THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Virginia Law Review October, 1988 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW Richard H. Fallon, Jr.a Copyright 1988 by the Virginia Law Review Association; Richard H. Fallon, Jr. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION I. TWO MODELS OF JUDICIAL FEDERALISM A. The Federalist Model B. The Nationalist Model II. JURISPRUDENTIAL CONFLICT A. Respect for State Judicial Proceedings 1. Injunctions Against State Judicial Proceedings 2. Res Judicata and Collateral Estoppel 3. Habeas Corpus a. Relitigation b. Procedural Defaults and Precluded Claims B. State Sovereign Immunity and the Eleventh Amendment 1. Scope of the Young Fiction 2. Abrogation of State Sovereign Immunity C. State Court Powers and Obligations 1. State Court Remedial Power 2. State Court Obligations to Accept Jurisdiction D. Congressional Control of Federal Jurisdiction 1. Article III Issues 2. ‘External’ Restraints on Congressional Power E. A Summary Diagnosis III. PRESCRIPTION: LAW BETWEEN THE POLES A. Choice Between the Models B. Renunciation of the Models C. Toward a Model-Free Jurisprudence? D. Adjudication Between the Poles 1. Between Mitchum and Younger a. The Mitchum Issue b. The Younger Issue 2. Other Issues from Between the Poles a. Respect for State Judicial Proceedings i. Res Judicata and Collateral Estoppel ii. Habeas Corpus b. State Sovereign Immunity and the Eleventh Amendment c. State Court Powers and Obligations i. Powers ii. Obligations d. Congressional Control of Federal Jurisdiction E. The Judicial Role in the Separation of Powers CONCLUSION 1142 1151 1151 1158 1164 1164 1164 1172 1179 1179 1185 1188 1195 1199 1202 1202 1207 1215 1216 1221 1223 1224 1224 1226 1228 1231 1232 1232 1236 1241 1241 1241 1242 1244 1245 1245 1246 1247 1248 1251 *1142 INTRODUCTION © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 1 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 THE law of judicial federalism1—an important subset of the standard federal courts curriculum—is wracked by internal contradictions. The problem is not simply the incompatibility of results in decided cases, though it is partly that. The difficulty grows from the availability and acceptance, within the law, of inconsistent sets of *1143 assumptions to guide legal analysis.2 This is an essay about two leading sets of incompatible assumptions, which I shall refer to as ‘models,’3 that tend to dominate debates about judicial federalism. My subjects are the nature of the models’ influence on thought about federal courts issues and the role that the models play in producing a conflicted and self-contradictory body of law. The defining premises of one of the models should be familiar, because they informed much, if not all, of the early editions of the influential Hart & Wechsler casebook4 and can be traced to the justly admired writings of Professors Henry Hart 5 and Paul Bator.6 This Federalist model, which also is the model most often dominant in Supreme Court opinions, has its roots in a theory of the understandings that surrounded the framing and ratification of the original Constitution in 1787 and 1788. When a Federalist vision of original text and history provides the interpretive framework for federal courts questions, states emerge as sovereign entities against which federal courts should exercise only limited powers, and state courts, which *1144 are presumed to be as fair and competent as federal courts, stand as the ultimate guarantors of constitutional rights.7 These Federalist assumptions8 resonate in numerous constitutional decisions, including many of those defining the constitutional scope of state sovereign immunity and fixing the meaning of the eleventh amendment. 9 Federalist postulates also inform many of the Supreme Court’s attempts to identify congressional intent under controverted jurisdictional statutes. In cases of doubt, the Court commonly reasons that Congress would have intended to respect state interests associated with the performance of traditional sovereign functions and especially to prescribe deference to state judicial proceedings. 10 But the Federalist model does not and could not control the entire field of federal courts jurisprudence. Most conspicuously, it fails to explain doctrines that reflect a divergent theory of federalism that minimizes the significance of state sovereignty in comparison with national interests and that posits a constitutional and statutory preference for federal over state courts as the guarantors of federal rights.11 Like its Federalist rival, this Nationalist model claims foundations in early constitutional history,12 but it also emphasizes the vast reordering of federal relations inaugurated by the Civil War and Reconstruction. 13 *1145 A Nationalist model of judicial federalism furnishes as plausible a set of assumptions to guide federal courts decisions as does the Federalist vision. Moreover, its power is attested in leading Supreme Court cases that reason from its premises that state sovereignty interests must yield to the vindication of federal rights 14 and that, because state courts should not be presumed as competent as federal courts to enforce constitutional liberties, rights to have federal issues adjudicated in a federal forum should be construed broadly.15 This Article uses the Federalist and Nationalist models, which Part I elaborates in greater detail, to illuminate a number of areas of conflict and contradiction in the law of judicial federalism. As the argument unfolds, the models play three roles. First, they function as ideal types of rhetorical structures. In explaining their positions, judges and commentators frequently appeal to the premises about judicial federalism that the models embody. The models thus help to capture, and at the same time to explain and unify, much of the rhetoric of federal courts debates. Second, the Nationalist and Federalist models serve as ideal types of structures of thought about issues of judicial federalism. Issues of judicial federalism assume diverse forms. Some are constitutional: Which suits against the states are excluded from the federal judicial power by the eleventh amendment? Must Congress vest some or all of ‘the judicial power of the United States’ in either lower federal courts or the Supreme Court? And are state courts precluded by the Constitution from awarding particular remedies against officials of the national government? Other issues are statutory: What powers and responsibilities has Congress given the federal courts under various jurisdictional and remedial statutes—for example, under the law that provides for federal habeas corpus review of state criminal convictions? What duties and limitations do federal statutes impose on state courts? Still others involve judge-made law: How ought the federal *1146 courts, as a matter of equitable discretion, to temper the exercise of jurisdiction against the states and their officials? On the surface, these questions might appear to have no more in common than this: each can be answered in a way that would tend to invest relatively more or less power in the federal judiciary and, correlatively, would call for the allocation of more or less judicial business to the courts of the states. But the possibility of divergent answers is not merely hypothetical. Each of the listed questions is a live one, to which the answer is much debated. Moreover, there seems to be a tendency, at least among prominent judges and theorists, to answer most or all of the questions in interestingly consistent ways. Serious thinkers about federal courts issues frequently conclude either that the federal judicial power is very broad in nearly all cases or, alternatively, consistently reach decisions that would narrow federal judicial power relative to that of the state courts. Prominent among those generally propounding a Nationalist line are Justices William Brennan and Thurgood Marshall, Judge John Gibbons, and Professor Akhil Amar. Those who espouse the Federalist model with relative consistency include Chief Justices Rehnquist and Burger, Justices Harlan, Frankfurter, and Powell, and, as noted above, Professors Hart and Bator. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 2 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Although it is by no means a startling revelation that many judges and scholars tend to divide predictably in their analyses of federal courts issues, it is worth pausing to consider why disagreements over seemingly diverse questions are apparently so systematic. A not implausible ‘realist’ view would be that judges tend to reach results that they find politically congenial and then invoke whatever justificatory framework best supports their preferred outcome. 16 According to this interpretation, modern ‘conservatives’ will generally, although not always, invoke the Federalist model; ‘liberals’ will gravitate to the Nationalist model, but will depart from it when Federalist rhetoric better rationalizes a liberal decision. 17 This explanation *1147 is perfectly consistent with the models’ role as ideal types of rhetorical structures, and it provides the most plausible account of some important Supreme Court decisions. 18 Nonetheless, it would be a reductionist mistake to view federal courts arguments as nearly always being crudely political ones in which judges and theorists claim for their predilections the status of the law.19 Functioning as ideal types of structures of thought, the models do not deny the significance of ideological orientation, but illuminate the way in which ideology exerts its influence. At least for some serious federal courts thinkers, deep structures of understanding may determine the resolution of many questions. Imagine, for example, a judge considering whether the eleventh amendment bars federal jurisdiction of all suits against unconsenting states or only of suits in which jurisdiction is predicated on the basis that a state is a party.20 Nearly all commentators who have studied this question agree that the historical evidence is mixed and that the textual language could support either conclusion. This does not mean that one anser is as good as another. But it does raise a question about how the conflicting evidence should be assessed. Although that question has no simple answer, it is accepted practice to test the plausibility of conclusions, and thus indirectly the persuasiveness of evidence itself, by their fit with stable theories or assumptions about the surrounding legal universe. 21 What, for example, were the prevailing assumptions about the nature of state sovereignty at the time of the *1148 Constitution’s framing and the subsequent adoption of the eleventh amendment? Because bits of historical evidence cannot be assessed except against a broader background, much of the power of the Federalist and Nationalist models lies in their capacity to provide a general theory of the historical nature of judicial federalism. But how, the question might be pressed, are background historical theories developed? Or, to sharpen the question: Is the framing of historical theories of American federalism—at least when those theories are developed for use in legal and constitutional analysis—typically unaffected by the normative preferences of the interpreter? For better or worse, 22 the answer to the latter question, within our legal tradition, is pretty clearly negative. For one thing, it is difficult if not impossible to approach historical problems without imposing analytical schemes that reflect contemporary concerns and preferences.23 For another, our traditions of constitutional and statutory interpretation, which accord relevance to original meaning and intent but do not always regard them as controlling varibles, 24 encourage the search for a ‘usable past.’25 In the face of reasonable uncertainty about historical understandings, legal interpreters tend to prefer conclusions that accord with their conceptions of good social policy.26 The Nationalist and Federalist models thus embody understandings of constitutional history that are influenced by political preconceptions and preferences. Moreover, to the extent that policy analysis explicitly enters the interpretive matrix, the models locate particular problems within general theories of judicial federalism that provide systematic justifications for a broad pattern of results. It is impossible to measure how far the Nationalist and Federalist models reflect the *1149 actual thought processes of individual thinkers. Nonetheless, legal analysis is a philosophically and psychologically complex process that can be interestingly illuminated by attention to the deep assumptions on which arguments frequently depend. The third function of the Federalist and Nationalist models, related to but distinct from their role as ideal typical structures of thought, is to provide an index of what is at stake in particular federal courts debates. Although federal courts disputes often turn on highly technical and occasionally arcane considerations, 27 they commonly implicate recurring issues of political and ideological concern. The Nationalist and Federalist models spotlight some of those recurring issues. For example, the models call attention to the extent to which assertions of state sovereignty interests are credited in various contexts and to when state courts are, and when they are not, presumed to be as fair and competent as federal courts. Even if they did not reflect common structures of throught about federal courts issues, the Federalist and Nationalist models would therefore provide a basis for interesting comparisons. By assigning multiple roles to the Federalist and Nationalist models, this Article sacrifices conceptual neatness and even some degree of descriptive precision. If the models were used solely as ideal types of rhetorical structures, the assertion that an opinion or article reflected a Federalist or Nationalist perspective would imply no claim concerning the processes of reasoning that lay behind it. By contrast, to the extent that the models are structures of thought, their invocation implies that the thinking of judges or scholars approaches the ideal types. Finally, in their capacity as measures of the implications of particular assumptions and values, the models do not purport to reflect either the rhetoric of particular decisions or the structures of thought that underlie them. As a result, my mixture of analytical modes introduces ambiguity into some of my claims that particular arguments and opinions reflect the Nationalist and Federalist models. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 3 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Having struggled with other approaches, however, I believe that assigning the models mixed roles ultimately proves more illuminating *1150 than would any more restrictive alternative. If the models have one function that is more important than the others, it is that of reflecting recurring rhetorical structures; the models capture the rhetoric of many federal courts debates. But once the models are developed as ideal types of rhetorical structures, they proffer illuminating explanations for patterns of decisions by particular judges, justices, and commentators on issues that otherwise seem unrelated. And the rhetorical structures are sufficiently common to make it interesting and useful to keep a tally of how well particular results accord with Federalist and Nationalist prescriptions. Moreover, as long as the rhetorical structures of Nationalism and Federalism remain prominent, decisions rendered in more tempered rhetoric will invite reinterpretation as expressions of Nationalist and Federalist ideology. In sum, the three functions of the models are not easily separated, and each yields insights. A residual uneasiness notwithstanding, the ambiguities introduced are thus, in my judgment, more than compensated for. In this Article I deploy the Federalist and Nationalist models in pursuit of three main goals: description, diagnosis, and prescription. The first of these purposes is easily explained. I have suggested already that the Federalist and Nationalist models can sharpen understanding of the conflict and contradiction embodied in present law and of the tendencies of thought that produce them. Demonstration of the law’s intermittent acceptance of contradictory assumptions suggests the instability of particular results and doctrines. Whatever the law may be today, adoption of different analytical premises could lead to a reversal tomorrow. The Federalist and Nationalist models also cast particular decisions and doctrines in new light. When recognized as expressions of a powerful theory of judicial federalism, some arguments gain new power. Others weaken as the contestability of their foundations is revealed. My diagnostic aim is to reach a critical assessment of the models and of their role in producing an internally conflicted and contradictory body of law. Despite their power and allure, the Federalist and Nationalist models are both too extreme in their exclusion of the other’s insights. Each, I shall argue, captures a part, but only a part, of the truth about judicial federalism. It is for this reason that both models persist and that neither is likely to triumph completely over the other. But if both models embody part of the truth about judicial *1151 federalism, then a diagnosis of the current predicament of federal courts law must recognize that the Federalist and Nationalist models represent tendencies to rhetorical excess. Both conduct to proclamations that too far exalt one set of assumptions and values and too far diminish another. The inevitable result is doctrinal contradiction and unpredictability. My critical or diagnostic conclusions yield the prescriptions that it is my third main purpose to provide. The first prescription is that the Federalist and Nationalist models ought to be abandoned as rhetorical structures. Arguments and conclusions ought to be expressed in terms that do not exaggerate the insights of either the Nationalist or the Federalist model and trivialize the claims of the other. Relatedly, insofar as the Nationalist and Federalist models function as structures of thought, they ought to be rejected on the ground that each is excessively one-sided in its approach to complex questions. Needed are structures of thought and rhetoric located between the Nationalist and Federalist poles. A between-the-poles approach to questions of judicial federalism would acknowledge and even celebrate tension between Nationalist and Federalist values. In light of the richness of American federalism, conflict is inevitable, healthful, and desirable. 28 But if tension is welcome in federal courts law, unidimensional analysis and doctrinal contradiction are not. Part I of this Article develops the Federalist and Nationalist models in greater detail. Part II traces their implications through a variety of federal courts issues. Part III draws critical conclusions about the models’ current roles and offers prescriptions for a better reasoned and more coherent body of law. I. TWO MODELS OF JUDICIAL FEDERALISM A. The Federalist Model The Federalist model takes as its analytical starting point a vision of the federal system that it attributes to the framers of the original Constitution and the first eleven amendments. 29 The model’s methodology *1152 is historical and structural.30 The model relies heavily on an interpretation of original intent, and the intent that matters most refers to constitutional structure.31 At the center of the Federalist model stand four premises that define the framework within which individual questions are answered. Premise 1: Within the constitutional scheme, the states retain many of the prerogatives and responsibilities, and therefore must enjoy at least some of the immunities, associated with the concept of sovereignty. This premise rests partly on inferences from constitutional structure and partly on an interpretation of constitutional history. Seen in a Federalist light, the Constitution is most importantly a document that allocates power among entities of government.32 This is not to deny that the © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 4 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Constitution also provides direct guaranties of individual liberties. But from a Federalist perspective, federalistic decentralization not only promotes values of democracy and local control but also functions as a safeguard of fundamental freedoms.33 According to a Federalist account, the authors of the original Constitution set out to create a national government adequate to meet national concerns. But, equally significant, the framers continued to view the states as *1153 important— indeed, in many ways as the primary—entities of government.34 The Federalist model emphasizes that the framers delegated only an enumerated set of functions to the national government. 35 In contrast, the states were left the ‘responsibility for dealing, and . . . the authority to deal, with the whole gamut of problems cast up out of the flux of everyday life.’ 36 Viewed from a Federalist perspective, the tenth and eleventh amendments ratify these understandings. The tenth amendment, providing that powers not delegated to the national government ‘nor prohibited . . . to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people,’37 supports Federalist arguments that the national government may not intrude on the states’ traditional sovereign functions.38 Federalists similarly regard the eleventh amendment,39 which limits federal jurisdiction in suits against unconsenting states, as embodying a fundamental principle of state sovereign immunity. 40 Premise 2: State courts are constitutionally as competent as federal courts to adjudicate federal issues and to award remedies necessary to vindicate federal constitutional norms. Behind this premise lies an account of the ‘Madisonian Compromise’—the plan that resulted in agreement regarding the most disputed provision of article III. Despite general agreement at the Constitutional Convention that there should be a national judiciary, consisting at least of a Supreme Court, 41 divisions emerged over whether federal trial courts would interfere unduly with the jurisdiction of the state courts. 42 To resolve *1154 the impasse, James Madison proposed a compromise43 that left the creation of lower federal courts to the discretion of Congress. The Madisonian Compromise was then adopted overwhelmingly.44 From a Federalist perspective, the Madisonian Compromise implies that state courts enjoy parity of constitutional competence with the lower federal courts. If state courts were inadequate to perform any of the judicial functions that can be invested in federal courts, then Congress’s option to rely on state trial courts would be practically eviscerated. A Federalist model derives further support for this conclusion from the language of the supremacy clause,45 which states that the Constitution, laws, and treaties of the United States ‘shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding.’46 The first two premises assert propositions that the Federalist model views as immanent in constitutional history or text. Two additional premises prescribe that Federalist understandings of constitutional structure should inform interpretation of congressional intent and the fashioning of judge-made law. Premise 3: Absent clear evidence to the contrary, it should be presumed that Congress, in enacting jurisdictional legislation, regards the state courts as being as competent as federal courts to adjudicate federal issues fairly and expeditiously. Premise 4: Absent clear evidence to the contrary, federal judges should assume that state courts are as fair and competent as federal courts in the enforcement of federal constitutional norms and should craft doctrines of judge-made law accordingly. *1155 Theories of constitutional structure and of congressional psychology ombine to support the third premise. The psychological thesis posits that Congress ordinarily legislates consistently with the assumption of state court parity that underlies article III and the supremacy clause. The theory of constitutional structure also indicates that all reasonable doubts should be resolved in favor of congressional intent to respect the competence of state courts. Believing that the Constitution presupposes the state courts’ fitness to serve as ‘the primary guarantors of constitutional rights, and in many cases . . . [as] the ultimate ones,’47 Federalists insist that Congress, if it wishes to depart from the presumption of state court parity with federal courts, should at least bear the burden of saying so clearly. Similar arguments undergird the fourth premise. One arises from a view of the dignity of the states in the constitutional scheme. It prescribes that the states generally ought to be free to apply federal law in their own courts, subject to Supreme Court review, but without being embarrassed or hampered by federal judicial action that implies a distrust of state judges. Several instrumental arguments also counsel federal judicial deference to state courts and their judges. First, state courts frequently are ‘closest to the problem at hand.’48 From a Federalist perspective, it is therefore often desirable for federal courts to stay federal actions in order to elicit the wisdom and expertise that state courts are able to bring to bear on controverted questions of great concern to the states.49 Second, ‘in the substantial class of cases in which process must run to a state officer,’ Federalists view it as politically desirable that the state courts serve ‘as intermediaries for the communication and enforcement of federal commands.’50 Finally, Professor Bator has argued that federal judicial respect for state courts and their judges tends to improve the quality of state court justice. According to Bator, ‘all the mysterious components of the subtle art of judging well . . . are . . . best evoked by a sense of responsibility, by the realization that one has been entrusted with a great and important task.’51 If this psychological assumption is correct, *1156 then federal judicial rulings that imply a distrust of state judges may be subtly self-validating, while a federal attitude of respectful deference conduces to improved © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 5 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 decisionmaking in the state courts—a result that ought to be welcomed by Federalists and Nationalists alike. With the Federalist model now described, it may be useful to clarify the relation of its premises to each other and to elaborate slightly on the sense in which they comprise a theory of judicial federalism. In the pages that follow, I want to show how the Federalist model—in conjunction with the rival Nationalist model—defines a fundamental tension in federal courts jurisprudence. But this project cannot succeed unless the four premises used to define the Federalist model can usefully be viewed as cohering into one perspective. If they were merely four unrelated claims about which people might agree or disagree, grouping them into a single model would do more to confuse than to illuminate. To a certain extent, the model’s utility depends upon its capacity to yield insights into the debates over particular issues. It is possible, however, to offer a preliminary defense of the grouping of the four premises. First, although the model is an ideal type and is not intended to describe the thought of any judge or theorist, the premises tend to cluster in the work of Supreme Court justices and well-known commentators. The premises can be found in or derived from the work of Professors Hart 52 and Bator53 and the Hart & Wechsler casebook.54 Among Supreme Court justices, the four defining premises help to explain, and frequently echo in, the opinions of Chief Justices Burger and Rehnquist 55 and Justices Frankfurter,56 Harlan,57 *1157 Powell,58 and O’Connor.59 The fit is not perfect. Some of the commentators and Justices would reject not only specific conclusions but the analytical approaches to particular issues that I will attribute to the Federalist model. But the clustering of attitudes is sufficient to be interesting. Second, while the relationship among the premises is not one of logical entailment, there is a kind of intellectual gravitational force that tends to hold them together. This force emanates most strongly from the Federalist model’s first premise, which interprets the Constitution as a document that vests important prerogatives and responsibilities in the states and in the state courts, and from the normative commitments that make this premise attractive. The Federalist model reflects many of the traditional values of American federalism. Each of the Federalist premises helps to promote local responsibility and control; to encourage reliance on local expertise; to avoid, at least in part, the familiar bureaucratic accompaniments to nationalization; and to permit efficiency and elegance of institutional design by implying that any function once performed by state institutions presumptively need not be interrupted or repeated by federal authorities. Finally, when the four premises are grouped together, it should be clear that they both embody and support a theory of judicial federalism sufficiently strong to determine the result in many close cases. 60 As will be seen, many federal courts issues are difficult precisely because the relevant legal materials either are vague or point in conflicting directions. In such cases, it is virtually impossible to test the persuasiveness of competing evidence, arguments, and interpretations without at least an informal understanding of the generally prevailing systemic norms. In conjunction, the four premises of the Federalist model express a clear vision of systemic purpose and order and thus exert a strong influence on a broad range of issues. *1158 B. The Nationalist Model The Nationalist model traces its claim to legitimacy to two historical events. It first provides a revisionist interpretation of the original Constitution—the document drafted in 1787, ratified by the states, and modified shortly thereafter by the first eleven amendments. In significant contrast with a Federalist theory, however, the Nationalist model also finds historical foundations in the revisions of federal relations, both constitutional and statutory, that followed the Civil War. Like its counterpart, the Nationalist model can be defined by four premises. Premise 1: The Constitution embodies a strong conception of national supremacy that exalts federal interests, especially the federal interest in the effective enforcement of constitutional rights, above asserted state sovereignty interests. Viewed from a Nationalist angle of vision, the Federalist model draws too heavily from the attitudes of historical Anti-Federalism in its theory of the constitutional protections afforded to state governments and state courts.61 Although forced to compromise, the proponents of broad national authority prevailed in the historical debates surrounding the Constitution’s drafting and ratification. And, the Nationalist theory holds, the Constitution should be interpreted as embodying their historical triumph— as vesting very expansive powers in Congress, even against the states, and as contemplating federal jurisdiction adequate to vindicate national supremacy over anticipated state recalcitrance.62 The history of Civil War and Reconstruction lends additional support to the Nationalist theory of judicial federalism. 63 In contrast with the Bill of Rights, which initially applied only to the national government, 64 the thirteenth, fourteenth, and fifteenth amendments bind the states. As a matter both of substance and symbol, the significance of the Reconstruction amendments was large.65 Opponents *1159 argued that the amendments’ subordination of state governments to federal norms was so intrusive on state prerogatives as to destroy the federal character of constitutional government.66 Equally important, each of the Civil War amendments includes an authorization to Congress to enforce federal norms against the states by appropriate legislation. According to a Nationalist theory, state sovereignty—a concept of dubious analytical power © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 6 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 even under the original Constitution67—must be viewed as vastly diminished, if not eviscerated, by the Reconstruction amendments, at least insofar as it is invoked to frustrate the enforcement of federal constitutional rights. 68 The second premise of the Nationalist model speaks to the constitutional competence and status of state and federal courts: Premise 2: The Constitution contemplates a special role for the federal judiciary, different in kind from that assigned to state courts, in ensuring the supremacy of national authority. Parallel to the provisions for legislative and executive power in articles I and II, article III prescribes that the judicial power of the United States ‘shall be vested’ in one Supreme Court and in such lower federal courts as Congress may ordain and establish. According to a Nationalist argument, the most natural reading of this language is a mandatory one: article III requires that textually specified portions of the federal judicial power ‘shall be vested’ in some federal court—either the Supreme Court or an ‘inferior’ federal tribunal created by Congress. 69 On this view, the Madisonian Compromise establishes that Congress need not create lower federal courts—but only so long as *1160 there is Supreme Court review of the most federally significant state court decisions. That state courts lack constitutional parity with the lower federal courts follows as a logical implication. If article III mandates the vesting of the federal judicial power in either the Supreme Court or a lower federal court, but not in both, then the Constitution allows a lower federal court, but not a state court, to make ultimate decisions on issues of constitutional magnitude. This implies that federal courts enjoy a superior constitutional status. A Nationalist model also finds stringent limitations on congressional controal of federal jurisdiction in the emanations of the Reconstruction Constitution.70 It is the influence of fourteenth amendment doctrine that gave rise to a fifth amendment jurisprudence of equal protection and fundamental rights. 71 And, Nationalists contend, congressional withdrawal of jurisdiction over important claims of federal right would offend these norms. 72 The Nationalist model’s third and fourth premises involve the relationship of background constitutional understandings to the construction of jurisdictional statutes and to the development of judge-made law. Premise 3: Absent clear evidence of contrary legislative intent, there should be a presumption in the construction of jurisdictional statutes that Congress generally legislates sympathetically to federal rights by authorizing easy access, as of right, to the lower federal courts. Premise 4: Absent clear evidence to the contrary, federal judges should assume that federal courts are likely to be more prompt and effective than state courts in protecting federal constitutional rights, and they should craft doctrines of judgemade law that permit the federal *1161 courts to act as the presumptively available enforcers of constitutional norms. Underlying the third and fourth premises are two empirical propositions and one normative judgment. The first empirical claim is that state courts often are not as fair and effective as federal courts in enforcing constitutional rights. Professor Neuborne, for example, argues that federal judges, who enjoy a constitutional guaranty of life tenure, are more protected than state judges from majoritarian pressures and therefore may be more willing to enforce unpopular constitutional principles; 73 that federal judges typically are more able than state judges and therefore more competent to assess complex and novel constitutional arguments;74 and that federal judges are more likely to have a ‘psychological set’ that predisposes them to honor claims of federal rights, while state judges are likely to respond more grudgingly when state authority is challenged on federal grounds.75 A related empirical argument holds that Congress, in enacting much of the remedial and jurisdictional legislation that is most controverted in federal courts jurisprudence, acted out of suspicion, if not antipathy, toward state courts and wholly rejected notions of practical parity.76 The great turning point occurred during Reconstruction, when Congress radically expanded the scope of federal jurisdiction, frequently into areas previously reserved to state courts. 77 Recurrent *1162 themes in the legislative history involved suspicion of state courts as inadequate guardians of constitutional norms and a preference for federal courts as the guarantors of federal rights against the states.78 According to a Nationalist account, there is a heavy presumption that Reconstruction jurisdictional and remedial legislation sought to replace state with federal judicial authority and to ‘interpose the federal courts between the States and the people, as guardians of the people’s federal rights.’ 