Post class Dynamics of contention The main thrust of the dynamics approach (see, Dynamics of Contention, McAdam, Tarrow, Tilly, 2001) is to show how different forms of contention – social movements, revolutions, strike waves, nationalism, democratization and more – result from similar mechanisms and processes and to argue that we can learn more about all of these mechanisms and processes by comparing their dynamics than by looking at each on its own. McAdam, Tarrow and Tilly, for example, explore several combinations of mechanism and processes with the aim of discovering recurring causal sequences of contentious politics. In a nutshell, Dynamics of Contention attempts to examine democratisation, nationalism, revolution, ethnic conflict, and social movements as a unified field by dissolving all these research areas under the aegis of contentious politics. Thisthe authors want to do not by identifying “wholesale repetitions of large structures and sequences” but by singling out “significant recurrent mechanisms and processes as well as principles of variation” (33). The purpose of this book, then, is to construct a theory of collective political struggles that can inform our understanding of a range of episodes of contentious without falling prey to the reifying effects of theories specific to particular episode types. The authors want to encourage a crossing of various boundaries (disciplinary, historical, geographic, and between different forms of contention) that divide the field of contentious politics and demonstrate how different forms of contention may be compared by constructing analytic narratives of episodes of contention and breaking these down into the mechanisms and processes that drive them and connect them to their origins and outcomes. One of the main theoretical contributions of this work is its attempt to categorise different types of cases – revolutions, democratisation, nation-state building, ethnic conflict, and civil war – all as episodes of contentious politics, not sui generis phenomena, each subject to its own laws. This, the authors do, by identifying a number of “significant recurrent mechanisms and processes” (33) across apparently diverse forms of action. These mechanisms are the causal links between independent and dependent variables – events that produce the same immediate effects over a wide range of circumstances. Brokerage, social appropriation, certification/decertification, collective attribution of opportunity/threat, category formation, identity shift, radicalisation, convergence and competition are some of the recurrent mechanisms mentioned – and specified for episodes of mobilisation, identity constitution, contentious trajectories and different forms of contention, including revolutions, nationalist mobilisation, and democratisation. These mechanisms have different origins and different outcomes depending on how they concatenate with other mechanisms and processes; they reveal causal connections underlying large-scale social contention (32): “Explanation consists of singling out problematic features of the phenomena at hand…then identifying recurrent mechanisms that produce those features,” (87). The sequences and combinations of these mechanisms in a variety of settings help explain particular causal chains and hence different collective outcomes. These mechanisms also establish ‘legitimate’ connections across social chasms, and within and between political groups that are already part of an emerging agonistic political divide. Indeed, they make it possible to develop and maintain an agonistic dynamic that in turn fuels the dynamics of contention. For instance, the mechanisms of certification/decertification respectively legitimate or de-legitimate political positions in the context of political competition and can thus potentially change the course of claim-making, alliances and challenges. In doing all the above, the authors are careful to deny any intent to provide a ‘general theory’ (see pages 23, 32, 34, 306, 313, 340) or a comprehensive explanation of contentious processes; they emphatically reject single models of any large-scale process. Instead of creating a general model for all contentious episodes, the authors suggest “the comparison of episodes of contention in light of the processes that animate their dynamics…Our goal was to interrogate a broad range of episodes to learn whether they concatenate in recurring combinations of mechanisms – robust process – that are consequential across a significant number of cases” (314). Such a relational approach, the authors contend, yields a better understanding of the causes and consequences of social interaction than do structuralist, phenomenological, rationalist, or cultural approaches alone. Critiques of McAdam, Tarrow, Tilly The authors say that the mechanisms they have identified fill in the underspecified causal arrows between the boxes in the political process model: political opportunities, mobilizing structures and frames. But some of their mechanisms seem to do less and some of them more than that. I am not convinced that an “opportunity spiral,” which involves the “perception of significant environmental uncertainty on the part of state and non-state elites and challengers alike” (97) solves the problems of underspecification that weakened the original political opportunity concept. On the other hand, it seems likely that the constitution of new identities that the authors describe will in some cases substitute for local mobilising structures in triggering contention. So should researchers hold on to the political process model or, as the authors themselves sometimes seem to be doing, break out of its categories altogether. Also, the assumption of the book is that by mapping crucial processes underlying contentious sequences, the authors have explained the phenomena. That such mapping may well provide apposite description of the events in question is acceptable; but doesn’t ‘explanation’ require, at