Perpetual Westphalia? Exploring Westphalian and NonWestphalian Politics Through Aleatory Materialism The majestic portal which leads from the old world into the new worldLeo Gross1 …new Philosophy calls all in doubt, The Element of firs is quite put out; The Sun is lost, and th’earth, and no mans wit Can well direct him where to looke for it. -John Donne.2 Writing about historical consensus on the ‘Thirty Years’ War,’ Nicola Sutherland argues: ‘the Thirty Years War is a largely factitious conception which has nevertheless become an indestructible myth.’3 Although Sutherland is referring to the common emplotment of the Thirty Years War as the end of ongoing conflict between the Habsburg and Valois dynasties, her words could easily be used to sum up the way the war’s conclusion- the Treaty of Westphalia- has become the foundational myth of international relations. This foundational myth, a common thread within academic International Relations and the practice of international politics, states that Westphalia- particularly in regard to the recognition of sovereign autonomy- instituted the modern practice of sovereignty.4 As such, Westphalia is understood as the point at which sovereignty is distinguished from other forms of authority, rendering state sovereignty the only source of properly political Gross, L., (1948), ‘The Peace of Westphalia, 1648-1948’, American Journal of International Law, 42(1), pp. 2041, p. 28-29. 2 Donne, J., (1611), ‘An Anatomy of the World’, (available at: http://rpo.library.utoronto.ca/poem/643.html) (accessed on: 27/02/2011). 3 Sutherland, N.M., (1992), ‘The Origins of the Thirty Years War and the structure of European Politics’, EHR 107, p. 587. 4 For the treatment of this issue, see for example Arrighi, G., (1994), The Long Twentieth Century: Money, Power and the Origins of Our Times, (London, Verso), pp. 36-47. Kratochwil, F., (1986), ‘Of Systems, Boundaries and Territoriality: An Inquiry into the Formation of the State System’, World Politics, 34(1), pp. 27-52. Ruggie, J.G., (1983), ‘Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity: Toward a Neorealist Synthesis’, in R.O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and its Critics, (New York, Columbia University Press), pp. 131-157. Wight, M., (1977), ‘The Origins of Our States-System: Chronological Limits’, in M. Wight (ed.), Systems of States, (Leicester, Leicester University Press), pp. 129-153. 1 authority. 5 This distinction between legitimate state authority and other, illegitimate authority continues to form the ‘normative core of international law,’6 as well as being the sine qua non of much modern IR theory. Indeed, thinkers as dissimilar as Hans Morgenthau 7 and Friedrich Kratochwil8 share the assumption that Westphalia was the point where modern international politics was born. This is not to say that there have not been dissenting views. Martin Wight, for example, locates an evolutionary process whereby the modern states system came into being over the three centuries following the failure of church reform in the late 15th Century, culminating in the Peace of Westphalia in 1648.9 Similarly, Benno Teschke has demonstrated that, although the origins of the modern international system can be found in social, political and economic developments, they are intrinsically tied to the transformation of property relations in the modern European (particularly the English) economy. 10 Where there has been a challenge to this orthodoxy, it has often been ambivalent and unconvinced. The writings of Stephen Krasner are a case in point, in which he has argued that the Treaty of Westphalia both was11 and was not12 a significant point of rupture within the history of ‘the international.’ What is more, where he does acknowledge the problems inherent in the Westphalian account of the origin of international relations, it is to suggest slight revisions to the thesis rather than to question the practice of identifying the origins of the international system. It seems that Krasner’s approach to Westphalia is symptomatic of Onnekink, D., (2009), ‘The Dark Alliance Between Religion and War’, in D. Onnekink (ed.), War and Religion After Westphalia, 1648-1713, pp. 1-15 (Farnham, Ashgate), p. 2. 6 Brown, S., (1992), International Relations in a Changing Global System: Toward a Theory of the World Polity, (Boulder, Westview), p. 74. 7 Morgenthau, H., (1967), Politics Among Nations, 4th Edition, (New York, Alfred Knopf), p. 299. 8 Kratochwil, F., (1986), ‘Of Systems, Boundaries and Territoriality: An Inquiry into the Formation of the State System’, World Politics 34(1), pp 27-52. 9 Wight, M., (1977), ‘The Origins of Our States-System: Chronological Limits’, in H. Bull (ed.), Systems of States, (Leicester, Leicester University Press), pp. 129-152. 10 Teschke, B., (2002), ‘Theorizing the Westphalian System of States: International Relations From Absolutism to Capitalism’, European Journal of International Relations 8(1), pp. 5-41. 11 Krasner, S.D., (1999), Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy, (Princeton, Princeton University Press). 12 Krasner, S.D., (1993), ‘Westphalia and All That’, Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions and Political Change, J. Goldstein & R.O. Keohane (eds.) pp. 235-264 (Ithaca, Cornell University Press), p. 235. 5 the discipline as a whole; the actual origins of the modern international system are less important than the way a ‘mythic foundation’ acts as a condition of possibility for a particular type of account of the international system. In light of this, rather than assessing the validity of the claims made by the ‘Westphalian thesis,’ 13 this paper examines Westphalia’s role as the mythic origin of the international system. It is the contention of this paper that the dominant approach to temporality within IR is dependent on a point of rupture between past and present, represented by the Peace of Westphalia, marking a transition from pre-modern to modern international systems. This paper argues that the assumption of a point of rupture between premodern and modern international systems is the hallmark of a modernist philosophy of history, in which the present is radically separated from the past.14 This rupture marks a break with tradition in the light of a self-grounding modernity, implying for international relations the move from the historical past to a relatively static, unchanging international present. If this is not an analytically neutral concept, nor is temporality ethically neutralit constitutes the normative horizon of modern politics. Although this has a great many implications, given the constraints under which this paper is being written, it is only possible to address some of them. As such, the paper will proceed by identifying and outlining three corollaries of IR’s ‘Westphalian moment’: a) A temporal thesis- Westphalia acts as a device whereby the modern international system is distinguished from the pre-modern by a radical rupture or break. b) A spatial thesis- Westphalia (that which is constitutive of the international) marks the birth of territory as the sole basis of international political order. Benno Teschke has produced a fantastically erudite and rigorously researched analysis of the emergence of the modern international system in The Myth of 1648: Class, Geopolitics and the Making of Modern International Relations (London, Verso, 2003). 14 Lowenthal, D., (1985), The Past is a Foreign Country, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), p. xxiv. 13 c) A political thesis- Westphalia implies a particular normative orientation to the practice of politics and a normative lens through which political community and organization are viewed. Once the implications of Westphalian idealism have been established, this paper goes on to explore the implications of Louis Althusser’s ‘aleatory materialism’ for looking at International Theory without the origin myth provided by Westphalian and postWestphalian narratives. Aleatory materialism offers us the capacity to think in terms of the primacy of practice and do away with the idealistic foundations of the IR canon that lock us into certain suppositions about where and how practices of politics must take place. Westphalia and the History of IR Theory: Within IR theory, the Treaty of Westphalia is regarded as a decisive ‘tipping point’ within the long transition between pre-modern and modern international relations. It is considered the decisive point at which the ‘soft-textured’ overlapping authorities of the medieval era were replaced by the state of sovereign equality central to modern international politics.15 In many cases, this has been used as a means of justifying the exceptionalism of the modern international system; through which IR’s disciplinary distinction from History can be established. Although Herbert Butterfield, and many others associated with the English School, have suggested that IR theorists should engage more critically with the historian’s task of ‘elucidat[ing] the unlikeness between past and present,’16 the way that most IR theorists have approached this task is through 15 16 Walker, R.B.J., (2010), After the Globe, Before the World, (London, Routledge), p. 131. Butterfield, H., (1949), The Whig Interpretation of History, (London, Bell), p. 10. asserting the