79 The final support for Premises Three and Four arises from an interpretation, implicit in Premises One and Two, of the relative importance in the federal constitutional scheme of, on the one hand, the structural values asserted to protect state sovereignty and efficiency interests and, on the other hand, the value of enforcing constitutional liberties. The Nationalist model does not deny the former values but, as a matter of emphasis, asserts the priority of the latter. 80 Like the Federalist model, the Nationalist model is an ideal type. It does not purport to describe the actual positions of any particular judge or theorist, though it is constructed out of them. The justification for the grouping of four premises as one model again obtains along two dimensions. First, although the premises are logically independent of each other, they tend to cluster in the work of judges and theorists. For example, most of the premises can be derived from, *1163 or are at least © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 7 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 consistent with, the work of Justice William Brennan,81 Judge John Gibbons,82 and Professor Akhil Amar.83 Important echoes sound in the writings of Professors Chayes,84 Fiss,85 Neuborne,86 and Sager,87 and in the judicial product of Justice Marshall.88 Although the correspondence is not perfect, the fit is tight enough to warrant search along a second dimension for intellectual and normative commitments that would explain why acceptance of one proposition might correlate with acceptance of the others. At this deeper level, the gravitational center of the Nationalist model is a vision of the Constitution as being most importantly a guarantor of individual rights. When this vision is supplemented by the empirical claim that state courts are less likely than federal courts to protect constitutional liberties effectively, it becomes easy to see how the disposition to prefer the enforcement of constitutional rights over other, structural values could lead to endorsement of all four of the premises that define the Nationalist perspective. Finally, as with the Federalist model, the four premises of the Nationalist model combine to produce a powerful theory of judicial federalism. Even when the premises do not directly determine the outcome of questions, their supporting values and assumptions almost inevitably inform the weighing of historical and other evidence, at least in cases in which the evidence is plausibly subject to varying interpretations. As subsequent sections of this Article will show, the Federalist and Nationalist models wield so much power not because ideologies alone drive legal arguments, but because relevant textual *1164 and empirical evidence so frequently is vague, conflicting, and open to alternative understandings. II. JURISPRUDENTIAL CONFLICT Examination of some leading federal courts debates will establish three conclusions about the Federalist and Nationalist models and their influence. First, both models possess substantial capacity to elucidate the case law and the surrounding literature. Second, both are invoked with some regularity, but only on a selective basis. Third, the acceptance within federal courts law of antithetical starting points for analysis gives rise to substantial doctrinal instability. A. Respect for State Judicial Proceedings The Federalist and Nationalist models exert prominent influence in federal courts controversies regarding overlaps of state and federal jurisdiction. Three sets of issues illustrate the ongoing debates. These involve the availability of federal injunctions against state judicial proceedings, the preclusive effects of state court judgments in subsequent federal litigation, and the respect to be accorded to state court judgments and procedures in federal habeas corpus actions. 1. Injunctions Against State Judicial Proceedings In a much controverted line of cases, the Supreme Court has struggled to articulate conditions under which a federal court may either enjoin apending state court proceeding or issue an injunction against future prosecutions. Two kinds of issues present themselves. The first involves statutory interpretation: Do the applicable statutes authorize federal injunctions against state judicial actions? If this question is answered affirmatively, there remains an issue of equitable discretion: What conditions must be satisfied before federal injunctive relief should be granted? The statutory issue arises at the intersection of two statutes. Originally enacted as part of the 1871 Civil Rights Act, 42 U.S.C. § 1983 creates a federal right of action against state officials, including prosecutors and judges, who violate federal constitutional rights. The legislative history makes clear that Congress provided for federal enforcement of the statute because it viewed the state courts with suspicion *1165 and hostility.89 Moreover, the statute provides expressly for injunctive relief. But section 1983 is not the only statute bearing on the question. The federal Anti-Injunction Act,90 an ancient statute first enacted in 1793,91 prescribes that ‘ a court of the United States may not grant an injunction to stay proceedings in a state court except as expressly authorized by Act of Congress, or where necessary in aid of its jurisdiction, or to protect or effectuate its judgments.’ Currently codified as 28 U.S.C. § 2283, the Anti-Injunction Act has frequently been portrayed by courts and commentators as embodying, and compelling judicial adherence to, the central values of the Federalist model.92 *1166 To the question whether section 1983 supersedes section 2283 and its prohibitions against federal injunctions of state court proceedings, the premises of the Nationalist model yield a clear affirmative answer. In the historical context of section 1983’s adoption, the Nationalist model finds it unimaginable that Congress could have intended to retain section 2283’s policy of deference to state court justice.93 From a Federalist perspective, on the other hand, the burdens of proof and persuasion are reversed. The starting point for Federalist analysis is the plain text of section 2283, which establishes that the anti-injunction proscriptions apply to section 1983 litigation unless an exception is ‘expressly authorized by Act of Congress.’ Because section 1983 says not a word about © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 8 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 displacement of the Anti-Injunction Act, the argument concludes, section 2283 and its policies prohibit injunctions against state judicial proceedings.94 From a Federalist perspective, this analysis does not represent excessive literalism in the interpretation of the ‘expressly authorized’ exception to section 2283, but is supported by a sound theory of judicial federalism: if Congress wished to depart from a principle of federalism as fundamental as that underlying the Anti-Injunction Act, it could at least be expected to say to clearly. Beyond the relationship of sections 1983 and 2283 remain issues concerning the appropriate exercise of equitable discretion. Traditional canons of equity permit injunctive relief only where stringent conditions are satisfied. These include requirements of imminence *1167 and irreparability of injury and of inadequacy of legal remedies. 95 Do these traditional barriers to injunctive relief remain operative in suits under section 1983? The Nationalist model contends that they do not. Its arguments proceed along two lines. First, the traditional standards are judgemade. According to the Nationalist model, the federal courts ought to interpret and develop those standards to promote effective enforcement of federal rights against the states.96 Second, because it is within the power of Congress to relax the traditional restraints on equitable remedies, it is an important question whether Congress, in enacting section 1983, intended to do so.97 Judges and scholars who emphasize the importance of congressional intent seldom argue that Congress expressly considered the specific conditions under which injunctions ought to issue in suits under section 1983. The debate therefore occurs at another level, where the Federalist and Nationalist models exert controlling authority through the premises that they prescribe to guide the interpretation of congressional intent in the absence of clear historical evidence. With the debate so cast, scholars propounding a Nationalist line of analysis have emphasized that the Reconstruction Congress that enacted section 1983 was animated by a deep suspicion of state courts.98 Given that context, they find it unlikely that Congress would have intended canons of equitable restraint to frustrate suits to protect federal civil rights from state abridgement. 99 But a contrary argument proceeds as naturally from Federalist assumptions: if Congress intended to upset settled understandings concerning the general impropriety of federal equitable relief against state officials in the performance of state sovereign functions, surely it would have said so clearly.100 *1168 When the debates concerning statutory interpretation and equitable discretion are seen as illustrative of a tension between the Federalist and Nationalist models, the case law reveals a fascinating duality. This duality exhibits itself most powerfully in the modern era101 in two cases decided less than a year apart: the seminal Federalist case of *1169 Younger v. Harris102 and the subsequent, but less influential, Nationalist decision in Mitchum v. Foster.103 Younger squarely posed the question whether section 1983 constituted an ‘expressly authorized’ exception to the antiinjunction strictures of section 2283.104 The Court, however, chose to avoid this issue of statutory construction. Instead it elected to assume, although pointedly not to hold, that Congress had intended section 1983 to create a legislative exception to the anti-injunction rule.105 This assumption required the Court to consider whether, as a matter of equitable discretion, a federal court ought nevertheless to deny relief against pending state criminal proceedings. Writing for the Court, Justice Black paid no heed to legislative history in determining whether an injunction ought to issue under section 1983, a statute adopted by a Reconstruction Congress in an era of suspicion of state courts. Instead the Court rested its decision directly on a familiar set of Federalist presumptions about the contours of judicial federalism: [The most] vital consideration [is] the notion of ‘comity,’ that is, a proper respect for state functions, a recognition of the fact that the entire country is made up of a Union of separate state governments, and a continuance of the belief that the National Government will fare best if the State and their institutions are left free to perform their separate functions in their separate ways. This, perhaps for lack of a better and clearer way to describe it, is referred to by many as ‘Our Federalism,’ and one familiar with the profound debates that ushered our Federal Constitution into existence is bound to respect those who remain loyal to the ideals and dreams of ‘Our Federalism’ . . .. It should never be forgotten that this slogan, ‘Our Federalism,’ born in the early struggling days of our Union of States, occupies a highly important place in our Nation’s history and its future.106 The power of the Federalist model is here displayed in most striking form. Its premises—founded in an interpretation of the original Constitution and only modestly adapted to accommodate changes *1170 wrought by the Civil War and Reconstruction—are invoked to hold that a federal court should decline to exercise jurisdiction under a Reconstruction statute, even though the statute’s enactment was motivated not by respect for state courts but by a suspicion of their inadequacy to protect constitutional rights. The history of Reconstruction notwithstanding, Justice Black held that the Court should adhere to a Federalist vision that he traced to ‘the early struggling days of our Union of States.’ 107 If Congress had wished to alter traditional policies of equitable restraint, the Court reasoned, then it would have said so clearly. Although it continues to be attacked by commentators, 108 Younger establishes the predominance of the Federalist model in © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 9 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 questions of equitable discretion under section 1983. But the Federalist hegemony is less than complete. The Nationalist model received at least its rhetorical due less than a year after Younger, when Mitchum v. Foster109 explicitly held what Younger had only assumed: that section 1983 represents an express congressional exception to the Anti-Injunction Act. Mitchum’s Nationalist language is as striking as it is incompatible with the theoretical foundations of Younger. Despite the Federalist tradition of federal noninterference in state judicial proceedings, the Court pronounced, the Civil War amendments and Reconstruction legislation must be viewed as divergent and controlling authority. In enacting section 1983, the Court reasoned: Congress clearly conceived that it was altering the relationship between the States and the Nation with respect to the protection of federally created rights; it was concerned that state instrumentalities could not protect those rights; it realized that state officers might, in fact, be antipathetic to the vindication of those rights; and it believed that these failings extended to the state courts. Section 1983 thus was a product of a vast transformation from the concepts of federalism that had prevailed in the late eighteenth century when the anti-injunction statute was enacted. The very purpose of section 1983 was to interpose the federal courts between the States and the people, as guardians of the people’s federal rights . . .. 110 *1171 As interesting as Mitchum’s language was the Court’s unanimity in accepting it, despite the plain availability of an alternative position supported by Federalist premises: if Congress had wished to depart from the principles of federalism embodied in the Anti-Injunction Act, it almost certainly would have said so; in any case, it should have been required to do so under the plain language of the Anti-Injunction Act, which requires that exceptions should be expressly authorized.111 When juxtaposed, Younger and Mitchum create a jurisprudence that legitimates two incompatible sets of governing premises. Nationalist assumptions underlie the Court’s unanimous holding that section 1983 creates an exception to the letter of the anti-injunction statute. The Federalist model informs the Supreme Court’s holding concerning the appropriate determinants of federal equitable discretion. As between the two models, the Federalist exerts much more influence. As Professor Bator has asserted, because Younger’s judge-made abstention rule was already in place, ‘Mitchum v. Foster had its fangs pulled even before it was announced.’112 But the incompatibility of the approaches remains, and it has not been without consequences. On the one hand, Younger has expanded dramatically.113 Originally limited in application to pending state criminal proceedings, the Younger doctrine has been extended to encompass quasi-criminal proceedings,114 state contempt processes,115 civil enforcement actions to which the state is a party,116 ‘processes by which the State compels compliance with the judgment of its courts,’117 and suits to restrain allegedly unconstitutional patterns of conduct by state prosecutors *1172 and police departments.118 On the other hand, Nationalist premises surface regularly in dissents. Justice Brennan has argued repeatedly that expansions of the Younger doctrine are inconsistent with the legislative history of section 1983 and thus reflect usurpations of congressional power.119 Nor does the Nationalist model appear only in dissenting opinions. Emphasizing the intent of Congress to facilitate access to a federal forum, the Court has held that declaratory judgments sought in anticipation of state criminal prosecutions should be easier to obtain than injunctions.120 Without interposing Federalist presumptions that Congress would wish to show deference to state courts or that rules of equitable restraint should be crafted to do so, the Supreme Court concluded in Steffel v. Thompson121 that the congressional plan, which ought to be implemented, was to establish the lower federal courts as “the primary and powerful reliances for vindicating every right given by the Constitution, the laws, and treaties of the United States.”122 Nationalist postulates also help to justify the occasional aberrant decision that upholds a federal injunction against a future state prosecution.123 Even when the traditional requirements of equity are satisfied, the Federalist model would suggest that the appropriate place to seek injunctive relief is a state rather than a federal court. 2. Res Judicata and Collateral Estoppel The Anti-Injunction Act is not the only ancient statute to embody a *1173 vision of federalism with which section 1983 finds itself in tension.124 Enacted initially in 1790,125 the Full Faith and Credit statute, 28 U.S.C. § 1738,126 provides that ‘judicial proceedings of any court of any state shall have the same full faith and credit in every court within the United States . . . as they have by the law and usage of such State.’127 This language prescribes that federal courts, in determining the effect in subsequent litigation of a state judgment,128 should look to the law of the state rendering the decision.129 In the context of *1174 relations between state and federal courts, the purpose of the statute appears to derive from Federalist assumptions: that state courts are as good as federal courts130 and that the dignity of the states requires federal respect for their judgments.131 *1175 The apparent purposes of section 1738132 are incompatible with a broad, Nationalist interpretation of section 1983. Section 1738 frequently directs federal courts to give preclusive effect to state court judgments. But sponsors of section 1983, © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 10 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 the later enacted of the two statutes, manifest deep suspicion of the adequacy of state courts to reach fair determinations in cases involving federal rights. Further, a line of Supreme Court decisions has held that section 1983 was intended to create a ‘uniquely federal’ remedy for violations of federal rights by state officials. 133 Commentators therefore have invoked Nationalist premises to argue, and prior to 1980 some lower courts had held, that ordinary rules about the effect of state judgments should not apply in actions under section 1983.134 The Federalist model directs a contrary conclusion. It argues that if Congress had intended section 1983 to create an exception to the prevailing Federalist full faith and credit doctrine, it would have said so explicitly. 135 In Allen v. McCurry,136 the Supreme Court adopted *1176 the Federalist analysis. The Court began by termining ‘comity between state and federal courts’ a ‘bulwark of the federal system’137 and by instancing section 1738 as an expression of this fundamental value. With this ‘background’ developed to justify its methodology, 138 the Court proceeded to read the legislative history of section 1983 through a prism of Federalist assumptions. In the absence of clear evidence to the contrary, the Court reasoned, section 1738 must be held controlling.139 Although the legislative history revealed a distrust of state courts, the Court found this evidence too equivocal to establish a ‘repeal by implication.’ 140 Finally, the Court brusquely rejected policy arguments based on ‘general distrust of the capacity of state courts to render correct decisions on constitutional issues.’141 The majority reaffirmed its ‘confidence’ in the willingness and capacity *1177 of state courts to decide federal issues fairly.142 Allen was a case in which the result was effectively determined by the Court’s choice of an analytical starting point in the Federalist model. Federalist presumptions resolved ambiguity in the legislative history and guided policy choices in the penumbra of legislative intent. Justice Blackmun’s dissenting opinion reveals an equally plausible Nationalist alternative. 143 Justice Blackmun began with the Reconstruction statute, not with section 1738, and asked whether it was consistent with the purposes of section 1983 for federal courts to give ‘full preclusive effect to prior state adjudications.’ 144 Seeking an answer in the legislative history, Justice Blackmun found evidence—all of it cited in other Supreme Court cases—that the fortysecond Congress though ‘substantive justice was unobtainable’ in state courts. 145 The dissent therefore deemed it ‘senseless to suppose that the authors would have intended the federal courts’ to defer to state court judgments. 146 The Allen dissent buttressed its argument with a telling analogy to Mitchum v. Foster, in which the Court had held unanimously that section 1983 constitutes an ‘express exception’ to another ancient statute, the Anti-Injunction Act. Although Justice Blackmun conceded that ‘the legislative history’ bearing on Allen was ‘capable of alternative interpretations,’ he argued that prior decisions construing section 1983 had established that a Nationalist approach to interpretation was required.147 *1178 Allen’s choice of a Federalist starting point has done much to inform subsequent decisions concerning ‘full faith and credit’ issues in section 1983 litigation.148 But Allen apparently has not wholly foreclosed Nationalist modes of analysis. Haring v. Prosise149 is illustrative. The question in Haring was whether a criminal defendant’s guilty plea in state court precluded a later section 1983 action alleging police violation of fourth amendment rights. 150 Writing for a unanimous Court, Justice Marshall first confirmed that section 1738 constituted presumptively controlling authority.151 But the Court, although holding section 1783 binding on the facts before it, noted that the motivation for section 1983 lay in ‘grave congressional concern that the state courts had been deficient in protecting federal rights.’ 152 It observed in dictum that ‘exceptions’ to the preclusion doctrines contained in section 1738 ‘may be warranted in section 1983 actions in light of the ‘understanding of section 1983’ that ‘the federal courts could step in where the state courts were unable or unwilling to protect federal rights.’’153 Although the Court subsequently seems to have affirmed the fundamentality of Allen’s Federalist holding that section 1738 applies with full force to section 1983 litigation,154 the *1179 ‘ confusing dicta’155 of Haring v. Prosise provide an arguable basis for future Nationalist arguments. 3. Habeas Corpus The law of habeas corpus provides one of the most prominent battlegrounds for the Federalist and Nationalist models. Two sets of issues hold special interest.156 The first involves the permissibility of relitigation on federal habeas corpus of issues already adjudicated by a state court in entering a criminal conviction. The second set of preclusion issues arises when prisoners in federal habeas corpus proceedings attempt to litigate constitutional defenses that were not properly raised and therefore not considered in state court. a. Relitigation The relitigation question is formally one of statutory construction: Did Congress, when it authorized federal habeas corpus jurisdiction to review state court convictions, intend to prescribe relitigation of issues already determined by a state trial court and reviewed by the state’s appellate system? 157 The relevant intent is that of the thirty-ninth Congress, which enacted the Habeas Corpus Act of 1867,158 the predecessor statute to the currently applicable provisions. 159 But the legislative history is sparse.160 Commentators therefore have agreed *1180 that the statute must be interpreted in light of its historical context 161 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 11 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 and of contemporary concerns of policy.162 A Federalist approach to the 1867 statute begins by asserting the limited historical scope of habeas corpus. The 1789 Judiciary Act withheld federal habeas corpus jurisdiction over prisoners held by the states.163 Even with respect to federal detainees, throughout early American history habeas corpus review inquired only into the jurisdiction of the convicting tribunal; where jurisdiction obtained, the merits of a judgment would not be reexamined.164 Resting both on this history165 and on a general principle of deference to state sovereign interests in the finality of criminal convictions,166 Federalist arguments hold that relitigation should be allowed in only a narrow range of cases.167 Generally, the arguments assert, state courts should be presumed as competent as *1181 federal courts to adjudicate federal issues correctly, and state judicial systems should not suffer the inconvenience or the insult of review of lawfully obtained convictions by a single federal district judge. 168 Professor Bator’s position epitomizes Federalist reasoning. Despite the current habeas corpus statute’s initial enactment by a Reconstruction Congress, Bator argues that ‘ i t would . . . require rather overwhelming evidence to show that it was the purpose of the legislation to tear habeas corpus . . . out of . . . its historical meaning . . . and convert it into an ordinary writ of error with respect to all federal questions.’ 169 If the debate is cast in terms of policy rather than historical intent, the Federalist model again finds the state interests more constitutionally weighty than those of the petitioner in all but exceptional cases. Professor Bator’s argument 170 has two relevant strands. One assumes the overall competence and fairness of state courts in protecting federal rights. 171 Within this framework, Bator argues that the values served by relitigation generally are inadequate to justify the drain that it imposes on judicial resources and the disruption that it causes to the state’s punitive and rehabilitative interests. 172 The second strand of his argument recognizes that state court quality and fairness may occasionally fall beneath federal standards. But, Bator argues, this makes it all the more important to create a structure that elicits maximum *1182 state court sensitivity to the requirements of federal law.173 Among his more interesting arguments is that ‘indiscriminate’ relitigation in federal court is likely to undermine the sense of personal responsibility that state judges ought to feel and thus may subvert the commitment of state judges to applying federal law conscientiously. 174 A Nationalist approach yields a wholly different reading of the 1867 Habeas Corpus Act. From this perspective, the starting point for statutory interpretation is the Reconstruction context in which the legislation was passed. 175 Emphasizing that the ‘ t hirty-ninth Congress thoroughly distrusted the State courts and expected nothing from them but resistance and harassment,’176 the Nationalist model holds that the legislature could not plausibly have intended to make the findings of the state courts binding on federal courts on habeas corpus. 177 If the debate is conducted on policy grounds, the Nationalist perspective affirms the superiority of federal courts over state courts as effective vindicators of constitutional norms and assumes the fundamental importance of protecting individual rights.178 Until relatively recently, the case law exhibited a predominantly Nationalist flavor. Whatever its intrinsic merits as an interpretation of congressional intent, the Federalist argument against relitigation *1183 suffered a signal defeat in 1953 in the case of Brown v. Allen.179 Speaking for a majority of the Court, Justice Frankfurter adopted a Nationalist perspective on the legislative history and asserted repeatedly that congressional intent mandated habeas corpus relitigation of decisions of constitutional law.180 Although he did not elaborate the basis for this conclusion, Justice Frankfurter, who normally would be associated with Federalist reasoning,181 also seemed to countenance questions about the parity of state the federal courts in contemporary as well as in Reconstruction times. There were, he acknowledged, instances in which ‘even the highest State courts’ have failed to give adequate protection to federal constitutional rights.182 He viewed it as the aspiration of federal habeas corpus jurisdiction to remedy the attendant injustices. Although Brown continues to establish the general permissibility of relitigation of questions of law on federal habeas corpus,183 the Supreme Court’s 1976 decision in Stone v. Powell reflected at least a *1184 partial movement toward Federalist premises.184 Stone held that fourth amendment search and seizure claims may not be relitigated on habeas. Because Justice Powell’s majority opinion rested primarily on a construction of the exclusionary rule, not the habeas corpus statute, Stone leaves Brown formally undisturbed.185 But the tension between the two cases is manifest. Stone acknowledges no presumption in favor of a federal forum for vindication of federal rights,186 and it accords with Federalist premises in assigning greater weight than Brown to state interests in the finality of their judgments.187 Since Stone, the Supreme Court has, somewhat surprisingly,188 limited its exception to the relitigation doctrine to fourth amendment claims.189 But the conjunction of the Nationalist assumptions of Brown and the Federalist perspective of Stone yields a tension bordering on contradiction. An obvious foundation exists for doctrinal movement in either a Federalist or a Nationalist direction. This situation raises questions about the long-term stability of the doctrine. *1185 b. Procedural Defaults and Precluded Claims Supreme Court decisions involving habeas review of precluded claims exhibit pronounced doctrinal swings between the Federalist and Nationalist models. The traditional doctrine, accepted even in a companion case to Brown,190 held that issues of law not duly raised in state court could not be litigated for the first time in federal habeas corpus proceedings. The © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 12 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 rationale for this rule, which accorded well with Federalist premises, was that the states should be free to develop their own law with only minimal federal interference and, accordingly, that they are entitled to formulate and enforce constitutionally valid procedural rules for raising federal issues in defense to state criminal prosecutions. 191 From this it follows that when a criminal defendant fails to comply with state procedural law, his default properly may exclude a federal issue from the case in state court. The state law basis for preclusion then will constitute an ‘independent and adequate state ground’ that bars Supreme Court consideration of the federal issue on direct review. 192 And when a petitioner subsequently seeks to raise a ‘precluded’ issue in a federal habeas corpus proceeding, it can be said—without regard to the merits of the unlitigated federal claim—that the underlying conviction was lawfully obtained. Thus, the argument concludes, the defendant who defaulted in state court cannot establish that he is held in custody in violation of the Constitution or laws of the United States—the statutory predicate for federal habeas corpus relief.193 In Fay v. Noia,194 a leading Nationalist decision of the Warren Court, the Supreme Court rejected this analysis. ‘Although the habeas corpus Act of 1867 . . . nowhere defines habeas corpus,’ Justice Brennan reasoned in his opinion for the Court, ‘its expansive language and imperative tone, viewed against the background of post-Civil War efforts in Congress to deal severely with the States of the former Confederacy, would seem to make inescapable the conclusion that Congress was enlarging the habeas remedy as previously understood.’195 *1186 Skepitcal of the adequacy of state court justice, Congress, the Court concluded, must have intended to make federal habeas corpus jurisdiction ‘additional to and independent of direct Supreme Court review,’196 not limited by the appellate jurisdictional obstacle posed by the independent and adequate state grounds doctrine.197 The Court did recognize that the states have an interest in ‘exacting compliance with their procedural rules.’198 But even this interest was measured against a Nationalist standard. Weighing the state interest against the competing federal interest in the vindication of constitutional rights, Fay held that state preclusion rules should bar federal habeas corpus review only when a prisoner had deliberately bypassed *1187 opportunities to litigate his federal claims in state court.199 While Fay typified the work of the Warren Court, the Burger and Rehnquist Courts more often have reasoned from Federalist premises, and their decisions concerning preclusion issues constitute no exception. 200 The central case if Wainwright v. Sykes,201 which, apparently limiting Fay nearly to its facts,202 holds that a petitioner generally may not raise a claim on federal habeas corpus if the claim was not duly litigated in state court. To qualified for an exception, the petitioner must either show both cause for his failure to raise the issue and prejudice issuing as a result 203 or, alternatively, make a colorable showing of probable innocence.204 Both of these standards have received exacting constructions. 205 Typical of the recent cases, Justice Rehnquist’s Wainwright opinion rested almost entirely on policy grounds, with only a nod of deference to legislative intent. Nevertheless, Wainwright’s cryptic arguments resonate with Federalist premises. The opinion supports its conclusion by invoking the necessity to respect the rules adopted by ‘a coordinate jurisdiction within the federal system’ 206 and emphasizes the interest of the states in constituting ‘the trial of a criminal case in state court as a decisive and portentous event,’207 rather than as ‘a ‘tryout on the road’ for what *1188 will later be the determinative federal habeas hearing.’208 Fay, however, has at least not been explicitly overruled. And its decision, coupled with the Nationalist perspective that appears regularly in dissenting opinions,209 leaves a lingering element of tension in the law of preclusion on federal habeas corpus. B. State Sovereign Immunity and the Eleventh Amendment Issues involving state sovereign immunity and the eleventh amendment define another prominent battleground for the Federalist and Nationalist models. As in cases involving potential conflicts of state and federal jurisdiction, the models supply assumptions or premises that help to identify historically intended meanings. In this context, however, the relevant questions involve constitutional, rather than statutory, interpretation. The general problem concerning the constitutional status of sovereign immunity and the meaning of the eleventh amendment is easily framed. Various provisions of the Constitution and laws of the United States create rights against the states. 210 But attempts to enforce those rights in federal court frequently raise complex, multidimensional issues. The roots of these issues lie in the ancient doctrine of sovereign immunity211—the doctrine, carried across the Atlantic from England and imported into the framework of the colonial governments,212 that the Crown could not be sued without its *1189 consent.213 At the Constitutional Convention, it was not made explicit whether state sovereign immunity survived the Constitution, and especially whether it could be invoked to defeat claims brought in federal court and founded on federal law. 214 In the absence of strong interpretive assumptions, the evidence of original intent is surely equivocal. From a Nationalist perspective, it is highly significant that article III authorizes federal jurisdiction of ‘all cases’ arising under the Constitution and laws of the United States215 and also of controversies ‘between a State and Citizens of another State.’216 Moreover, state sovereign immunity is arguably incompatible both with the accepted constitutional concept of federal supremacy217 and with the theory of ‘popular sovereignty’ that underlies the constitutional regime. 218 The Federalist perspective, on the other hand, would demand clear evidence that the framers intended to displace an immunity rooted in historical tradition.219 Moreover, when the evidence is examined, Federalists find irrefutable testimony that the framers intended to *1190 retain sovereign immunity. During the ratification debates, the Constitution’s leading © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 13 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 contemporary theorist, James Madison, gave assurances that article III did not alter the traditional principle that ‘ i t is not in the power of individuals to call any state into court.’220 Both Alexander Hamilton221 and John Marshall222 also argued that the Constitution retained the states’ immunity from suit.223 In its first encounter with the issue of state sovereign immunity, the Supreme Court adopted a thoroughly Nationalist interpretation of *1191 article III. Chisholm v. Georgia,224 decided in 1793, involved a contract action by a South Carolina citizen against the state of Georgia.225 Upholding its jurisdiction under the constitutionally enumerated category of suits against a state by a person not a citizen of that state, four of the five participating Justices held that sovereign immunity did not bar the action.226 The ensuing reaction clearly establishes Chisholm’s incompatibility with prevailing political assumptions. 