chronological-cartographic tropics of modernity amply suggests a certain polarity or warp among the possible ways to conceive of the world historically and geopolitically. For the West to be, there must be a scheme of the world that is organized by the polarity, and this polarity continually reproduces unbalance or extra-ordinary one-sidedness between the West and the Rest, so that the West is regarded as the source of global flow of commodities, ideas and institutions. The classic vision of modernization has never questioned this reproducibility of the polarity upon which not only the developmental teleology but also the disciplines of area studies have wittingly or unwittingly relied. As some Asian intellectuals pointed out in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, there is no inherent reason why the West/non-West opposition should determine the geographic perspective of modernity except for the fact that it definitely serves to establish the putative unity of the West, a nebulous but commanding positivity whose existence has been increasingly tainted with a sense of uncertainty in recent decades. After all, the West is a name for a positionality, which is postulated in the microphysics of power relations and is also an object constituted discursively. Evidently, the West is a name always associating itself with those regions, communities, and peoples that appear politically or economically superior to other regions, communities, and peoples. Basically, it is just like the name 27 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 ‘Europe,’ which reputedly designates a geographic area, a tradition, a religion, a culture, an ethnos, a market, a population, and so on; yet, unlike all the other names associated with geographic particularities, it also implies the refusal of its self-delimitation or particularistic determination; it claims that it is capable of sustaining, if not actually transcending, the impulse to transcend all the particularizations. This is to say that the West is never content with what it is recognized as by others; it is always urged to approach others in order to ceaselessly transform its self-image; it continually seeks itself in the midst of interaction with other peoples, civilizations, and races; it would never be satisfied with being recognized but would also wish to recognize others; it would rather be a supplier of recognition than a receiver thereof. In short, the West must represent the moment of the universal, which subsumes the particular. It is the source of spontaneity, whose initiative must be received by its subordinates. Thus, the West is supposed to assume the positionality of universal activity by assigning to the Rest of the world the positionality of particular passivity, as Takeuchi Yoshimi clearly saw in the way in which Asia was identified as such in colonial modernity. Indeed, the West is particular in itself, but it also constitutes the universal point of reference in relation to which others recognize themselves as particularities. Empirically it is a particularity, but it always engages in the universal validity of how particular objects are identified. In this respect, it is transcendental. The West is structured as a doublet with one side in the empirical 28 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 and the other in the transcendental, striding over both the determinate and the indeterminate; it is fashioned after what 18th century neologism called the ‘subject.’ Unlike Asia whose identity must depend upon its recognition, the West does not seem to need the other to recognize it. Or, to put it slightly differently, it is claimed - and this claim must be questioned as I have already hinted at – that the West is capable of initiating its self-recognition. And, in this regard, the West thinks itself to be ubiquitous and spontaneous; it is omnipresent and unique; it represents the universalism of the international world and is the unique and exceptional leader of the world. Normalcy, with the presumption of which an intimate association of theory and the West is taken for granted, comes from this peculiar status of the West. And, this normalcy was once called ‘man’ by Michel Foucault, namely a problematic of ‘an empirico-transcendental doublet’ that has continued to motivate the sciences of man or the humanities in general for the last two centuries.18 Michel Foucault deployed the Heideggerian problematic of finitude in his archeological analysis of ‘human being’ and thrived on illustrating the internal dynamic of humanism in the production of knowledge in the humanities. However, I do not think that he explored the significance of his own formula empirico-transcendental doublet in colonial modernity.19 The modern positivity of man is characterized by man’s mode of being, that is, the mode of ‘repetition – of 29 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 the identity and the difference between the positive and the fundamental’ ‘within the figure of the Same.’20 ..man became that upon which all knowledge could be constituted as immediate and non-problematized evidence; he became, a fortiori, that which justified the calling into question of all knowledge of man. Hence that double and inevitable contestation: that which lies at the root of the perpetual controversy between the sciences of man and the science proper – the first laying an invincible claim to be the foundation of the second, which are ceaselessly obliged in turn to seek their own foundation, the justification of their method, and the purification of their history, in the teeth of ‘psychologism,’ ‘sociologism,’ and ‘historicism.’21 It is important to note that the politically and intellectually significant debates of the crisis of the European spirit or Western humanity in the first half of the 20th century – Weber, Valéry, Husserl and Heidegger, to mention only the representative figures – could not evade calling the foundation of scientific reason into question in specifically humanistic terms. Through theory, therefore, they had to address how it was ever possible to find ‘human’ legitimacy for scientific rationality, but in this process they had to encounter the problem of European humanity. Precisely because of the humanistic problematic – the finitude of man - motivating the production of knowledge in the humanities, 30 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 they could not but doubt about the destiny of European humanity. This explains why the crisis of scientific rationality was first construed in terms of the crisis of European humanity. Let me note in passing that, despite an alluring analysis of ‘the empirical – transcendental doublet’ called man, the notion of Western culture or its unity is never under suspicion anywhere in Foucault’s career, and that he never interrogated the putative unity of the West in relation to modern humanism. Nevertheless, his analysis offers the most important insight into the presumed affiliation between theory and the West, or the teleology of reason