radical incommensurability of past and present, emphasizing the way in which the ‘Christian unity of the medieval world seem[s] remote and alien.’17 Within the discipline of IR, this is a remarkably common way of approaching the emergence of the international system. Even the most historical-sociologically inclined thinkers, including the nuanced and sophisticated accounts of Justin Rosenberg 18 and John Ruggie 19 incorporate a structural discontinuity between modern and pre-modern international relations. Perhaps the most radical critique of the modernism implicit within IR’s emplotment of the onset of modernity has come from the wholly a-historical approach taken by structural realism, with practitioners of this theoretical school arguing that the nature of international politics has essentially been static since the emergence of the Sumerian City States system circa 3,500BC.20 However, given the manifold reasons to reject the philosophy of history implicit in structural realism,21 there is reason to suggest that neo-realism does not offer a desirable remedy to the temporality found within Westphalian IR. It does, however, give us cause to question why IR theory has not situated itself within the totality of human history and engaged more fully with the ‘long view of history.’22 In accepting the notion of a discontinuity between modern and pre-modern international politics, IR employs a modernist philosophy of history. Although IR is a specifically 20 th Wight, M., (1979), Power Politics, (Harmondsworth, Penguin), p. 24. Rosenberg, J., (1994), The Empire of Civil Society: A Critique of the Realist Theory of International Relations, (London, Verso). 19 Ruggie, ‘Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity’. 20 Buzan, B. & Litle, R., (2002), ‘International Systems in World History: Remaking the Study of International Relations’, in Hobden, S. & Hobson, J.M., (eds.), Historical Sociology of International Relations, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), pp. 200-220. 21 For an excoriating critique of the assumptions of neo-realism, see Ashley, R.K., (1984), ‘The Poverty of Neorealism’, International Organization 38(2), pp. 225-286. Cox, R.W., (1987), ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory’, in R.O. Keohane (ed.), Neorealism and its Critics, pp. 204-255. 22 Buzan, B., & Little, R., (2000), International Systems in World History: Remaking the Study of International Relations, (Oxford, Oxford University Press), p. 2. 17 18 Century endeavor,23 it utilises a method of separating the past from the present that has been in operation since the early modern period. Although a detailed discussion of how and where International Relations theory is modernist, is not possible here, John Ruggie has identified the core modernist assumptions of both realist power balancing theories which rely on the notion of a new self-relating equilibrium at the heart of the European society 24 and idealist theory which locates the new international order at the heart of projects such as Abbe St. Pierre’s institutionalist plan for peace and the Perpetual Peace enshrined in the writings of Immanuel Kant.25 All of this is to create an artificial divide between the past and the present.26 In this, International Relations participates in what Jurgen Habermas called the ‘project’ of enlightenment, whereby systematic efforts were conducted ‘to develop objective science, universal morality and law, and autonomous art, according to their inner law.’27 Conceptualizing a rupture between past and present, which first emerged in renaissance humanism, 28 was a representational schema deeply ingrained in early modern political theory’s attempt to understand the origins of political authority. During this period, the dominant understanding of the nature and origins of law were reformulated as Thomistic natural law interpretations were challenged by the collapse of medieval cosmology under the weight of the nominalist-scholastic controversy. 29 Although the transition from natural law to positive law understandings of political authority was not marked by the Schmidt, B.C., (2002), ‘On the History and Historiography of International Relations’, in W. Calsnaes, T. Risse and B.A. Simmons, (eds.), Handbook of International Relations, (London, Sage). 24 Anderson, M.S., (1963), Europe in the Eighteenth Century, 1713-1783, (London, Longmans) identifies the Treaty of Utrecht as the point at which self-balancing European powers was first instituted. 25 Hinsley, F.H., (1963), Power and the Pursuit of Peace, (London, Cambridge University Press), chapter 2 & 4. 26 Hobden, S., (1998), International Relations and Historical Sociology, (New York, Routledge), p. 21. 27 Habermas, J., (1981), ‘Modernity and Postmodernity’, New German Critique 22, p. 9. 28 Kellner, H., (1980), ‘A Bedrock of Order: Hayden White’s Linguistic Humanism’, History and Theory, 19(4), p. 5. 29 Gillespie, M.A., (2008), The Theological Origins of Modernity, (Chicago, Chicago University Press), p. 11. 23 neat discontinuity some accounts suggest,30 it is fair to say that the political thought of the early modern period was driven by the question of how and where to found political authority given the apparent inadequacy of hitherto dominant theological justifications.31 Given that it was also heavily influenced by the political consequences of reformation 32 and the subsequent necessity to re-think the political foundations of the polis, the nature of Christendom and the relationship between political authority and religion, it is clear that the political-theoretical landscape of the day was governed by questions about how and where political authority was to be founded. In light of this, there is a need to see modern international politics not as an era or epoch, but as a practice of distinguishing the present from the past as a way of making claims about the foundations of legitimate authority. This way of understanding modernity has emerged from attempts by historians of ideas to come to terms with the developments of early modern thought. During the enlightenment, it was accepted that the transition to modernity was one of triumph, as great minds threw off the shackles of superstition and established a new understanding of the world based on reason.33 However, by the 20th Century this narrative was contested by intellectual historians such as Etienne Gilsen and Karl Löwith, who argued that the apparent ‘early modern revolution’ was based not on Rather than simply being an invention of early modernity, this intellectual foment was a key element of ‘the nominalist revolution’ in late medieval philosophy, having a significant impact on the political thought of Marsilius of Padua and William of Ockham, among others. See for example van Caenegem, R., (1988), ‘Government, Law and Society’, in J.H. Burns (ed.) The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought c. 3501450, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), pp. 174-210. 31 The philosophy of Thomas Hobbes is symptomatic of this approach. Hobbes founds the authority of positive law as an inescapable corollary of a reasoned argument from first principles. The univocal, anthropogenic law of the leviathan replaces the hierarchical orders of law found in medieval political thought. 32 Gorski, P.S., (1999), ‘Calvinism and State Formation in Early Modern Europe’, in G. Steinmetz (ed.), State/Culture: State-Formation After the Cultural Turn, (Ithaca, Cornell University Press), pp. 147-181. 33 Gillespie, M.A., (2008), The Theological Origins of Modernity, (Chicago, University of Chicago Press), p. 11. 30 reason, but on the secularization of late medieval theological concepts.34 This thesis was in turn challenged by scholars such as Hans Blumenberg who argued that modernity was in fact a project, wherein a self-founding modernity created distance and separation from the past.35 According to this view, the transition to modernity was not simply the move from one worldview or era to another, but an attempt to create self-grounding meaning and authority in a world from which God is absent, or at best capricious. Whilst this project of modernity utilized a number of concepts, devices and themes from late medieval thought (nominalism was the philosophical and theological leitmotif of both the late middle ages and early modernity) the period should be thought of in terms of the replacement of theological and hierarchical understandings of law, authority and knowledge claims with self-founding authorities.36 Although it is incorrect to read this period as a simple process whereby positive law simply replaced natural law- there is reason to suggest that the dominant ideas of the early modern period were those in the voluntarist tradition of natural law37 (the nominalist/voluntarist challenge to Thomistic natural law did require a new way of understanding the nature of law and authority in the world. 38 ) In order to ground this new form of authority, early modern thought developed an understanding of positive law rooted in natural law.39 No-one epitomizes this philosophy better than Thomas Hobbes, who located the absolute necessity of the authority of the sovereign source of positive law in an argument made through natural law.40 Löwith, K., (1949), Meaning in History: The Theological Implications of the Philosophy of History, (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). 