227 Within six months Congress had passed, and within two years the states had ratified, 228 the eleventh amendment to the Constitution of the United States: ‘The Judicial power of the United States shall not be construed to extend to any *1192 suit in law or equity, commenced or prosecuted against one of the United States by Citizens of another State, or by Citizens or Subjects of any Foreign State.’229 The meaning of the eleventh amendment remains disputed. Nationalists emphasize that the amendment says nothing about state sovereign immunity. If the framers had intended to vest the states with immunity from suits to enforce the federal Constitution, Nationalists argue, they at least could have been expected to say so. 230 This argument is buttressed by the fact that sovereign immunity would have been protected absolutely in federal court if the amendment had simply ended fourteen words earlier—the point at which the judicial power has been asserted not to extend to suits against the states, but before any qualifying language about the kinds of suits, defined by party, to which the amendment applies. 231 According to modern Nationalists, the language of the eleventh amendment, when closely parsed, forbids federal jurisdiction of suits against the states only when jurisdiction is based solely on the diverse citizenship of the parties. 232 This interpretation allows the states to invoke sovereign immunity in suits, such as the breach of contract action in Chisholm, that arise under state law and are candidates for federal jurisdiction only because of the identity of the parties. But it creates no prohibition against federal jurisdiction in suits based on the Constitution or laws of the United States.233 Federal supremacy, the rule of law, and other Nationalist values are thus preserved in the most important categories of cases. 234 *1193 From a Federalist perspective, the oddly framed language of the eleventh amendment is less significant than the spirit, perceived through the lens of Federalist assumptions, that animated it. According to modern Federalists, the states enjoy sovereign immunity from suit, whether conferred by the eleventh amendment 235 or by the intended meaning of the Constitution as originally ratified by the states, 236 even in cases to which the language of the eleventh amendment does not literally apply.237 Although early Supreme Court decisions were at least consistent with the Nationalist interpretation,238 the watershed Federalist case of Hans v. Louisiana,239 decided in 1890, defines the background against which the doctrine has subsequently developed. Interpreting the language and history through the filter of Federalist assumptions, the Hans Court concluded that the purpose of the eleventh amendment was to reestablish a general regime of state immunity from suit, at *1194 least in federal court.240 Over the past several years, four justices of the Supreme Court have argued repeatedly that Hans ought to be overruled.241 Adopting a Nationalist perspective, these justices have disputed Hans’s interpretation of eleventh amendment history and have decried its reliance on what they view as the same misconception of state sovereignty ‘as the Tenth Amendment jurisprudence of National League of Cities v. Usery242 that wa recently abandoned in Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority.’243 The attack on Hans is by no means quixotic. When the issue was last joined, 244 Justice Scalia, though concurring in the result, declined to join the plurality’s Federalist *1195 defense of Hans’s historical and political foundations.245 Moreover, Justice Powell, who was the Court’s leading proponent of the Federalist model in eleventh amendment cases, has retired. For now, however, Hans stands at the center of eleventh amendment jurisprudence and endorses a principle of state sovereign immunity so strong that exceptions are required to vindicate the minimal requirements of national supremacy.246 Aside from the vitality of Hans itself, the two leading eleventh amendment issues both involve the appropriateness of exceptions to Hans’s conception of state sovereign immunity. Each reflects a tension between the Federalist and Nationalist models.247 1. Scope of the Young Fiction. An important question in sovereign immunity jurisprudence is entirely definitional: When is a suit a suit against a state? In one of the first important cases construing the eleventh amendment, Chief Justice Marshall held that the jurisdictional limitation did not apply to suits in which the party of record was not a state but a state official. 248 This construction, which prevailed throughout the entebellum period and well into Reconstruction, 249 represented virtually a total *1196 victory for Nationalist premises and values. Because a state can function only through its officers, it is almost always possible to plead an action as one against a state official, even when the state is the real party in interest. Moreover, as Professor Currie has © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 14 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 observed, ‘ p eople are not likely to amend constitutions just to change captions on complaints.’ 250 Shortly after the end of Reconstruction, however, the consistency of the pattern broke,251 and Federalist rhetoric entered the case law. For example, In re Ayers,252 decided in 1887, included language sometimes interpreted as suggesting that the Court had moved to the extreme Federalist position that the states’ eleventh amendment immunity extended to state officials whenever they were acting within the scope of their state law authority. 253 Ex parte Young254 inaugurated the modern era of dialectical doctrinal development between the Nationalist and Federalist extremes. In Young, the Court stood closer to the Nationalist pole as it held that a federal court could enjoin the attorney general of Minnesota from attempting to enforce an unconstitutional rate regulation statute in state court. Because states had no authority to act unconstitutionally *1197 themselves, the Court reasoned, they could not ‘impart to any official any immunity from responsibility to the supreme authority of the United States.’ 255 Accordingly, the Court ruled, there could be no constitutional prohibition against a federal injunction that did no more than order a state official to cease violations of federal law.256 Young presents a constitutional fiction. Although a state can act only through its officers, state officials, even when performing their official duties, can be sued for injunctions on the theory that they are not ‘the state’ and thus not entitled to eleventh amendment protection.257 Somewhat paradoxically, the Young fiction applies even in suits in which the substantive cause of action arises under the fourteenth amendment, which forbids only those deprivations of rights that are caused by a ‘state.’258 Young lived, moved, and had its being in the assumptions and values of the Nationalist model. The case’s doctrinal innovation lay in its authorization of an injunction to prevent a state’s attorney general from initiating a suit in state court, where federal rights at least in theory would have been protected as fully as in federal court.259 The decision’s plain policy was to permit the vindication of federal rights in federal court, implicitly on the assumption that a federal forum would ensure more effective vindication of federal constitutional claims. This point was not lost on Justice Harlan, whose dissenting opinion in Young sounded the Federalist theme. Beyond demanding greater respect for the states’ sovereign integrity, he argued that ‘ w e must assume—a decent respect for the States requires us to assume—that the state courts will enforce every right secured by the Constitution.’260 Young, however, marks the beginning of the modern era, not its end. The contending forces of the Federalist and Nationalist models have persisted. In Edelman v. Jordan,261 for example, the majority *1198 relied on the Federalist premise of state sovereignty to bar retroactive financial relief that was payable from a state’s treasury. Because of the practical certainty that equitable restitution could be made only from funds in the state’s treasury, Justice Rehnquist reasoned that the state’s sovreign interests, which were demonstrable, were more directly implicated than in Young.262 Although Edelman establishes Federalist values in the law interpreting Young, the emerging doctrinal lines are both blurry and potentially unstable. Edelman appears to prohibit relief that compensates a plaintiff for harm already done. 263 Yet the Court subsequently has upheld a decision that effectively ordered the state of Michigan to pay half the cost of compensatory educational programs as part of the remedy for past unconstitutional segregation. 264 The Court also has upheld the award of attorneys’ fees against state defendants.265 When the decisions are put together, the reach of Edelman’ s underlying Federalist values, within the bounds defined by the Nationalist decision in Young, remains uncertain. As the lines of authority increasingly embody conflicting interpretive schemes, the law as a whole grows less determinate,266 and direct appeal to the values represented by the Federalist and Nationalist models becomes more necessary to the resolution of individual cases. 267 *1199 2. Abrogation of State Sovereign Immunity Although Hans v. Louisiana holds that the states enjoy sovereign immunity from suit in federal court, a question remains about whether Congress, in the exercise of its constitutional powers, can strip the states of the immunity that they would otherwise enjoy. If Congress does possess the power to abrogate a state’s immunity, a subsidiary question involves how the congressional intent ought to be identified. The Federalist and Nationalist models shed light on the debates over both these questions. In Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer,268 a unanimous Supreme Court held that Congress, when acting pursuant to section five of the fourteenth amendment, may eliminate the states’ immunity from suit in federal court. 269 This holding represents a clear triumph of Nationalist over Federalist assumptions and values. From a Federalist perspective, the conclusion that section five of the fourteenth amendment authorizes Congress to abrogate the states’ constitutional immunity reflects a judgment about historical intent that is by no means obvious and is *1200 probably mistaken. As Professor Currie has argued, the Civil War amendments would not authorize Congress to impose cruel and unusual punishment as a penalty for civil rights violations. 270 Why, then, should they be held to license transgression of other constitutional limitations on congressional power? 271 The Court’s unanimity in Fitzpatrick thus stands as a testament to the fundamentality in our constitutional scheme of the values and assumptions embodied in the Nationalist model. Fitzpatrick, however, was a carefully limited opinion, which specifically tied Congress’s power to abrogate state sovereign © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 15 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 immunity to section five of the fourteenth amendment. Justices Brennan and Stevens, who concurred separately, both took the broader view that congressional power is not limited to section five of the fourteenth amendment, but exists under other grants of congressional authority, notably the commerce clause. 272 Whether Congress can brogate state sovereign immunity under its article I commerce power is a question that the Court apparently regards as open. 273 When the Court does confront that issue,274 the Nationalist and *1201 Federalist models call for different results. From a Nationalist perspective, the eleventh amendment’s bar to federal jurisdiction should apply only in cases in which federal jurisdiction over a suit against a state is predicated on diversity of citizenship.275 Under this interpretation, the eleventh amendment counts for nothing in a case arising under federal law. Even if Hans’s rejection of this position must be accepted, the Nationalist model would counsel that Hans should be read to limit only judicial, not legislative, power and thus to permit federal jurisdiction of suits involving congressionally authorized causes of action. 276 Among its virtues, this position would bring eleventh amendment jurisprudence into line with tenth amendment doctrine. In tenth amendment cases, the court has held that the principal protection of state sovereignty interests must come not from the courts but from the states’ political representation in Congress.277 The Federalist model prescribes opposite conclusions. Indeed, from a Federalist perspective, the question of Congress’s power to abrogate the states’ eleventh amendment immunity would be resolved by Hans itself, which held the states’ immunity from suit too fundamental to yield even to constitutional claims. However the Court may resolve the issue of Congress’s power to abrogate eleventh amendment immunity under the commerce clause, its long failure to reach the question reflects the influence of the Federalist model in an antecedent inquiry. The antecedent question is whether Congress, under any particular statute, in fact intended to abrogate the states’ immunity. Under the premises of a Nationalist model, this question ought to be resolved under ordinary rules of statutory construction. State sovereignty not being a particularly weightty concern, Congress, in creating rights and providing for their enforcement, would presumably intend to make states as vulnerable to suits as other defendants. 278 The Court, however, has embraced rules of inference suggested by the Federalist model. 279 Postulating that sovereign *1202 immunity is a fundamental constitutional value,280 it has propounded a clear statement rule of the most stringent form. If Congress intends to abrogate the states’ immunity, it must express its intention to do so ‘in unmistakeable sic language in the statute itself.’ 281 C. State Court Powers and Obligations Many disputed issues in federal courts law involve the powers and obligations of state courts in adjudicating federal claims. Resolution frequently requires resort to background understandings or premises about the nature of judicial federalism within the constitutional scheme. Nationalist premises then generate one set of conclusions, Federalist premises another. 1. State Court Remedial Power Issues concerning the remedial power of state courts lie at the center of one of the most fascinatingly arcane debates in the law and theory of federal courts.282 The leading precedent is Tarble’s Case.283 *1203 The case arose after a boy from the state of Wisconsin allegedly lied about his age in order to enlist in the United States Army. Wanting his son back, the boy’s father asked a Wisconsin state court to order his son’s release on habeas corpus—a writ directing an executive officer to come forward to justify a challenged detention. The jurisdictional question was whether a state court could enter a writ of habeas corpus commanding action by a federal official in the performance of his federal office. From a Federalist perspective, the Madisonian Compromise marks the lines of analysis. Because Congress need not create any federal courts at all, state courts must be considered constitutionally competent to decide any case arising under the Constitution and laws of the United States and, accordingly, to issue any traditional legal orders reasonably necessary to the judicial function.284 Congress of course could divest the state courts of parts of their general jurisdiction by prescribing exclusive federal responsibility for certain classes of lawsuits. 285 But when Congress has not expressly chosen to do so, the Federalist model holds that the competence and status of the state courts should not be derogated. On the contrary, the state courts should be presumed as fair and able as federal courts to perform any judicial function, including the award of coercive remedies. A Nationalist model frames the issues quite differently. Especially in light of the experience of Civil War and Reconstruction,286 later *1204 replicated in part in the civil rights struggles of the 1960s,287 a Nationalist approach maintains that state court must be regarded as potentially disruptive of effective federal supremacy. And, the Nationalist reasoning continues, the Constitution should not be read to allow the singular dislocations that the state courts cause by issuing mandatory orders to federal officials.288 Individual rights may indeed be threatened by federal official action. But federal rather than state courts should be considered the preferred guardians of federal constitutional rights. 289 Tarble’s Case, which was decided during the Reconstruction era, adopts the Nationalist analysis. The Supreme Court reasoned that state courts could not be presumed to be as fair and competent as federal courts: ‘The experience of the late © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 16 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 rebellion has shown us that . . . the powers of the National government could not be exercised with energy and efficiency at all times, if its acts could be interfered with and controlled for any period by [state] officers or tribunals.’ 290 The Court acknowledged that the writ of habeas corpus must, under the Constitution, be available. In the Court’s view, however, the Constitution also required that the writ come from a federal court, not a *1205 state court.291 More than 100 years after its decision, Tarble’s Case remains a focus of debate.292 Some of the controversy arises from the implications of the Court’s Nationalist holding for closely related issues involving the state courts’ remedial capacity.293 Of potentially greater significance, however, is that Tarble’s Case, if read literally as founded on propositions of constitutional law, strikes directly at one of the foundation stones of the Federalist model: the proposition that state courts enjoy constitutional parity with federal courts. Rejection of this premise has potentially far-reaching implications. For example, proponents of Nationalist premises have deployed Tarble’s Case to argue that, the Madisonian Compromise notwithstanding, the existence of lower federal courts is now a constitutional requirement; 294 for if the state courts are disabled from issuing constitutionally required remedies against federal officials, Congress’s discretion to define the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts is substantially circumscribed. Answering from a Federalist perspective, Professor Bator attacks Tarble’s Case as wrongly decided and therefore incapable of demonstrating the failure of the Federalist model in other areas of federal courts law. Tarble’s Case, he writes, is a ‘dubious tail’ that is much too weak to ‘wag such a large dog.’ 295 Although Tarble’s Case clearly reflects the ascendancy of the Nationalist model within its own domain, its capacity to influence other cases remains in doubt, and the battle between Nationalist and Federalist assumptions continues unabated. Indeed, it is an indication of the continuing force of both models that even many Nationalists are uncomfortable about reading Tarble’s Case for the *1206 constitutional proposition that state may not command action by federal officers. 296 Among its difficulties, this interpretation entails conclusions that are likely to prove untenable—for example, that Congress could not expressly authorize the state courts to issue injunctions and writs of mandamus and habeas corpus against federal officials.297 Though other rationales for Tarble’s Case are available, they limit the reach of its significance. One plausible reading of Tarble’s Case emphasizes congressional intent. When Congress authorized the federal court to entertain habeas corpus petitions such as that in Tarble’s Case,298 it arguably intended to create exclusive federal jurisdiction.299 And if the statute can be so read, there is no need to reach ultimate constitutional questions about what state court remedies might be available if Congress had not provided for federal jurisdiction. An alternative interpretation construes Tarble’s Case note as resting on legislative intent but as embodying a federal common law of state-federal relations.300 Being judge-made, a common law rule of skepticism of state judicial power could be overridden by Congress.301 Both of these readings of Tarble’s Case avoid the ultimate constitutional issue of state court power and thus save from explicit rejection the Federalist premise *1207 that the Constitution assumes the parity of state and lower federal courts. It is important, however, to note the cost to the Federalist model that is exacted by these saving interpretations. If Tarble’s Case rests on a construction of congressional intent, it is significant that the Court did not examine any actual legislative history. Instead it relied entirely on a presumption about the relative competence and trustworthiness of state and federal courts that issues directly from the Nationalist model. Alternatively, if Tarble’s Case is explained as involving a principle of federal common law, that principle again expresses Nationalist values. Thus, however Tarble’s Case is parsed, it promotes the assumptions of the Nationalist model and, in doing so, provides precedential authority for applying Nationalist norms in areas where Federalist premises currently predominate. 2. State Court Obligations to Accept Jurisdiction When a state court accepts jurisdiction of a case, it must apply all relevant federal law. 302 This is the core requirement of the supremacy clause.303 But must state courts exercise jurisdiction of cases asserting federal bases for relief? 304 This question arises both in suits to enforce constitutional rights and in suits under federal statutes. *1208 From a Federalist perspective, a requirement that state courts entertain federal causes of action is at least in tension with the premise of state sovereignty.305 Yet issues of state obligation to enforce federal rights also implicate the integrity of the Madisonian Compromise. If state courts could refuse to entertain federal causes of action, Congress could be forced to create lower federal courts in order to preserve the supremacy of federal law. 306 In light of this tension, two positions plausibly claim roots in Federalist premises. The first, issuing from a broad construction of the premise of state sovereignty, denies that federal law ever can require the exercise of jurisdiction by a state court. 307 The second attempts to reconcile state sovereignty with a view of the Madisonian Compromise as embodying the central assumptions of judicial federalism. It endorses a compromise that minimally requires state courts not to discriminate against claims based on federal law. 308 Moreover, if no federal court has jurisdiction of a case, they the state courts—in order to validate the presuppositions of the Madisonian Compromise—must exercise their jurisdiction *1209 to vindicate federal rights. In other situations, however, the value of state sovereignty prevails. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 17 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Tension also exists in the Nationalist model, though less acutely. From a Nationalist perspective, state sovereignty imposes no impediment to requiring state courts to enforce federal law. More difficult to comprehend within this model is why it should be important to make them do so. Requiring the state courts to exercise jurisdiction creates a situation in which it is easier for Congress to commit federal matters to state adjudication—and the Nationalist model regards federal courts as the preferred vindicators of federal rights. Although this is a cause for unease, it ultimately weighs less heavily than Nationalist assumptions about the paramount importance of vindicating individual rights. 309 When Congress wishes the states to enforce federal rights, the Nationalist model indicates that the states’ sovereignty interests must give way where congressional power begins.310 The case law reveals a complex mixture of and competition between the Federalist and Nationalist approaches. In cases involving constitutional claims, an old line of authority reflects the Nationalist model. General Oil Co. v. Crain,311 decided in 1908, held that a state court must give a remedy for constitutional rights violations, despite the state court’s lack of jurisdiction to award relief under state law. 312 *1210 Objections based on state sovereignty, such as those raised in Justice Harlan’s dissenting opinion,313 were deemed less important than the Nationalist concern to vindicate rights. Later cases followed Crain in holding that the Constitution gives rise to remedies for constitutional rights violations that the state courts are obliged to enforce.314 Although Nationalist principles thus have exercised significant influence, the Federalist model is by no means clearly vanquished. It is even possible, though barely so, to characterize the law as reflecting the models’ contradictory premises. Reading a couple of decisions from the 1940s and 1950s for the most that they might stand for, the second edition of the Hart & Wechsler casebook315 suggested that the Supreme Court had more recently followed Federalist premises in assessing the obligations of the state courts and, that in doing so it had disregarded or even overruled Crain.316 Although affirmative support *1211 for this position was and remains weak,317 no case since Crain has squarely held that state courts have a general obligation to hear even those constitutional claims that Crain marks as most compellingly in need of state adjudiciation—claims barred from federal court under Hans v. Louisian’s construction of the eleventh amendment.318 If this important issue arises again, the Court might feel entitled to resort to first principles and invoke either Federalist or Nationalist premises to reach its decision.319 *1212 Cases involving the states’ obligation to enforce federal statutes reflect a parallel struggle between Nationalist and Federalist premises. The influence of the models manifests itself in efforts to answer two kinds of questions. One involves the identification of congressional intent, the other Congress’s ultimate power to impose obligations on the states. The prior question is whether, in cases in which Congress has not stated explicitly that it intends to require state adjudication of federal statutory causes of action, it should be inferred that Congress would have wished to do so. The absence of an affirmative statement requires a reliance on presumptions of the kind that the Nationalist and Federalist models supply. Although the cases are sparse, Federalist premises generally prevail. The law presumes that Congress would not have intended to impose on the states an absolute duty to adjudicate. 320 If Congress means to impair the states’ prerogative to define the jurisdiction of their courts in rational and nondiscriminatory ways, it must say so clearly. 321 But a second presumption then gives Nationalist values a balancing presence. Absent clear indication to the contrary, it will be inferred that Congress would have wanted to require adjudication of federal causes of action in state courts that do not have a valid, nondiscriminatory excuse for declining to exercise jurisdiction. 322 The lurking constitutional question, which equally implicates the Federalist and Nationalist models, is whether Congress can require the state courts to take jurisdiction of federal statutory causes of action when they would not entertain comparable state law cases.323 *1213 Although the Supreme Court has sought to avoid this question, 324 recent decisions powerfully support the Nationalist conclusion that congressional power should be upheld against claims founded on state sovereignty interests. In Federal Energy Regulatory Commission v. Mississippi,325 the Court held that state sovereignty interests did not preclude federal legislation requiring the states to adapt their administrative and judicial processes to advance federal energy policy.326 Recent developments in tenth amendment jurisprudence also cast a long Nationalist shadow. In a resoundingly Federalist and apparently pathbreaking 1976 decision, a sharply divided Supreme Court had held in National League of Cities v. Usery327 that the tenth amendment limits Congress’s capacity to regulate state and local governments in wasy that interfere too deeply with their performance of traditional governmental functions. Read for all that it might have meant, this decision would have raised serious doubts about the capacity of Congress to require state adjudication of federal claims, even in circumstances where settled precedent had upheld congressional authority. 328 But the analytical framework of National League of Cities was at once vague and cumbersome, and the case conspicuously failed to produce *1214 progeny.329 In 1985 the Court overruled the decision entirely in Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority.330 Of potentially greater significance is that the Court, in doing so, more or less renounced the effort to give judicial content to the concept of state sovereignty under the tenth amendment. According to Garcia, the principal protection of state sovereignty interests lies in the national political process, not in judicial enforcement of constitutional provisions.331 Although the demise of National League of Cities will seriously impair Federalist arguments asserting the prerogative of the © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 18 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 states to define the jurisdiction of their courts without federal interference, it would be naive to assume that Nationalist principles will now dominate the field. Even in its Garcia decision, the Supreme Court asserted, albeit somewhat perfunctorily, that ‘we continue to recognize that the States occupy a special and specific position in our constitutional system and that the scope of Congress’ authority under the Commerce Clause must reflect that position.’332 Moreover, where issues of large constitutional principle exhibit a tension between powerful and entrenched theories, few broad holdings should be considered stable. This certainly is the view of Chief Justice Rehnquist. Dissenting from the Court’s recent enshrinement of Nationalist above Federalist principles, he reiterated his belief in an enforceable set of state sovereign prerogatives under the tenth amendment that would, he predicted, ‘in time again command the support of a majority’ of the Supreme Court.333 As indicated by that call to battle, the struggle between the Nationalist and Federalist models seems likely to continue indefinitely in this area of the law.334 *1215 D. Congressional Control of Federal Jurisdiction The scope of congressional power to define and limit the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts has been a perennial topic of debate. The issue typically arises when Congress dislikes certain substantive decisions of the federal courts and responds, not by seeking to amend the Constitution, but by limiting federal jurisdiction. As recently as 1979, for example, the Senate passed a bill that would have barred federal district court and Supreme Court jurisdiction of ‘any case arising out of any . . . State statute [that] relates to voluntary prayers in public schools and public buildings.’ 335 Although few decided cases address the issues presented by legislation of this kind, the academic literature is ‘choking on redundancy.’ 336 Not surprisingly, the Nationalist and Federalist models play large roles in the debate. If Congress withdraws lower federal court jurisdiction over a class of cases, the normal result will be that adjudication must occur in state court. Disputes about the scope of congressional power to control federal jurisdiction thus implicate a central disagreement between the *1216 Federalist and Nationalist models: Does the Constitution assume that the state courts are as competent as federal courts to perform any function that Congress might wish to leave exclusively to them? The debate about Congress’s power to substitute state for federal adjudication generally divides into two parts. 337 One involves the question whether article III restricts Congress’s discretion to define the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts. The other addresses restraints on congressional power that arise from other parts of the Constitution, such as its equal protection and due process guaranties. 1. Article III Issues Could Congress eliminate the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts over cases involving the lawfulness of, for example, voluntary prayer in public schools and public buildings? The problem, as so often, is to draw conclusions from sources that are arguably ambiguous. On the one hand, the language of article III, as supported by the Madisonian Compromise, contemplates that Congress need not create any lower federal courts at all. Drawing on this background, the Supreme Court pronounced in Sheldon v. Sill338 that legislation limiting the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts ‘cannot conflict’ with article III.339 On the other hand, the framers contemplated a tripartite scheme of government, in which the federal courts would perform an important checking function. 340 Moreover, the language of article III, like that of articles I and II, sounds in mandatory terms: the judicial power ‘shall be vested.’341 In the effort to draw a conclusion from ambiguous and possibly conflicting sources of constitutional wisdom, the Federalist and Nationalist models provide both a historical and a normative compass. From a Federalist perspective, the language of article III and the history of the Madisonian Compromise are dispositive. 342 Both indicate that the decision whether to create any lower federal courts *1217 should be discretionary with Congress.343 And, in Professor Bator’s words, ‘ i t would make nonsense of’ the compromise to hold that ‘the only power to be exercised is an all-or-nothing power to decide whether none or all of the cases to which the federal judicial power extends need the haven of a lower federal court.’ 344 Nor would it matter if Congress’s choice to exclude a certain category of cases arose from a political dissatisfaction with substantive judicial decisions. When viewed through a Federalist lens, the historical evidence suggests that the decision whether to provide a federal forum was intended to be ‘a matter of political . . . judgment.’ 345 Disputing the Federalist view, a tradition of Nationalist argument that commences with Justice Joseph Story, 346 includes Lawrence Sager,347 and has been advanced most recently by Professor Amar 348 emphasizes the mandatory language of article III. Although some Nationalists have argued that this language requires the creation of lower federal courts and their investiture with sweeping jurisdiction,349 this view is implausible in light of the Madisonian Compromise. 350 Thus, other Nationalists have taken a more modest position: although article III does not specify that the judicial power of the *1218 United States must be vested in a lower federal court, it does mandate that the judicial power shall be vested in some federal court with either original or appellate jurisdiction.351 This interpretation implies that Congress can remove the jurisdiction of the district courts over school prayer cases, for example, but only if there remains Supreme Court review of state court © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 19 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 judgments. Alternatively, Congress could withdraw Supreme Court appellate jurisdiction over school prayer disputes, but only if it provided for access as of right to an inferior federal tribunal. Although this restraint on congressional power may appear modest, it suffices to maintain the central claim of the Nationalist as against the Federalist model: the Constitution does not presume the parity of state and lower federal courts. Somewhat more specifically, the Constitution trusts the lower federal courts, but not the state courts, to function as ultimate guarantors, free from Supreme Court review, of the supremacy of federal law and federal rights.352 The case law reflects no clear choice between the Federalist and the Nationalist positions. Judicial dicta strongly support the Federalist view,353 but the precise claim on which modern Nationalists typically rest—that Congress could not eliminate both district court and Supreme Court jurisdiction over the same class of cases—has seldom *1219 been considered.354 Traditionally, arguments based on the assertedly mandatory language of article III have been embarrassed by the Judiciary Act of 1789, which is often viewed as a repository of insight into the intended meaning of article III. 355 The original Judiciary Act withheld both lower court and Supreme Court jurisdiction in many of the categories of cases listed in article III.356 But objections founded on that history are at least substantially avoided by the recent Nationalist argument of Professor Amar.357 According to Amar, Congress’s constitutional obligation to vest jurisdiction in some federal court is subject to an important limitation derived from article III, section 2, which recites the nine classes of cases to which the judicial power ‘shall extend.’358 In the first three classes—but only in the first three—does the textual language provide that the judicial power shall extend to ‘all Cases.’ These three classes encompass cases defined by subject matter; and the subject matter that they specify is of the highest national interest, including all cases ‘arising under’ the Constitution, laws, and treaties of the United States.359 In contrast with the first three, the final six jurisdictional categories, which are defined in terms of parties, rather than subject matter, lack the mandatory, inclusionary reference to ‘all Cases.’ Amar argues that this disparity limits Congress’s obligation to provide a federal tribunal to cases in the first three categories, which, he argues, are the most important. By achieving as much consistency as he does with the language of *1220 article III with the 1789 Judiciary Act,360 Amar adds enormously to the plausibility of the Nationalist model in debates about the congressional power to control the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts. Although the dearth of case law makes it difficult to pronounce any sort of concluding judgment about the current balance of power between the Nationalist and Federalist models,361 their influence should not be doubted. With textual and historical evidence available *1221 to support both the Federalist and the Nationalist positions on the congressional power to limit federal jurisdiction, it is difficult to proceed without a guiding theory of judicial federalism. And if either Federalist or Nationalist assumptions enter the analysis, their power is likely to prove conclusive. 2. ‘External’ Restraints on Congressional Power In debates over whether Congress could exclude federal district court jurisdiction of school prayer cases, the question whether state courts enjoy constituional parity with the lower federal courts under article III may have a slightly abstract quality. This is because Congress’s power to define federal jurisdiction is clearly limited by constitutional provisions other than article III, notably those establishing due process and equal protection norms. No one, for example, believes that Congress could withdraw jurisdiction of cases brought by plaintiffs who are Black or Jewish. 362 To consider all possible due process and equal protection restraints on Congress’s power to restrict the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts would carry the discussion far into the domain of substantive constitutional law. But the familiar debates partake sufficiently of the assumptions of the Nationalist and Federalist models to merit a few words. Although the literature includes a variety of due process and equal protection objections to statutes that carve away federal jurisdiction over congressionally disfavored rights, 363 nearly all depart from the fundamental Nationalist premise that the Constitution attaches high priority to the prompt and effective enforcement of constitutional rights. The purpose of most ‘jurisdictional gerrymandering’364 statutes is transparently to hinder the enforcement of the affected constitutional norms, if not to invite state court defiance of federal authority. 365 According to a Nationalist argument, this purpose is constitutionally invalid.366 If legislation is so motivated, and if it effectively invites defiance of binding Supreme Court precedent, the Nationalist model holds that it must, under prevailing due process *1222 and equal protection principles, fail of constitutionality.367 The Federalist model provides reasons for rejecting this claim. According to a Federalist reading of the Madisonian Compromise, the motive of registering dissatisfaction with the substance of federal judicial decisions is by no means impermissible. On the contrary, the point of making the existence of lower federal courts and the scope of their jurisdiction discretionary with Congress was to license political judgments about the desirability of reliance on state tribunals. 368 Nor do Federalist premises permit the assumption that jurisdictional gerrymandering would burden the enforcement of federal rights. If the state courts fulfill their obligations to enforce federal law, as the Federalist model presumes that they will, there is no reason to prefer federal to state tribunals as the guarantors of federal rights. 369 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 20 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Although reflecting no definitive choice between the models, a number of congressional statutes and Supreme Court decisions are most easily explained by Federalist principles. For example, Congress has frequently denied federal jurisdiction of suits seeking to enforce particular constitutional rights through particular judicial remedies. Federal statutes dating to the New Deal era thus provide that constitutional suits to enjoin the enforcement of state tax statutes370 and public utility rate orders may not ordinarily be brought in a federal court. 371 Nor has the Supreme Court interposed objections to such prohibitions. On the contrary, in Lauf v. Shinner372 the Supreme Court specifically upheld legislation that denied federal jurisdiction to issue certain labor injunctions. But the specific arguments formulated by recent Nationalist theorists were neither clearly raised nor clearly *1223 rejected in the most relevant Supreme Court cases.373 The due process and equal protection questions presented by jurisdictional gerrymandering statutes therefore remain open. When and if they are decided, the Nationalist and Federalist models are likely to be in the forefront of the argument. E. A Summary Diagnosis The topics that I have selected to demonstrate the power of the Federalist and Nationalist models have a partly random quality. Each subject area was chosen to illustrate doctrinal developments and academic debates that show the models’ influence. Yet other topics might have served equally well—for example, questions about the proper scope of federal common law,374 the correct interpretation of the civil rights removal statute,375 or Pullman abstention376 and related doctrines.377 The addition or substitution of topics would not, however, alter the diagnosis that is implicit in the descriptions offered thus far: federal courts law is contradictory and unstable at its foundations, because it credits the antinomic premises of the Federalist and Nationalist models and oscillates between them. Supreme Court decisions accept and legitimate the premises of both models. Yet both models cannot be valid; each denies the most fundamental claims of the other. As long *1224 as both models are implicitly, if only partially, accepted in the law, each case presents an occasion for choice—and contradiction, unpredictability, and volatility are only to be expected. The challenge is to fashion a prescription appropriate to the diagnosis. III. PRESCRIPTION: LAW BETWEEN THE POLES This Part examines the prescriptive implications of the description and diagnosis offered thus far. But implications are not deductions; the movement from description to diagnosis to prescription does not always follow a path of linear progress. I therefore begin by examining and rejecting some tempting conclusions about the current predicament of federal courts law that turn out to be misguided. After this preliminary inquiry has brought some of the problems of prescription more sharply into focus, I argue in favor of an approach that locates itself between the poles defined by the Federalist and Nationalist models. Affirmatively, the prescribed approach celebrates tension, rather than attempting to resolve it, but eschews rhetorical excess and its attendant contraditions. Needed, I argue, are modes of thought and discourse that more adequately capture the complexity and richness of American federalism and that check destabilizing swings between the Nationalist and Federalist extremes. A. Choice Between the Models One possible conclusion would be that it is necessary or desirable simply to choose between the Federalist and the Nationalist models. The prescribed course would be to determine which of the models was correct, or more nearly so, and to act consistently with its dictates. But this approach, at least if stated in strong form—that all federal courts questions ought to be resolved to accord with either the Federalist or the Nationalist model—underestimates the diversity and complexity of the problems requiring resolution. The Federalist and Nationalist models were defined initially as collections of premises. Much of the subsequent discussion, however, has aimed to show how those premises function together to define angles of approach to nearly all questions of judicial federalism. It is this aspect of the models—their provision of determinative perspectives on a very large range of federal courts questions—that makes choice between them unattractive. *1225 The problem, stated somewhat summarily, is that the perspective of each model obscures the genuine power and insights of the other. Viewed together, the Federalist and Nationalist models define a pervasive tension in the law and literature of judicial federalism. Perceived individually, however, each stands not only in support of, but also in conflict with, a set of norms that is fundamental in the constitutional scheme. It is the fundamentality of the models’ underlying values that explains not only why both persist, but also why even those judges, justices, and theorists most associated with one model at least occasionally speak from the perspective of the other. It is easy to cite cases in which a unanimous Supreme Court has reached a Nationalist result that was explained in resoundingly Nationalist rhetoric. Prominent examples include Mitchum v. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 21 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Foster378 and Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer,379 the latter authored by no less staunch a Federalist than Chief Justice Rehnquist. On the other side, many Federalist assumptions are so firmly entrenched in the law that they are never seriously challenged—for example, the presumption that Congress, in the absence of decisive indications to the contrary, would intend the state courts to exercise concurrent jurisdiction over federal causes of action. 380 As a further indication of the power of the Federalist model, even normally Nationalist judges and justices, in seeking to explain their decisions in a particular case, easily adopt Federalist rhetoric.381 When the models are viewed in conjunction, it thus becomes clear that the choice of one would entail too costly a sacrifice of the values underlying the other. Some perspective that accommodates the insights of both clearly possesses strong prima facie attractiveness. But can the Federalist and Nationalist models be abandoned so easily? *1226 B. Renunciation of the Models The conclusion that the Nationalist and Federalist models ought to be rejected is not far from correct. But the problems surrouding that conclusion are sufficiently subtle to require further discussion. In particular, it is important to recall that the models play at least three ideal typical roles: they represent rhetorical paradigms, structures of thought, and measures of the implications of fundamental assumptions and values in particular disputes. My argument against simply choosing between the Federalist and Nationalist models has treated the models perhaps most importantly as structures of thought. In the face of vague, ambiguous, or conflicted sources of legal authority—constitutional text, evidence of the framers’ intent, judicial precedent, and so forth—the Federalist model reflects a set of values and assumptions that call for all arguable doubt to be resolved in one way, while the Nationalist model dictates a different resolution. It is difficult, however, to specify the practical significance of calling for the renunciation of ideal typical structures of thought. By definition, an ideal type is an artificial construct, not a reflection of the views that any particular person or group of people actually holds. 382 The utility of the models as structures of thought lies in their definition of ‘pure’ but artificially designed sets of assumptions and beliefs that particular people might approximate. This being the case, it may well be that there are no perfect Federalists and no perfect Nationalists; there are only people who approximate the models more or less closely. As a result, to say that the models should be renounced as structures of thought is only to say that people ought not to approximate too closely the background assumptions and patterns of analysis that the models exemplify. Left open, at least for the moment, are how far from the models any particular person ought to move and to what alternative set of premises. Insofar as the Federalist and Nationalist models function as ideal types of rhetorical structures, however, the practical import of the call for their renuciation is clearer. A large number of judicial opinions reflect the rhetorical excesses of the Federalist and Nationalist models. It is the law’s embrace of incompatible Federalist and Nationalist rhetoric, more even than its pattern of results, that supports the charge that federal courts laws is internally contradictory and therefore *1227 inherently unstable. In this context, the prescription that follows the diagnosis is rather plain: judicial opinions ought to avoid exaggerated rhetorical claims, the implications of which are likely to seem unacceptable when applied to other issues and other contexts. It may be easier, in explaining a legal conclusion, for a judge or scholar to avail herself of the rhetorical arsenal furnished by either the Nationalist or Federalist tradition. But the judicial function includes a responsibility for the development of a body of law that permits fair and predictable application. Polar swings between incompatible Nationalist and Federalist rhetoric represent a betrayal of this central judicial charge. Federal courts law needs a reformed rhetorical tradition that more closely aligns judicial explanations with principles whose implications are reasonably acceptable across a range of cases.383 A reformed approach to federal courts issues would not dispense entirely with the Nationalist and Federalist models. The models would continue to function as important indicia of the implications of particular decisions for the critical, competitive values underlying judicial federalism. But the models’ status as measuring rods should be disjoined from their current, more decisive functions as rhetorical structures and salient structures of thought. *1228 C. Toward a Model-Free Jurisprudence? If the Federalist and Nationalist models ought both to be renounced, a question immediately arises about the next step in the agenda for reform. Are new models and background assumptions needed, or should reliance on models, assumptions, and background premises be abandoned altogether? An impulse to call for total rejection may spring from the intuition that the Federalist and Nationalist models somehow reflect the corruption of adjudication by politics. The idea, crudely stated, would be that judges’ background or theoretical understandings frequently reflect their personal political preferences and that, in weighing legal arguments and historical and other evidence, both Nationalist and Federalist judges allow either their assumptions or their straightforwardly normative beliefs to distort their legal judgment. However tempting it may be, the conclusion that federal courts law ought to renounce reliance on assumptions and premises that are less than value-neutral is not viable. The reasons could be traced deep into the philosophy of law, 384 but also permit a © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 22 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 plainer explanation that emphasizes the context in which the Federalist and Nationalist models exert their characteristic influence—one in which the legal materials that bear most directly on the resolution of a question either are ambiguous or point in conflicting directions. Nearly any of the controverted questions discussed earlier would suffice as an illustration. Take again as an example the question whether the eleventh amendment bars federal jurisdiction of all suits against unconsenting states or only of suits in which jurisdiction is predicated solely on the basis that a state is a party.385 Identifiable bits of historical evidence suggest that the eleventh amendment was intended to constitutionalize the states’ immunity from suit in federal court.386 Yet other evidence, at least as consistent with the constitutional language, points to a far narrower interpretation: that the amendment forbade federal jurisdiction only of suits arising under state law in which federal jurisdiction could be founded only on diversity of citizenship. 387 *1229 Moreover, within our modern constitutional practice, few legal questions are determined solely by reference to the best evidence concerning the framers’ intent.388 The effort to identify the framers’ intent is, at least in part, the search for a past that is ‘usable’389 in the context of a constitutional calculus that also gives weight to judicial precedent, arguments of constitutional theory, and concerns of normative attractiveness. 390 At least where other evidence and arguments are nearly in equipoise, the most functionally attractive conclusion—the one that fits best with a general understanding of the Constitution’s allocation of governmental responsibilities, with judicial precedent, and with modern practical needs—ought to be preferred. Thus does the web of theory and value become as essential to the process of constitutional decisionmaking. Similar pressures exist in discerning congressional intent. Consider again the general problem of interpretation posed by Reconstruction jurisdictional and remedial statutes. Passed in an atmosphere of hostility to state courts, section 1983, for example, reasonbly can be construed as prescribing the most far-reaching changes in traditional federal relations. 391 Yet in many cases the specific intent to do so was not made explicit. This gives credibility to the competing claim that Congress, had it seriously wished to revise long-settled practices, would have said so expressly.392 How, then, should specific questions of statutory interpretation—for example, whether section 1983 displaces the res judicata rules embodied in the full faith and credit statute393—be resolved? If the question is considered purely one of congressional intent, it is difficult, if not impossible, to proceed without the aid of a presumption when Congress did not address itself specifically to a disputed question. Moreover, as much here as in the constitutional context, the presumption could hardly be innocent of theory. The interpretive process requires at minimum a historical theory concerning the general intentions *1230 of the Reconstruction Congresses.394 Nor, again as in the constitutional context, is it clear that the search for congressional intent should both be divorced from contemporary concerns of policy and regarded as dispositive of current problems of judicial federalism. Once again, the search is frequently for a usable past,395 and the criterion of ‘usability’ is substantially normative. It thus seems unavoidable that theory, assumptions, and values are necessary to decisionmaking in hard federal courts cases and that there can be no neutrality, if neutrality means that cases should be decided without reference to background understandings, presumptions, or even value preferences. 396 In emphasizing the extent to which background assumptions and understandings are important to the resolution of federal courts questions, I do not, I should make clear, mean to deny the partial autonomy of law from politics or to suggest that judges and commentators should feel uninhibited about the pursuit of political ends within the framework of legal analysis. In developing a background theory of judicial federalism, conscientious judges and theorists are constrained by factors— constitutional text, historical evidence, judicial precedents, and so forth—other than their value preferences.397 Rarely will all of the ‘data’ to be explained by compatible with every set of mediating assumptions, much less with all particular outcomes, that individual judges might find congenial. Indeed, it is part of my objection to the Federalist and Nationalist models that they are incompatible with too much that is fundamental to American federalism. A further restraint on judicial decisionmaking, which is at least as powerful, ought to emerge from the evidence or legal materials most relevant to the decision in a particular case. It is a feature of many federal courts debates—or so I have argued—that the relevant materials are sufficiently indeterminate to support, or at least not to foreclose, alternative resolutions. But when the evidence points with sufficient clarity to only one conclusion, as it sometimes does, then the conscientious judge must reach it, however badly it may accord either with previously *1231 held theories of judicial federalism or with personal normative preferences. 398 But the findamental point remains. To do their jobs effectively, judges and justices need theories of judicial federalism. The problem with the Nationalist and Federalist models is not that they reflect contestable premises or values. It is that their values and premises are overstated and substantively misguided. D. Adjudication Between the Poles With the Nationalist and Federalist models both rejected and with the abandonment of all background assumptions and guiding values adjudged impossible, the general form of my prescription is clear. Thought and argument about issues of judicial federalism ought to occur between the poles defined by the Nationalist and Federalist models.399 The arguments yielding this conclusion, it should also be clear, have two dimensions. First, reliance on the rhetorical structures associated with the Federalist and Nationalist models gives rise to contradiction and instability within the case law. With the Supreme © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 23 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Court unwilling to adhere consistently to either one model or the other, alternate invocation of the models’ competing premises sows confusion. Second, this problem cannot reasonably be solved by a choice between the models, since both suffer from their dismissal of the other’s genuine insights. In arguing for a federal courts jurisprudence that functions between the Nationalist and Federalist poles, I have no sharp vision of what the best possible model might look like. But it may be useful, nonetheless, to offer some examples of how reasoning without strong Nationalist or Federalist assumptions might proceed and to identify some mediating conclusions and doctrines that commend themselves to a between-the-poles perspective. I begin with a relatively detailed *1232 discussion of the first substantive issue that I used to illustrate the influence of the Nationalist and Federalist models—the relationship of section 1983 to the strictures and policies of the Anti-Injunction Act. The other topics addressed in my earlier doctrinal critique then receive more abbreviated consideration. 1. Between Mitchum and Younger In considering the relationship between section 1983 and the letter and spirit of the Anti-Injunction Act, two questions should be separated: Should section 1983 count as an exception to the Anti-Injunction Act (the issue in Mitchum v. Foster)400 and, if so, what principles should govern the availability of federal injunctions against state judicial proceedings (the issue in Younger v. Harris)?401 a. The Mitchum Issue The question whether section 1983 constitutes an exception to the Anti-Injunction Act, as we have seen already, admits of easy resolution based on either Federalist or Nationalist premises. 402 The aspiration of a perspective from between the poles cannot be to avoid an outcome that comports with either one model or the other; section 1983 either does constitute an exception (the Nationalist conclusion) or it does not (the Federalist conclusion). The aims, rather, are a heightened sensitivity to all relevant considerations and an explanation of the result that avoids rhetorical excess. The substantive problem arises from three congressional enactments. The first is the original Anti-Injunction Act, enacted in 1793 and long construed by the Supreme Court as subject to a variety of nonenumerated exceptions; 403 the second is section 1983; the third is the revised Anti-Injunction Act passed in 1948. In considering the relationship of section 1983 to the original Anti-Injunction Act, it is surely significant that section 1983 authorizes injunctive remedies. But it is equally relevant that the statute, on its face, says nothing about injunctions against state judicial proceedings. Efforts to identify congressional intent from the legislative records also encounter *1233 irreducible uncertainties. The concept of a group intent is philosophically elusive under the best of circumstances,404 and the absence of floor debates about the issue of injunctions against state judicial proceedings gives the construction of a legislative intention an especially unguided character. This is not to say that reference to legislative intent ought to be abandoned;405 it is only to recognize that the inquiry aims more at a constructive interpretation of congressional purposes, conceived somewhat abstractly, than at a historically shared understanding that can be discovered as a matter of fact.406 With the concept of legislative intent inderstood in this way, the context of the historical debate about section 1983 becomes highly significant. Section 1983 originated as a provision of the Ku Klux Klan Act of 1871, a major piece of Reconstruction legislation that occupied the forty-second Congress for a period of several months. 407 The focus of concern, as the title of the legislation suggests, was violence committed by the Ku Klux Klan, frequently abetted or at least tolerated by southern officials. In this context, leading proponents of the Ku Klux Klan Act voiced passionate skepticism about the willingness of state courts to vindicate federal statutory and constitutional rights. 408 Particularly in light of floor statements about the necessity of substantial revisions of traditional state/federal relations,409 it is hard to conceive that proponents would not have meant to provide a federal judicial remedy against state judicial enforcement of unconstitutional state laws that fell within the core of Congress’s concern—for example, against the cynical enforcement by southern judges of racially discriminatory statutes affecting fundamental rights.410 This, of course, was not the kind of state judicial action that gave rise to the lawsuit before the Supreme Court in Mitchum. Nevertheless, at least with respect to a core of historically definable wrongs, the conclusion seems irresistible that the central historical purposes of section 1983 *1234 require an exception to the AntiInjunction Act and that the forty-second Congress would have intended such an exception. It is arguable, of course, that the forty-second Congress, though intending to authorize injunctions against state judicial proceedings in cases of a historically exceptional kind, would not have wanted to override state sovereignty and efficiency interests in every instance in which a federal plaintiff might seek to enjoin a state criminal prosecution. 411 Nevertheless, a conclusion that section 1983 constitutes an across-the-board exception to the Anti-Injunction Act need not entail a broad elevation of Nationalist over Federalist alues. The forty-second Congress enacted section 1983 against the background of the historical traditions of equity jurisprudence, which made the award of injunctions a matter of equitable discretion, not of © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 24 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 right. Retention of equitable discretion in the award of injunctions, at least in cases falling outside the core historical problems that triggered the enactment of section 1983, is thus a reasonably imputed legislative intent. Moreover, a construction of the statute that retains a degree of judicial discretion permits attractively fine-tuned accommodations of competing Federalist and Nationalist values in particular cases. This judgment about the significance of equitable discretion forms an important part of the backdrop to my between-the-poles assessment of whether section 1983 should be viewed as a historically intended exception to the Anti-Injunction Act. Although I would conclude that section 1983 was intended to authorize injunctions against state judicial proceedings, I would reach this broad conclusion—rather than trying to frame the intent as linked to the types of state court actions and inactions that were at the center of Congress’s concern—partly in reliance on a related judgment that the award of injunctions should be subject to the equitable discretion of the federal courts. I shall say more about equitable discretion shortly. First, however, it remains to consider an additional layer of complexity to the problem of whether section 1983 represents an exception to the Anti-Injunction Act. Congress revised the Anti-Injunction Act in 1948. Although the surrounding history is complicated,412 two facts are critically relevant. First, however section 1983 might have *1235 related to the older version of the Anti-Injunction Act, it can create an exception to the revised statute only if it qualifies as ‘expressly authorized by an act of Congress.’413 Second, the Reviser’s Note states that the purpose of the revised section 2283 was not to toughen the traditional anti-injunction policy but, on the contrary, to restore the law’s prior meaning in the wake of a surprisingly restrictive Supreme Court decision.414 The issue, then, is whether section 1983, which says not a word about the antiinjunction statute, constitutes an exception to section 2283 that is ‘expressly authorized by act of Congress.’ This is a very hard question.415 The statute, on its face, seems to mandate a strongly Federalist rule of inference: in the absence of express statements to the contrary, it must be assumed that the Congress would not have wanted to authorize injunctions against pending state judicial proceedings. But the Reviser’s Note, which says that the statute’s purpose was to restore the law as it was previously understood, suggests that Congress would not have intended this presumption to be as strong as the statutory language suggests. Under these rather peculiar circumstances, I would conclude that section 1983 constitutes an expressly authorized exception to the revised Anti-Injunction Act now codified as section 2283. Although the Reviser’s Note cannot license recognition of exceptions that the statute does not permit, 416 it does suggest the permissibility of some loosenses in determining when the statute and its exceptions apply.417 Here, section 1983 specifically authorizes injunctive remedies, and, as I have argued already, its core historical purposes would at least sometimes require enjoining state judicial proceedings. These are ample reasons for holding section 2283 inapplicable. *1236 In reaching this conclusion, I would have to acknowledge that my interpretation of the legally pertinent materials is colored by my preference to reach, if reasonably possible, a particular substantive result. Substantively, I would prefer a between-the-poles structure of judicial federalism that sometimes, although not routinely, permits federal injunctions againt state judicial proceedings. To my mind, ‘routinely’ and ‘never’ reflect the Nationalist and Federalist positions that misrepresent the vital tension at the heart of American federalism. But a between-the-poles approach ought to be methodologically fair and open, not just substantively centrist, and the arguments are troublingly powerful that section 1983 cannot qualify as an ‘expressly authorized’ exception to section 2283. Although not shaken in my own conclusion, I know that not everyone who favors a between-the-poles approach to judicial federalism will share my judgment on this difficult issue. There is enough space between the poles for reasonable people to differ. b. The Younger Issue As viewed from between the poles, questions about the role of equitable discretion under section 1983 are both difficult and diverse. The facts of Younger v. Harris418 provide a useful point of entry. Younger arose when Harris was charged with violation of a California antisyndicalism statute of dubious constitutional validity. Although Harris could have raised the constitutional question as part of his criminal defense in state court, he instead sought a federal injunction against the state prosecution. Because the Anti-Injunction Act does not bar suits under section 1983, the question was whether the federal district court ought to rule on the merits or should instead invoke its equitable discretion to abstain. Perceived from between the Nationalist and Federalist poles, the purposes and legislative intent of section 1983 are relevant but not sufficiently clear to be independently controlling. Did the forty-second Congress intend, as Nationalists suggest, to compel federal adjudication?419 Or, as Federalists maintain, did the framers invite a continued implementation of notions of federalism that have survived *1237 essentially unchanged since the formative years of the republic? 420 A federal injunction against pending state judicial proceedings impinges greatly on fundamental Federalist values. Because a state judge could equally well order a prosecution dismissed on federal constitutional grounds, a federal injunction often conveys the message that state courts cannot be trusted to resolve federal issues fairly. Moreover, a federal action commenced after state © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 25 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 proceedings have commenced imposes on the state the burdens of dual litigation and may disrupt the conduct of a trial in state court. As I have argued already, the purposes and legislative intent underlying section 1983 require this deep an encroachment on the states’ traditionally sovereign prerogatives in cases within the historical core of the statute’s concerns. Outside the core, however, matters are at least more doubtful. Moreover, the traditions of equity jurisprudence, of which the forty-second Congress was presumably aware, clearly established that injunctions were a matter of discretion, not right, and that they would seldom issue against a pending criminal prosecution. 421 Under the circumstances, my between-the-poles conclusion would be that equitable discretion continues to exist under section 1983, but should be exercised in light of the statute’s substantive purposes and the legislature’s reasonably ascertainable intent. 