and European humanity. ***** The West is a peculiar designee – and a social imaginary as far as its modality of existence is concerned - because, in the first place, it may appear to be the name of a certain geographical place and, by extension, that of the people inhabiting it. On the somewhat strained assumption that it is a primarily geographic designation with fairly clear contours, the West could regulate our way of representing the production of knowledge, particularly in the humanities or human sciences. Yet it is impossible to verify that the West is either a geographic territory with an affiliated population, or a unified cultural and social formation. Its indexing function changes according to the contingent conditions 31 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 of its particular use in each instance it is applied. One may expect to find some substance underlying many uses of this appellation, but one will realize how hard it is to establish any coherence among varied instances where the West is called forth. The West can mean a different thing each time. It is excessively overdetermined. Nonetheless, it cannot be called an anomaly since every proper noun seems to subsume a wide variety of heterogeneous referents under its singular designation. So, what is somewhat exceptional about the West? I have already remarked on this point in these ways; first, the West is not a place-name in the same way as California or Shandong because it is incapable of specifying a fixed point on the surface of the earth; second, the West is a directional designation by which the position of the speaker is indicated in terms of its relationality. It is open to a wide variety of appropriations, as a result of which it can gather together all sorts of different referents to such an extent that it appears contradictory in concept. It is impossible to find the features by which the different manifestations of the West are coherent. On the contrary, its internal coherence is presumptive; its unity always remains putative. It is only our essentialist insistence upon its geographic and cultural uniformity that evokes its putative unity. This putative unity of the West seems to bestow a sense of coherence upon the configuration of disciplines in the humanities. It serves to mark a distinction between the areas and peoples that can be objects of ethnic and area-studies and those that cannot. People in the West ordinarily do not receive the attribute 32 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 ‘ethnic,’ because, supposedly, they are not to be defined in terms of their status as an object of study: before being studied, known, and recognized, they are expected to take an active attitude in that studying, knowing, and recognizing. Instead of being passively inspected, classified, compared, and analyzed, they are supposed to engage in applying their own means of inspection, classification, comparison, and analysis to some object, which might well be themselves. When a group of people are characterized exclusively in their communal mores and local histories, they are demoted to ethnicity and treated as though they were mute, passive and anonymous objects of the West’s observing gaze. Let us recall that, when Husserl denied the status of philosophy to ‘Indian and Chinese philosophies,’ he attributed ‘anthropological types’ to knowledge produced by Indian and Chinese philosophers.22 I am not sure how familiar Husserl was with works by those philosophers, but his comments are in accord with the regime of the polarity characteristic of colonial modernity. The Asians may well produce certain wisdom, but their wisdom could never transcend their ethnic particularity to the domain of theoretical universality. What was lacking in Indian and Chinese philosophies was the practical commitment to theory, an attitude of theoretical universality open beyond the institutional conditions of their life worlds. Let us keep in mind that, in this implicit racism of theory, Husserl was not exceptional. Due the lack of space here, a more adequate reading of racism in Western philosophy must be executed elsewhere. In short, in this epistemic 33 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 transaction, the West insists on being determined in terms, not of its characteristics as an object of knowledge, but rather of its subjective faculties and productivity. Tentatively, let me attribute the name ‘theory’ to these certain subjective faculties and productivity, which distinguish European ‘men’ from ethnicity, the West from the Rest of humanity. Accordingly, we could discern two radically different ways for people to relate themselves to the production of knowledge in the humanities. The group of people whose regional, civilizational, national, or ethnic identity constitutes the objective legitimacy of the discipline would participate in the production of knowledge within that discipline, primarily as suppliers of raw data and factual information. Information thus supplied by them helps identify their ethnic particularities and types, but they remain positive and empirical in their production of knowledge. They need to engage neither in the application of a classificatory system or of the evaluative methods in the processing of such data, nor the preparation of an epistemic framework through which the data are appropriated into a general interpretative narrative. In not engaging in those tasks, they do not need to participate in the critical review or innovation of those means of knowledge-production. In this respect, their attitude toward knowledge production is ‘traditional’ in the classical sense of the word. They inherit the methods of scholarship from their mentors and are devoted to the conservation of what they have been handed. Their scholarship is characterized as a sort of apprenticeship rather than by its scientificity. In due course it is 34 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 beyond apprentices’ expectation to criticize their mentors, to desire to overcome the mentors’ accomplishments, or to continually innovate the means and scope of knowing. In this sense, the traditional scholars are undoubtedly hostile to theory. As they are supposedly not held responsible for this kind of critical review and innovation, they rarely confront the reality of existing knowledge in the humanities, namely, the reality that the presumptions and procedures circulated within the disciplines are far from being systematically coherent or complete. Indeed, as ‘modern’ – supposedly opposed to ‘traditional’ - scholarly disciplines, these are under trenchant scrutiny and constant revision, and, moreover, the humanities are maintained and revitalized by constant revision and innovation of their own means of knowledge-production. What keeps the sciences of man going is this insatiable movement of self-overcoming; in this respect, the sciences are totally subordinate to the locus of modernity, an ambiguous position occupied by Foucault’s ‘man.’ Thus the humanities are produced in the element of the historicity of ‘man,’ and must be a part of historical knowledge. Hence, unless one engages in the historical overcoming of knowledge, one cannot be said to be actively participating in the discourse of modern man, not to mention the spirit of European humanity. The suppliers of raw data and factual information are involved in the production of knowledge in the humanities, but they are not participating there as ‘men.’ Certainly they are humans, and, in that capacity, 35 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 offer information concerning the particular cases of humanity and human nature. And, most often, they are found outside the West, or more precisely, they are supposed to constitute the outside of the putative unity of the West. They are disqualified as European humanity because they are unfit for the mission the West is endowed with. On the other hand, there is another sort of people who seek to know about humanity and human nature, but who would never be content as suppliers of information. They refuse to be content with the accumulation of factual and empirical knowledge. For them, knowing is an essential part of their being, so that their way of life will be affected as their relationship to knowledgeproduction changes. They necessarily engage in the collection, evaluation, comparison, or analysis of raw data, but, more importantly, they are continually involved in the critical review of the existing means of knowing and the invention of new means. Their concern for their subjective conditions in knowing carries the weight of an almost moral imperative. For them, knowledge about humanity and human nature must not only consist of the variety of particular cases but must also entail commitment to a critical inspection of existing knowledge and to the project of changing and creating the means of knowing about humanity and human nature. They must constantly strive to overcome the limits of their own accomplishments. Everyone within the putative unity of the West is not automatically inside this group of people – e.g. Husserl excluded gypsies from European humanity! And this exclusion must be thought through 36 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 with regard to the very demarcation of European humanity. - but presumably they are representative of the West and can only be found in the West. The project of changing and creating the means of knowing is commonly called ‘theory,’ and it is taken to be a distinguishing mark or even mission of the West. In this sense, ‘theory’ is presumably the essence of Western humanity. Thus, two different relationships to the production of knowledge presuppose two different conceptions of humanity in the humanities. Humanity is studied through many cases of, and particular manifestations of man’s nature. It is presumed that, by extracting what many peoples in the world have in common, ultimately knowledge about ‘human nature’ will be attained. In such an instance, the notion of humanity as the guiding principle is that of general humanity which inheres in every particular manifestation of man. Yet a completely different relationship is also possible. It relates to the production of knowledge reflectively, and tries to set new conditions of knowing, thereby transforming both the constitution of the object for knowledge-production and the subjective conditions of knowing. In this latter relationship to knowledgeproduction, humanity is problematized not only as a generality that encompasses all the particular cases but also in the aspect of subjective conditions: humanity manifests itself in self-reflective knowing about knowing and in the legislation of the new means of knowing to which ‘man’ willingly subjects himself. The humanity that is sought in the second relationship is, therefore, not only epistemic but also practical: what is at issue here is not general but universal 37 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 humanity, to use the Kantian distinction between generality and universality. And this rift of the epistemic and the practical is probably the site where modern ‘man’ resides; this was the topos where European humanity was perceived as in crisis by many in the first half of the 20th century. Since the nineteenth century, as Dipesh Chakrabarty and Osamu Nishitani have observed independently of one another,23 the difference between these two relationships to knowledge-production in the humanities has been hinted at by the juxtaposition of two classical analogues, humanitas and anthropos. As the historical evolution of anthropology suggests, humanitas has meant people who could engage in knowledge-production in both the first and the second relationships, while anthropos has gradually been reserved for peoples who participate in knowledge-production only in the first. Thus, humanity in the sense of humanitas has come to designate Western or European humanity, to be distinguished from the rest of humanity as long as we trust in and insist upon the putative unity of the West. This means that humanity in the sense of humanitas authorizes the very distinction of the West from what Stuart Hall incisively called ‘the Rest.’24 This is one reason why I suspect that, as ethnic studies generally implies a disciplinary knowledge imposed on anthropos, the idea of the ethnic studies of European Americans would not be welcome. In fact, until recently, North America and Western Europe were not ‘areas’ in higher education in the United States, for supposedly the objects of area studies could only be found outside the West. The ethnic studies of European Americans or the area studies 38 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 of North America could have undermined this configured division of humanitas and anthropos, and opened up the way towards treating European Americans as ‘anthropological types.’ This might just conjure up some resistance. As if following from such a separation of humanitas and anthropos, the global circulation of information maps two different flows of academic information. The first is a centripetal flow from peripheral sites to various metropolitan centers in Western Europe and North America. However, this flow of factual data about anthropos provided by the peripheries is not presumed to be immediately legible to those not familiar with local contexts. Such obstacles to transparent legibility are often attributed conceptually to the cultural and ethnic particularities of peoples in the Rest. And such information is regarded as too raw or particularistic to be understood by a non-specialist metropolitan readership because of its dense empirical content; it therefore requires translation into the more general theoretical language of humanitas. The second movement is a centrifugal flow of information about how to classify domains of knowledge, how to evaluate given empirical data, how to negotiate with the variety and incommensurability inherent in the body of empirical data from the peripheries, and how to