35 Blumenberg, H., (1989), The Legitimacy of the Modern Age, (Cambridge, Massachusetts, MIT Press). 36 Gillespie, Theological Origins of Modernity, p. 12. 37 Oakley, F. (1961), ‘Medieval Theories of Natural Law: William of Ockham and the Significance of the Voluntarist Tradition’, The American Journal of Jurisprudence 6, pp. 72-73. 38 The relationship between nominalism and the rise of humanism is becoming increasingly established in the history of science. See for example Koyré, A., (1957), From Closed World to Infinite Universe, (Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press) & Blumenberg, Legitimacy of the Modern Age. 39 Gillespie, Theological Origins of Modernity, p. 19. 40 Hobbes, T. (1994), Elements of Law: Natural and Positive, (London, Penguin), p. 254. 34 The conception of modernity as a self-grounding project underwent a revival in the 18th and 19th Centuries, when it became inextricably linked to a particular normative and political project. It was in 18th and 19th Centuries that the ‘international problematic’ as understood by contemporary international relations emerged. 41 In particular, it was intimately connected to the sovereign state. As Constantin Fasolt has argued, the freedom of the modern state is defined in terms of both spatial and (most importantly) temporal freedom. 42 The modern nation state is intimately connected to the ‘autoproduction’ of modernity, through which the modern idea of sovereignty (and its corollary ideas such as citizenship, rights and the rule of positive law) as a regulative norm, is founded not only through spatial borders, but also borders in time. Indeed, this rupture in time is primary, acting as a condition of possibility of spatial border practices.43 Only in asserting man’s freedom from the tradition and custom that governed past politics can the authority of self-grounding human freedom associated with the modern nation state be founded. As such, this form of temporality has both theoretical and political implications. It is intrinsically tied to the nation state and the sovereign order as a way of understanding the world. Indeed, ‘professional’ history-44 with which political science shares a number of common intellectual and institutional origins- is intimately tied to the emerging nation state, with the pioneers of modern historical explanation engaged in telling national Patomaki, H., (2002), After International Relations: Critical Realism and the (Re)construction of World Politics, (London, Routledge), 42 Fasolt, C., (2004), The Limits of History, (Chicago, University of Chicago Press), p. 7. 43 Walker, R.B.J., (2006), ‘Lines of Insecurity: International, Imperial, Exceptional’, Security Dialogue, 37(1), pp. 65-82. 44 That is to say historical explanation carried out in Universities following the rise of History as a profession in 19th Century Germany. 41 histories.45 Knowledge about the past becomes the search for power and independence, through which the project of modern authority is continually re-founded.46 International Relations, a discipline which finds its intellectual roots in the 19th Century,47 participates in this intellectual project, drawing upon the legacy of the enlightenment and the idea of an international order comprised of states in their proper place. 48 The conceptual apparatus of International Relations theory has statist, rationalist and nationalist origins and the ‘myth of Westphalia’ is a significant condition of possibility for this mode of emplotment. As such, the temporality of political modernity is not simply a means by which the present is defined as radically different to the past; it also shapes the normative horizon of international politics. The cleavage between past and present implicitly contains a set of theses about how man is to behave in the world. 49 In particular, it places the territorially bounded state (as part of a states-system, within which borders mark the boundary between the jurisdiction of sovereign authorities) at the centre of the normative frame. Within this normative frame, both ‘conservative’ and ‘progressive’ readings of the world share a common understanding of the nature and location of politics. 50 This at once makes the state the sine qua non of politics in the Westphalian system and- in emphasizing the institution of sovereign authority as the origin of the For an interesting discussion of this, see Harrison, R., Jones, A. & Lambert, P.A., (2004)‘The institutionalization and organization of history’, in P. Lambert & P. Schofield (eds.), Making History: An introduction to this history and practices of a discipline’, (London, Routledge), pp. 9-25. Lambert, P., (2003), ‘The Professionalisation and Institutionalisation of History’, in S. Berger, H. Feldner & K. Passmore, (eds.), Writing History: Theory and Practice, (London, Arnold), pp. 42-60. 46 Fasolt, The Limits of History, pp. 13-14. 47 Knutsen, T., (1992), A History of International Relations Theory (Manchester, Manchester University Press). Walker, After the Globe, p. 41, n.10. 48 Koskenniemi, M., (2001), The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law, 1870-1960, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), p. 20. 49 Walker, After the Globe, p. 32. 50 Fasolt, The Limits of History, p. 15. 45 modern international system- de-politicises borders as sites where politics is performed.51 The self-foundation of modern political authority also makes clear normative prescriptions (and, conversely proscriptions) about the nature and location of legitimate politics. Within ‘Westphalian order,’ the state is the sole legitimate source of political authority and- as such- delegitimizes political practices taking place in other forms and in other contexts. The processes and temporalities through which activities are designated as ‘properly political’ are inherently political processes themselves! The idea that modernity is an era, a move from the past to the present, obscures the contingency of this political order. Within IR, there is a tendency to read the emergence of the modern international system teleologically,52 which simultaneously naturalises and depoliticizes ‘Westphalian’ order. In light of this, it is important to recognize the emergence of modern states as specific practices whereby political authority was legitimized as a response to the concrete intellectual and political problems of the age. As Hidemi Suganami has argued, the practice of sovereignty- in both Schmittian and Kelsonian guises- is based in the mutual imbrication of sovereignty and the ‘possibility of arbitrary violence.’53 This practice emerged as a response to the conflicts of the late 16th and early 17th Centuries 54 and the difficulties of establishing a foundation for legal authority after the demise of Thomism.55 However, if modernity is not the move from one era to another, but the foundation of authority in the present through the establishment of the radical alterity of the past, these foundations are as much the root of Walker, After the Globe, pp. 32-33. John Hobson identifies two tendencies within International Relations Theory- Chronofetishism and Tempocentrism – which he argues is responsible for naturalizing the modern international system. Hobson, J.M., (2002), ‘What’s at Stake in ‘Bringing Historical Sociology Back Into International Relations? Transcending ‘Chronofetishism’ and ‘Tempocentrism’ in International Relations’, in S. Hobden & J.M. Hobson (eds.), Historical Sociology of International Relations, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), pp. 3-41. 53 Suganami, H., (2007), ‘Understanding Sovereignty Through Kelsen/Schmitt’, Review of International Studies, 33 pp. 511-530, p. 530. 54 Knutsen, A History of International Relations Theory, p. 72. 55 Gillespie, Theological Origins of Modernity, pp. 253-254. 51 52 present political order as they are the historical origins of the modern international system. The corollary of this is that there is clear scope for a re-assessment of the way that foundational practices constitute political order. There is a particular need to re-assess the bordering processes of the international system in the 21st Century. Not only might this prove useful in highlighting the implications of the bordering practices through which borders are created and sustained, 56 but it could also help change the way that some major problems in international politics are approached. Particularly prominent amongst these is the question of the authority of the state in the 21st Century world. International Relations theorists obsesses about the move ‘beyond Westphalia,’ using language which suggests that the early 21st Century marks a period of epochal change, 57 but perhaps this is to fall into the same error as those accounts addressing the transition between the medieval period and modernity. If transition takes place in the changing location of and practices of founding political authority, it is on these issues that analysis must focus. There is historical precedent for this situation, in which political authority has not been coterminous with the dominant economic forms or organisation, particularly because, as Benno Teschke has argued, the rise of the modern, international market was not only compatible with, but existed in a symbiotic relationship with the modern state. 