422 Those purposes and intent are clearest at the core, and in core cases they should be accorded controlling weight. In cases such as Younger, however, the Court should shoulder the responsibility for developing equitable guidelines that are responsive to modern conditions. Its task, which is informed by history but is substantially one of judicial lawmaking, is to reach a sensible accommodation of Nationalist and Federalist values in a framework of competition and balancing.423 When judicial balancing then occurs, certain normative disagreements, measurable by reference to the Nationalist and Federalist ideal types, may prove irreconcilable. But there is still hope for limited consensus between the poles. This hope resides in the acknowledgement *1238 that Nationalist and Federalist values are differentially implicated in different kinds of disputes. A short list of some relevant factors will illustrate this point: Pending or nonpending prosecution. It is more disruptive of state processes, and arguably more of an insult to state judges, for a federal court to enjoin a pending prosecution than to entertain a suit for an injunction when no state action has yet been filed.424 As a result, Federalist values are more strongly threatened in cases involving pending prosecutions. Criminal or civil action. The state is likely to have a stronger sovereign interest in the enforcement of its criminal than of its civil law.425 An injunctions against civil proceedings, whether pending or nonpending, is therefore a lesser intrusion (although still an intrusion, to be sure) on traditional state sovereignty interests. Past, future, or continuing conduct. The traditional rule against enjoining criminal prosecutions makes most sense when a criminal defendant seeks to challenge the constitutionality of state law as applied only to past conduct that she has no plan to repeat. When only past conduct is involved, there is relatively little threat of ‘chilling’ future action that is constitutionally protected and possibly socially desirable.426 As more future conduct is involved—because the criminal defendant intends to continue the activity that led to prosecution, or because others plan to engage in the same or similar activity—the Nationalist concern to ensure efficacious protection of federal rights becomes more powerful. Even if a state criminal court were as competent as a federal court, the federal court adjudicating a civil action can give interlocutory and class-based relief that a criminal *1239 court generally cannot.427 Nature of the relief sought. Depending on how it is drafted, an injunction may often be more intrusive on traditional state sovereign prerogative than a declaratory judgment. 428 The former functions as a coercive order against state officials; the latter may leave more avenues for prosecutors to prosecute other persons and thereby obtain narrowing construction that would bring state statutes within constitutional bounds. 429 But the degree of a federal remedy’s intrusion on state judicial processes defies measurement in terms of a simplistic distinction between declaratory and injunctive relief. Much depends on the way that either an injunction or a declaratory judgment is drafted and on whether the plaintiff is an individual, a group of named individuals, or a much broader class. The broader the plaintiff class, the more far-reaching the res judicata and collateral estoppel effects of a federal judgment,430 and thus the deeper the intrusion on Federalist values. These observations do not, of course, point directly to a conclusion about how particular disputes ought to be resolved. On the one hand, the Nationalist interest in avoiding chill of constitutionally protected conduct can best be protected by enjoining a statute’s enforcement against a broadly defined class. 431 On the other hand, an injunction of this kind frustrates the state’s procurement of narrowing constructions and the enforcement of its statutes to the greatest possible degree. When balancing occurs between the poles, however, it is crucial to know precisely what is at stake. Although factors such as those that I have cited seldom yield algorithmic solutions, they help to illustrate that all cases involving calls for equitable restraint under section 1983 do not present identical issues. Younger, for example, presented an extremely strong case for federal abstention: (i) a prosecution was pending in state court; (ii) the action arose under the state’s criminal law; (iii) the only plaintiff to have standing apparently made no allegation that the threat of prosecution interrupted a continuing course of conduct; and (iv) a relatively *1240 intrusive injunctive remedy was sought. The conjunction of these factors presumably helps to explain why even so Nationalist a Justice as William Brennan concurred in the Court’s disposition of the case. But while I think that Younger was rightly decided, many of its extensions and applications encroach © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 26 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 too far on Nationalist values to be defensible outside of the extreme position defined by the Federalist model. There are too many Younger-type issues for me to address any in much detail. In general, however, my between-the-poles strategy would be to attempt to accommodate Nationalist and Federalist concerns by pursuing three guiding precepts with something less than unbending rigor. First, in cases, in which a named plaintiff presents a ripe and justiciable claim to relief from the threat of prosecution based on future conduct, federal courts generally ought to exercise their jurisdiction. Such cases involve claims for relief not available in criminal prosecutions;432 generally they will not disrupt pending state actions;433 and the threat of repeated prosecutions, if not alleviated by prospective relief, would often chill constitutionally protected conduct. Second, however, the scope of discretionary remedies should generally be limited to permit state prosecutors to proceed against persons who are not parties to the action. This approach would facilitate efforts by state prosecutors to obtain narrowing constructions of overbroad statutes from the state judiciaries. 434 Third, I would view with skepticism—although without irrebuttable presumptions—particular claims that a state possesses sufficiently important interests in the conduct of civil litigation in its courts or administrative agencies to require federal abstention. But I am at least as concerned with modes of reasoning as with ultimate conclusions. Judicial opinions elaborating the Younger doctrine should move quickly beyond ritualistic incantation of general values and should eschew mechanical formulae for the identification of congressional intent. In their place should come careful, context-specific identifications of *1241 competing concerns and the development of standards for the exercise of equitable discretion on a case-by-case basis. 2. Other Issues from Between the Poles a. Respect for State Judicial Proceedings Like the Younger abstention, res judicata and collateral estoppel doctrines and the federal courts’ habeas corpus jurisdiction raise questions about appropriate federal respect for state judicial proceedings. i. Res Judiciata and Collateral Estoppel As I discussed earlier, res judicata and collateral estoppel issues involving the full faith and credit statute arise acutely in actions under section 1983. Although some tension between the two statutes is irreducible, it merits emphasis that not all section 1983 actions are alike. The historical purpose of section 1983 and its accompanying jurisdictional statute was to give plaintiffs the option to sue in a federal forum.435 There is no requirement that a plaintiff, even in a suit under section 1983, litigate in a federal rather than a state court.436 In section 1983 actions that implicate res judicata and collateral estoppel issues, it therefore becomes relevant to ask why the initial judgment, whose preclusive effect is in issue, came from a state rather than a federal court. In a case in which the federal plaintiff selected the state forum or failed to remove a removable action, the argument for giving full effect to section 1738 at its strongest; the section 1983 policy of creating a fair opportunity to litigate in a federal forum is not implicated at all. To me, however, matters look different when, as in Allen v. McCurry,437 issue preclusion in invoked against a section 1983 plaintiff who appeared involuntarily in the state litigation as a criminal defendant. Commentators as diverse as Professors Cover438 and Bator439 have argued that state trial courts and federal civil courts are likely to possess distinctive perspectives. When a federal constitutional issue is abstracted from the context and pressures of a criminal *1242 trial, it is no derogation of the state trial court to say that a federal civil court may view that issue differently, or that the federal court’s perspective is one that section 1983 invites plaintiffs to solicit. My conclusion that Allen v. McCurry was wrongly decided on its facts is not the only possible between-the-poles assessment, but neither is the between-the-poles label wholly conclusory. In seeking a mediating solution between the values and assumptions underlying section 1983 and those embodied in section 1738, a common assumption of between-the-poles stances might be that the law should draw distinctions on a context-sensitive basis.440 ii. Habeas Corpus. Subject to the fourth amendment exception carved out in Stone v. Powell,441 the federal district courts generally have jurisdiction to relitigate questions of law duly raised in state criminal proceedings. Although the reigning doctrine is substantially Nationalist, it does not carry Nationalist values to their logical extreme, since relitigation is routinely available only for questions of law, not questions of fact. 442 This distinction reflects sensitivity to Federalist values; it would be much more intrusive on legitimate state interests to require routine relitigation of issues of fact—which would often entail a substantial *1243 repetition of a criminal trial—than to countenance relitigation of questions of law. Moreover, the prevailing relitigation rule of Brown v. Allen443 has at least one effect that ought to be viewed as salutary for reasons having little to do with the familiar tension between Nationalist and Federalist values: it makes the habeas corpus jurisdiction of the federal © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 27 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 district courts and the appellate jurisdiction of the Supreme Court roughly coextensive in state criminal cases. 444 This jurisdictional parallelism reduces pressure on the appellate docket of the Supreme Court, since the Court knows that legal issues over which it declines to exercise direct review will still be subject to federal habeas jurisdiction. This is an important consideration that too easily falls out of view in a pairing of Nationalist against Federalist arguments. Here, as elsewhere, a between-the-poles approach is distinguished by its openness to arguments outside the Nationalist and Federalist paradigms. Determining the appropriate rule in habeas cases involving procedural defaults is enormously difficult. As the Federalist model emphasizes, the states must be permitted to establish reasonable procedural rules, and some preclusionary sanctions may be necessary to create incentives for conformity. 445 But Nationalist values also demand recognition. Pressure should be put on the states to develop rules that truly are reasonable. 446 Moreover, even under reasonable rules, substantive miscarriages of justice, which typically arise through the fault of the lawyer, not the client, 447 should be correctable. These considerations yield no easy or meachanical rules. As an example of between-the-poles reasonableness, however, I would commend the thoughtful and meticulous study of my colleague Daniel Meltzer, who has illustrated in detail one shape that mediating doctrines might take.448 Two aspects of his approach deserve attention. First, throughout his analysis, Meltzer manifests sensitivity to the *1244 competing Nationalist and Federalist interests at stake.449 Second, in balancing those interests, he insists on the relevance of context.450 Proceeding in this vein, Meltzer concludes that the pertinent habeas corpus doctrine should embody federal common law standards that not only define the availability of federal collateral review but also fix obligations of the state courts to forgive procedural defaults with respect to federal issues. 451 Among the virtues of Meltzer’s proposal, it would hasten vindication of federal rights in the state courts and would tend in the long run to reduce frictions between the state and federal systems by giving state courts both the opportunity and the obligation to pass in the first instance on more constitutional claims.452 b. State Sovereign Immunity and the Eleventh Amendment The eleventh amendment generates a set of issues on which my own considered convictions, though I view them as betweenthe-poles, have a somewhat Nationalist flavor. Like federal sovereign immunity, state immunity under the eleventh amendment threatens the rule of law.453 A sensible federal system cannot permit the states to violate federal norms and then raise state sovereign immunity or the eleventh amendment as an impenetrable shield. My own preference, which recent scholarship has shown to be reasonably consistent with the text and history of the eleventh amendment, 454 would therefore be for overruling Hans v. Louisiana455 and recognizing that the states are vulnerable to suit in federal court in actions arising under the Constitution and, where Congress so directs, under the laws of the United *1245 States.456 Despite overtones of Nationalism, this position need not ignore central Federalist concerns. As Professor Shapiro has observed, many of the legitimate functions currently served by eleventh amendment doctrine could better be performed by ‘flexible doctrines of construction, comity, and restraint.’457 Clear statement rules provide one example. Although it should be held that Congress possesses power under the commerce clause to subject the states to suit in federal court, the special rule of the states in our federal system makes it reasonable to presume that Congress would not take this step lightly. Requiring a clear statement of congressional intent to do so thus constitutes a mediating formula that even predominantly Nationalist writers have accepted.458 Similarly, when a state or its officers are sued on mixed state and federal constitutional grounds, a between-the-poles approach would often call for the invocation of Pullman abstention, a flexible doctrine that permits a federal court to stay a pending federal action until the plaintiffs have had an opportunity to pursue resolution of state law issues in a state court.459 From a Federalist perspective, it is an important benefit of this procedure that the state court’s decision may not only avert federal judicial involvement with complex state law questions, but may also moot a plaintiff’s federal claims. A reasonably circumscribed Younger doctrine would also protect some of the Federalist values that underlie restrictive eleventh amendment holdings.460 c. State Court Powers and Obligations i. Powers Although a contrary Nationalist argument has achieved some prominence,461 the best reading of the Madisonian Compromise presumptively *1246 permits the state courts to prescribe all remedies reasonably necessary to vindicate federal rights. The supremacy of law requires that this power reside in some court, and if Congress does not want to risk state judicial interference with federal functions, it need only vest responsibility for enforcing federal norms exclusively in the federal courts—a step clearly within its constitutional power. At least one prominent Nationalist, Professor Amar, has concurred with Federalists in reaching this conclusion.462 Indeed, contrary arguments likely owe their origin to the pervasive competition between the Nationalist and Federalist models. In the context of this rivalry, it is a natural Nationalist impulse to deploy Tarble’s Case463 to attack the Federalist premise that state courts enjoy constitutional parity with the lower federal courts. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 28 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Following a between-the-poles rejection of this competitive purpose, constitutional questions involving state court powers should present few difficulties. Questions of statutory construction remain: Did Congress intend particular grants of federal jurisdiction to be exclusive? Especially in light of the general availability of statutes permitting removal by any federal official threatened with a coercive state judicial order, a presumption should favor concurrent jurisdiction. ii. Obligations With respect to state court obligations to entertain cases involving claimed federal rights, the supremacy clause implies a duty of the states’ judiciaries to enforce the Constitution. A between-the-poles approach must of course worry about undue intrusion on the states’ sovereign prerogatives in the management of their judicial systems. But the flexible nature of a between-the-poles methodology permits accommodation through mediating doctrines. A between-the-poles decisionmaker can cheerfully concede that there is generally no requirement that any particular state court have authority to entertain particular claims or award particular remedies. Not every traffic court need be empowered to adjudicate constitutional disputes; federal intrusion on the states’ discretion to define and limit the jurisdiction of their courts should be minimized. But the states are subject to *1247 the federal Constitution, and it is not too much to ask that state courts not discriminate against constitutional causes of action464 or that a state judicial system provide some court with authority to enforce the Constitution’s guaranties. In cases involving federal statutes, the first question from a vantage point between the poles involves congressional intent: Did Congress intend to impose an obligation to adjudicate on the state courts? Where a federal court is open to hear a claim, the Supreme Court has rightly assumed that Congress would not wish to require the exercise of jurisdiction in the presence of a nondiscriminatory and otherwise ‘valid excuse.’465 The recent case of Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority466 can be read to imply that this doctrine of statutory construction constitutes the states’ sole judicially enforceable protection. Where Congress makes its intrusive wishes clear, the Court suggested, the only protection of state sovereign or quasi-sovereign interests must come from the political safeguards of federalism. 467 From a between-the-poles perspective, Garcia represents a puzzling abdication of judicial responsibility. Sensible judicial federalism almost always requires linedrawing between state and federal interests. This being so, there is no more justification for judicial abandonment of that role here than there would be elsewhere.468 d. Congressional Control of Federal Jurisdiction A between-the-poles analysis of the complex compromises underlying article III demands recognition of considerable congressional discretion to define, limit, and adjust the jurisdiction of the lower federal courts. At the same time, the federal judiciary is a coordinate branch within a tripartite division of powers, and it is implausible to construe the Constitution as allowing the judicial branch to be striped of its partnership role. Beneath these lofty generalities, some conflicts will likely prove unavoidable, even among those who reject the Nationalist and Federalist models as partial and misleading. I personally am persuaded *1248 by recent arguments that, although Congress can eliminate either federal appellate or federal original jurisdiction, it cannot eliminate both in the most important categories of cases. 469 This solution tends toward the Nationalist end of the spectrum of between-the-poles approaches, since it implies that the state courts do not enjoy constitutional parity with the lower federal courts in all contexts. In cases in which the Supreme Court retains the power to review state court judgments, however, I would hesitate to invalidate ‘jurisdictional gerrymandering’ that did not directly burden a suspect class. If the state and federal courts are likely to possess different perspectives, it seems wholly appropriate for Congress to prefer that of the state courts to that of the federal courts, subject to federal appellate review. I should emphasize again, however, that I mean to be illustrating an analytical stance, not providing an algorithm for decision or a canon of substantively correct results. If there is a common thread to what I would consider between-the-poles approaches to this issue, it is that positions should be assessed in light of their reasonableness in the context in which they arise, not tailored to fit a broader theory about the parity or lack of parity of state and federal courts in other doctrinal areas. E. The Judicial Role in the Separation of Powers Implicit in my prescription of a between-the-poles approach to questions of judicial federalism is the assumption that the federal courts, and especially the Supreme Court, have and ought to have a large responsibility for the substance and health of judicial federalism. There is at least an important difference of degree between my position and that of federal courts commentators who have argued that, where competing values are at stake, the business of the courts is not to ‘weigh the competing arguments and [try] to arrive at an acceptable middle ground,’ 470 but to paly a more chaste and nonpolitical role and to leave ‘balancing’ choices either to Congress or to the processes of constitutional amendment.471 I characterize the difference as one of degree because, as I have tried to make clear, I wholly agree that constitutional and statutory interpretation are precisely *1249 that—interpretation, not lawmaking. Judges have a responsibility to reach the best © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 29 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 understanding of a legal text as it was written, not to author an independent command, and the intent of Congress and the framers are important components of the interpretive enterprise within our legal tradition. But our interpretive tradition, which is the repository of the interpretive standards to which conscientious judges must adhere, is not self-defining.472 And I do, more than some, assume that legal interpreters frequently have not only the power but also the duty to choose between plausible outcomes on the basis of normative attactiveness. Justifications for this view are implicit in many of the arguments that I have offered already. A substantial judicial responsibility for substantive outcomes is partly the result of the nature of the interpretive enterprise, partly the product of the historical accident that the original meaning and intent of so many leading sources of federal courts law are obscure or ambiguous. Although more deserves to be said, this is not the place to say it. But it may be useful to identify two strands of argument that a full justification for the prescribed judicial role under the separation of powers would need to draw upon. First, my view accords with what courts familiarly do and must do. 473 For courts to act as the legislature’s presumptive partners in creating a workable body of law is firmly and desirably rooted in the American legal tradition.474 I do not mean to make the point too simplistically. We have moved from the era of the common law to an ‘age of statutes,’ 475 and constitutional interpretation has always represented a special case in our legal tradition. 476 But no statutory or constitutional framer could ever foresee all of the problems, or the changed future circumstances, that time and experience inevitably generate.477 Where large issues of constitutional and quasi-constitutional policy are involved, it would be a *1250 brash set of framers indeed who would not wish to enlist the aid of an interpretive community with substantial discretion. Our system not only of interpretation but of statutory and constitutional lawmaking presupposes flexibility in the courts to accommodate language reflecting core historical purposes to the perceived needs of changing interpretive contexts.478 The need for the courts to function as partners in a continuing lawmaking enterprise becomes stronger as statutes and constitutional provisions grow older. 479 Second, a system that locates substantial responsibility in judges for the substantive desirability of outcomes is likely to generate better results than one that views its judges as disinterested researchers questing for historical meaning and intent.480 As I have argued repeatedly in this essay, it is frequently impossible to tease determinate meaning from legal texts without undertaking explicit or implicit normative commitments. The power of the Nationalist and Federalist models may frequently shield interpreters from any sense of personal responsibility for choice; the models may prevent the truly determinative choice—that of an angle of vision or a set of interpretive premises—from being experienced as a choice at all. But choice is unavoidable. This being so, the influence of policy considerations should be acknowledged openly, so that assumptions and premises can be tested and, when found wanting, rejected. To the extent that argumentative premises, such as those furnished by the Nationalist and Federalist models, function merely as rhetorical structures providing justifications for results reached on other grounds, the argument that the truly driving considerations should be brought into the open is even more compelling. So long as alternative and inconsistent sets of background assumptions are available, judges will seldom experience difficulty in providing a rhetorical explanation for any result that they may reach. But this situation is pathological. Judges responsible for their decisions in the appropriate sense would not deploy overstated and inconsistent interpretive assumptions to ‘rationalize’ results on an ad hoc basis while creating an internally *1251 contradictory body of law. Accepting responsibility for the law that they develop, judges in a better tradition would relate their considerations of original meaning and the framers’ intent to the world for which they are crafting their interpretive decisions. They would do so not only with an eye to the particular result but, more broadly, to the whole body of federal courts law of which judges are at once the custodians and the architects. CONCLUSION Two models of judicial federalism—Nationalist and Federalist—pervade contemporary federal courts debates. Viewed individually, both the Nationalist and the Federalist models locate individual problems in a relatively orderly conceptual structure. The models thus clarify and simplify historical data and legal arguments for those who accept them. Moreover, recognizing the influence of the two models helps to unite and clarify a number of debates that otherwise might seem discrete. When the Nationalist and Federalist models are viewed in conjunction, however, it becomes clear that they function as engines of distortion and disorder. They are engines of distortion because each is too partial in its perception of judicial federalism and of the values and evidence central to a number of particular disputes. The familiar models are instruments of disorder because, although both are partly legitimated by their acceptance in the case law, judicial decisionmaking and rhetoric tend to swing too sharply and unpredictably between them. The result is a body of law that embodies contradictions, produces unpredictability, and invites mockery.481 It is time to move beyond the Nationalist and Federalist models and to establish the dominance of structures of thought and a rhetorical tradition that lie between the Nationalist and Federalist poles. Footnotes © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 30 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 a Professor of Law, Harvard University. The author would like to thank Akhil Amar, Erwin Chemerinsky, Robert Clark, Louis Kaplow, Daniel Meltzer, Martin Redish, and David Shapiro for their extremely helpful comments on earlier drafts. 1 Throughout this Article, I use the term ‘judicial federalism’ somewhat loosely to encompass virtually all questions involving the respective competences of state and federal courts to adjudicate issues and award remedies in cases of joint state and federal interest. For some examples, see infra p. 1145. 2 Cf. Bator, The State Courts and Federal Constitutional Litigation, 22 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 605, 606-08 (1981) (discussing two inconsistent rhetorical traditions running through much of the law and literature in the federal courts field). 3 What I call models are what have been known since Weber as ‘ideal types.’ See M. Weber, Economy and Society 19-22 (G. Roth & C. Wittich eds. 1978); C. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation 155-71 (1965). They are intellectual constructs, formed by a synthesis of familiar arguments and views. Although the elements of the models thus have foundations in actual legal argument, the models themselves are my own creations, and their elements are arranged to exhibit a conceptual purity that ‘cannot be found in reality’ but with which ‘concrete phenomena can be compared for the purpose of explicating some of their significant components.’ C. Hempel, supra, at 156. 4 P. Bator, D. Meltzer, P. Mishkin & D. Shapiro, Hart & Wechsler’s The Federal Courts and the Federal System (3d ed. 1988) [hereinafter Hart & Wechsler]. The current third edition of the casebook is much less consistently ‘Federalist,’ in the sense in which I use that term, see infra notes 29-61 and accompanying text, than were the first two editions: H. Hart & H. Wechsler, The Federal Courts and the Federal System (1953), and P. Bator, P. Mishkin, D. Shapiro & H. Wechsler, Hart & Wechsler’s The Federal Courts and the Federal System (2d ed. 1973). 5 Hart, Foreword: The Time Chart of the Justices, 73 Harv. L. Rev. 84 (1959) [hereinafter Hart, Foreword]; Hart, The Power of Congress to Limit the Jurisdiction of Federal Courts: An Exercise in Dialectic, 66 Harv. L. Rev. 1362 (1953) [hereinafter Hart, Dialogue]; and Hart, The Relations Between State and Federal Law, 54 Colum. L. Rev. 489 (1954) [hereinafter Hart, State & Federal Law]. 6 Bator, Congressional Power Over the Jurisdiction of the Federal Courts, 27 Vill. L. Rev. 1030 (1982) [hereinafter Bator, Congressional Power]; Bator, Finality in Criminal Law and Federal Habeas Corpus for State Prisoners, 76 Harv. L. Rev. 441 (1963) [hereinafter Bator, Finality]; Bator, supra note 2. 7 This is not the only possible view of the intent and history of the original Constitution. See, e.g., W. Crosskey, Politics and the Constitution in the History of the United States (1953); Amar, A Neo-Federalist View of Article III: Separating the Two Tiers of Federal Jurisdiction, 65 B.U.L. Rev. 205 (1985) [hereinafter Amar, Neo-Federalist View]; Amar, Of Sovereignty and Federalism, 96 Yale L.J. 1425 (1987) [hereinafter Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism]. 8 Although the Federalist model claims to be the descendant of the Federalists who authored the original Constitution and shaped the nation’s early constitutional history, the accuracy of this claim is disputed. Professor Amar, for example, argues that extreme deference to claims of state sovereignty interests and to state courts more closely parallels historical Anti-Federalism than Federalism. Amar adopts the mantle of ‘Neo-Federalism’ for his quite different—what I shall call ‘Nationalist’—views. See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 208 n.9; Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1426 n.9. 9 See, e.g., Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 S. Ct. 2941 (1987); Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 465 U.S. 89 (1984). 10 See, e.g., Allen v. McCurry, 449 U.S. 90, 103-04 (1980); Quern v. Jordan, 440 U.S. 332, 338-45 (1977). 11 See, e.g., Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225, 240-43 (1972); Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397 (1872). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 31 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 12 See W. Crosskey, supra note 7; Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7; Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7; Powell, The Compleat Jeffersonian: Justice Rehnquist and Federalism, 91 Yale L.J. 1317, 1360-70 (1982). 13 See, e.g., Patsy v. Board of Regents, 457 U.S. 496, 502-12 (1982); Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225, 240-43 (1971); Fiss, Dombrowski, 86 Yale L.J. 1103, 1107-09 (1977); Soifer & Macgill, The Younger Doctrine: Reconstructing Reconstruction, 55 Tex. L. Rev. 1141, 1170-71 n.136, 1175-77 (1977). 14 See, e.g., Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer, 427 U.S. 445, 456 (1976); Ex parte Young, 209 U.S. 123 (1908). 15 See, e.g., Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963); Monroe v. Page, 365 U.S. 167, 172-83 (1961). 16 See Fiss, supra note 13, at 1103; Neuborne, The Myth of Parity, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 1105, 1107-09 (1977); see also Stewart, Federalism and Rights, 19 Ga. L. Rev. 917, 917 (1985) (noting the view that ‘federalism is merely a politically opportunistic card to be played or not depending upon the substantive interests thereby advanced’). 17 The association of the models with substantive political beliefs is historically contingent. See Neuborne, supra note 16, at 110615. For example, during the ‘Lochner era,’ political liberals frequently sounded Federalist themes in criticizing the federal courts not only for substantive errors but for violating sound principles of judicial federalism. See, e.g., H. Friendly, Federal Jurisdiction: A General View 3 n.7 (1973) (describing Ex parte Young, an important Nationalist decision interpreting the eleventh amendment, as ‘the bete noir of liberals in [my] law school days’). In yet an earlier era, ‘liberal’ opponents of Supreme Court decisions that were protective of chattel slavery adopted ‘a forceful states’ rights stance’ because of their belief that state law and state courts ‘would be less effective [than their federal counterparts] in protecting the rights of slaveholders.’ Neuborne, supra note 16, at 1111. 18 See, e.g., Neuborne, supra note 16, at 1108-09 (1977) (discussing Ex parte Young); Redish, Supreme Court Review of State Court ‘Federal’ Decisions: A Study in Interactive Federalism, 19 Ga. L. Rev. 861, 863 (1985) (discussing Michigan v. Long., 463 U.S. 1032 (1983)). 19 See, e.g., Powell, supra note 12, at 1362-63 (arguing that Justice Rehnquist has a relatively consistent federalist theory of federalism that sometimes forces him to results inconsistent with his ‘conservative politics’). 20 See, e.g., Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 S. Ct. 2941 (1987); Atascadero State Hosp. v. Scanlon, 473 U.S. 234 (1985); Gibbons, The Eleventh Amendment and State Sovereign Immunity: A Reinterpretation, 83 Colum. L. Rev. 1889 (1983). 21 See, e.g., Bator, supra note 2, at 622 n.49; Durfee & Sloss, Federal Injunction Against Proceedings in State Courts: The Life History of a Statute, 30 Mich. L. Rev. 1145, 1145-46 (1932); Saltzburg, Habeas Corpus: The Supreme Court and the Congress, 44 Ohio St. L.J. 367, 373 (1983). 22 See, e.g., Oaks, Legal History in the High Court—Habeas Corpus, 64 Mich. L. Rev. 451, 472 (1966) (legal rules fashioned to cover new problems should be cloaked in reason, ‘not garbed in a regal patchwork of history that, on close examination, proves as embarrassingly illusory as the Emperor’s new clothes’). 23 See Nelson, History and Neutrality in Constitutional Adjudication, 72 Va. L. Rev. 1237, 1241-45 (1986) (developing a ‘contextualiz [ing]’ model of historical research). 24 See Fallon, A Constructivist Coherence Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 100 Harv. L. Rev. 1189, 1194-1209, 1237-68 (1987). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 32 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 25 See Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1426 n.9. 26 See Fallon, supra note 24, at 1254-58 (discussing how other factors of legal relevance frequently can and do influence interpretations of the framers’ intent in constitutional analysis). 27 See, e.g., Franchise Tax Bd. v. Construction Laborers Vacation Trust, 463 U.S. 1, 4 (1983) (denying federal jurisdiction, for ‘reasons involving perhaps more history than logic,’ over an ‘important issue’ that ‘affects thousands of federally regulated trusts’ and ‘must eventually receive a definitive, uniform resolution’ for ‘reasons involving perhaps more history than logic’). 28 See Cover & Aleinikoff, Dialectical Federalism: Habeas Corpus and the Court, 86 Yale L.J. 1035 (1977). 29 The model is developed largely from arguments advanced in scholarly literature and in Supreme Court opinions. Important sources of ideas in the scholarly literature include Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4; Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6; Bator, Finality, supra note 6; Bator, supra note 2; Hart, Dialogue, supra note 5; Hart, State and Federal Law, supra note 5; and Powell, supra note 12. Among the most suggestive Supreme Court opinions are Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 465 U.S. 89 (1984); Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37 (1971); Henry v. Mississippi, 379 U.S. 443 (1965) (Harlan, J., dissenting); Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963) (Harlan, J., dissenting); Toucey v. New York Life Ins. Co., 314 U.S. 118 (1941); Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U.S. 1 (1889). It should be emphasized, however, that the model is an intellectual construct developed to show the underlying relationships among a set of ideas. There is no claim that any of the authors from whose work the model is constructed subscribes to each of the premises advanced as constitutive of the model. 