render intelligible the details and trivia coming from particular peripheral sites to “a Western audience.” This is to say that the centrifugal flow corresponds roughly to the inquiry into the selfreflective ‘theory’ about the subjective conditions of knowing. Academic information of this second kind is generally called ‘theory,’ and its production 39 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 has largely occurred according to a historically specific division of intellectual labor in which ‘theory’ is associated with the mythical construct of the West, and moves out from it to the Rest of the world. Predictably, the economy of the centripetal and centrifugal flows maps the outline of the polarized world of colonial modernity. Let me again issue a cautionary disclaimer. I am not offering a description of the state of the humanities today. On the contrary, this presumed division of intellectual labor has been eroded, and we must conduct an archaeological analysis on how our essentialist insistence upon the putative unity of the West restricts us from acknowledging the dislocation of the West. There are so many instances in which such an old distinction between humanitas and anthropos has been abraded that nowadays the actual practices of ethnic studies, area-studies, and anthropology no longer abide by expectations resulting from the putative unity of the West. Increasingly the configuration of the humanities deviates from the economy of information flow, regulated by the old distinction of humanitas and anthropos. Already in the 1980’s cultural anthropology was no longer capable of finding its legitimate object of inquiry among the ‘primitive’ people. Only some in old area studies can still believe that their object people are located away from them, and that the natives of those areas are separated from the area specialists geographically, culturally, and epistemologically. It may appear that the transformation of the humanities in the late 20th century and the early 21st 40 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 century is characterized by the disappearance of ‘primitive people’ and of the conditions of the polarity characteristic of colonial modernity. The prevailing view of global academic exchange is no longer acceptable because, clearly, its material conditions are in the process of being undermined. (The West, astonishingly, is not fading. But precisely because the historical conditions for the separability of the West from the Rest are being undermined, I am afraid, its distinction might well be emphasized all the more obsessively. For, the distinction can only be sustained with a ‘possessive investment in the West,’ to rephrase the title of George Lipsitz’s book.25) ***** What, then, is the West, after all? Let me first respond to this inquiry from the standpoint of Asian Studies, a collection of area-studies fields left over from the days of the Cold War in American higher education and the surviving legacy of even older oriental studies in European imperial centers. Partly because of the consequences of accelerating globalization and the emergence of what, for the last decade or two, a number of people have referred to as postmodern conditions discernible almost everywhere on the globe, we are urged to acknowledge that the unity of the West is far from being unitarily determinable. What we believe we understand by the West is increasingly 41 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 ambiguous and incongruous: the West’s immoderately overdetermined nature can no longer be buried. Until recently, the indigenous or local characteristic of a social and cultural construct found in places in Asia, Africa, and Latin America has routinely been earmarked in contrast to some generalized and euphemistic quality specified as being ‘Western.’ Without this institutionalized gesture with which to identify what is unfamiliar or enigmatic to those who self-fashion themselves to be ‘Westerners’ in terms of the West-and-the Rest binary opposition, it would be impossible to understand the initial formation of Asian Studies as a set of academic disciplines in North American academia. Things Asiatic were first brought to scholarly attention by being recognized as ‘different and therefore Asian.’ Then, tacitly from the presumed vantage point of the West, ‘being different from us’ and ‘being Asian’ were taken to be synonymous in an anthropologizing gesture. A similar operation could well be performed with Africa or Latin America, so as to identify Africa or Latin America as belonging to the Rest of the World, the Rest which remains when the humanity of the West is forcibly extracted from the World. Too often, therefore, the designation ‘Asian,’ a representative designation of the Rest, has been accompanied by a sense of ‘being different from us’ which in a reflective manner earmarks the ethnic or racial positionality of the Asianists as Westerners. What is fundamental in the ‘anthropological’ description of Asia is the primordial exposure of the observer to the look of the natives, what Rey 42 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Chow calls ‘the to-be-looked-at-ness,’ which precedes the self-determination of the observer as a Westerner and the native as Asian, and also discloses the position of the observer in ethnographic description primarily as the observed rather than the observer. 26 It follows that the anthropologizing observer’s selffashioning as a Westerner is essentially a reactive self-posturing, reactive precisely because, in order to posture him-or-herself as a Western observer, the observer has to disavow the initial moment of what Johannes Fabian called ‘coevalness.’27 As outlined in my critique of Takeuchi Yoshimi, the self-referentiality of the West is a consequence of this reversal, of reactive self-posturing. But for this reversal, the West could never postulate itself as an active and spontaneous agent whose identity is expected to be independent of an encounter with an other. It follows that what is decisive in the putative unity of the West is the postulation of separation, an operation of inscribing a border – ‘bordering,’ as conceptualized by Sandro Mezzadra and Brett Neilson – to make the world appear as if it had already and always been divided between the West and the Rest, to presume that, somewhat naturally and essentially, the separation of the West from the Rest or Asia had been preordained and prescribed. Therefore, in the discussions of European humanity during the first half of the 20th century, the anxiety concerning the crisis of the European spirit was accompanied by the essentialist insistence upon the unity of the West; the essentialist insistence on the West’s unity had to seek the archê of what originarily constituted the West – or Europe – 43 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 as the Greek origin to which the Europeans returned to assert their future as Europeans. In the fields of Asian studies, however, this level of commitment to theory can hardly be