58 Rather than assuming opposition of interests between the state as locus of authority in the modern political world and global markets or civil society,59 it is necessary to address the way that this relationship entails a This topic has been discussed at some length in Walker, R.B.J., (1992), Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). 57 See for example Linklater, A., (1998), The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the PostWestphalian Era, (Oxford, Polity). Held, D., (2004), A Globalizing World? Culture, Economics & Politics, (London, Routledge). 58 Teschke, The Myth of 1648, p. 23. Teschke, ‘Theorizing the Westphalian System of States’, p. 38. 59 See for example Gilpin, R., (1987), The Political Economy of International Relations, (Princeton, Princeton University Press), p. 10. 56 mutually co-dependent grounding of legitimate political authority. 60 Although it is not possible to enter into a fuller discussion of this issue here, it is the supposition of this author that if the issue were approached from this perspective, the ‘globalisation debate’ and the analysis of the changing role of the state may have a somewhat different- and significantly more productive- outcome. Philosophical Idealism in International Relations Theory: At this point, it is worth examining in greater detail the extent to which IR has inherited a philosophical idealist worldview. Refracted through the lens of early modern international law and the influence of German philosophers and jurists such as Hegel, Schmitt and Kelsen, philosophical idealism has come to assume a dominant position within modern IR theory. Although the origins of idealist thought in IR theory can be found in the influence of this legal and juridical thought on IR, it was brought into the discipline in two distinct ways: the role of early modern international law in defining and delimiting ‘the international’ as a sui generis form of law and the influence of German legal thought on the sociological formalism of early realist thought within IR. Although these theories tend to be associated with very different approaches to IR, they share a common set of philosophical assumptions, which leads them to define ‘the international’ in similar ways. Castells, M., (1996), The Information Age: Economy, Society and Culture; Volume 1, The Rise of the Network Society, (Oxford, Blackwell). Cerny, P., (1996), ‘International Finance and the Erosion of State Policy Capacity’, in P. Gummett (ed.), Globalization and Public Policy, (Cheltenham, Edward Elgar). 60 This is not a new argument in International Political Economy circles, as Mann, M., (1993), ‘Nationstates in Europe and Other Continents: Diversifying, Developing, not Dying’, Daedalus: Journal of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 122(3), pp. 115–40 indicates. What is new however, is making this argument through the problem of temporality, modernity and the practice of locating legitimate political authority. This would bring questions of political foundation to a debate which has usually been conducted in sociological and/or economic terms. There is certainly reason to suggest that a debate conducted in a political theoretical register would have a greater impact on International Relations theory, overcoming the tendency for this issue to be marginalized as an ‘IPE matter.’ Legal thinking has had a profound, and often underestimated, influence on the way that IR has come to terms with the world. Of particular importance is the centrality of early modern international legal thought such as that of Pufendorf, Vattel and Kant, in shaping the horizons of the discipline;61 evidence of their influence on the contemporary discipline of academic International Relations can be found in its continued engagement with these thinkers. 62 The formative processes whereby international law was codified and promulgated have gone hand-in hand with the way we understand the modern state; the Treaty of Westphalia (as the point at which the principle of sovereign equality was formally recognized) is both of central importance to the development of international law and the emergence of modern international politics.63 The theoretical discourse of the state in late 19th and early 20th Century social, political and legal thought also had a significant influence on early IR theory. This is an argument that Brian Schmidt makes in The Political Discourse of Anarchy, in which he contends that the ‘pre-history’ of the discipline of international relations has had a significant impact on IR, where “the theoretical discourse of the state tacitly laid the groundwork for the political discourse of anarchy.” 64 In early 20th Century intellectual culture, heavily influenced by Hegel and Weber, the study of the state was the study of man’s modern See for example Suganami, H., (1989), The Domestic Analogy and World Order Proposals, (Cambridge, Cambridge University press), p. 13. 62 See for example Wight, M., (2005), Four Seminal Thinkers in International Relations: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant and Mazzini, G. Wight & B. Porter (eds.), (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Wight, M., (1991), International Theory: The Three Traditions, (Leicester, Leicester University Press). Linklater, A., (1982), Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, (Basingstoke, Palgrave MacMillan) Koskenniemi, M., (2001), The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law, 1870-1960, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). 63 Knutsen, T.L., (1992), A History of International Relations Theory, (Manchester, Manchester University Press), p. 115. Teschke, B., (2003), The Myth of 1648: Class, Geopolitics and the Making of Modern International Relations, (London, Verso). 64 Schmidt, B.C., (1998), The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of International Relations, (Albany, SUNY Press), p. 45. 61 condition: the modern state was both the teleological culmination of man’s progress and the guarantor of modern life.65 As Anna Haddow has argued, the nascent discipline of Political Science (and by extension, International Relations), at least in the USA, shared a lot of the philosophical assumptions of (particularly German) legal and historical thought.66 It appears that not only is there a close relationship between the theory of the state outlined in 19th Century historical, legal and political enquiry and early theories of international relations, but there is also a close relationship between the philosophical assumptions of fin de siècle social and political thought and early international relations theory. Another key way in which (particularly German) legal thinking was brought into IR was through the sociological concepts pioneered by Max Weber. “The key conceptualization of politics, definitely in International Relations but arguably also in social theory generally, is Max Weber’s.”67 Weber’s theoretical project was dominated by a desire to develop a nomothetic theory of the way in which social organization takes place, developing his ‘ideal typical’ approach to social theory- treating ‘the political’ (as he would any other facet of social existence) as an abstraction that can be made to analyse any society. 68 Students of Weber’s approach proved instrumental in defining the methods and limits of the discipline69 as early IR theorists such as Hans Morgenthau adopted Weber’s ideal types as a cornerstone of their conception of ‘the international’ and firmly ensconced Knutsen, A History of International Relations Theory, pp. 148-150. Haddow, A., (1939), Political Science in American Colleges and Universities, 1636-1900, (New York, AppletonCentury Company). 67 Neumann, I.B. & Sending, O.J., (2007), ‘”The International” as Governmentality’, Millenium- Journal of International Studies 35, p. 679. 68 Weber’s approach to the ideal type is most clearly articulated in Weber, M., (1976), The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, (London, Allen & Unwin), p. 28. 69 Neumann & Sending, ‘The International as Governmentality’, p. 682. 65 66 Weber at the heart of IR.70 Although Carl Schmitt offers a slightly different theory of sovereignty to Weber- replacing the monopoly of political violence with the sovereign decision- the implications are similar. The idea that sovereignty resides with the power that can declare and enforce a state of exception, a self-grounded legal order71 is based on a similar theoretical basis to Weber’s and has influenced much the same theorists. 72As has been argued elsewhere, 73 this does not just define ‘the international’ as a clearly demarcated sphere of action, but it also implies a certain type of politics will take place in the international sphere: the politics of struggle and rationalisation. It is worth noting here Weber’s insistence on the relativity of political values: Weber- and the most Weberian of IR theorists, Hans Morgenthau- was quick to point out that his nomothetic theory of ‘the political’ was relevant only to the specific cultural and historical context of the period in which he was writing. 