30 See, e.g., Bator, supra note 2, at 633-34 (emphasizing the Constitution’s ‘structural and institutional’ values); Powell, supra note 12, at 1327-28 (identifying history and constitutional structure as the sources of Justice Rehnquist’s federalist theory). 31 See, e.g., Nevada v. Hall, 440 U.S. 410, 433-34 (1979) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting). 32 See, e.g., Powell, supra note 12, at 1320 (Justice Rehnquist’s federalist theory holds that ‘the constitutional first principle intended by the framers was the maintenance of the federal system and of the dignity and autonomy of the states’); Bator, supra note 2, at 632 (arguing that structural norms are as important in the constitutional scheme as those that protect individual rights). 33 Merritt, The Guarantee Clause and State Autonomy: Federalism for a Third Century, 88 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 3-4 (1988). For other discussions of the values promoted by federalism, see McConnell, Federalism: Evaluating the Founders’ Design, 54 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1484, 1491-1511 (1987) (discussing the framers’ plan and what they hoped to accomplish through a federalist system); Stewart, supra note 16, at 917-19 (explaining how federalistic decentralization promotes the well-being of society). 34 See Hart, State and Federal Law, supra note 5, at 491. 35 See, e.g., Powell, supra note 12, at 1346-47. 36 Hart, State and Federal Law, supra note 5, at 491. 37 U.S. Const. amend. X. 38 See, e.g., National League of Cities v. Usery, 426 U.S. 833 (1976), overruled by Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth., 469 U.S. 528 (1985). 39 U.S. Const. amend. XI. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 33 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 40 For a discussion of the respective Federalist and Nationalist interpretations of the eleventh amendment, see infra notes 210-81 and accompanying text. 41 Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 10. 42 As viewed from a Federalist perspective, the political science of the framers recognized that the state courts frequently served and would continue to serve, as ‘the initial agency’ of state regulation and lawmaking, with the legislatures functioning characteristically only ‘as a second level of official adjustment.’ Hart, State and Federal Law, supra note 5, at 492, 499. Within a Federalist account, this assumption about the lawmaking function of state courts helps to explain how the framers could be fearful that constitutional provision for lower federal courts could ‘mak[e] an unnecessary encroachment on the jurisdiction’—and thus on the lawmaking prerogatives—of the state courts. Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 10 (quoting John Rutledge). It was apparently because of this concern that the Constitutional Convention, having first agreed in principle to the mandatory creation of federal trial courts, later rescinded its decision on a motion for reconsideration. See id. at 10-11. 43 Madison was joined by James Wilson in offering the compromise resolution. Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 11. 44 Id. Out of the compromise came the language in article III that the federal judicial power would be vested in one Supreme Court and in ‘such inferior courts as the Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.’ U.S. Const. art. III, § 1. Analogous constitutional language provides that the Supreme Court shall have appellate jurisdiction subject to ‘such Exceptions . . . as the Congress shall make.’ U.S. Const. art. III, § 2, cl. 2. 45 See Bator, supra note 2, at 606. 46 U.S. Const. art. VI. 47 Hart, Dialogue, supra note 5, at 1401. 48 Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1037. 49 See, e.g., Louisiana Power & Light Co. v. City of Thibodaux, 360 U.S. 25 (1959); Railroad Comm’n v. Pullman Co., 312 U.S. 496 (1941). 50 Hart, State and Federal Law, supra note 5, at 506; see Bator, supra note 2, at 620. 51 Bator, supra note 2, at 624. 52 Hart, Dialogue, supra note 5; Hart, Foreword, supra note 5; Hart, State and Federal Law, supra note 5. 53 Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6; Bator, Finality, supra note 6; Bator, supra note 2. 54 Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4. This was especially true of earlier editions of that work. See supra note 4. 55 See Powell, supra note 12; Shapiro, Mr. Justice Rehnquist: A Preliminary View, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 293 (1976). 56 See, e.g., Amalgamated Clothing Workers v. Richman Bros., 348 U.S. 511, 518 (1955); Toucey v. New York Life Ins. Co., 314 U.S. 118 (19841). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 34 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 57 See, e.g., Henry v. Mississippi, 379 U.S. 443, 457 (1965) (Harlan, J., dissenting); Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391, 448 (1963) (Harlan, J., dissenting). 58 See, e.g., Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 S. Ct. 2941 (1987); Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 465 U.S. 89 (1984); Schneckloth v. Bustamonte, 412 U.S. 218, 250 (1973) (Powell, J., concurring). 59 See Note, Justice Sandra Day O’Connor: Trends Toward Judicial Restraint, 42 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1185, 1222 (1985) (‘The overwhelming trend in O’Connor’s opinions, motivated by . . . considerations of federalism, is to limit access to federal courts and to infuse state government with increased independence to maintain the health of a federal system.’). 60 See, e.g., Powell, supra note 12, at 1362-63 (arguing that Justice Rehnquist’s theory of federalism is reasonably determinate and occasionally leads to results contrary to his substantive political instincts). 61 See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 208 n.9; Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1426 n.9; Powell, supra note 12, at 1366-70. 62 See, e.g., Wisdom, Foreword: The Ever-Whirling Wheels of American Federalism, 59 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1063, 1074-78 (1984). 63 See, e.g., Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1429, 1451-66; Fiss, supra note 13, at 1107; Soifer & Macgill, supra note 13, at 1143. 64 See Barron v. Baltimore, 32 U.S. (7 Pet.) 243 (1833). 65 See, e.g., Blackmun, Section 1983 and Federal Protection of Individual Rights—Will the Statute Remain Alive or Fade Away? 60 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1, 3-7 (1985). 66 See Gressman, The Unhappy History of Civil Rights Legislation, 50 Mich. L. Rev. 1323, 1324 (1952). 67 See Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1466-78. A major difficulty is that the Constitution’s supporters and oppopents alike attributed ‘complex and often contradictory meanings’ to the concept of state sovereignty. Powell, The Modern Misunderstanding of Original Intent, 54 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1513, 1524 (1987). For useful discussions, see also G. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-87, at 306-89 (1969) (describing the conflict and confusion that surrounded the framers’ attempts to allocate the power of the people between state and federal governments); Fletcher, A Historical Interpretation of the Eleventh Amendment: A Narrow Construction of an Affirmative Grant of Jurisdiction Rather than a Prohibition Against Jurisdiction, 35 Stan. L. Rev. 1033 (1983) (describing how the framers, Federalists, and Anti-Federalists all had difficulty grasping a shared conception of state sovereignty). 68 See, e.g., Nichol, Federalism, State Courts, and Section 1983, 73 Va. L. Rev. 959, 960 (1987). 69 See Martin v. Hunter’s Lessee, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 304, 327-29 (1816); Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 231-33; Clinton, A Mandatory View of Federal Court Jurisdiction: A Guided Quest for the Original Understanding of Article III, 132 U. Pa. L. Rev. 741, 749-50 (1984). 70 On the concept of a ‘Reconstruction Constitution,’ see, e.g., Soifer & Macgill, supra note 13, at 1170-71, 1175-77. 71 The Supreme Court made this clear in Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497 (1954). Although the fourteenth amendment’s equal protection clause does not literally apply against the national government, the Court in Bolling, following the decision in Brown v. Board of Education, pronounced it unthinkable that the national government should not be held to the same antidiscrimination norm as the states. The Court thus held that the due process clause of the fifth amendment effectively incorporates fourteenth © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 35 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 amendment norms and makes them applicable against the national government. See id. 72 See, e.g., Tribe, Jurisdictional Gerrymandering: Zoning Disfavored Rights Out of the Federal Courts, 16 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 129 (1981). 73 See Neuborne, supra note 16, at 1127-28. For a historical argument that ‘the . . . experiment of relying . . . on state courts for federal law enforcement’ during the years 1790-1860 was unsuccessful and shows the necessity of ready access to federal courts to enforce federal rights, see Gibbons, Federal Law and the State Courts 1790-1860, 36 Rutgers L. Rev. 399, 401-453 (1984). 74 Neuborne, supra note 16, at 1121-24. 75 Id. For similar arguments, see Sedler, The State Constitutions and the Supplemental Protection of Individual Rights, 16 U. Tol L. Rev. 465, 470-71 (1985); Developments in the Law, Federal Habeas Corpus, 83 Harv. L. Rev. 1038, 1060-61 (1970). 76 See, e.g., Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225, 240-43 (1972); Monroe v. Pape, 365 U.S. 167, 172-84 (1961); Nichol, supra note 68, at 971-83; Zeigler, A Reassessment of the Younger Doctrine in Light of the Legislative History of Reconstruction, 1983 Duke L.J. 987, 990-1020. 77 See, e.g., S. Kutler, Judicial Power and Reconstruction Politics (1968); Amsterdam, Criminal Prosecutions Affecting Federally Guaranteed Civil Rights: Federal Removal and Habeas Corpus Jurisdiction to Abort State Court Trial, 113 U. Pa. L. Rev. 793, 805-30 (1965); Wiecek, The Reconstruction of Federal Judicial Power, 1863-1875, 13 Am. J. Legal Hist. 333 (1969). Reconstruction Congresses adopted at least twelve pieces of removal legislation. S. Kutler, supra, at 147. Reconstruction also witnessed the conferral of power on the lower federal courts to issue writs of habeas corpus on behalf of prisoners detained by state authorities. See Act of Feb. 5, 1867, ch. 28, § 1, 14 Stat. 385 (current version at 28 U.S.C. § 2241(c)(3)). Prior provisions for federal habeas corpus, apparently reflecting Federalist assumptions about state sovereign prerogatives and the adequacy of state courts for protecting fundamental freedoms, had excluded state prisoners from the reach of federal authority. See Wiecek, supra, at 343. It was also during the Reconstruction Era, in 1875, that Congress gave the lower federal courts their first sustained grant of ‘general federal question’ jurisdiction over all substantial civil suits based on the Constitution and laws of the United States. With the enactment of this statute, the Supreme Court has observed, ‘the lower federal courts . . . ‘became the primary and powerful reliances for vindicating every right given by the Constitution, the laws, and treaties of the United States.’’ Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452, 464 (1974) (quoting F. Frankfurter & J. Landis, The Business of the Supreme Court: A Study in the Federal Judicial System 65 (1928)). 78 Typical is the legislative history surrounding enactment of the 1871 Civil Rights Act, Act of Apr. 20, 1871, ch. 22, § 1, 17 Stat. 13 (the predecessor statute of 42 U.S.C. § 1983), which authorized suits for damages or equitable relief against state officials who violated or caused the deprivation of federal civil rights. Proponents argued that the legislation was necessary because ‘state courts were being used to harass and injure individuals, either because the state courts were powerless to stop deprivations or were in league with those who were bent upon abrogation of federally protected rights.’ Mitchum, 407 U.S. at 240. 79 Mitchum, 407 U.S. at 240; see, e.g., Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 828-30; Nichol, supra note 68, at 971-83; Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1017-20. 80 See, e.g., Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1428-29; Fiss, supra note 13, at 1107 (discussing views of Justice Brennan). 81 See, e.g., Atascadero State Hosp. v. Scanlon, 473 U.S. 234, 247-302 (1985) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Steffel, 415 U.S. 452; Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U.S. 479 (1965); Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963). 82 See, Gibbons, supra note 20; Gibbons, supra note 73. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 36 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 83 See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7; Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7. 84 See Chayes, How Does The Constitution Establish Justice?, 101 Harv. L. Rev. 1026 (1988) [hereinafter Chayes, Justice]; Chayes, The Supreme Court, 1981 Term—Foreword: Public Law Litigation and the Burger Court, 96 Harv. L. Rev. 4 (1982). 85 See Fiss, supra note 13. 86 See Neuborne, supra note 16; Neuborne, Toward Procedural Parity in Constitutional Litigation, 22 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 725 (1981) [hereinafter Neuborne, Procedural Parity]. 87 See Sager, The Supreme Court, 1980 Term—Foreword: Constitutional Limitations on Congress’ Authority to Regulate the Jurisdiction of the Federal Courts, 95 Harv. L. Rev. 17 (1981). 88 See, e.g., Patsy v. Board of Regents, 457 U.S. 496 (1982). 89 See, e.g., Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225, 240-43 (1972); Monroe v. Pape 365 U.S. 167, 174-80 (1961); Amsterdam, supra note 77; Nichol, supra note 68, at 971-83; Zeigler, supra note 76. 90 28 U.S.C. § 2283 (1982). 91 The language of the 1793 Act spoke in seemingly absolute terms: ‘. . . nor shall a writ of injunction be granted to stay proceedings in any court of a state.’ Act of Mar. 2, 1793, ch. XII, § 5, 1 Stat. 333, 335. But the Supreme Court did not so construe the statute through most of its history; by 1941 the case law reflected a number of judicial exceptions. See, e.g., Kline v. Burke Constr. Co., 260 U.S. 226 (1922) (action in rem where federal court first acquired jurisdiction of the subject matter); Julian v. Central Trust Co., 193 U.S. 93 (1904) (matter already litigated in state court); Marshall v. Homes, 141 U.S. 589 (1891) (state judgment obtained by fraud); Providence & N.Y.S.S. Co. v. Hill Mfg. Co., 109 U.S. 578, 599-600 (1883) (federal statute provided for exclusive remedy); French v. Hay, 89 U.S. (22 Wall.) 250, 253 (1874) (state proceedings removed to federal court). Toucey v. New York Life Ins. Co., 314 U.S. 118 (1941), appeared to signal a reversal in the Supreme Court’s policy of loose construction. But Congress responded with a 1948 statutory revision that created the three statutory exemptions contained in the present version of the statute as quoted in the text. The Reviser’s Note states that ‘the revised section restores the basic law as generally understood and interpreted prior to the Toucey decision.’ 28 U.S.C. § 2283 (Reviser’s Note) (1982). For a critical survey of the doctrine as it has developed since the 1948 revision, see Redish, The Anti-Injunction Statute Reconsidered, 44 U. Chi. L. Rev. 717 (1977). For histories of the original act, see Durfee & Sloss, supra note 21; Taylor & Willis, The Power of Federal Courts to Enjoin Proceedings in State Courts, 42 Yale L.J. 1169 (1933); Warren, Federal and State Court Interference, 43 Harv. L. Rev. 345 (1930). 92 See, e.g., Atlantic Coast Line R.R. v. Brotherhood of Locomotive Eng’rs, 398 U.S. 281, 287 (1970) (the anti-injunction statute ‘in part rests on the fundamental constitutional independence of the States and their courts’); Amalgamated Clothing Workers v. Richman Bros., 348 U.S. 511, 518 (1955) (responding to the argument that ‘federal rights will not be adequately protected in the state courts’ by affirming that ‘§ 2283 is but continuing evidence of confidence in the state courts reinforced by a desire to avoid direct conflicts between state and federal courts’). Revisionist histories of the Anti-Injunction Act have disputed the view that Congress in 1793 intended to erect any broad or substantial barrier to federal judicial interference with state court proceedings. See, e.g., Mayton, Ersatz Federalism Under the Anti-Injunction Statute, 78 Colum. L. Rev. 330, 332 (1978) (‘Congress in 1793 seems to have enacted only a law prohibiting a single Justice of the Supreme Court from enjoining a state court proceeding’ and did not undertake to limit the injunctive powers of federal courts of competent jurisdiction); Note, Federal Court Stays of State Court Proceedings: A Re-examination of Original Congressional Intent, 38 U. Chi. L. Rev. 612, 624 (1971) (the 1793 Act left intact federal judicial power to stay state court proceedings by writs other than injunctions and ‘reflects . . . an intention to let the federal courts themselves work out the situations in which such stays would issue’). Supporting this Nationalist interpretation is the fact that the act was passed by a Congress that, in the historical context, would have been most unlikely to want to retract the power of the federal courts. Mayton, supra, at 335-36 & n.35. The actual intent of the Anti-Injunction Act, however, seems destined to remain shrouded in doubt. Among other difficulties, there is no record of legislative debates over the statute. See Durfee & Sloss, supra note 21, at 1145-46 & n.3. But it is interesting and important that the history even of § 2283, long a symbol of the Federalist tradition, can very © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 37 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 plausibly be read—as the Nationalist model would suggest that it should be—in a way that would deny it a strong Federalist purpose. 93 See Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225, 238-43 (1972). 94 See Currie, Res Judicata: The Neglected Defense, 45 U. Chi. L. Rev. 317, 329 (1978). 95 See Whitten, Federal Declaratory and Injunctive Interference with State Court Proceedings: The Supreme Court and the Limits of Judicial Discretion, 53 N.C.L. Rev. 591, 597-611 (1975). 96 See, e.g., Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1891, 2003-05. 97 See Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1017-25. 98 See, e.g., Nichol, supra note 68, at 993-94; Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1017-25. 99 See, e.g., Nichol, supra note 68, at 993-94; Zeigler, supra note 76, at 988, 1017-25. 100 See Bator, supra note 2, at 622 n.49; cf. Nichol, supra note 68, at 987 (‘[w]hen deference [to state courts] carries the day, opinions typically maintain that ‘nothing in the legislative history of section 1983’’ requires a contrary result) (quoting Allen v. McCurry, 449 U.S. 90, 104 (1980)). 101 At the risk of oversimplification, the judicial history can be divided into three periods. The first begins in 1908 with the Supreme Court’s decision in Ex parte Young, 209 U.S. 123 (1908). After Young, there were few if any cases in which federal injunctions stayed pending prosecutions, but while ‘a few prominent cases said that injunctions against future prosecutions should be hard to get, in practice they became routine.’ Laycock, Federal Interference with State Prosecutions: The Need for Prospective Relief, 1977 Sup. Ct. Rev. 193 (emphasis added); see Soifer & Macgill, supra note 13, at 1149-55. The restrictive cases are more interesting, however, because of the important way in which they fuse a vision of American federalism with the conceptual apparatus of equity jurisprudence. A leading example is Douglas v. City of Jeannette, 319 U.S. 157 (1943). Writing for the Court in Douglas, Chief Justice Stone affirmed the Federalist presumption that state courts are as adequate as federal courts to protect federal constitutional rights. Because important concerns of federalism are implicated whenever a federal court is asked to ‘interfere with or embarrass threatened proceedings in state courts,’ Chief Justice Stone held, courts of equity should invoke their discretionary powers to withhold relief ‘save in those exceptional cases’ where a threat of ‘irreparable injury . . . is clear and imminent.’ Id. at 162-63. The second era occurred during the years of the Warren Court, when events surrounding the civil rights movement imparted new urgency to questions about the relative sensitivity of state and federal courts to federal constitutional rights. The central case is Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 U.S. 479 (1965), in which a civil rights organization sought federal injunctive protection against threatened future prosecutions under the Louisiana Subversive Activities and Communist Control Law. A divided Supreme Court held that an injunction was barred neither by § 2283, because no prosecution was pending when suit was filed, nor by traditional limits on the availability of equitable remedies. Id. at 492, 497. The case’s most straightforward doctrinal innovation occurred within the traditional equitable requirement of irreparable injury: Justice Brennan’s opinion for the Court surmounted that barrier by postulating the transcendent value of first amendment freedoms, the exercise of which might be chilled if they could be vindicated only as defenses to criminal prosecutions. Because Dombrowski retained the analytical apparatus of Douglas, the decision might appear reasonably consistent with Federalist assumptions. But as Justice Harlan made clear in his dissent, ‘underlying the Court’s major premise that criminal enforcement of an overly broad statute affecting rights of speech and association is itself a deterrent to the free exercise thereof seems to be the unarticulated assumption that state courts will not be as prone as federal courts to vindicate constitutional rights promptly and effectively.’ Dombrowski, 380 U.S. at 499 (Harlan, J., dissenting). In an opinion much more faithful to the Federalist tradition, Harlan thought this premise impermissible. According to a sympathetic commentator, it later emerged as a weakness of the Dombrowski opinion that Justice Brennan had not explicitly rested the holding on an alternative vision of federalism. Fiss, supra note 13, at 1107. At the time of the Dombrowski opinion, Professor Fiss argues, Justice Brennan clearly believed that the Federalist vision was ‘wholly inconsistent with the revisions of federal jurisdiction that had occurred after the Civil War and that had given the citizen the right to choose which forum—state or federal—would best adjudicate his grievance against the state.’ The third, ‘modern’ period is discussed in text. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 38 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 102 401 U.S. 37 (1971). 103 407 U.S. 225 (1972). 104 As re-enacted in 1948, § 2283 admits of exceptions in only a limited number of congressionally prescribed or ratified categories. Section 1983 plausibly qualified as an exception only under the category of ‘expressly authorized by act of Congress.’ 105 See Younger, 401 U.S. at 54. 106 Id. at 44-45. 107 Id. 108 See, e.g., Nichol, supra note 68, at 993-96; Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1022-25. 109 407 U.S. 225, 243 (1972). 110 Id. at 242. 111 Because § 1983 says not a word about enjoining proceedings in state courts, one respected commentator has concluded that ‘[t]here is no excuse for the Mitchum decision.’ Currie, supra note 94, at 329. 112 Bator, supra note 2, at 620. 113 See Edwards, The Changing Notion of ‘Our Federalism,’ 33 Wayne L. Rev. 1015 (1987). 114 Huffman v. Pursue, Ltd., 420 U.S. 592, 603-05 (1975). 115 Juidice v. Vail, 430 U.S. 327, 334-35 (1977). 116 Moore v. Sims, 442 U.S. 415, 423 (1979) (finding that the ‘basic concern’ of the Younger doctrine—‘that threat to our federal system posed by displacement of state courts by those of the National Government—is also fully applicable to civil proceedings in which important state interests are involved’). 117 Texaco v. Pennzoil, 107 S. Ct. 1519, 1527 (1987). 118 See City of Los Angeles v. Lyons, 461 U.S. 95, 111-13 (1983); Rizzo v. Goode, 423 U.S. 362 (1976) (‘The principles of federalism . . . governing the relationship between federal courts and state governments, though initially expounded and perhaps entitled to their greatest weights in cases where it was sought to enjoin a criminal prosecution in progress,’ have far broader implications). For a criticism of this expansion of the Younger doctrine, as well as a more general critique of the Lyons decision, see Fallon, Of Justiciability, Remedies, and Public Law Litigation: Notes on the Jurisprudence of Lyons, 59 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1 (1984). 119 See, e.g., Juidice, 430 U.S. at 343 (Brennan, J., dissenting); Huffiman v. Pursue, Ltd., 420 U.S. 592, 615-17 (1975) (Brennan, J., © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 39 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 dissenting). Commentators have urged similar arguments. See, e.g., Redish, supra note 91; Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1017-25. 120 Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452, 460-75 (1974). 121 Id. 122 Id. at 464 (quoting F. Frankfurter & J. Landis, supra note 77, at 65). 123 See Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705, 709-12 (1977); Doran v. Salem Inn, 422 U.S. 922, 930-31 (1975). 124 But cf. supra note 79 (discussing revisionist histories of the Anti-Injunction Act). 125 Act of May 26, 1790, ch. XI, 1 Stat. 122. 126 28 U.S.C. § 1738 (1982). 127 The statutory language remains essentially unchanged from the original. A 1948 amendment substituted the present ‘same full faith and credit’ for the original ‘such full faith and credit.’ Act of June 25, 1948, § 1738, 62 Stat. 942. But the linguistic revision was not intended to alter the statute’s meaning. See Nadelman, Full Faith and Credit to Judgments and Public Acts, 56 Mich. L. Rev. 33, 81-82 (1957). 128 Section 1738 gives effect to two distinct doctrines. See Migra v. Warren City School Dist. Bd. of Educ., 465 U.S. 75, 77 n.1 (1984); Allen v. McCurry, 449 U.S. 90, 94-96 (1980). ‘Claim preclusion’ or ‘res judicata’ refers to the effect of a judgment in precluding relitigation of claims and defenses that arose from one transaction and were raised, or could have been raised, in an earlier proceeding. Claim preclusion thus encompasses principles of merger and bar. See Restatement (Second) of Judgments §§ 18-20 (1982). The doctrine of ‘issue preclusion’ or ‘collateral estoppel’ holds that a decision of an issue of fact or law that is necessary to a final judgment in one action may prevent relitigation of the same issue in a suit on a different claim by one of the parties to the first action. Id. §§ 27-28. 129 See Migra, 465 U.S. at 81; Kremer v. Chemical Constr. Corp., 456 U.S. 461, 466 (1982). A partial qualification is required for cases, mostly involving the litigation of federal questions in which state preclusion rules are themselves preempted by federal common law. See Burbank, Interjurisdictional Preclusion and Federal Common Law: Toward a General Approach, 70 Cornell L. Rev. 625, 638-40 (1985). Despite the broad literal scope of § 1738, commentators agree that § 1738 is ‘infrequently . . . mentioned,’ Smith, Full Faith and Credit and Section 1983: A Reappraisal, 63 N.C.L. Rev. 59, 81 (1984), ‘frequently disregarded,’ Developments in the Law—Section 1983 and Federalism, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 1133, 1334 (1977), or neglected, see Currie, supra note 94, at 318, in cases in which it would seemingly apply. The neglect of § 1738 has two dimensions. First, in a large class of cases, federal courts apply federal preclusion law without reference to § 1738 and its command that federal courts should apply state preclusion law, possibly on the assumption that federal and state preclusion rules would be similar if not identical. See Smith, supra, at 80. Second, there are instances in which either the Supreme Court or the lower federal courts have recognized exceptions to the rule of § 1738 that state law preclusion rules are binding in federal court. In the Supreme Court jurisprudence, habeas corpus constitutes an unambiguously accepted exception. See, e.g., Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963). Other Supreme Court cases implicitly or explicitly creating exceptions are rare but not nonexistent. See, e.g., Brown v. Felsen, 442 U.S. 127 (1979) (bankruptcy court not bound by prior state court judgment when reviewing dischargeability of debt); England v. Louisiana State Bd. of Medical Examiners, 375 U.S. 411, 415-17 (1964) (plaintiffs required by abstention doctrine to litigate state issues in state court are not barred by ordinary preclusion rules from litigating related constitutional claims in federal court following state litigation). In the lower federal courts, despite uncertainties and divisions, a number of decisions have recognized exceptions to otherwise binding preclusion rules based on exclusive grants of federal jurisdiction. Patent, antitrust, and securities litigation provide examples. For a discussion and collection of cases, see 17 C. Wright, A. Miller & E. Cooper, Federal Practice and Procedure § 4470 (1981). Most of the cases allowing relitigation apparently do not discuss the relevance of § 1738. Id. at 677. But other courts have confronted the difficulty raised by § 1738 and have reasoned that the congressional mandate reflected in exclusive jurisdictional statutes would be offended by giving preclusive effect to prior state judgments. See, e.g., Lyons v. Westinghouse Elec. Corp., 222 F.2d 184 (2d Cir.) (L. Hand, J.), cert. denied, 350 U.S. 825 (1955). See generally 17 C. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 40 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Wright, A. Miller & E. Cooper, supra, at 677-78 (‘Perhaps it is proper to assume that this old statute [§ 1738] is subject to implied exceptions drawn from modern views of exclusive jurisdiction. Centainly there is no reason to suppose that the statute was drafted with any thought of these questions.’). 130 Cf. Allen v. McCurry, 449 U.S. 90, 105 (1980) (rejecting an argument for an exception to the preclusion principles of § 1738 and expressing confidence in the willingness and ability of state courts to render correct decisions of constitutional issues). 131 See, e.g., Migra, 465 U.S. at 84 (section 1738 embodies principles of comity). The statute also imposes principles of full faith and credit on state courts, requiring that the courts of one state give full faith and credit to judgments entered in another. In the context of early debates about the meaning of federalism, prior to the conferral of broad grants of federal jurisdiction, the prescription for relations among states and their courts may have seemed the statute’s more important aspect. But the initial intent is clouded. First, the records of legislative debate and committee deliberations have not survived; apparently they were destroyed during the War of 1812. See Nadelman, supra note 127, at 60 n.124. Second, to lawyers of the period, the crucial language of the 1790 enactment may well have appeared ambiguous. The terms ‘faith’ and ‘credit’ were common law concepts used to describe the effect to be given to judgments from a foreign jurisdiction. Id. at 48-53. Under the Articles of Confederation, judgments from one colony were treated in the courts of another as those of a foreign sovereign. And while ‘comity’ required recognition of such judgments under international law principles, the colonial courts did not always accord them the conclusive effect given to a judgment from within the same colony. See id. The full faith and credit clause adopted at the Constitutional Convention, U.S. Const. art. IV, § 1, reflected a legislative compromise, which was accepted only after failed efforts to specify the degree of conclusive effect to which sister state judgments should be entitled. See Nadelman, supra note 127, at 55-59. Because the 1790 Act simply echoed the constitutional language, lower federal courts initially divided as to whether the statute required that conclusive effect, or instead only some form of prima facie or evidentiary effect, must be given to state court judgments under the statute. See Whitten, The Constitutional Limitations on State-Court Jurisdiction: A Historical-Interpretive Reexamination of the Full Faith and Credit and Due Process Clauses (pt. 1), 14 Creighton L. Rev. 499, 559-70 (1981). Early Supreme Court decisions by Justices Story and Marshall authoritatively resolved any ambiguity in favor of conclusive effect. Hampton v. McConnel, 16 U.S. (3 Wheat.) 234 (1818); Mills v. Duryee, 11 U.S. (7 Cranch) 481 (1813). But the leading decisions were entered in cases involving the full faith and credit that must be given by a state court to the judgment of a court from another state. In this context, concerns to forge a unified nation out of the states demanded a strong construction of full faith and credit. The balance of concerns arguably might have appeared somewhat different in case of a collision between state sovereignty interests on the one hand and national interests in the fairness of federal judicial decisions on the other. 132 See supra note 131. 133 Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225, 239 (1972); see Monroe v. Pape, 365 U.S. 167, 183 (1961). 134 See, e.g., Averitt, Federal Section 1983 Actions After State Court Judgments, 44 U. Colo. L. Rev. 191, 202-04 (1972); Theis, Res Judicata in Civil Rights Act Cases: An Introduction to the Problem, 70 Nw. U.L. Rev. 859, 878 (1976); Vestal, State Court Judgment as Preclusive in Section 1983 Litigation in a Federal Court, 27 Okla. L. Rev. 185, 210-12 (1974); Note, Preclusive Effect of State Judgments in Subsequent 1983 Actions, 78 Colum. L. Rev. 610 (1978). Among the lower courts, exceptional treatment for § 1983 cases represented only a minority stance. See 18 C. Wright, A. Miller & E. Cooper, supra note 129, at 69598, 717-21. But a significant number of decisions had adopted the position that claim preclusion does not apply in civil rights actions following state litigation in which specific federal claims advanced in the federal action had not been raised in state courts. See, e.g., Lombard v. Board of Educ., 502 F.2d 631, 635-37 (2d Cir.), cert. denied, 420 U.S. 976 (1974). And a small minority of courts suggested that issue preclusion might be denied at least in some circumstances. See, e.g., Chicago Sheraton Corp. v. Zaban, 593 F.2d 808, 809 (7th Cir.), cert. dismissed, 444 U.S. 911 (1979). For a fuller summary of the cases, see 18 C. Wright, A. Miller & E. Cooper, supra note 129, at 695-96. 135 See, e.g., Currie, supra note 94, at 327-28. 136 449 U.S. 90 (1980). In Allen, the plaintiff McCurry brought a § 1983 action against police officers alleging that they had unconstitutionally searched his home. At the time that McCurry brought the action, he had already been convicted of a crime, and the state criminal court had adjudged the officers’ search to be constitutional in denying McCurry’s motion to suppress evidence. The case thus presented a question of ‘issue preclusion’ or collateral estoppel—whether the state court’s decision of the constitutional issue should prevent its being relitigated in a suit for damages in federal court. In denying issue preclusion, the court of appeals had relied on Nationalist premises, emphasizing ‘the special role of federal courts in protecting civil rights.’ © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 41 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 McCurry v. Allen, 606 F.2d 795, 799 (8th Cir. 1979), rev’d, 449 U.S. 90 (1980). 137 Allen, 449 U.S. at 96. Significantly, the Court cited its own staunchly Federalist decision in Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37 (1971), as supporting authority. 138 See Allen, 449 U.S. at 96 (‘It is against this background [of traditions of comity and the existence of the full faith and credit statute] that we examine the relationship of § 1983’ and issue preclusion.). 139 See id. at 97-98 (‘Nothing in the language of § 1983 remotely expresses any congressional intent . . . to repeal the express statutory requirement’ of § 1738.) There is some ambiguity in the Court’s opinion about whether it actually intended to hold § 1738, and therefore state law, directly controlling of preclusion issues in § 1983 actions or whether it meant to lay down judicially adapted federal rules of collateral estoppel—rules for which § 1738 presumably would serve as a font of policy. Cf. Younger, 401 U.S. at 37 (employing the Anti-Injunction Act, though not held to be applicable by its terms, as a source of policy for crafting doctrines of equitable restraint). The Court initially introduced § 1738 only as ‘background’ to its decision. Allen, 449 U.S. at 96. Moreover, at various points it referred to its decision as concerning ‘the applicability of collateral estoppel to section 1983 suits,’ id. at 93 n.2, ‘normal rules of collateral estoppel,’ id. at 95 n.7, 97 n.10, and the ‘traditional doctrines of preclusion,’ id. at 98. On the other hand, the reference to ‘repeals by implication,’ id. at 88, implies that the Court assumed that § 1738 prescribed a binding congressional choice of state preclusion law. Subsequent cases seem to have established the direct applicability of § 1738. See Kremer v. Chemical Constr. Corp., 456 U.S. 461, 467, 470-72 (1982) (section 1738 applies ‘by its terms’ to actions under the 1964 Civil Rights Act); Migra v. Warren City School Dist. Bd. of Educ., 465 U.S. 75, 84-85 (1984) (section 1738 is applicable in § 1983 actions). 