MARA MARIN BOOK MANUSCRIPT ABSTRACT CONNECTED BY COMMITMENT RETHINKING RELATIONS OF OPPRESSION AND OUR RESPONSIBILITY TO UNDERMINE THEM Oppression is acknowledged as a deep and serious form of injustice. Yet, even as the responsibility to address injustice has received increased attention from theorists of justice, there has been little discussion of our responsibility to transform oppressive structures. To advance this discussion we need to address two questions: the normative question of our obligations to transform oppressive structures and the social theoretical question of how these structures endure and are supported by individual, everyday action. In contrast to normative thinking which typically ignores the social theoretical question, I believe that we can tackle the normative question only in light of a social theoretical account. But even those normative approaches that do so by taking the view that our actions perpetuate structures conceive of this fact as a barrier to the possibility of transformation. In contrast, I argue that we should recognize its transformative potential: if our actions support structures, changing our actions can weaken them. However, we lack a proper understanding of the relation between individual actions and structures. This lack is partly conceptual: we need a concept that would serve us simultaneously at the normative and social theoretical levels. “Commitment” – a notion I elaborate in the first chapter – fills this gap. Commitments are relationships of obligations agents create via their voluntary actions but without knowing in advance the precise content of their obligations. The obligations thus arise as the accumulated effect, over time, of openended actions and responses to them. Two of its features recommend commitment as a model for understanding our obligations under conditions of oppression: the voluntary yet not deliberate character of its obligations and the role of cumulative action in creating them. At the social theoretical level I argue that structures are sustained by constant action that conforms to them. This means that our actions reinforce oppressive structures in virtue of their cumulative effect, regardless of our intentions, and even in spite of our intentions to the contrary. This makes commitment better suited to tackle the social-theoretical question. It also suggests, at the normative level, that we have an obligation to dismantle oppressive structures because they are the results of our actions. As they are the cumulative effects of our actions, our obligation to dismantle oppression takes the corresponding form of repeatedly acting against norms that support it. This makes commitment better suited than its alternatives to tackle the normative question as well. Chapter One elaborates my notion of commitment and extends it from personal to structural relations. Commitments are developed through actions that are voluntary yet, unlike contractual or consent-based relationships, not under the agent's deliberative control. They implicate the agent in a relationship whose precise details are not transparent at the outset of the relationship. When repeated over a significant period of time, actions of this type incur obligations of a special kind, viz. obligations based on the voluntary character of action, yet whose precise content is not known in advance to the agent. Commitments are relationships of “open-ended” obligations. Chapters Two through Four advance the argument of the book by examining three spheres of human life that are particularly vulnerable to oppression: political relations, adult relationships of care, and work relations. Chapter Two, “Political Obligations of Commitment,” takes up a problem raised by the legal proposals that Chapters Three and Four will advance. Such legal measures are meant to protect those vulnerable to oppression, yet they also have to rely on the power of the state. For this reason, they create a tension between the demand for justice and that of legitimate authority. While the former demand requires criticism and suspicion of the authority, the latter requires its opposite: obedience to the demands of the authority and its law even when we deeply disagree with them. I analyze this tension through a reading of Locke’s Second Treatise. I argue that Locke’s use of trust as the basis of a legitimate government is marked by a similar tension between the people’s right to rebel and their obligations under the law. Behind this tension, which is fundamentally about the question of who should have final say on controversial claims of justice, there are several assumptions about how the question of political obligation should be asked, assumptions that need to be abandoned. In order to do so we need to modify the question of political obligation by making it about the relationship we have to those governed by the same system of law. This relationship can be structured equally – when the benefits of the law flow equally to all those governed by it – or hierarchically – when the law’s benefits flow to some groups to the disadvantage of others. I show how laws depend on continuous action conforming to them. Consequently, the structural relation between those governed by the same system of law is best understood on the model of commitment. Chapter Three, “Care, Oppression, and Marriage,” argues that caregiving creates a hierarchical relation between caregivers and care receivers. This hierarchy, leading to oppressive constraints on the selfdevelopment of caregivers, is the result of the processes of interaction between a feature of the work of care – its flexibility – and the norms, expectations and institutions that structure caregiving. Flexibility is the attitude that helps caregivers respond to needs. Good caregiving requires flexibility because, first, needs have to be assessed and their precise demands determined, secondly, they make demands at unpredictable moments and, thirdly, needs change over time. In the process of developing and exercising “skills of flexibility,” caregivers create obstacles to their self-development that make them vulnerable to oppression. A reformed marriage law should provide protections against this vulnerability in the form of entitlements against both the adult recipients of care and wider institutions. These entitlements would be best modeled on the idea of commitment because their precise content would be unpredictable, given the flexibility of caregiving. Chapter Four, “Labor Relations and Obligations of Commitment,” argues that work as currently organized in the formal economy produces a hierarchy between two groups, employers and employees. This hierarchy is the result of two factors: features of the work activity and of the social organization of work. It turns into oppressive constraints for employees, an injustice that calls for legal protections for labor unions in the form of rights of collective bargaining, union shop and the right to strike. A full transformation of the hierarchical relationship between employers and employees requires, in addition to the legal change, a change in workrelated politics. Laws can change the constraints and enabling conditions partly responsible for the hierarchical relationship, but action within those constraints needs to be taken by agents for a full transformation of the relationship. The notion of commitment enables us to see the possibilities for this action in the structural relationship. II. Contribution to the field My book makes several contributions to discussions of oppression and of our responsibility to dismantle it. Methodologically, it illustrates the virtues of an approach that tackles normative questions in light of social theoretical accounts. Conceptually, it elaborates a novel notion – commitment – and introduces it to discussions of oppression. Substantively, I approach oppression via spheres of social life that contribute to gender and racial oppression rather than as a general phenomenon. At this third level, my book has implications for controversies over citizenship, marriage law and the role of trade unions in improving the quality of work and labor conditions. Moreover, my book shows that the difficulties encountered in these controversies, difficulties typically discussed in isolation from each other, have a similar structure, and are connected as aspects of a more general problem. Understanding commitment as a distinct category through which to understand social relations allows us to better understand how these difficulties are related.