74 Nonetheless, the influence of Weber- albeit a particular reading of Weber- has led to the dominance of a vision of international politics in which conflict, tension and dispute at the level of the state are the sine qua non of ‘the political.’ 75 Despite the insistence of Weberians that Weber’s methodologies were historically sensitive, they have entrenched a particular set of interests and concerns at the heart of IR theory: that of the nationalist state. The particular set of philosophical concepts through which International Relations theorists view the world is a direct inheritance of this philosophical idealist tradition. If Guzzini, S., (1998), Realism in International Relations and International Political Theory: The Continuing Story of a Death Foretold, (London, Routledge), p. 26. See also Williams, M.C., (2004), ‘Why Ideas Matter in International Relations: Hans Morgenthau, Classical Realism and the Moral Construction of Power Politics’, International Organization 58(3), pp. 633-665. 71 Schmitt, C., (2003), The Nomos of the Earth: in the International Law of the Jus Publicum Europaeum, (New York, Telos Press), p. 73. 72 Clohesy, A.M., Isaacs, S. & Sparks, C., (2009), Contemporary Political Theorists in Context, (London, Routledge), p. 39. 73 Williams, ‘Why Ideas Matter in International Relations’. 74 Hobson, J.M. & Seabrooke, L., (2001), ‘Reimagining Weber: Constructing International Society and the Social Balance of Power’, European Journal of International Relations 7 (2), pp. 239–74. 75 Neumann & Sending, ‘The International as Governmentality’, p. 689. 70 the philosophical idealism of late 19th Century Germany represents a particular set of interests, then the international political theory built on these ideas shares these interests. Concepts such as the state, international anarchy and sovereignty which are often considered irreducible starting points for the investigation of international politics are not then neutral starting points for the investigation of world politics, but ideologically located foundations. The basic premises of International Relations are rooted in the particular predispositions of this tradition in such a way that it is very difficult to depart from them and still be classified as ‘doing IR.’ Indeed, it is from this tradition that international political theory has inherited its liberal76 as well as its statist characteristics. 77 Likewise, the persistence of nationalist assumptions within International Relations is a function of the discipline’s heavy debt to a late 19th Century intellectual culture beholden to nationalist themes and tropes. 78 The inside/outside formulation through which domestic and international politics are counterposed, 79 has similar origins. The nation state and the concept of sovereignty that goes hand-in glove with it, has become something of the sine qua non of IR. This has had a sclerotic effect on the forms of social and political organisation the discipline recognizes in the world, but it has also fundamentally conditioned the way that we ask questions about the political world. It is not simply that enlightenment critique has not been extended to the liberal societies Irrespective of the divide between ‘realist’ and ‘liberal’ theories of international politics, IR has a much broader foundation in the political philosophical assumptions of liberal theory. See for example Schmidt, B.C., (1998), The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of International Relations, (New York, SUNY Press). 77 Prichard, A., (2010), ‘Deepening Anarchism: International Relations and the Anarchist Ideal’, Anarchist Studies, 10(2), pp. 29-57. 78 See for example the early American realist thinkers and their intellectual inheritance from Schmitt and German formalist sociology. Not only was their thought heavily legalistic in its outlook (that is to say based in the juridical philosophy which undergirds theories of power and the state in late 19th Century thought), but it was inherently tied to the nationalist tropes inherent within late 19 th and early 20th Century German sociological and legal thought. Niebuhr, R., (1960), The Children of Light and the Children of Darkness, (New York, Charles Schribner’s Sons). Morgenthau, H.J., (1965), Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, (Chicago, Phoenix Books). Morgenthau, H.J., (1978), Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New York, Alfred A. Knopf). 79 Wight, M., (1960), ‘Why is there no international theory?’, International Relations, 2(1), pp. 35-48. Walker, R.B.J., (1992), Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). 76 within which the enlightenment has taken place, 80 but that the idealism of Western liberalism has obscured and occluded forms of organization and political possibility within the world. John Meyer and Ronald Jepperson wonder at ‘a surprising feature of the modern system [which] is how completely the Western models dominate world discourse about the rights of individuals, the responsibilities and sovereignty of the state, and the nature of preferred organizational forms,’81 but this should be hardly surprising considering the hegemonic power of Western, idealist modernity. But this does not mean that the problem simply goes away. As Jens Bartelson and Rob Walker have argued, if they are to overcome these problematic elements of international thought, International Relations theorists will have to re-examine the foundations of international theory in order to propose alternatives.82 As such, if IR is to overcome these problematic elements of mainstream international thought, in both theory and practice,83 it must look outside the philosophical idealism that constructed this problematic. Despite hinting at the Eurocentrism of the IR canon, I hope that, given the subject of this conference and the philosophical resources available to me as a scholar in a Western social science institution, I will be excused if I suggest another Western tradition of thought might be a useful way of re-thinking some of the idealisms that predominate within our discipline! Despite being Western, this tradition is a subversive one. If we are to believe Louis Althusser & Antonio Negri, materialism exists as the ‘hidden history’ or ‘unspoken Other’ that Foucault, M., (1984), ‘What is Enlightenment?’, in P. Rabinow (ed.), The Foucault Reader, (New York, Pantheon Books), pp. 32-50. 81 Meyer, J.W., & Jepperson, R., (2000), ‘The Actors” of Modern Society: The Cultural Construction of Social Agency’, Sociological Theory 18 (1), p. 106. 82 Bartelson, J., (2009), Visions of World Community, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), p. 21. Walker, R.B.J., (2010), After the Globe, Before the World, (London, Routledge). 83 Overcoming ‘the international problematic’ as understood in 20 th and 21st Century context, has become a central feature of contemporary IR theory, with ‘Critical’ International Relations Theory attempting to envision new forms of community that cannot be conceived within ‘the international’ as we currently understand it. See for example Shaw, M., (2000), Theory of the Global State: Gobality as an Unfinished Revolution, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Bartelson, Visions of World Community. Walker, After the Globe. Linklater, A., (2011), The Problem of Harm in World Politics, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). 80 possesses the potential to unsettle the dominant narrative of Western modernity. It is to the materialist tradition that I must now turn. The Return to Materialism: Materialism, like Marxism, is not a body of theory, to be accepted or rejected as a whole, but a philosophical tradition that can act as a ‘foundation stone’84 for philosophy in the present. The 20th Century materialism espoused by Althusser is not one of ‘causal’ or necessary relations, but a materialism of the contingent and the aleatory. As such, it should not be confused with the crude reduction of reality to the atomic, as has characterized ‘post-Aristotelian’ materialism. 85 As Bertrand Russell has stressed, ‘traditional’ or ‘atomistic’ materialism has been challenged by Einstein’s theories of relativity; the traditional philosophical notion of substance persisting through time is untenable following the merger of time into ‘space-time.’86 In light of this, the notion of substance and individualistic metaphysics- manifest as mechanistic atomism87- integral to classical materialisms must be replaced with a relational ontology of forces. In a curious manner, this places contemporary materialism in line with both 20th Century physics88 and the pre-Socratic metaphysics of Stoic, Cynical and Megarian thought.89 This is not a materialism of the necessary or the teleological, but one of contingency, freedom and the Althusser, L., (1990c), ‘Is it Simple to be a Marxist in Philosophy’, G. Lock (trans.), Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of the Scientists and Other Essays, G. Elliott (ed.), (London, Verso), p. 230. Lenin, V.I., (1960), ‘Our Programme’, in Collected Works, (Moscow, Progress Publishers), pp. 211-212. 85 Olssen, M., (2006), Michel Foucault: Materialism and Education, (London, Paradigm), p. 207. See also Laruelle, F., (2001), ‘The Decline of Materialism in the Name of Matter’, Pli 12, pp. 33-40. 86 Russell, B., (1925), ‘Introduction: Materialism Past and Present’, in F.A. Lange (ed.) The History of Materialism, E.C. Thomas (trans.), pp. v-xix, (London, Kegan Paul). 