140 Allen, 449 U.S. at 99. 141 Id. at 105. 142 Id. The Allen Court expressly recognized an exception to its prohibition against relitigation for cases in which the parties lacked a ‘full and fair opportunity to litigate’ the issue concerning which preclusion was sought. Id. at 101. This exception exists within § 1738 itself; the statute has been held not to bar religigation in such contexts. Significantly, however, the ‘full and fair opportunity to litigate’ formula represents a standard Federalist response to allegations of state court inferiority or inadequacy as guarantors of federal constitutional rights; it presumes that state courts enjoy parity with federal courts, subject only to the possibility of proof of manifest unfairness in a particular case. The formula has been adapted into doctrines concerning federal habeas corpus, see Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465, 480-82 (1976), and federal abstention, see Moore v. Sims, 442 U.S. 415, 430 (1979), as well as issue preclusion. See Bator, supra note 2, at 620-29; Bator, Finality, supra note 6. 143 Allen, 449 U.S. at 105-16 (Blackmun, J. dissenting). Justice Blackmun’s dissenting opinion was jointed by Justices Brennan and Marshall. 144 Id. at 110. 145 Id. at 108. An accompanying footnote quoted liberally from the legislative history. 146 Id. at 110. 147 Although he rejected the majority’s holding that § 1983 actions are subject to state law preclusion rules under § 1738, Justice Blackmun would have applied preclusion doctrine—as a matter, he implied, of federal common law—based on consideration of ‘all relevant factors in each case,’ insofar as consistent with ‘the policies underlying section 1983.’ Id. at 113 (Blackmun, J., dissenting). He cited three factors that made issue preclusion inappropriate in Allen: (1) because a nonparty could not have invoked collateral estoppel at the time that § 1983 was enacted, ‘the 42d Congress could not have anticipated or approved that a criminal defendant, tried and convicted in state court, would be precluded from raising against police officers a constitutional claim arising out of his arrest’; (2) the context of a civil action may be more sympathetic than a criminal trial for litigation of a © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 42 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 fourth amendment claim; and (3) a criminal defendant, who does not make a truly voluntary choice to litigate his constitutional claim as a defense to a prosecution in state court, must have the opportunity to relitigate in federal court in order to enjoy the choice of a federal forum that § 1983 aims to provide. See id. at 114-16. 148 For a brief survey of the subsequent cases, see Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 1624-30. 149 462 U.S. 306 (1983). 150 See Shapior, Should a Guilty Plea Have Preclusive Effect?, 70 Iowa L. Rev. 27, 32 (1984). 151 Haring, 462 U.S. at 312. 152 Id. at 323 (quoting Allen, 449 U.S. at 98-99). 153 Id. at 313-14. 154 See Migra v. Warren City School Dist. Bd. of Educ., 465 U.S. 75 (1984). Migra also settled an important question left open in Allen by holding that state court judgments may be given preclusive effect with respect to claims that could have been raised, but were not, in earlier state court litigation. Id. at 898. 155 Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 1626 n.1. 156 Other important issues involving federal habeas corpus jurisdiction also could be viewed as revealing a division between the Federalist and Nationalist models. These include issues concerning the appropriate scope of the requirement that a prisoner must ‘exhaust’ available state remedies before seeking federal habeas corpus relief, see, e.g., Rose v. Lundy, 455 U.S. 509, 513-22 (1982), and the scope of federal review of state court decisions of fact, see, e.g., Sumner v. Mata, 449 U.S. 539 (1981); Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963). The issues discussed in text are selected principally because of their prominence. But they also are generally representative of the Federalist/Nationalist divisions that run throughout federal habeas corpus jurisprudence. 157 See Brown v. Allen, 344 U.S. 443, 499 (1953) (opinion of Frankfurter, J.); Saltzburg, supre note 21, at 382, 388-90. 158 Ch. XXVIII, 14 Stat. 385. The language of the 1867 statute was sweeping: it granted jurisdiction to ‘the several courts of the United States . . . to grant writs of habeas corpus in all cases where any person may be restrained of his or her liberty in violation of the constitution, or of any treaty or law of the United States . . ..’ Id. 159 29 U.S.C. §§ 2241-2255 (1982). 160 For summaries, see Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 819-25; Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 475-77. 161 See, e.g., Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 829 (atmosphere of hostility to state courts surrounding post-Civil War jurisdictional legislation supports resolving ‘fair doubts in favor of the assumption’ of federal jurisdiction); Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 47576 (because of ‘strikingly sparse’ legislative history, the statute must be read in the context of the traditionally limited function of habeas corpus); Saltzburg, supra note 21, at 373 (because the legislative history is inconclusive if read alone, guidance must be taken from attitude of hostility toward state courts manifest in other contemporaneous legislation). 162 See Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 802-03; Bator, supra note 2, at 612-16, 621-23 & n.49. But see Saltzburg, supra note 21, at 368, 382 (arguing that the proper interpretation of a statute should be resolved by reference to congressional intent and that contemporary policy concerns should not be accorded significance). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 43 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 163 Act of Sept. 24, 1789, ch. 20, § 14, 1 Stat. 73, 81. 164 See Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 466; Oaks, supra note 22, at 468; Developments in the Law—Federal Habeas Corpus, 83 Harv. L. Rev. 1038, 1045 (1970). This interpretation of the history of habeas corpus has not gone unchallenged, especially by legal scholars generally adopting a Nationalist perspective on habeas corpus. See, e.g., Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391, 408-14 (1963); Peller, In Defense of Federal Habeas Relitigation, 16 Harv. CR.-C.L. L. Rev. 579, 610-16 (1982). 165 See, e.g., Scheckloth v. Bustamonte, 412 U.S. 218, 253-55 (1973) (Powell, J., concurring); Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 475. 166 See, e.g., Rose v. Mitchell, 443 U.S. 545, 584-85 (1979) (Powell, J., concurring); Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 451-54. 167 Exceptions generally compatible with a Federalist perspective include those for circumstances when a prisoner has not had a ‘full and fair opportunity [in state court] to make his defense and litigate his case,’ Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 456, and when the sentencing court lacked jurisdiction, see id. at 460-62. An influential third position, which attempts to mediate between the Federalist and Nationalist perspectives, would allow litigation on federal habeas where there is a colorable showing of innocence. See, e.g., Rose, 443 U.S. at 586-87 (Powell, J., concurring); Schneckloth, 412 U.S. at 265 (Powell, J., concurring). The argument for this position is stated forcefully in Friendly, Is Innocence Irrelevant? Collateral Attack on Criminal Judgments, 38 U. Chi. L. Rev. 142 (1970). 168 See generally Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 451-54 (systematic federal review would tax resources, demean state judges, undermine deterrence, and defeat the important goal of repose). 169 Id. at 475; see Rose, 443 U.S. at 580 (Powell, J., concurring); Schneckloth, 412 U.S. at 255 (1973) (Powell, J., concurring); Brown v. Allen, 344 U.S. 443, 533 (1953) (Jackson, J., concurring). 170 In addition to advancing historical arguments, Bator argues generally that a policy of continuing the search for ultimate truth beyond the trial level is both epistemologically and pragmatically misguided. While every criminal defendant should have one full and fair opportunity to raise federal defenses, he would limit federal habeas corpus review to the question whether the state court had jurisdiction and whether it allowed this opportunity. See Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 451-62. 171 See Bator, supra note 2, at 623-35. Bator argues that state supreme court judges in particular typically enjoy as much pay and prestige as do federal district judges and avers that ‘[t]hose that I have met seem to me to be as expert on issues of federal constitutional laws [sic] as are federal judges.’ Id. at 630. He also argues that state judges are possibly even more likely than federal judges to be sensitive to ‘structural principles’ that limit the intrusion of federal norms on state processes and prerogatives. Id. at 631-34. 172 See Bator, supra note 2, at 614; Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 451-52. 173 Bator, supra note 2, at 624-25. 174 I can think of nothing more subversive to the judge’s inner sense of responsibility than the notion that, to the greatest possible extent, all the important shots will be called by someone else because we don’t believe in his or her competence and sensitivity. If we want the state judges to internalize the sense that they, too, speak for the Constitution . . . we must not too easily construct our jurisdictional and remedial rules on the premise that they can’t and won’t speak for the Constitution. Bator, supra note 2, at 624-25; see Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 451. 175 See Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 821-25; Brennan, Federal Habeas Corpus and State Prisoners: An Exercise in Federalism, 7 Utah L. Rev. 423, 426 (1961); Peller, supra note 164, at 619-20; Saltzburg, supra note 21, at 373-76. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 44 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 176 Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 818. 177 Although the Supreme Court retained its jurisdiction to review state criminal convictions on direct appeal by writ of error, a Nationalist view of the legislative history would not see this as making relitigation in the lower federal courts unnecessary on federal habeas corpus; many claims are difficult to raise on direct review in the Supreme Court because of the Court’s lack of capacity to receive testimony or to find facts. See, e.g., Saltzburg, supra note 21, at 375-76. 178 See, e.g., Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465, 525-30 (1976) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Amsterdam, supra note 77, at 802-03; Peller, supra note 164, at 666-69; Wright & Sofaer, Federal Habeas Corpus for State Prisoners: The Allocation of Fact-Finding Responsibility, 75 Yale L.J. 895, 898-99 (1966). 179 344 U.S. 443 (1953). Professor Bator characterizes Brown v. Allen as a significant departure from prior practice. See Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 463-65, 499-50. In contrast, Professor Peller has argued that the Supreme Court and the lower federal courts had almost uniformly construed the 1867 Habeas Corpus Act as conferring jurisdiction to relitigate claims of constitutional rights. When the cases are carefully read, Peller argues, most of the decisions that Bator characterizes as jurisdictional actually recognized the existence of federal jurisdiction; they simply denied relief on the merits because of the narrow understanding of substantive constitutional rights against the states that obtained throughout most of the nineteenth century. See Peller, supra note 164, at 620-21, 630-34. It is extremely difficult to judge the results of the Bator-Peller debate without the aid of organizing assumptions such as those provided by the Nationalist and Federalist models. Many of the cases resonate with jurisdictional language, but without absolutely foreclosing Peller’s reading. 180 See Brown, 344 U.S. at 499-500, 506, 508-10 (Frankfurter, J., concurring). 181 See Hart, Foreword, supra note 5, at 107 n.68 (‘Mr. Justice Frankfurter . . . never seems to be wanting in deference to the states . . ..’). 182 Brown, 344 U.S. at 511. 183 In Brown, the Court importantly distinguished between questions of constitutional law, with respect to which relitigation should occur on a de novo basis, and questions of fact, with respect to which state findings apparently were to be given greater deference. See, e.g., Brown, 344 U.S. at 463; id. at 506 (Frankfurter, J., concurring). The Court’s ambiguous formulations gave rise to considerable jurisprudential confusion as to the scope of federal habeas corpus review of state court findings of fact. See Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 502. At least some of the confusion has been eliminated by subsequent decisions, see, e.g., Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963), and by congressional amendment of the governing statute, which added the current 28 U.S.C. § 2254(d), in 1966. This section establishes that the factual determinations of the state courts ‘shall be presumed to be correct,’ unless one of eight enumerated criteria is satisfied. To overcome this presumption, the petitioner must show by ‘convincing evidence’ that the state determination was erroneous. Id.; see Sumner v. Mata, 449 U.S. 539, 550 (1981). 184 428 U.S. 465 (1976). 185 The Stone Court does trace some of the history of the habeas corpus statute, see Stone, 428 U.S. at 474-81, but discussion of the statute’s meaning vanishes somewhat abruptly as the majority opinion turns to the justifications for and the scope of the exclusionary rule. 186 See Stone, 428 U.S. at 494 n.35 (rejecting arguments based on skepticism about the fairness and competence of state courts and affirming that there is no ‘intrinsic reason’ to support the notion that a federal judge should be ‘more competent, or conscientious, or learned . . . than his neighbor in the state courthouse’ (quoting Bator, Finality, supra note 6, at 509)). 187 See Stone, 428 U.S. at 491 & n.31. Dissenting from a Nationalist perspective, Justice Brennan argued that the Court’s decision © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 45 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 was incompatible with the purposes of the habeas corpus act. He also vigorously disputed the Court’s Federalist premise that state courts were as competent as federal courts to adjudicate federal constitutional rights. See id. at 525, 530 (Brennan, J., dissenting). 188 See Peller, supra note 164, at 596 & n.98. 189 See, e.g., Rose v. Mitchell, 443 U.S. 545 (1979) (holding that a petitioner may relitigate a claim of racial discrimination in the composition of the grand jury). Interestingly, the Court did not rest its Rose decision solely on the authority of Brown, but directly addressed the question whether a state court was likely to be as fair and reliable as a federal court in adjudicating claims of grand jury discrimination. With the inquiry so framed, Justice Blackmun’s majority opinion reached the Nationalist conclusion that, when ‘the allegation is that the state judiciary itself engages in discrimination,’ there is ‘strong reason’ to believe that constitutional errors may not be ‘appreciated by state judges.’ Id. at 563. Dissenting from a Federalist perspective, Justices Powell and Rehnquist, objected that the decision wrongly ‘denigrate[d]’ state courts and state judges. Id. at 585 & n.7 (Powell, J., concurring). 190 That case, Daniels v. Allen, was consolidated with Brown. See Brown, 344 U.S. at 443. 191 See Hart, Forward, supra note 5, at 118. 192 For an insightful discussion of the independent and adequate state ground doctrine, see Meltzer, State Court Forfeitures of Federal Rights, 99 Harv. L. Rev. 1128 (1986). 193 See Hart, Foreword, supra note 5, at 118-19 & n.102. 194 372 U.S. 391 (1963). 195 Id. at 415. 196 Id. at 416. 197 The Court attempted to distinguish appellate from habeas corpus review by noting that while the ‘appellate function is concerned only with the judgments or decrees of state courts,’ Fay, 372 U.S. at 430, which the Supreme Court can disturb solely on grounds of federal error, the habeas corpus jurisdiction is premised not on a judgment but on ‘detention simpliciter.’ Id. at 430. With its jurisdiction based solely on a detention, not a judgment, a federal district court, the Court reasoned, could grant relief on habeas corpus on the basis of a ‘precluded’ federal claim without either impugning the validity of the underlying state conviction or offending the independent and adequate state ground doctrine that would be applicable on direct review. See id. at 424, 429-34. Among the difficulties with this argument is that it fails to answer the question how someone validly convicted in state court can be said to be in detention in violation of the Constitution, laws, or treaties of the United States. See Hart, Foreword, supra note 5, at 119 & n.102. Focusing on this difficulty, Justice Harlan’s dissenting opinion in Fay argued that a federal district court lacked constitutional (as distinct from merely statutory) power to order the release on habeas corpus of a state prisoner who had not properly litigated his federal claim in state court. Fay, 372 U.S. at 468-70 (Harlan, J., dissenting). Where state courts had obtained a lawful conviction, Justice Harlan argued, it was the state’s sovereign constitutional prerogative to retain the prisoner in state custody. See id. at 466-67. Although not without rhetorical force, this extreme version of Federalist argument ultimately seems untenable. It is settled that Congress can, if it so chooses, require state courts in federal procedural rules to observe protection of federal interest in cases involving federal statutes. See, e.g., Dice v. Akron, C. & Y. R.R., 342 U.S. 359 (1952). Yet if Congress possesses this power in cases involving federal statutes, it also would appear that Congress, at least if it were to proceed under section five of the fourteenth amendment, could constitutionally enact procedural legislation requiring the states to waive procedural defaults involving federal constitutional claims in criminal cases. But if Congress could prescribe that state procedural rules could not be enforced to bar consideration of federal issues in state court, then Congress also ought to be able to direct that procedural defaults in state court do not prohibit decision of federal issues on habeas corpus; it is no more objectionable to undermine the state interest in enforcing its preclusion rules through habeas corpus than it is through direct legislation preempting those preclusion rules in criminal cases. If this view is correct, the ultimate question in Fay is not one of constitutional power but of the extent of judicial power conferred by Congress under its grant of habeas corpus jurisdiction. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 46 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 198 Fay, 372 U.S. at 431. 199 Id. at 438. 200 See, e.g., Wainwright v. Sykes, 433 U.S. 72 (1977); Francis v. Henderson, 425 U.S. 536 (1976). 201 433 U.S. 72 (1977). 202 See id. at 87-88 & n.12. 203 Id. at 87. The Court in Wainwright did not attempt to specify the content of the ‘cause’ and ‘prejudice’ standards. See id. at 91. Subsequent cases have begun to develop their meaning. See, e.g., Amadeo v. Zant, 56 U.S.L.W. 4460 (May 31, 1988); Murray v. Carrier, 106 S. Ct. 2639 (1986); Smith v. Murray, 106 S. Ct. 2661 (1986); Reed v. Ross, 468 U.S. 1 (1984); Engle v. Isaac, 456 U.S. 107 (1982) (all applying ‘cause’ standard); United States v. Frady, 456 U.S. 152 (1982) (applying ‘prejudice’ standard). 204 See Smith, 106 S. Ct. at 2668. 205 See, e.g., Carrier, 106 S. Ct. 2639; Smith, 106 S. Ct. 2661; Engle, 456 U.S. 107 (applying ‘cause’ standard); Frady, 456 U.S. 152 (applying ‘prejudice’ standard). But see Amedeo, 56 U.S.L.W. 4460 (finding ‘cause’ for a defendant’s failure to challenge racial discrimination in the composition of both the grand and travers juries where the evidence of intentional discrimination was purposely concealed at the time of trial and the statistical underrepresentation of blacks was insufficient to establish a prima facie case of intentional discrimination under the then applicable legal standard); Reed, 468 U.S. 1 (finding ‘cause’ where, at time of trial, the defendant’s lawyer could not reasonably have been expected to anticipate the change of law effected by a subsequent Supreme Court decision). 206 Wainwright, 433 U.S. at 88. 207 Id. at 90. 208 Id. 209 See, e.g., Wainright, 433 U.S. at 105-07 (Brennan, J., dissenting); Francis v. Henderson, 425 U.S. 536, 548-51 (1976) (Brennan, J., dissenting). 210 See, e.g., U.S. Const. amend. XIV. 211 See Borchard, Government Liability in Tort (pts. 1, 4, & 5), 34 Yale L.J. 1 (1924), 36 Yale L.J. 1, 757 (1926); Jaffe, Suits Against Governments and Officers: Sovereign Immunity, 77 Harv. L. Rev. 1 (1963). 212 This, at any rate, is the consensus view. See, e.g., Field, The Eleventh Amendment and Other Sovereign Immunity Doctrines: Part I, 126 U. Pa. L. Rev. 515, 527 n.50 (1978); C. Jacobs, The Eleventh Amendment and Sovereign Immunity 151 (1972); Mathis, The Eleventh Amendment: Adoption and Interpretation, 2 Ga. L. Rev. 207, 207-10 (1968). Judge Gibbons has reached a contrary conclusion. See Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1899. Gibbons argues that the early colonial governments were suable under their charters, see id. at 1896-97, that there is no evidence that the state governments that succeeded them considered themselves to be immune from suit, see id. at 1897-99, and that the widespread adoption of bills of rights during the Revolutionary era indicates the contrary conclusion that the states must have been amenable to enforcement actions. See id. at 1898-99. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 47 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 213 Under English law at the time of the American Revolution, the monarch enjoyed a personal immunity from suit in common law courts. But this immunity was subject to two important limitations. First, by the eighteenth century, the petition of right, a writ by which the monarch could be sued with consent, was routinely entertained. See Jaffe, supra note 211, at 3, 5-9. Second, the monarch’s personal immunity did not extend to other government officials, all of whom were subject to suit without consent. See id. at 9, 9-16. Based on these limitations, Professor Jaffe concludes that the true meaning of ‘the king can do no wrong’ was that the king never would do wrong intentionally and, if he did, that he would provide a remedy. Id. at 4. But Jaffe’s conclusion is ultimately equivocal. Despite the general availability of remedies for unlawful action by the sovereign, Jaffe leaves unanswered whether the doctrine of sovereign immunity left any instances in which there could be wrongs by the sovereign that were without remedies under English law. 214 See Mathis, supra note 212, at 211 & n.16. 215 U.S. Const. art. III, § 2; see Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 S. Ct. 2941, 2964-66 (1987) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Atascadero State Hosp. v. Scanlon 473 U.S. 234, 261 (1985) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1467-75; Fletcher, A Historical Interpretation of the Eleventh Amendment: A Narrow Construction of an Affirmative Grant of Jurisdiction Rather than a Prohibition Against Jurisdiction, 35 Stan. L. Rev. 1033 (1983); Gibbons, supra note 20. 216 U.S. Const. art. III, § 2; see Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 419 (1793) (holding that the state of Georgia was not entitled to claim sovereign immunity in a suit brought in federal court and falling within this jurisdictional category). 217 See, e.g., Atascadero, 473 U.S. at 294-302 (Brennan, J., dissenting); Welch, 107 S. Ct. at 2967-68 (Brennan, J., dissenting); Fletcher, supra note 215; Gibbons, supra note 20. 218 See Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1435-36, 1448-78. 219 See Currie, The Constitution in the Supreme Court: 1789-1801, 48 U. Chi. L. Rev. 819, 836 (1981) (‘In the states, apparently to suit lay against the government. Was it likely that without specifically mentioning it, the convention meant to overthrow this established principle?’). 220 3 The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal Constituion 533 (J. Elliot ed. 1836) [hereinafter Elliot’s Debates] (speech of James Madison to the Virginia ratifying convention). 221 See The Federalist No. 81 (A. Hamilton). 222 See 3 Elliot’s debates, supra note 220, at 555 (speech of John Marshall to the Virginia ratifying convention). 223 Their statements, like Madison’s, present a number of purzzles to legal historians. Throughout the ratification debates, both champions and opponents of the proposed Constitution plainly tailored their positions on state sovereign immunity to gain political advantage. See, e.g., 1 C. Warren, The Supreme Court in United States History 96 (2d ed. 1926); Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1047-51; Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1903-07. Modern Nationalists have therefore resisted the conclusion that Madison, Hamilton, and Marshall truly believed that the Constitution upheld state sovereign immunity. Judge Gibbons, for example, has argued that Madison’s much quoted remarks reflected a subtle distinction between suits predicated on state law, in which cases states would retain their sovereign immunity, and suits based on federal law, in which cases their immunity would have to yield to the requirement of federal supremacy. See id. at 1906. The second most plausible interpetation, gibbons believes, is that Madision was ‘merely dissembling.’ Id. Gibbons similarly argues that Hamilton, in The Federalist No. 81, probably intended his remarks about the states’ nonamenability to suit to refer to causes of action arising under state law, with respect to which the states retained many attributes of sovereignty, but not to suits arising under the Constitution, laws, or treaties of the United States. See id. at 1911-12. Nationalists also draw comfort from the fact that some of the Constitution’s leading proponents, including Edmund Randolph and James Wilson, explicitly assumed that article III abrogated the states’ sovereign immunity from suit in federal court and defended it on this basis. See 3 Elliot’s Debates, supra note 220, at 207 (quoting remarks of Edmund Randolph to the Virginia Convention); 2 Elliot’s Debates, supra note 220, at 491 (quoting remarks of James Wilson to the Pennsylvania Convention). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 48 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 In light of the innumerable ambiguities and uncertainties that attend the historical record, most commentators have agreed that the evidence concerning the constitutional status of state sovereign immunity in the wake of the ratification debates and before the adoption of the eleventh amendment is mixed, contradictory, and ultimately indeterminate. See, e.g., Field, supra note 212; Fletcher, supra note 215; Gibbons, supra note 20. More general theories of substantive and judicial federalism, rooted in interpretations of history but also informed by contemporary concerns of policy and of value, therefore make their way almost inevitably into the historical debate. 224 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 419 (1973). 225 For an illuminating analysis of the opinions in the case, including a discussion of the justices’ background assumptions as they interpreted the relevant constitutional language, see Currie, supra note 94, at 831-39. 226 Chief Justice Jay and Justices Wilson, Blair, and Cushing each wrote separate opinions. None of the justices in the majority distinguished between common law claims, in which federal jurisdiction must be predicated on the identity of the parties, and suits ‘arising under’ the Constitution, laws, and treaties of the United States. All of the majority justices relied on the constitutional language. See Chisholm, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.), at 450-53 (Blair, J.); id. at 466-69 (Cushing, J.). But Chief Justice Jay and Justice Wilson also introduced other considerations. Before coming to the relevant constitutional language, Chief Justice Jay found amenability to suit not to be incompatible with the limited sovereignty retained by the states. See id. at 471-72. Justice Wilson carefully examined and minimized the concept of sovereignty before arguing that the Constitution clearly ‘could vest jurisdiction,’ id. at 464, over states if the framers had so intended, as he concluded from the language of article III that they did. Id. at 466. In his interesting dissent, Justice Iredell appeared to draw on Federalist assumptions as he argued that (i) the language of the Judiciary Act of 1789, read in light of the historical tradition of sovereign immunity, should not be construed to confer federal jurisdiction of common law actions against a state and (ii) ‘nothing but express words, or an insurmountable implication (neither of which I consider, can be found in the case)’ could justify holding the suit within article III. Id. at 449-50. Justice Iredell, however, noted that the suit in Chisholm was based on state law and that jurisdiction was predicated solely on the diverse citizenship of the parties. With respect to actions under state law, Iredell concluded that Congress would have intended to invest the federal courts with no more jurisdiction to entertain suits under the common law than was possessed by Georgia state courts, which would have been obliged to honor the state’s claim of sovereign immunity. Chisholm, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) at 436-37. Justice Iredell explicitly reserved the question of the states’ immunity from suits based on federal law. Id. at 449-50. 227 See, e.g., Hans v. Louisiana, 134 U.S. 1, 11 (1890) (the decision ‘created . . . a shock of surprise’); 1 C. Warren, supra note 223, at 96; Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1058. But see Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1926 (‘Congress’s initial reaction to the Chisholm decision hardly demonstrates the sort of outrage so central to the . . . thesis’ that the decision was universally perceived as an affront to state sovereign interests that was incompatible with the constitutional plan). 228 See Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1058-59. 229 U.S. Const. amend. XI. 230 See, e.g., Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1060; Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1926-27. 231 See Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1926-27. 232 See Fletcher, supra note 215; Gibbons, supra note 20. 233 See, e.g., Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1060-63; Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1934-38. Although their processes of reasoning are somewhat different, substantially the same conclusion is reached by other respected commentators. See, e.g., Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1473-75; Field, supra note 212, at 538-46; Nowak, The Scope of Congressional Power to Create Causes of Action Against State Governments and the History of the Eleventh and Fourteenth Amendments, 75 Colum. L. Rev. 1413, 1445-46 (1975); Tribe, Intergovernmental Immunities in Litigation, Taxation, and Regulation: Separation of Powers Issues in Controversies About Federalism, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 682, 693-99 (1976). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 49 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 234 Supportive of this interpretation is that the eleventh amendment received ‘overwhelming support from Federalists in both houses of Congress.’ Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1934. 235 See, e.g., Florida Dep’t of State v. Treasure Salvors, Inc., 458 U.S. 670, 683 n.17 (1982); Edelman v. Jordan, 415 U.S. 651, 66263 (1974). 236 See, e.g., Employees of the Dep’t of Pub. Health & Welfare v. Department of Pub. Health & Welfare, 411 U.S. 279, 291-92 (1973) (Marshall, J., concurring in the result); Poindexter v. Greenhow (The Virginia Coupon Cases), 114 U.S. 270, 337-38 (1885) (Bradley, J., dissenting). 237 See Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderan, 465 U.S. 89, 98-100 (1984); Hahs v. Louisiana, 134 U.S. 1 (1889). 238 See, e.g., Cohens v. Virginia, 19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264, 412 (1821) (holding that the eleventh amendment did not bar Supreme Court jurisdiction of a criminal appeal because the suit was not brought ‘by a citizen of another State, or by a citizen or subject of a foreign State’ and thus was not ‘within the amendment, but is governed entirely by the Constitution as originally framed, and we have already seen, that in its origin, the judicial power extended to all cases arising under the constitution or laws of the United States, without respect to parties’) (alternative holding). Only once prior to the Civil War, in Ex parte Madrazzo, 32 U.S. (7 Pet.) 627, 632 (1833), did the Supreme Court accept a claim of immunity based on the eleventh amendment. See Orth, The Interpetation of the Eleventh Amendment, 1798-1908: A Case Study of Judicial Power, 1983 U. Ill. L. Rev. 423, 429 (1983); Shapiro, Wrong Turns: The Eleventh Amendment and the Pennhurst Case, 98 Harv. L. Rev. 61, 68-69 (1984). But cf. Collins, The Conspiracy Theory of the Eleventh Amendment (Book Review), 88 Colum. L. Rev. 212, 223-24 (1988) (noting a potentially important reservation in Chief Justice Marshall’s Madrazzo opinion). 239 134 U.S. 1 (1890). Hans barred federal jurisdiction of a suit against a state by one of its own citizens—an action beyond the eleventh amendment’s literal prohibition, which encompasses only suits against a state by the citizens of another state or by citizens or subjects of a foreign power—in which the plaintiff advanced a constitutional claim that strongly implicated federal supremacy concerns. 240 Id. at 14-15. The Hans opinion was equivocal on the source of state sovereign immunity—whether in the eleventh amendment, see, e.g., C. Wright, Law of Federal Courts § 48, 287 & n.6 (4th ed. 1983); Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1893-94; the common law, see, e.g. Employees of Dep’t of Pub. Health & Welfare v. Department of Pub. Health & Welfare, 411 U.S. 279, 313 (1973) (Brennan, J., dissenting); Field, supra note 212, at 537 & n.81, or the constitutional plan as it existed prior to the eleventh amendment, see, e.g., Department of Pub. Health, 411 U.S. at 291-92 (Marshall, J., concurring). Nevertheless, the case represents the principal source of authority for subsequent cases suggesting that the eleventh amendment requires a general recognition of state sovreign immunity, despite the amendment’s literal applicability only to suits brought in federal court and ‘commenced or prosecuted against one of the United States by Citizens of another State, or by Citizens or Subjects of any Foreign State.’ U.S. Const. amend. XI; see, e.g., Pennhurst, 465 U.S. at 98; Edelman v. Jordan, 415 U.S. 651, 663 (1974); United States v. Mississippi, 380 U.S. 128, 140 (1965); Ford Co. v. Department of Treasury, 323 U.S. 459, 464 (1945). 241 See, e.g., Atascadero State Hosp. v. Scanlon, 473 U.S. 234, 260 (1985) (Brennan, J., joined by Marshall, Blackmun, and Stevens, JJ., dissenting); Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 S. Ct. 2941, 2965-68 (1987) (Brennan, J., joined by Marshall, Blackmun, and Stevens, JJ., dissenting). 242 426 U.S. 833 (1976). 243 Atascadero, 473 U.S. at 303 (Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, and Stevens, JJ., dissenting) (citing Garcia, 469 U.S. 528). The reference to the Court’s tenth amendment jurisprudence is doubly revealing. First, from a Nationalist perspective, potential federal jurisdiction should be coextensive with Congress’s legislative powers under article I. Second, as revealed by the Court’s Garcia opinion, which was joined by all four of the dissenting justices in Atascadero, from a Nationalist perspective the concept of state sovereignty under the tenth amendment imposes few if any limitations on congressional power. Thus, the Nationalist model views issues of judicial federalism as closely related to, and sometimes determined by, a more substantive theory of congressional prerogatives vis-a-vis the states in the constitutional scheme. For a discussion of the relationship between the Supreme Court’s recent cases involving state sovreignty claims under the tenth and eleventh amendments, see Brown, State © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 50 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Sovreignty Under the Burger Court—How the Eleventh Amendment Survived the Death of the Tenth: Some Broader Implications of Atascadero State Hospital v. Scanlon, 74 Geo. L.J. 363 (1985). 