expected even though many of the specialists frequently appeal to the opposition of the West and the Rest. As a matter of fact, many of the experts working in the fields of Asian studies, are least interested in theory and, in some cases, positively hostile to it. Even though it is glaringly obvious that the majority of experts should be classified into anthropos, they do not have misgivings about the very binary of humanitas and anthropos; rarely do they challenge the presumption that we normally do not expect theory of Asia. Yet, this peculiar situation exists not only in the West. Notwithstanding the fact that the binary serves to figure out not only the non-Western or Asian ‘other’ but also ‘the Western self’ of North American and European Asianists in the regime of self-referentiality, we must not overlook the fact that it also operates practically in the production and reproduction of knowledge in countries in Asia (and other sites believed to be located in the Rest). In these places the institutions of human and social sciences, such as sociology and English departments at universities, have been established initially as local agents for the propagation and translation of European or North American - and one might add Japanese as well, although much less obvious and smaller in scale - knowledge which is euphemistically labelled as ‘Western’; and, even today, most of these institutions are still caught in the habit of regarding themselves as 44 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 secondary or derivative, that is, as imitators or importers, of Western theory: it is somewhat held as a truism that theory cannot be generated in the Rest, so that it must be imported from the West. What they have deliberately overlooked is that, in ‘the West’ too, scholars imitate and import just as in natural sciences and the fields of engineering. They have so far failed in objectifying the mythology of European humanity originating ancient Greek geometry as spontaneous, creative and productive agent. They have yet to rid themselves of their undue sense of indebtedness to the influence of the West and its metropolitan centers. In fact, the sense of separation between the West and Asia is best manifest among scholars in Asian countries who feel somewhat excluded or rejected by the West. The West-and-the-Rest opposition does not only designate the boundary of one civilization from another fantastically: it is also interwoven into the texture of the imaginary reality of the ethnic nation as it has been formulated in Asia. In other words, the national, civilizational, and racial identity of the nation in Asia requires the implicit and ubiquitous presence of the West. The binary of humanitas and anthropos is indeed a matter of epistemic positionality, but it also serves as a trope for other power relations. Only insofar as the West is felt to be the point of counter-reference can nationality in the Rest be rendered sensible to the populace. In this instance, let me take a moment to note, one more time, that the West thus disclosed is not a determinate position which exists prior to the anthropologizing gesture of equating ‘being different from us’ to ‘being Asian.’ 45 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 In ‘our’ encounter with people of unknown background, of linguistic heritage, or intellectual tradition, ‘we’ may well be incapable of comprehending what is going on between ‘you’ and ‘us’; ‘we’ can be at a loss at the locale of incommensurability; ‘we’ might go through an experience of non-sense as to what ‘you’ and ‘we’ are doing together. This is to say that the relationship of ‘you’ and ‘us’ cannot be subsumed under the existing system of comprehension, so that it fails to make sense within the common-sense making mechanism. Yet, this experience of non-sense or radical difference cannot be appropriated by the trope of gap, border or separation. If ‘you’ and ‘we’ are separated by a gap or insulated from one another by a border, an encounter in which non-sense is experienced would never happen. Preceding the demarcation of ‘you’ and ‘us,’ a different type of ‘we’ - ‘we’ as the place or khora of primordial sociality - must exist as the locale of encounter. This ‘we’ is no longer a position determined in the system of personal pronominals; it is rather a surface on which distinct pronominal positions, ‘I,’ ‘you,’ ‘we,’ and ‘they,’ are emblazoned. It is the surface of sociality on which personal relations can be inscribed. Unless it is possible to talk about this ‘we,’ the bordering of the West and the Rest would be inconceivable. Consequently we would not recognize the presence of either a gap or border that prevents us from making sense together. On the contrary, in such an encounter, we come across the experience of discontinuity.28 But, discontinuity cannot be equated to a cut, gap, barrier, or border. By ascribing two distinct binary figures of the West and the Rest or 46 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Europe and Asia to ‘us’ and ‘you,’ however, the sense of incomprehensibility is appropriated into the tropics of civilizational difference, a difference already in the order of continuity. By locating the occasion of non-sense, incommensurability or incomprehensibility within the binary configuration of the West and the Rest, the very difference of discontinuity is anthropologized, and apprehended as if it bore the order of continuity from the outset. As I argued elsewhere, the regime of co-figuration operates in the element of continuity, and the experience of discontinuity disrupts the schematism of co-figuration.29 What is overlooked in this insidious transition from discontinuity to continuity is that discontinuity means something unrepresentable; incomprehensibility, non-sense, or incommensurability points to an experience – if experience is strictly a statement describing a state of affairs empirically meaningful, then it should not be called ‘experience’ – that can not be rendered in representation. It is, therefore, impossible to represent it in terms of a figure of gap or border, since gap or border always implies some sort of break within the continuous space. This binary of the West and the Rest is made to imply a lot more than a contrast of epistemic attitudes; condensed in the opposition of humanitas and anthropos are other social and personal features such as gender, wealth, profession, social class background, and level of cultural capital, features which are most frequently appealed to in order to differentiate one individual from another, to classify people within a social hierarchy. 