87 Particularly representative of this tradition is Thomas Hobbes, for whom an individualistic philosophy and a mechanistic atomism went hand in hand. Skinner, Q., (1999), ‘Hobbes and the Purely Artificial Person of the State’, The Journal of Political Philosophy 7(1), pp. 7-8. 88 Heisenberg, W., (2000), Philosophy and Physics: The Revolution in Modern Science, (London, Penguin). 89 See for example Deleuze, G., (2004), The Logic of Sense, M. Lester with C. Stivale (trans.), (London, Continuum), p. 143, p. 147, p. 161, n.1. 84 encounter. This materialism offers the opportunity to re-orient International Relations, as well as social sciences more generally along properly materialist lines. Constituent Power and Constituted Power in International Relations Theory: In order to fully appreciate the materialist position, it is necessary to understand the distinction between two types of power: constituent power and constituted power. These are usually considered in juridical terms, with constituted power used to refer to a legal or juridical order and constitutive power indicate the processes within which this authority is grounded. 90 Within Western political thought, constituent power- the power that makes world order is suppressed and ignored, whilst juridical power, the power that merely regulates existing order is placed at the centre of analysis. Indeed, this very schema originates in political and philosophical attempts to challenge the apparent neutrality of legal orders.91 The understanding of the relationship between constitutive power and social order that has been adopted by IR theory is one that, in focusing on concepts such as sovereignty and ‘the international’, highlights juridical order over and above the practices that produce it. These constitutive processes only come to light when disturbing the dominant order; this creates the image of a world in which a stable international ordercomprising of institutions (such as sovereignty, the law) and organizations (such as the state)- is interrupted by the operation of constitutive power. Events, such as the Negri, A., (1999), Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State, (Minneapolis, Minnesota University Press), p. 10. 91 These theories of power have been developed within French and Italian Marxism as a means of challenging Leninist assumptions about political action. See for example Virno, P. & Hardt, M., (eds.), (2006), Radical Thought in Italy: A Potential Politics, (Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press). 90 formation of the state92 and revolutions within the international system are exceptions to the normal order of the international system. Temporary periods of exceptional politics such as the ‘twenty years’ crisis’ spoken of by E H Carr 93 or the ‘interregnum’ the international system entered after the Cold War 94 are exceptions to the norm; the sovereign order prevails except during periods of exceptionalism. Althusser & Orthodox Marxism In rejecting International Relations’ focus on the institutional existence of ‘the international,’ Althusserian Marxism offers a similar challenge to IR as it does to classical or orthodox Marxism (whatever that might be). As Marx outlines in The German Ideology, the distinctive feature of his own work- in contradistinction to idealism in general and (in particular) that of both Hegel and the young Hegelians- is not just the assertion that the juridical, political and religious order are unjust (such critique can be found in many places), but that to pose the questions of politics and life in these terms is fundamentally misleading. 95 Hitherto existing, or bourgeois, sciences had concerned themselves with superstructural factors, completely ignoring the productive base that was ultimately responsible for the existence of institutions such as the law.96 Marx argues that to ask questions about the state or the law as an abstract entity is illegitimate as they can only be comprehended in terms of the material conditions of their existence. 97 Marx’s key The acceptance of Machiavelli’s writings about the constitutive power inherent in the formation of the state is a case in point. 93 Carr, E.H., (2001), The Twenty Years’ Crisis: 1919-1939, (New York, Harper Collins). 94 Cox, M., Booth, K. & Dunne, T., (1999), ‘Introduction’, in The Interregnum: Controversies in World Politics, 1989-1999, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press) 95 Marx, K. & Engels, F., (1987), The German Ideology: Introduction to a Critique of Political Economy, (London, Lawrence and Wishart). 96 Marx, K., (1859), ‘Introduction’ in A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, (Available at: 92 http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1859/critique-poleconomy/preface.htm), (Accessed on: 01/05/2011). 97 Althusser, L., (2006), ‘Marx in his Limits’, in Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings- 1978-1987, (London, Verso), p. 55. contribution to materialist philosophy is to reject the idealism of German philosophy and the juridical thought that is implied by this, replacing this with a focus on the productive means through which man provides for his own subsistence. This re-orients the relationship between constituent power and constituted power in such a way that it treats the production of social and political order not as an exception, but as something that needs to be understood as part of its regular operation. The majority of Marxist IR theory has been based around a deterministic reading of the relationship between ‘base’ and ‘superstructure.’98 This reflects much of the literature on Marx’s philosophy in which the mode of production (comprised of both ‘means’ and ‘relations’ of production) is seen to determine the superstructure ‘in the last instance.’99 Within IR, engagements with Marxism have broadly taken three forms. The first of which is historical sociological, with authors such as Fred Halliday,100 Justin Rosenberg101 and Benno Teschke 102 writing Marxist-inspired historical sociological analyses of the international system. The second is in international political economy, where authors such as Immanuel Wallerstein and Giovanni Arrighi have utilized Marxian ideas to develop a theory of international politics in which the global economy acts as driver of world politics. 103 Finally, Critical Theory and Gramscian approaches have utilized This idea was first developed in the preface of Marx’s A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. It has subsequently become a point of contention for Marx, K., (1859), ‘Preface’, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, (available online at: 98 http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1859/critique-poleconomy/preface.htm), (accessed on: 12/04/2011). Olssen, M., (2004), ‘Foucault and Marxism: Rewriting the theory of historical materialism’, Policy Futures in Education 2(3), p. 256. 100 Halliday, F., (1994), Rethinking International Relations, (Basingstoke, Palgrave MacMillan). 101 Rosenberg, J., (1994), The Empire of Civil Society: Critique of the Realist Theory of International Relations, (London, Verso). 102 Teschke, B., (2009), The Myth of 1648: Class, Geopolitics and the Making of Modern International Relations, (London, Verso). 103 See for example Wallerstein, I., (2004), World-Systems Analysis: An Introduction, (Durham, Duke University Press). Arrighi, G., (2009), The Long Twentieth Century: Money, Power and the Origins of Our Time, (London, Verso). These theorists have also utilized the writings of Lenin, V.I., (2010), Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism, (London, Penguin). 99 Marxian analysis to develop theories of international politics that eschew the instrumental or ‘problem-solving’ focus of traditional theory and attempt to develop critical, transformative approaches to international politics.104 These approaches, unlike traditional theory which re-enforce existing world order, self-consciously follow Marx’s ‘Eleventh Thesis on Ludwig Feuerbach,’ seeking to change the world rather than simply to interpret it.105 Despite the success of these approaches in making ‘elbow room’ for Marxist theory within the discipline of IR, they have almost exclusively relied on approaches that have offered an economic determinist reading of Marx. In these accounts, ‘the international’ is but a superstructural epiphenomenon, with international politics merely reflecting the dominant mode of production of any given historical situation. By way of contrast to this, Althusser’s materialism rejects the division of the world into productive base and epiphenomenal superstructure. Althusser Against Orthodox Marxism: The Critique of Determinism Marx’s economic determinism has been subject to considerable contestation and revision, from contemporaries such as Joseph Bloch,106 to modern thinkers such as Gilles Deleuze The distinction between traditional and critical theorizing was first brought into being by Max Horkheimer in his essay ‘Traditional and Critical Theory’, in Horkheimer, M., (1999), Critical Theory: Selected Essays, (London, Continuum), pp. 188-243. It was first applied to International Relations in Cox, R.W., (1981), ‘Social Forces, States and World Order: Beyond International Relations Theory’, Millenium: Journal of International Relations 10(2), pp. 126-155. Other examples of this approach in International Relations include: Gill, S., (1993), Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Linklater, A., (2007), Critical Theory and World Politics: Citizenship, Sovereignty and Humanity, (London, Routledge). Neufeld, M., (1995), The Restructuring of International Relations Theory, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Roach, S.C., (2010), Critical Theory of International Politics: Complementarity, Justice and Governance, (London, Routledge). 