a minimum, telling us why the phenomenon in question happens in certain settings rather than others. A still more demanding notion would have it that explanation requires formulas that predict, or retrodict, the quantitative extent or qualitative form of the explanandum. This would mean statements of the following form: When you start with situations like abc, under conditions like def, you get outcomes like xyz.” The biological metaphor In an attempt to theorise the study of movements in strategic interaction with their bystanders and opponents and to account for the contingency and uncertainty in actors’ choices and the unfolding of events, Oliver and Myers (2003) draw an analogy with coevolutionary theory in biology: “Social movements are...like species. Unlike an organism, which has a distinct set of properties, a species is a breeding population characterised by a statistical distribution of properties. Species evolve when these statistical distributions change” (2). Therefore, Oliver and Myers conclude that social movements are not long unitary collective actions but populations of collective actions with statistical distributions of properties: “actions are structurally equivalent to genes. Biologically, genes are not selected directly but rather indirectly, through selection on organisms. However, in protest evolution, actions are usually selected directly by actors’ choices, not through indirect selection on actors, although indirect selection may also occur. Thus we understand a social movement as a distribution of events across a population of actors” (2-3). Oliver and Myers are clearly following in the Dynamics of Contention (McAdam, Tarrow, Tilly, 2001) tradition in so much as they seek to identify the process and their constituent mechanisms that constitute contention. The assumption of using the biological metaphor is that as in biology, in contentious politics too, the same mechanisms can appear in different processes. Diffusion, framing, competition, adaptive learning, or scale shift are all different mechanisms that could be at work in different processes and episodes of contention. However, what differ are the circumstances in which they occur and their combination or sequence with other mechanisms. It makes sense that to be able to understand processes better, you can disaggregate them into their component mechanisms and understand their interaction with other mechanisms. As Tarrow puts it in The New Transnational Activism (2005), “in biology the mechanism of muscle contraction contributes to respiration, locomotion, digestion and even reproduction. Mitosis is a mechanism that prepares a cell for division but sometimes replaces healthy cells and produces cancer. If biologists are interested in any of these process, they can ill afford to ignore their constituent mechanisms. The same is true of contentious politics” (30). Indeed, “serious attention to the underpinnings of coevolutionary theory provides new and powerful ways of theorising relations among social movements and other actors” (Oliver and Myers 2). Koopmans (2005) too is indebted to the ‘dynamics of contention’ school and calls for an evolutionary approach to collective action that prioritises changing social processes over time. One of the major implications of using such an approach is a shift from explanations based on the assumption of rational actors to a model of adaptive rationality. The notion of adaptive rationality is a more realistic assumption that improves on the rational choice approach. Instead of assuming fully rational actors that make detailed calculations based on accurate beliefs about the future, it is more realistic to argue, for instance, that actors will also use trial and error. Another core argument of this literature is that protest and repression cannot be seen in isolation but are connected by a dynamic interdependence. The behaviour of the opposition towards the government is influenced by the way in which the government reacts to the behaviour of the opposition; similarly, the behaviour of the government towards dissent is conditioned on the action of the opposition toward the government. When faced with government sanctions or coercion, dissidents are expected to respond with resistance. Analysing the Iranian Revolution for instance, Rasler (1996) argues that due to micromobilisation process, protest increases in the long run when faced with government sanctions. Micromobilisation occurs because overt dissident behaviour shows the willingness and commitment of others, makes the goal of their activities desirable, and raises the social rewards for participating in the dissent movement. Opp and Roehl (1990) argue that “repression sets in motion ‘micromobilisation process’ that raise the awards and diminish the costs of participation” (523). The reaction of the government to dissident activities is expected to be similar to the response of dissidents to repression. If a government is faced with protest, it is likely to respond with coercion in order to reduce the threat posed by such dissent. Reading the ‘dynamics of contention’ literature, one is left wondering if it provides a mere description of processes and misses out for the most part on a causal account of the phenomena described. My own sense is that these works fail to explain why a particular protest happened at a particular time or why a particular movement took the form it did. Do we take away anything from this literature besides mere description and typologising? It is necessary to take stock of the mechanisms of contentious politics to understand their operation and outcomes, but is this exercise useful without a corresponding correlational analysis? Do efforts to elaborate typologies of mechanisms and processes generate intellectual payoffs that justify the effort? Is attention to social processes and interactions enough or is it necessary to employ this process-oriented thinking to look toward the future of contention?