47 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 The West comes into being precisely when ‘being different from us’ is thus rendered analogous to ‘being Asian,’ ‘being African,’ and so forth. Similarly, from the viewpoint of those who fashion themselves as non-Westerners and as belonging to the Rest, the West is also postulated at the moment that ‘being different from us’ and ‘being Western’ are taken as synonymous. Instead of being construed in view of many different social features, conversation and interaction about knowledge are figured exclusively in terms of a schema consisting of the two poles of the West-and-the-Rest. All the other social relations palpable in intellectual exchange are subordinated to this bi-polar co-figuration; any cultural incommensurabilities one may encounter are all reduced to figures commensurate with the schema of co-figuration.30 So, for ‘the Westerners,’ the thematization of things Asiatic as ‘being different from us’ is the first move to negate or exorcise ‘them’ from ‘us’ in such a way as to prepare the very possibility of representing ‘them’ as Asia, and ‘us’ as the West, according to the schema of co-figuration. The Asiatic essence of things Asiatic is thematized and isolated just like a figure separated by its frame from its background, so to speak. And one of the necessary conditions for the West to be perceived real is that it is assumed to be recognized as such by its counterpart, the Rest, in a symmetrical and transferential manner. ***** 48 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Another disclaimer must be issued at this juncture. I have not so far offered a concise description of how theory has been conceived of or what it ought to be. Nor have I suggested by theory any specific protocol by which a formula in the form of a theorem can be applied to individual empirical cases to draw some conclusive generalized judgment. First of all, I want to keep in mind that the relationship that regulates theory and experience is not one of generality and particularity. So, by theory, I do not imply something that is applied to empirical data. To be theoretical is not to search for general formulae by which particular cases can be classified and subsumed under general patterns. Yet at the same time, by theory, I assume certain openness to repetition and refutation. Unless it is able to be reproduced, reinscribed, or reinstated by any person or any group of people, I do not think it is worth examining as such. Thus, theory always is concerned with knowledge production, but it is further involved in the reproduction and modification of the mode of knowledge production. In this sense, theory is universal. Theory is thus open to anybody; it must be institutionally guaranteed that the process of knowledge production not be confined to a closed circle of connoisseurs or apprentices; it can be imitated, reproduced, reinscribed or modified by anybody; the type of knowledge that cannot withstand this open process of imitation, reproduction, reinscription and modification cannot qualify as theoretical. The system of specialization we adhere to in our universities today may well be far too inadequate to be called theoretical in this sense. 49 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 After the devastation of the First World War, Paul Valéry concluded that Europe could only find its uniqueness in the essential openness and universality to which supposedly it was committed. Only through its continual selftransformation and self-innovation in the project of self-transcendence could it remain identical as Europe. Above I referred to Takeuchi Yoshimi’s insight about Asian modernity, in which it is difficult not to detect a resonance with Valéry, whose publications were translated into Japanese. As a matter of fact, the crisis of European humanity was no longer a matter exclusively for the Europeans, even in the 1930’s. For Valéry, Europe emerged for the first time as internally unified only when its self-transcendence and coherence, or what he eventually capitulated to – in spite of himself - the Hegelian naming, ‘spirit,’ was fundamentally threatened. Europe came into being simultaneously with the ‘crisis’ of its spirit. One may find a resolute expression of the project of transcendental and universalistic thinking in his adoption of this term ‘spirit’ as well as his idiosyncratic notion of the ‘method.’ Valéry emphasized that Europe is not a continent,31 which would imply that it was distinguished from the Rest of the world not predominantly in terms of geographic markers, historical heritages, residential populations, or other historical continuities. Instead what he recognized as the actuality of Europe consisted in an extraordinary inbalance and unequal distribution of resources and wealth in the world; beyond this existing one-sidedness, Europe could be defined only as a capacity to reproduce this 50 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 inbalance against the natural law of energy dispersion. Just as a drop of blood in the ocean spreads, dilutes, and eventually disappears, an artificially created inbalance gradually dissolves and moves towards an equilibrium in which balance is restored. Europe is a perversion against the law of equilibrium; it betrays the natural progression in which entropy is bound to increase; Europe has a miraculous capacity to reverse this process which nature dictates. Valéry believed that Europe could only find its unity in the essential openness and universality to which it is committed. But, precisely because of its adherence to what makes it possible for Europe to exist, it could not help being exposed to the constant danger of its dilution, dispersal, and dissolution. In short, Europe was to express the two extremities inherent in capitalism: maximization in the unequal distribution of wealth and resources, on the one hand, and endless commodification and standardization, on the other. Europe was theory in the sense that it thus meant a commitment to the mutually contradictory principles of the openness and universality that work in accordance with the increase of entropy in the world system, on one side, and a miraculous reversal of nature that reproduces the inbalance against the law of thermodynamics, on the other. Today, nearly one century later, what Valéry summarized as the essential feature of Europe can be seen in the emanation vision of colonial modernity. Retrospectively we can see that, perhaps unwittingly, his diagnosis of the crisis 51 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 of the European spirit disclosed an essential condition for the formation of European humanity, that is, modern colonialism. Therefore, what was perceived as crisis was an intimation of the age of decolonization, when the distinction between humanitas and anthropos can no longer be projected onto a cartographic plane. Perhaps the crisis of European humanity anticipated a situation in which Europe no longer commands a miraculous inbalance and where it is thoroughly provincialized - European humanity being reduced to anthropological types. In this situation, theory would not have to be ascribed to any geopolitically-determined location. By no means can I be certain that modern colonialism is over today. Therefore, I hesitate to speak as if the two classical analogues of humanitas and anthropos have lost the relevance they once enjoyed. But this much seems certain. It is impossible to comprehend the differentiation of humanitas and anthropos in terms of geopolitical tropes. Two types of people cannot be differentiated from one another by their residential locations. Their distinction cannot be prescribed by geographic parameters. With this understanding, we now can see that a series of important questions remain unarticulated in the statement I referred to at the outset: ‘theory is something that we normally expect theory of Europe (or the West).’ The question we cannot evade today: Who is in Europe or the West? Who are Europeans or Westerners in the very distinction of humanitas and anthropos? Already Husserl cautioned us in a dubious manner32 that European humanity 52 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 was not a matter of territory. Then, how could he somewhat imply European humanity could be distinguished from such anthropological types as Indians and Chinese? How could he differentiate Europeans from the mere residents of the European territory or area (Westerners from the residents of the West) without resorting to the naturalizing tactic of identifying Europeans in terms irrelevant to historical imperatives? Is it feasible to insist that classifying Europeans by such empirical variables as physiognomic features and economic status would not signify determining them essentially as an anthropological type? We know that this implicit inquietude invoked by these questions propelled many who were concerned with European humanity during the interwar period towards the problem of historicity and the Greek origins of European sciences. But, can we still today cling to the lineage of Western civilization in order to know who Westerners are? Can we respond to this series of questions about how to distinguish Europeans from non-Europeans, Westerners from non-Westerns, without inquiring into the conduct and conflicts specific to the locale of the power relation? These positionalities are relational and contingent upon the local conditions of power that frame up the contrasting positionalities of Europe and Asia, the West and the Rest. Neither Europe nor the West is a long-lasting substance or an internally coherent organism. In extremely diverse situations, what we should understand is the microphysics of power relations in which Europe or the West – Asia or the Rest as well - appears substantialized and naturalized? 53 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Through an examination of the microphysics of power relations, let us continue to hope we will eventually disentangle ourselves from the ‘civilizational spell’ about theory and Asian humanity. Yet, it must be stated unambiguously that this analytic of the microphysics of power relations does not remove theory or reject the practical commitment to reflectively and critically engage in the transformation of disciplinary conditions of existent knowledge production. Rather, it is to demonstrate that theory does not require a civilizational selffashioning on the part of one who engages in theory. 1 The first version was published in Postcolonial Studies, vol. 13, no. 4, 2010: 441-464 2 Edmund Husserl repeatedly argued that theory is exclusively European. See, for instance, ‘The Vienna Lecture’ included as an appendix to The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, David Carr trans. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970. 269-299 3 ‘Transpacific Complicity and Comparatist Strategy,’ positions east asia cultures critique, vol. 17, no. 1, 2009. 159-207 4 Friedrich Stadler, ‘The emigration and exile of Austrian intellectuals’ in Vertreibung der Vernunft The Cultural Exodus from Austria, Friedrich Stadler and Peter Weibel ed. Wien and New York, Springer-Verlag, 1995, p. 15. Also cited in Mark Mazower, Dark Continet: Europe’s Twentieth Century, Vintage eBook. 5 The question of the victim speaking on behalf of the victimizer has been explored in my “Two Negations: Fear of Being Excluded and the Logic of Slef-Esteem” in Novel, vol. 37, no. 3, Summer 2004: 229-257. 6 It goes without saying that the West and Europe are clearly two distinct designations, and it is important to differentiate them historically. However, I must undertake the task of historically 54 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 differentiating these two geopolitical, cartographic, racial, and/or civilizational terms elsewhere, mainly for lack of space. Instead, as it is commonly accepted in the use of Eurocentrism – one does not bother to fabricate such terms like Westocentrism or West-centeredness to differentiate the West’s global domination from Europe’s - I would like to allow myself to proceed provisionally in my demonstration in this article as if the West and Europe were interchangeable. 7 For Takeuchi’s discussion of Asian modernity, see; Sakai, “Critique of Modernity: the Problem of Universalism and Particularism” in South Atlantic Quarterly, 87.3, (Summer 1988) or its Japanese translation in Gendai Shiso, 15.15, (December 1987); Takeuchi Yoshimi, “Chûgoku no kindai to nihon no kindai (Chinese modernity and Japanese modernity)” (originally in 1947) in Nihon to Ajia (Tokyo: Chikuma Shobo, 1993): 11–57 ( also published under a different title “Kindai toha nanika (What is modernity?)” in 1948 ). [English translation, ‘What is Modernity’ in What is modernity? Writings of Takeuchi Yoshimi, Richard F. Calichman trans. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005. 53-81] 8 Takeuchi Yoshimi, “Chûgoku no kindai to nihon no kindai (Chinese modernity and Japanese modernity)” op. cit. pp. 15-19. (‘What is modernity?’ in What is modernity? Writings of Takeuchi Yoshimi, op cit. pp. 55-58) 9 Against American scholars of the Modernization Theory, a number of Japanese social scientists and intellectual historians tried to offer a different model of modernization in the 1950’s and 1960’s. In ‘Asia as Method’ (in What is Modernity? Writings of Takeuchi Yoshimi, Richard L. Calichman trans. and ed. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005. 149-165), Takeuchi referred to Tsurumi Kazuko, who advocated for the two distinct types of modernization: the naihatsu type that is motivated from within or ‘development from within’ and the gaihatsu type that imitates the outside model or ‘imposition from without.’ As a critical endeavour against American Imperialism, Tsurumi’s attempt and Takeuchi’s endorsement must be appreciated, but 55 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 what should be called into question is the tropics of the inside and the outside underlying this typology. 10 “You Asians” in ‘We Asians’ between Past and Future, Kwok Kian-Woon, Indira Arumugan, Karen Chia, Lee Chee Keng ed., Singapore, Singapore Heritage Society, 2000: 212-246; “Civilizational Difference and Criticism: On the Complicity of Globalization and Cultural Nationalism” in Modern Chinese Literature and Culture, vol. 17, no. 1, Spring 2005: 188-205. 