105 Marx, K., (1845), Theses on Feuerbach, (available online: http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/theses/theses.htm), (accessed on: 12/04/2011). 106 Olssen, M., (2004), ‘Foucault and Marxism: Rewriting the theory of historical materialism’, Policy Futures in Education 2(3), p. 455. 104 and Felix Guattari,107 and Michel Foucault, who has criticised Marx’s political economy for its affinities with the liberal political economy of the 19th Century- resembling very closely the type of ‘meta-economics’ employed by David Ricardo. 108 Central to this resemblance is the idea that the ‘social, political and spiritual’ processes of life are determined by the ‘deeper’ or ‘underlying’ reality of the economic base. 109 The relationship between base and superstructure is one of model and copy,110 a feature of Marx’s philosophy that is inherently Platonic. In this context, it is helpful to think of Platonism as a doctrine that suggests that everyday reality is determined by a deeper metaphysical reality; 111 consequently, the understanding we have of the world and the things in it can takes one of two forms: an imperfect appreciation of surface illusions (in Marx’s case ideology112) or a direct engagement with the ‘thing in itself’113 (in Marx’s case his critical political economy114). This forms the basis of the Marxist critique of ideology, where the imperfect ideological view of the world is replaced by an appreciation of the world in terms of a non-ideological perspective. By way of contast, thinking ‘beyond’ ideology is anathema to Althusser. Where Althusserian Marxism differs from more orthodox Marxisms is in its rejection of the directionality of the relationship between base and superstructure. It was in the face of the practice of identifying concrete historical laws (most commonly associated with the See for example Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F., (2004), Anti Oedipus, (London, Continuum). Foucault, M., (2001), ‘Interview with Michel Foucault’, in J.D. Faubion (ed.), Michel Foucault: Power, pp. 239-297, (London, Penguin), p. 269. 109 Marx develops this idea most strongly in Marx, K., (1904), A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, N.I. Stone (trans.), (London, International Library Publishing Company), pp. 11-12. 110 Williams, R., (1980), Problems in Materialism and Culture, (London, Verso), p. 33. 111 Plato’s discussion of the forms in the analogy of the cave in The Republic is central to this. Plato, (2007) The Republic, H.D.P. Lee & D. Lee (trans.), (London, Penguin), book VII. 112 Marx, K. & Engels, F., (1987), The German Ideology: Introduction to a Critique of Political Economy, (London, Lawrence and Wishart). 113 This Kantian terminology would be familiar to Marx but not, naturally, Plato. 114 Perhaps the most substantive development of this approach can be found in Marx, K., (2004), Capital: Critique of Political Economy vol. 1, B. Fowkes (trans.), (London, Penguin); Marx, K., (2006), Capital: Critique of Political Economy vol. 2, D. Fernbach (trans.), (London, Penguin); Marx, K., (2006), Capital: Critique of Political Economy vol. 3, D. Fernbach (trans.), (London, Penguin). 107 108 ‘official’ historical materialism of Marxist-Leninist parties) 115 that Althusser sought to develop his non-deterministic theory of Marxism. Although Althusser accepts Marx’s critique of the philosophical idealism of legal and political theory that employs the juridical as a frame of reference, Althusser does not accept that the economic should be determinate ‘in the last instance’; arguing instead that ‘anything can be determinate in the last instance (which is to say that anything can dominate).’116 Here, it is important to note that Althusser regarded himself as ‘following in the footsteps of Marx and Engels,’ quoting Friedrich Engels who said: “one must not think that the economic situation is cause, and solely active, whereas everything else is only passive effect.”117 An example of this can be found in Marx’s writings on the ancient world, where the politics of Ancient Greece and the religion of Ancient Rome displaced the mode of production as determining Greek and Roman society in the last instance. 118 In any case, what is important here is that Althusser overturns a dominant interpretation of the relationship between ‘base’ and ‘superstructure’ as deterministic through developing a theory of overdetermination. The next section will explore Althusser’s theory of overdetermination as well as its implications for the study of international politics. Overdetermination and ‘the international’: In order to describe social systems ‘without origin,’ thereby eradicating the problem of economic reductionism, Althusser developed a theory of overdetermination. 119 Although Althusser, L., (2006), ‘Philosophy and Marxism’, in Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings- 1978-1987, (London, Verso), pp. 253-254. 116 Althusser, ‘Philosophy and Marxism’, p. 263. 117 Friedrich Engels, quoted in Sinclair, A., (2010), International Relations Theory and International Law: A Critical Approach, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), p. 73. 118 Althusser, ‘Philosophy and Marxism’, p. 263. 119 Althusser’s motivations were political as well as theoretical. As well as challenging the predominance of dogmatic “Bolshevik Marxism” within Marxist scholarship, his writings were also a thinly-veiled attack on the hegemonic influence of Leninist politics within the French Communist Party. His thoughts on this subject are most elaborately elucidated in: 115 overdetermination was a concept first developed by Sigmund Freud, 120 it formed the centerpiece of Althusser’s writing on structure and causation,121 later being adopted by Mark Olssen (among others) to explain structure and cause in Foucault’s writings.122 The concept of overdetermination encourages us to think of the world in terms of multiple open causal systems. Although within any given causal mechanism, 123 every level makes a causal contribution, the relative importance of each varies on a case-by-case basis. Both Althusser’s theory of overdetermination (and the theory of causation employed by Foucault), suggest that we should view social relations as complex systems 124 which cannot be thought of in terms of either autonomous, closed systems or base-superstructure logics, where a multifarious social field is determined by one central causal determination. An Althusserian approach to the autonomy of the international argues neither that the international is an autonomous sphere, nor that it can be wholly reduced to a deeper reality. Its liminal existence between casua sui and wholly determined renders the Althusser, L., (2006), ‘Philosophy and Marxism’, Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings- 1978-1987, (London, Verso). 120 Freud, S., (1976), The Interpretation of Dreams, (London, Harper Collins). 121 Althusser, L., (1969), ‘Contradiction and Overdetermination’, in For Marx, (London, Penguin). 122 Olssen, Materialism and Education, p. 54. It should be immediately clear that Olssen’s reading of Foucault is a particular one, not only locating Foucault as a materialist, but also attributing to Foucault a form of causal theory. Whilst most Foucauldian theorists argue that Foucault is explicitly not a causal theorist, Olssen contends that this assertion can only be maintained if we operate within the classical definition of causation as efficient cause. By way of contrast, materialist thought (including Olssen’s reading of Foucault) allows us to pose the ‘problem’ of causation in a way that utilizes contemporary complexity science (and the concept of cause implicit in this) as the basis for a new approach to causation in a similar way that classical conceptions of causation were/are undergirded by the mechanistic physics of Newtonian science. 123 To adopt a term (if not necessarily its full meaning) borrowed from Bhaskar, R., (1979), A Realist Theory of Science, (London, Verso). 124 Broadly defined, a complex system is one for which system-level ‘behaviour’ cannot be predicted through the study of its parts. In recent times, interest in complex social systems- developed through Foucauldian and Althusserian theory as well as rooted in other social theoretical foundations- has caused a considerable ‘overlap’ between social theory and science. Fractal geometry, non-Eucilidean geometry and chaos theory have all garnered attention from social theorists seeking to think of social social systems as complex entities. See for example Delanda, M., (2006), A New Philosophy of Society: Assemblage Theory and Social Complexity, (London, Continuum). Borch, C., (2011), Niklas Luhmann, (London, Routledge). Protevi, J., (2009), Political Affect: Connecting the Social and the Somatic, (Minneapolis, Minnesota University Press), particularly part 1: ‘A Concept of Bodies Politic’. Urry, J., (2002), Global Complexity, (London, Polity). international a set of social relations without origin. Overdetermination describes social spheres or sites of action (such as ‘the international’) as supervenient upon other spheres, albeit in such a way that it can neither be reduced to any of them, nor treated as an autonomous sphere for analytical purposes. In Althusser’s terms, this is the hallmark of a materialist philosophy; in setting aside the question of origin and the problem of foundation, materialist philosophy asks not about the origin, meaning or telos of the international, but simply about its performance.125 The international is not simply the product of one logic (Westphalia)- be it competing sovereignties or capital- but the result of multiple logics. In this regard, the type of international system that might be envisaged through Althusser is distinctly nonWestphalian. The Westphalian system is but one encounter amide a series of encounters that comprise the multitextured space of international politics. What is more, the relationship between these causes and ‘the international’ is inherently non-linear: it is not clear which of these are sufficient and which of these are necessary to produce the modern international political system. All social relations are, ultimately, contingent. The aleatory encounters that forms the basis of the international could always be other than they are. This is not simply to suggest that everything is wholly indeterminate. Rather, global politics is both determined and indetermined; neither wholly subject to deterministic laws, nor wholly indeterminate. Philosophically, this is the difference between complete indeterminacy and what is called hyperchaos.126 Whilst the international is not without foundation, its foundations are loose and there is a considerable degree of ‘play’ between the international system and its constituent parts. 125 126 Althusser, ‘Philosophy and Marxism’, p. 273. Meillassoux, Q., After Finitude, p. 53, 57-60, 63-64, 73-75. The implication of this is that the site at which the international is performed is- at basea negativity or absence of being which makes possible the freedom to be otherwise. However, this freedom to be otherwise is not limited to relations between states. Althusser’s conception of interlocking, overlapping overdetermined social systems means that political change is non-linear, with changes at one level of human activity impacting on others. This form of causation not only means that ‘lower levels’ can cause change at ontologically higher levels, but also that change at higher levels can impact on those below it. 127 For example, changes in diplomatic practices in the early modern period played a role in bringing the modern state into being and the rise of the absolutist state acted as a condition of possibility for the onset of European capitalism. Likewise, in contemporary context, the performance of international financial markets impacts on the micropolitics of local communities as the global economy goes through a period of recession. Although many scientists and environmental campaigners have been deeply critical of the efforts of the UNFCC to deal with the causes and consequences of anthropogenic climate change, international agreements have had an impact on the way in which business, industry and citizens interact with their environment. Working in the other direction, from ‘macro’ to ‘micro’, we see the everyday performance of stock traders comprising the overall ‘market.’ Similarly, the emerging practice of capital accumulation in 17th Century England was responsible for the development of the capitalist mode of production128- a set of practices which ultimately changed the face of the international system. 129 In contemporary context, this suggests that it is not Where the term ontologically higher is used, this refers only to scale. Althusser’s ontology is a ‘flat’ ontology insofar as no sphere of human activity is considered a priori to be supervenient on another. For more on flat ontologies, see Bryant, L.R., (2011, forthcoming), The Democracy of Objects, (Melbourne, Re:press). 128 Although this is contestable, this is where Marx allocates the emergence of the capitalist mode of production. Marx, K., (1867), ‘Part VIII: Primitive Accumulation’, in Capital, S. Moore & E. Aveling (trans.), (Available at: http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/), (accessed on: 03/05/2011). 129 See for example Benno Teschke’s analysis of the origin of the modern international system. It is simultaneously the product of the sovereign authority of early modern absolutist government combined 127 immediately obvious where- or indeed when- the next major transformation in international politics will arrive. The twofold emphasis on practice (or encounter) and overdetermination gets to the heart of the materialist ‘challenge’ to Westphalian and post-Westphalian modes of politics. Althusser’s position can ultimately be summed up as the rejection of the juridical, idealist frame of reference that would seek to determine the institutions of the social world a priori, replacing it with an emphasis on constitutive power and the process which make and sustain the world we live in. To put the problematique in terms more commonly associated with Giorgio Agamben than Louis Althusser: The central problem of a materialist politics (in the Western tradition or otherwise) is not sovereignty, but government.130 To the extent that Althusser subscribes to this doctrine, it is hard to find a better summary of the contribution of 20th Century materialist philosophy to International Relations Theory than this. Conclusion: For most IR theory, Westphalia marks the ‘mythic origin’ of the modern international system. Although there are clear historical inaccuracies in the Westphalian account,131 it persists as a legitimating myth of the discipline because its significance is not historical, but as a condition of possibility for modern International Relations. This paper has with the revolution in the mode of production that was the emergence of capitalism in 17 th Century England. Teschke, B., (2002), ‘Theorizing the Westphalian System of States: International Relations from Absolutism to Capitalism’, European Journal of International Relations 8(5), pp. 5-48. 130 Agamben, G., (2011), ‘Introductory Note on the Concept of Democracy’, in G. Agamben et al. (eds.), Democracy in What State?, W. McCuaig (trans.), (New York, Columbia University Press), p. 4. 131 See for example Teschke, The Myth of 1648. Osiander, A., (2001), ‘Sovereignty, International Relations and the Westphalian Myth’, International Organisation 55(2), pp. 251-287. sought to challenge the temporality of this account on theoretical and political grounds, proposing that we understand Westphalia not as a transition that international relations has already gone through, but as a contingent encounter that is continually performed and it is continually undergoing. The assumption of periodization and the location of points of origin- such as the move from the pre-modern to the modern- unduly naturalises contemporary political practices, making them the ineradicable horizon of modern international politics. In re-casting the problem of modernity not in terms of the transition from one era to another, but as a transition in practices/ways that political authority is founded, two corollaries immediately jump out. The first is that we are to think about political (sovereign) authority not as something that has historical foundation, but as something that is continually and perpetually re-founded. If this is the case, the institution of the authority of positive law, and the authorities that undergird the modern international system, is not an historical event, but an on-going process. The second implication of this is that the potential of a politics beyond Westphalia should not be understood as a move beyond ‘Westphalia,’ but a re-engagement with the foundations of ‘Westphalian order.’ To paraphrase Andreas Osiander, we cannot move ‘beyond Westphalia’ if ‘Westphalia’ is simply a particular way of articulating claims about political authority and international order. 132 It is these foundational concepts that we must address when engaging with questions about the transformation of political community, be it the emergence of modern international relations or any move beyond ‘the international.’ Similarly, an International Relations looking to escape its statist, nationalist foundations and seeking to address questions about the spatial organization of the world, must also ask questions about time and the way that certain types of political authority and particular forms of knowledge claims about international politics are founded through temporal claims about the nature of modernity. To the extent that ‘Westphalia’132 Osiander, ‘Sovereignty, International Relations and the Westphalian Myth’, p. 284. as a way of founding claims about legitimate political authority- marked the beginning of international relations, it marks the continued operation of the modern international system and will also mark its end.