11 Let me issue a disclaimer here. I do not believe that there is anything abnormal or exceptional in the derivative nature of the designation ‘Asia’ in relation to Europe. Self-referentiality is impossible without the presence of alterity. Although the use of pronominals may well impose a prejudice on our analysis in this case, it is appropriate to say that ‘I’ is a derivative of ‘you.’ Unless ‘you’ can be postulated, ‘I’ cannot be ‘here.’ See Nishida Kitarô, ‘Ware to nanji (I and Thou),’ in Mu no jikaku-teki gentei (Apperceptive determination of mu) Nishida Kitarô Zenshû, vol. 6, Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1965. 341-427 12 Antonio Gramsci, Selections from Prison Notebooks, Quintin Hoarse and Geoffrey Nowell Smith trans., (New York: International Publishers, 1971): 447 13 Takeuchi Yoshimi, What is Modernity? Writings of Takeuchi Yoshimi, op cit. 59 14 Social relation of ‘you’ and ‘I’ should not be construed in terms of activity and passivity. See, Nishida Kitarô, Mu no jikakuteki gentei, [Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1932] (Reprint, Nishida Kitarô Zenshû, vol. 6, Tokyo: Iwanami Shoten, 1965) 15 The Invention of the West - Joseph Conrad and the Double-Mapping of Europe and Empire Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995. 232 16 Ibid. 17 Oswald Spenglar, The Decline of the West, Charles Francis Atkins trans. New York: A. A. Knopf, 1926-1928. Cited in GoGwilt, ibid. 56 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 18 According to Michel Foucault, man is fundamentally historical precisely because man can never be exhaustively determined in its positivity, because the limitlessness of history, inherent in the modern determination of the human being, “perpetually refers certain positivities determining man’s being to the finitude that causes those same positivities to appear.” (Michel Foucault, Les mots et les choses – une archéologie des sciences humaines, Paris: Gallimard, 1966. p. 395) [The Order of Things, New York: Vintage Books, 1973] p. 371] 19 Michel Foucault, The Order of Things, op cit. 20 ibid. p. 315 21 ibid. p. 345 22 See note 2 above. 23 See: Dipesh Chakrabarty, “Marx after Marxism: Subaltern Histories and the Question of Difference” in Polygraph 6, no. 7. Also see: Osamu Nishitani, Translator’s Postface II for Pierre Legendre’s Le Crime du caporal Lortie ( Kyoto: Jinmon Shoin, 1998): 287-8; Osamu Nishitani & Naoki Sakai, Sekaishi no kaitai, (Deconstruction of World History) (Tokyo: Ibunsha, 1999): 20-2, 103-8. Also see: Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, “The awakening of the power of myth – the auto-poietic act – becomes a necessity once the inconsistency of the abstract universals of reason has been revealed and the beliefs of modern humanity (Christianity and belief in humanity itself), which were at bottom only bloodless myths, have collapsed. But here again we should be careful: Nazism is a humanism in so far as it rests upon a determination of humanitas which is, in its view, more powerful – i.e. more effective – than any other. The subject of absolute self-creation, even if, occupying an immediately natural position (the particularity of the race), it transcends all the determinations of the modern subject, brings together and concretizes these same determinations (as also does 57 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 Stalinism with the subject of absolute self-production) and constitutes itself as the subject, in absolute terms. The fact that this subject lacks the universality which apparently defines the humanitas of humanism in the received sense, still does not make Nazism an anti-humanism.” In Heidegger, Art and Politics, Chris Turner trans. (Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1990): 95 24 See: Stuart Hall, “The West-and-the-Rest: Discourse and Power” in Modernity, Stuart Hall, David Held, Don Hubert and Kenneth Thompson ed. (Cambridge, MA and Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1996) : 184-227 25 George Lipsitz, The possessive investment in whitneness, (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1998) According to Lipsitz, the term ‘investment’ [in the possessive investment in whiteness] denotes time and energy spent on the creation and re-creation of whiteness. ‘Despite intense and frequent disavowal that whiteness means anything at all to those so designated, recent surveys have shown repeatedly that nearly every social choice that white people make about where they live, what schools their children attend, what careers they pursue, and what policies they endorse is shaped by considerations involving race. I use the adjective “possessive” to stress the relationship between whiteness and asset accumulation in our society, to connect attitudes to interests, to demonstrate that white supremacy is usually less a matter of direct, referential, and snarling contempt that a system for protecting the privileges of whites by denying communities of color opportunities for asset accumulation and upward mobility.’ (viii) 26 Rey Chow: Primitive Passions – Visuality, Sexuality, Ethnography, and Contemporary Chinese Cinema, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995): 176-82. The notion of the “to-belooked-at-ness”, introduced in Primitive Passions is a conceptual development of Chow’s earlier assertion about the colonial encounter. Cf. 58 Dislocation of the West/July 2014 27 28 Johannes Fabian, Time and the Other (New York: Columbia University Press, 1983) I am not sure whether or not the idiom ‘experience of discontinuity’ is appropriate. It may well be because it does not allow us to have an experience that it is termed ‘discontinuous.’ It is well known that the modern concept of continuity is defined in terms of infinite divisibility. For a segment to be continuous is for it to be infinitely divisible. Its antonym, discontinuity, therefore implies an impossibility of cutting or dividing. To be discontinuous at Point A is to be impossible to divide in the neighborhood of Point A infinite times. When it is possible to conceive of a border or barrier between ‘you’ and ‘us,’ the relationship at least accommodates the possibility of cut, division, or gap. A border, cut, gap or divide means the possibility of continuity rather than of discontinuity. The radical difference of ‘us’ from ‘you’ that is at stake here in reference to incommesurability, non-sense, and incomprehensibility must be in the order of discontinuity for this reason. 29 See: Translation and Subjectivity – On ‘Japan’ and Cultural Nationalism, Mineapolis & London, University of Minnesota Press, 1997. 1-17, 40-71. 30 For a more detailed discussion on the schema of cofiguration, see: Naoki Sakai, “The Problem of “Japanese Thought”: The Formation of “Japan” and the Schema of Cofiguration”, in Translation and Subjectivity, op cit 40 - 71 31 Of course, Jacques Derrida adopted Valéry’s rhetoric in his discussion of the fate of Europe in L’autre cap, Paris: Les Editions de Minuit, 1991. 32 As I mentioned above ( see note 2 above), Husserl found an example of non-European in gypsies living in European territory. 59