244 See Welch, 107 S. Ct. 2941. 245 See id. at 2957-58. 246 Federalists as well as Nationalists concur in this conclusion. See, e.g., Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 465 U.S. 89, 104-05 (1984) (accepting as ‘necessary’ the exception associated with Ex parte Young) (opinion of Powell, J.). 247 Cf. Shapiro, supra note 238, at 84-85 (describing disputes over the application of sovereign immunity doctrine as being between those who approach the doctrine with a degree of respect approaching ‘awe’ and those who, like himself, have been content to work with the doctrien while recognizing that ‘the notion of the state’s immunity from suit is itself [a] fiction . . . that never properly stands in the way of ultimate vindication of the rights of the individual against the state’ (footnote omitted)). 248 Osborn v. Bank of the United States, 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 738, 842-43 (1824). Marshall also propounded the complementary theory that, because a state cannot authorize its officials to violate the Constitution, any unconstitutional action must be that of some individual rather than the state. See id. at 838, 859. But cf. Collins, supra note 238, at 223 (noting that Marshall, in Georgia v. Madrazzo, 26 US. (1 Pet.) 110, 124 (1828), posited that ‘even were the state not named, the defendant officer still had to have a real interest in the controversy familiar to the common law’ in order to justify a decree against the officer personally). 249 The Supreme Court allowed injunctive relief against state officers, consistently through Board of Liquidation v. McComb, 92 U.S. 531 (1876), even when the purpose and effect of the lawsuit were to determine their official actions. See Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1978. The departure from this pattern appears to have come in Louisiana v. Jumel, 107 U.S. 711 (1882), in which seven justices held that a suit to prevent a state’s impairment of its obligations on a contract was effectively a suit against the state itself brought by the citizens of another state and that ‘under the Eleventh Amendment of the Constitution no State can be sued in the courts of the United States by the Citizens of another State.’ Id. at 720. 250 Currie, Sovereign Immunity and Suits Against Government Officers, 1984 Sup. Ct. Rev. 149, 151 n.11. 251 See Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1991-2002. In its stead came a period of vacillation. During this period, the leading issue involved the capacity of the federal courts to compel the former Confederate states to make payments on debts that they had incurred before the Civil War. So enormous was the burden, and so politically unpopular was repayment, that in the post-Reconstruction years all of the southern states repudiated at least part of their debts. Orth, supra note 238, at 435. Historians have suggested that the Court shied from authorizing jurisdiction in cases involving the former Confederate states because it recognized that judicial decrees could not be enforced against them. See, e.g., Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1998; Orth, supra note 238, at 435. During the same period the Court generally continued to uphold federal jurisdiction in suits involving states where the prospects for obedience or enforcement were better. See id. at 447-50. 252 123 U.S. 443 (1887). 253 In part the Ayers opinion was written as if to suggest that constitutional significance attaches to the fact that the suit essentially was one to enforce a contract. See id. at 505. But the suggestion that the states enjoyed substantive freedom to violate contracts was inconsistent with Supreme Court authority dating to Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87 (1810). Moreover, other language in the opinion suggested a more broadly Federalist interpretation of the eleventh amendment: ‘To secure the manifest purposes of the constitutional exemption guaranteed by the 11th Amendment requires that it should be interpreted, not literally and narrowly, but fairly, and with such breadth and largeness as effectually to accomplish the substance of its purposes.’ Ayers, 123 U.S. at 505-06. 254 209 U.S. 123 (1908). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 51 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 255 Id. at 160. 256 Id. 257 This fiction was in fact firmly established prior to Young, see, e.g., Gunter v. Atlantic Coast Line R.R., 200 U.S. 273, 283-84 (1906); Smyth v. Ames, 169 U.S. 466, 518-19 (1898), and arguably traces back to Osborn v. Bank of the United States, 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 738, 842-43 (1824). 258 See, e.g., Neuborne, supra note 16, at 1108. 259 See Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1041 n.25. 260 Ex parte Young, 209 U.S. 123, 176 (1908) (Harlan, J., dissenting). 261 415 U.S. 651 (1974). 262 See id. at 665 (‘The funds to satisfy the award in this case must inevitably come from the general revenues of the State of Illinois, and thus the award resembles far more closely the monetary award against the State itself . . . than it does the prospective injunctive relief awarded in Ex parte Young.’). 263 See Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1120. 264 Milliken v. Bradley, (II), 433 U.S. 267 (1977). The Court reasoned that, although the programs were designed to compensate for past harms, they were permissible under Edelman because ‘they are part of a plan that operates prospectively to bring about the delayed benefits of a unitary school system.’ Id. at 290. But this rationalization is not convincing, since all judicial orders— including awards of damages—operate prospectively in the same sense as the compensation in Milliken (II). 265 See Hutto v. Finney, 437 U.S. 678 (1978). 266 See, e.g., Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1480. 267 A constitutional value judgment lies plainly on the surface of the important decision in Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 46k U.S. 89 (1984), in which a passionately divided Supreme Court held by a five-to-four vote that the Young fiction could not be used to strip state officers of eleventh amendment immunity based on their alleged violations of a state constitution. Prededent plainly did not determine the result. Distinguishing large numbers of cases, see id. at 109-17, Justice Powell’s Court opinion took its main support directly from Federalist values. Justice Powell characterized state sovereignty as a bedrock value of the federal system that was embodied in the eleventh amendment. See id. at 97-100. Bowing partially to Young and the Nationalist values on which it rests, the majority acknowledged that federal courts must be available to vindicate federal rights in suits for injunctions against state officials. See id. at 105-06. But where a plaintiff sought to enforce the state constitution, and federal rights thus were not directly in issue, Justice Powell concluded that the Federalist interests must prevail. See id. at 106. Justice Stevens’s angry Pennhurst dissent accused the Court of overruling at least twenty-eight cases, see id. at 127 (Stevens, J., dissenting), in which, he asserted, the Court had either held that a suit against an officer was not a suit against a state or had upheld pendent jurisdiction of state law injunctive claims against state officials when the plaintiff also had asserted a claim to relief under federal law that was actionable in federal court under the fiction of Young. More was at stake, however, than fidelity to state decisis. The opportunity to litigate both state and federal claims in one proceeding provides a strong reason for plaintiffs seeking injunctions against state officials to present their federal claims in state court, rather than in a federal forum, where Pennhurst would allow only federal claims to be heard. Though it remains a possibility, the bifurcation of the claims—federal claim in federal court, state claim in state court—could be both excessively costly and procedurally treacherous. See Shapiro, supra note 238, at 80-82; Werhan, Pullman Abstention After Pennhurst: A Comment on Judicial Federalism, 27 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 449 (1986). As a result, Pennhurst seems to make it less likely that all meritorious federal claims will be presented in a © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 52 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 federal forum. As much as the reasoning on which the majority rested, this is a result uncongenial to the Nationalist values that most adequately explain the result in Young. 268 427 U.S. 445 (1976). 269 Writing for the Court, Justice Rehnquist reasoned that a settled ‘line of cases has sanctioned intrusions by Congress, acting under the Civil War Amendments, into the judicial, executive, and legislative spheres of autonomy previously reserved to the States’ and has recognized an expansion of congressional power ‘with the corresponding diminution of state sovereignty.’ Id. at 455. 270 See D. Currie, Federal Jurisdiction in a Nutshall 161 (2d ed. 1981). 271 See id.; Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1113. 272 See Fitizpatrick v. Bitzer, 427 U.S. 445, 457-60 (Brennan & Stevens, JJ., concurring separately) (1976). 273 See Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 Sup. Ct. 2941 (1987); Fitzpatrick v. Bitzer, 427 U.S. 445 (1976). The Court has visited this question before, but with results that now seem inconclusive. Parden v. Terminal Ry., 377 U.S. 184 (1964), squarely put the question of congressional powerBut the Court’s opinion left the answer unclear. At one point, Justice Brennan’s opinion for the Court appeared to issue a Nationalist conclusion: ‘By empowering Congress to regulate commerce, then, the States necessarily surrendered any portion of their sovereignty that would stand in the way of such regulation,’ including their sovereign immunity from suit. Id. at 192. No sooner had Justice Brennan taken this position, however, than he tacked in a Federalist direction. ‘It remains the law,’ he wrote, ‘that a State may not be sued by an individual without its consent.’ Id. Consistently with the latter premise, the Court undertook a ‘waiver’ analysis to determine whether the state of Alabama, by continuing to operate a railroad in interstate commerce after Congress had provided that all such railroads would be suable in federal district court, had impliedly consented to suit. Parden’s conjunction of the ‘abrogation’ and ‘waiver’ questions rests on a transparent confusion. See, e.g., M. Redish, Federal Jurisdiction: Tensions in the Allocation of Judicial Power 142 (1980); Tribe, supra note 233, at 688-89. If Congress has power to abrogate state sovereign immunity under the commerce clause, then state consent to suit is not required. Nonetheless, the confusion has not been clearly resolved by subsequent cases. 274 The time of decision may be close, since the Supreme Court has granted certiorari in a case that the court of appeals found to raise this question. United States v. Union Gas Co., 832 F.2d 1343 (3d Cir. 1987), cert. granted sub nom. Pennsylvania v. Union Gas Co., 108 S. Ct. 1219 (1988). In the Supreme Court, however, the antecedent question will of course be whether Congress made its intent to abrogate state sovereign immunity sufficiently clear for this question to be properly presented. See infra notes 278-81 and accompanying text. 275 See supra notes 230-34 and accompanying text. 276 See, e.g., Nowak, supra note 233, at 1441-42; Tribe, supra note 233, at 693-94. 277 See Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth., 469 U.S. 528, 556-57 (1985). 278 See Parden v. Terminal Ry., 377 U.S. 184 (1964) (reasoning that the Court ‘should not presume to say, in the absence of express provision to the contrary, that [Congress] intended to exclude’ the states from otherwise applicable substantive and jurisdictional legislation). 279 For a forceful defense, see Brown, supra note 243. 280 See, e.g., Atascadero State Hosp. v. Scanlon, 473 U.S. 234, 238-46 (1985); Pennhurst State School & Hosp. v. Halderman, 465 U.S. 89, 99 (1984) (‘Our reluctance to infer that a State’s immunity from suit in the federal courts has been negated stems from © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 53 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 recognition of the vital role of sovereign immunity in our federal system.’); Edelman v. Jordan, 415 U.S. 651, 674 (1974). 281 Atascadero, 473 U.S. at 243, quoted in Welch v. Texas Dep’t of Highways & Pub. Transp., 107 S. Ct. 2941, 2946 (1987) (pluralit opinion). 282 The controversy focuses almost exclusively on the power of state courts to compel action by federal officials in the performance of their official functions through writs of habeas corpus and mandamus and injunctions. In other kinds of actions, state courts routinely interpret and apply federal law and in the process of doing so must rule on the lawfulness of federal administrative action and on the constitutionality of acts of Congress. See Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 488-92. Nor, subject to the removal provisions of 28 U.S.C. §§ 1441, 1442, and 1442a, are state courts generally disabled from exercising jurisdiction over federal officials in criminal actions, see, e.g., Colorado v. Symes, 286 U.S. 510 (1932), suits for damages, see, e.g., Scranton v. Wheeler, 179 U.S. 141 (1900); Teal v. Felton, 53 U.S. (12 How.) 284 (1851), or in actions at law for specific relief, such as replevin and ejectment, see, e.g., Scranton, 179 U.S. 141; Teal v. Felton, 53 U.S. (12 How.) 284 (1851), or in actions at law for specific relief, such as replevin and ejectment, see, e.g., Scranton, 179 U.S. 141; United States v. Lee, 106 U.S. 196 (1882); Slocum v. Mayberry, 15 U.S. (2 Wheat.) 1 (1817). But see Stanley v. Schwalby, 162 U.S. 255 (1896) (action may not be brought in state court if United States is a necessary party). For general discussions of state court jurisdiction and powers in cases involving federal officers, see Arnold, The Power of State Courts to Enjoin Federal Officers, 73 Yale L.J. 1385 (1964); Note, Limitations on State Judicial Interference with Federal Activities, 51 Colum. L. Rev. 84 (1951). 283 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397 (1871). Tarble’s Case was itself decided largely on the authority of Ableman v. Booth, 62 U.S. (21 How.) 506 (1858). 284 See Arnold, supra note 282, at 1401-02 (the supremacy clause, which binds state courts to enforce the Constitution, implies the power as well as the obligation to do so); Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 491. The Judiciary Act of 1789 did not confer original federal jurisdiction over suits or proceedings against federal officers arising out of their official acts. One commentator thus has concluded that [t]he theory of that legislation seems to have been that remedies against Federal officers were to be enforced in the State courts except when in case of diverse citizenship the circuit court had concurrent jurisdiction, and that supervision by the national government could be sufficiently exercised by writ of error from the highest court of the State to the Supreme Court of the United States. Bishop, The Jurisdiction of State and Federal Courts Over Federal Officers, 9 Colum. L. Rev. 397, 397 (1909). 285 See The Moses Taylor, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 411, 429-30 (1866). 286 See, e.g., Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397, 408-09 (1871); Redish & Woods, Congressional Power to Control the Jurisdiction of Lower Federal Courts: A Critical Review and a New Synthesis, 124 U. Pa. L. Rev. 45, 97-101 (1975). 287 See, e.g., Alabama ex rel. Gallion v. Rogers, 187 F. Supp. 848, 852 (M.D. Ala. 1960) (denying state court power to enjoin federal enforcement of federal civil rights law and noting that ‘[s]uch action by the state courts . . . cannot be tolerated without there being created frustration of national purposes’), aff’d per curiam, 285 F.2d 430 (5th Cir.), cert. denied, 366 U.S. 913 (1961); Kennedy v. Bruce, 298 F.2d 860 (5th Cir. 1962) (affirming the earlier holding in the Rogers case in a similar civil rights action); Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 89-92 (arguing that civil rights cases support the proposition that state courts lack power to enjoin federal officials); Note, Draft Reclassification for Political Demonstrations—Jurisdictional Amount in Suits Against Federal Federal Officers, 53 Cornell L. Rev. 916, 928 (1968) (arguing that due to concerns about efficiency and the possibility of state obstructionism, state courts should not have the power to enjoin federal officials). 288 See, e.g., Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397, 408-09 (1871) (state authority to issue writs of habeas corpus against federal officials could undermine constitutional power to raise and support armies and provide for regulation of armed services); Ableman v. Booth, 62 U.S. (21 How.) 506, 515 (1858) (state courts may not issue writs of habeas corpus against federal officers, because the national government could not fulfill its constitutional functions ‘if offences against its laws could not [be] punished without the consent of the State in which the culprit was found’); Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 82-102; Note, supra note 287, at 929. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 54 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 289 See Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 102; cf. Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397, 411 (1871) (federal courts stand ready to vindicate constitutional rights in cases where state courts lack jurisdiction). See generally Neuborne, supra note 16 (federal courts are recognized by constitutional litigators as preferable to state forums for the vindication of federal constitutional rights). 290 Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397, 408-09 (1871). 291 Id. at 410-11 292 Compare Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 84-109 (defending Tarble’s Case and promoting a general theory of congressional power to control state and federal jurisdiction based on its rule) with Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 491 (attacking the reasoning in Tarble’s Case and, with respect to theory advanced by Redish and Woods, wondering ‘Why should the dubious tail of Tarble’s Case was such a large dog?’); see also Sager, supra note 87, at 80-84 (discussing the debate over Tarble’s Case and concluding that the dispute is of little practical importance, because Congress could always ensure exclusive federal jurisdiction by affirmatively expressing such an intent). 293 These include questions of state judicial authority to issue writs of mandamus and injunctions commanding action by federal officials. See Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 489-90. 294 See Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 93-109. 295 Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 491. 296 Although Redish & Woods argue that the case expresses a constitutional mandate, see Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 94-95, they also take the seemingly incompatible position that Congress could override the decision by specifically authorizing the state courts to issue writs of mandamus against federal officials. See id. at 106; cf. Redish, Constitutional Limitations on Congressional Power to Control Federal Jurisdiction: A Reaction to Professor Sager, 77 NW. U.L. REV. 143, 157-59 (1982) (asserting that Tarble’s Case should be read as involving ‘simply an inference of congressional intent to exclude state court power in the face of congressional silence’). 297 See Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 491 & n.7; Note, supra note 282, at 87 n.31. 298 The Court specifically noted the existence of an available remedy in federal court. See Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397, 411 (1871). 299 See Redish, supra note 296, at 157-59; cf. Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 488 (suggesting that Tarble’s Case may have been based on a variety of factors, of which the existence of a federal statute was one). 300 See, e.g., Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 488. 301 For illuminating iscussions of the capacity of the federal courts to craft subconstitutional rules of federal common law, implementing constitutional norms but not required by them and therefore subject to replacement by Congress, see Field, Sources of Law: The Scope of Federal Common Law, 99 Harv. L. Rev. 881 (1986); Monaghan, The Supreme Court 1974 Term— Foreword: Constitutional Common Law, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1 (1975). For more restrictive views of the scope of federal judicial power to craft common law rules, see Merrill, The Common Law Powers of Federal Courts, 52 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1 (1985); Schrock & Welsh, Reconsidering the Constitutional Common Law, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 1117 (1978). 302 Martin v. Hunter’s Lessee, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 304 (1816). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 55 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 303 U.S. Const. art. VI, cl. 2. 304 Although Congress has undoubted power to create exclusive federal jurisdiction in cases presenting federal issues, see The Moses Taylor, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 411 (1866), it has rarely done so. For a general discussion of congressional exclusion of state court jurisdiction over cases presenting federal issues, see Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 479-81. Moreover, an established and virtually unchallenged presumption holds that a grant of federal jurisdiction generally should not be interpreted to preclude concurrent state jurisdiction. See, e.g., Claflin v. Houseman, 93 U.S. 130, 136 (1876) (the state court has ‘jurisdiction, where it is not excluded by express provision, or by incompatibility in its exercise from the nature of the particular case’); Charles Dowd Box Co. v. Courtney, 368 U.S. 502 (1962). But cf. Tarble’s Case, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397, 407 (1872) (federal jurisdiction is inappropriate, ‘except so far as it may be necessary . . . to preserve [the National government’s] rightful supremacy in cases of conflict of authority’). The presumption that state courts may exercise jurisdiction concurrent with that of federal courts reflects in substantial part the influence of the Federalist model, even among judges and commentators who more commonly reason from Nationalist premises. But see Redish & Muench, Adjudication of Federal Causes of Action in State Courts, 75 Mich. L. Rev. 311, 313-40 (1976) (criticizing the presumption). But prevailing principles governing the parties’ selection of a state or federal forum render concurrent jurisdiction almost wholly inoffensive to Nationalist values. If federal jurisdiction exists by statute, a plaintiff enjoys the option to sue in federal court. Further, in nearly any case in which the plaintiff could have selected a federal forum, the defendant has a right of removal. See 28 U.S.C. § 1441(a) (1982). 305 The best known and most forceful statement of this position comes from Justice Frankfurter’s concurring opinion in Brown v. Gerdes, 321 U.S. 178, 188-89 (1944) (Frankfurter, J., concurring): Neither Congress nor the British Parliament nor the Vermont Legislature has power to confer jurisdiction upon the New York Courts . . . [s]ubject to only one limitation, each State of the Union may establish its own judicature, distribute judicial power among the courts of its choice, define the conditions for exercise of their jurisdiction and the modes of their proceeding, to the same extent as Congress is empowered to establish a system of inferior federal courts within the limits of federal judicial power, and the States are as free from control by Congress in establishing state systems for litigation as is Congress free from state control in establishing a federal system for litigation. 306 See Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 497 (asking whether the view that Congress may not require the states to accept jurisdiction is ‘tenable in light of the possibility that Congress may may choose not to create any lower federal courts at all’); cf. Hart, Dialogue, supra note 5, at 1401 (asserting that state courts ‘are the primary guarantors of constitutional rights, and in many cases they may be the ultimate ones’). 307 See Brown, 321 U.S. at 188 (Frankfurter, J., concurring); General Oil Co. v. Crain, 209 U.S. 211, 232-33 (1908) (Harlan, J., concurring). 308 See Dice v. Akrone, C. & Y. R.R., 342 U.S. 359, 367 (1952) (Frankfurter, J., dissenting) (recognizing, despite Justice Frankfurter’s views as expressed in Brown, 321 U.S. at 188, that ‘a State must entertain negligence suits brought under the Federal Employers’ Liability Act if it entertains ordinary [state law] actions for negligence’); cf. Federal Energy Regulatory Comm’n v. Mississippi, 456 U.S. 742, 784-85 (1982) (O’Connor, J., dissenting) (acknowledging that state courts can be required not to discriminate against federal claims but distinguishing, and finding violative of the tenth amendment, a federal requirement that state administrative agencies consider adoption and implementation of federal standards). 309 See, e.g., Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1509-10; Neuborne, Procedural Parity, supra note 86, at 761-62. 310 See, e.g., Neuborne, Procedural Parity, supra note 86, at 759-60; Redish & Muench, supra note 304, at 342-43; Sandalow, Henry v. Mississippi and the Adequate State Ground: Proposals for a Revised Doctrine, 1965 Sup. Ct. Rev. 187, 207 n.84; cf. Federal Energy Regulatory Comm’n v. Mississippi, 456 U.S. 742 (1982) (upholding congressional authority, in a preemptible field, to require state utility regulatory commissions and state reviewing courts to conform to federal regulations). 311 209 U.S. 211 (1908). 312 See Crain, 209 U.S. at 224-228. One sentence in the Court’s opinion could be read to suggest that, because of the eleventh amendment, the suit could not have been litigated in federal court: © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 56 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 If a suit against state officers is precluded in the national courts by the Eleventh Amendment to the Constitution, and may be forbidden by a state to its courts, as is contended in the case at bar that it may be . . . it must be evident that an easy way is open to prevent the enforcement of many provisions of the Constitution, and the Fourteenth Amendment, which is directed at state action, could be nullified as to much of its operation. Id. at 226. If this was in fact the Court’s understanding, its holding would be consistent with one version of the Federalist position. See supra note 304 and accompanying text. But it is highly uncertain that the Court actually believed that a suit in federal court would have been barred; Crain was decided on the same day as Ex parte Young, 209 U.S. 123 (1908), which held that a suit against a state official for injunctive relief—the same relief sought in Crain—was not a suit against the state and thus not barred from federal court by the eleventh amendment. Moreover, the surrounding sentences suggest that the crucial distinction determining the obligations of the state courts is not one involving the availability or nonavailability of federal judicial relief; it is, rather, ‘between valid and invalid state laws, as determining’ whether the suit is one against the state—in which case the state may insist upon its sovereign immunity—or one against state officials. Crain, 209 U.S. at 226. Because a state cannot authorize its officers to behave unconstitutionally, official action pursuant to an invalid state law cannot be protected by sovereign immunity; and a state court cannot decline to exercise jurisdiction on this basis. 313 See Crain, 209 U.S. at 232-33 (Harlan, J., dissenting). 314 See Iowa-Des Moines Nat’l Bank v. Bennett, 284 U.S. 239, 247 (1931) (a state court is obliged by federal law to order a refund as the remedy for taxes collected in violation of the fourteenth amendment, despite the court’s lack of state law authority to award this remedy); Ward v. Love County, 253 U.S. 17, 24 (1920) (no state statutory authority is necessary to establish a right to recover money exacted by a county ‘through imposition’ and ‘in contravention of the Fourteenth Amendment’); see also Allied Stores v. Bowers, 358 U.S. 522, 526 (1959) (federal rather than state law determines whether a state court must recognize a plaintiff’s standing to assert federal constitutional claims). 315 P. Bator, P. Mishkin, D. Shapiro & H. Wechsler, Hart & Wechsler’s The Federal Courts and the Federal System 935 (2d ed. 1973). The more recent third edition of Hart & Wechsler, see supra note 4, does not repeat the claims discussed in the text. 316 The relevant case are Musgrove v. Georgia R.R. & Banking Co., 335 U.S. 900 (1949), and Georgia R.R. & Banking Co. v. Redwine, 342 U.S. 299 (1952). In the Musgrove case, which came first, the Georgia Supreme Court had held that the Georgia court could not exercise jurisdiction over a lawsuit asserting constitutional claims because the action was an unconsented action against the state barred by the state law of sovereign immunity. See Musgrove v. Georgia R.R. & Banking Co., 204 Ga. 139, 49 S.E.2d 26 (1948). By dismissing an appeal on the basis that the state court’s judgment rested on an adequate nonfederal ground, see Musgrove, 335 U.S. 900, the United States Supreme Court Court clearly implied that the state court was under no constitutional obligation to entertain the suit. The second Supreme Court decision in Redwine occurred when the same action was refiled in federal court. In Redwine the Court treated as open the question whether the suit must be dismissed from federal court as a forbidden action against the state within the meaning of the eleventh amendment. To this question the Court in fact gave the answer that the eleventh amendment did not apply. Redwine, 342 U.S. at 305. But Redwine’s view that the federal action presented an open question concerning the existence of federal jurisdiction, when coupled with the earlier dismissal of the appeal from the state’s refusal to exercise jurisdiction in the state action between the parties, could be read to imply that a state court need not grant a remedy for the violation of federal constitutional rights, even in a case in which federal jurisdiction might be found not to exist. 317 A careful reading of the Georgia Supreme Court’s opinion in the Musgrove case reveals a highly plausible basis on which Crain might be distinguished. The state court in Musgrove stated specifically that its holding implied no conclusion as to the remedies that might be available if the defendant should seize or levy upon the plaintiff’s property—‘the defendant having done no more than theaten to make assessments.’ Musgrove v. Georgia R.R. & Banking Co., 204 Ga. 139, 159, 49 S.E.2d 26, 38 (1948). With the case in this posture, the Supreme Court, in dismissing an appeal as resting on an adequate state law ground, could have viewed the decision as based on a valid state law rule concerning not the existence but the timing of remedies against the state. Cf. Atchinson, T. & S.F. Ry. v. O’Connor, 223 U.S. 280, 285 (1912) (no constitutional right to an injunction against state taxes). 318 See Flectcher, supra note 215, at 1096. An exception to this generalization is required for cases in which plaintiffs seek just compensation for the taking of their property for public use. The Court has held that the just compensation clause of the fifth amendment compels the states to provide a damages remedy for permanent or temporary takings of private property. See First English Evangelical Lutheran Church v. County of Los Angeles, 107 S. Ct. 2378 (1987). Chief Justice Rehnquist’s opinion in First English was careful to rest its holding on the remedial significance of the just compensation clause and thus not to imply any broader obligation of the state courts to provide remedies not authorized by state law. See id. at 2388-89. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 57 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 319 For a thorough elaboration of the relevant considerations, see Wolcher, Sovereign Immunity and the Supremacy Clause: Damages Against States in Their Own Courts for Constitutional Violations, 69 Calif. L. Rev. 189 (1981). This issue is closely related to, and partially overlaps with, the dispute over whether the eleventh amendment should be construed to bar federal jurisdiction of a case against a state based on a claim of constitutional right. That debate, and the opposed Federalist and Nationalist positions, are discussed above. See supra text accompanying notes 282-301. Also bearing on the question would be the decision in Nevada v. Hall, 440 U.S. 410 (1979), that one state need not extend to another the privilege of sovereign immunity from suit in its courts. As the dissenting justices noted, the implication of the holding is that ‘the sovereign-immunity doctrine has no constitutional source.’ Id. at 428 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (emphasis added). If so, the claim that a state may invoke sovereign immunity against suits to enforce federal and even constitutional rights seems much weakened. 320 See, e.g., Douglas v. New York, N.H. & H.R.R., 279 U.S. 377, 387-88 (1929); Missouri ex rel. S. Ry. v. Mayfield, 340 U.S. 1, 45 (1950). 321 For a defense of this presumption, see Sandalow, supra note 310, at 207. 322 See McKnett v. St. Louis & S.F. Ry., 292 U.S. 230 (1934). There is language in some Supreme Court cases suggesting that the obligation to accept jurisdiction absent a federally valid excuse stems directly from the Constitution. See, e.g., Testa v. Katt, 330 U.S. 386, 391 (1947); McKnett, 292 U.S. at 233-34. But it is hard to regard the nondiscrimination requirement as being constitutionally mandated in the sense that it could not be modified by Congress. If Congress so chose, no constitutional principle would seem to be offended by a statute authorizing state courts to refuse jurisdiction of federal causes of action, even on a discriminatory basis, in cases where federal courts were open to vindicate the federal rights. 323 It is clear that Congress can require state courts to adjudicate federal causes of action in the absence of a nondiscriminatory excuse, such as a uniformly applied policy of forum non convenies. See, e.g., Testa, 330 U.S. 386; McKnett, 292 U.S. 230; Redish & Muench, supra note 304, at 341. 324 The Court’s constructions of both state and federal law sometimes have seemed designed to obviate the need for decision. Redish & Muench, supra note 304, at 346; see Douglas, 279 U.S. 377 (the Employers’ Liability Act imposes no duty of adjudication ‘as against an otherwise valid excuse’). 325 456 U.S. 742 (1982). 326 Federal Energy Regulatory Comm’n involved the constitutionality of the Public Utility Regulatory Policies Act of 1978, Pub. L. 95-617, 92 Stat. 3117. Among other effects, the Act directed state regulatory commissions to enforce certain federal standards; required the state commissions to consider the adoption and implementation of specific rate design and regulatory standards; prescribed procedures to be followed in the administrative consideration; and established that ‘any person’ may bring an action in state court to enforce the state’s obligations under the Act. Upholding the constitutionality of the Act against a tenth amendment challenge based on state sovereignty interests, the Court reasoned that, where Congress could have preempted the field entirely, the legislatively chosen alternative was less intrusive on traditional state sovereign prerogatives and therefore constitutionally permissible. Federal Energy Regulatory Comm’n, 456 U.S. at 764-71. Significantly, only Justice Powell dissented from the Court’s sustaining of Congress’s power to require judicial enforcement in the state courts of state administrative obligations lawfully imposed by Congress. See id. at 773-75 (Powell, J., dissenting). 327 426 U.S. 833 (1976). 328 See Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 498. 329 See Merritt, supra note 33, at 11-12. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 58 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 330 469 U.S. 525 (1985). 331 See Garcia, 469 U.S. at 537-54 (overruling National League of Cities); see also South Carolina v. Baker, 108 S. Ct. 1355, 1360 (1988) ( ‘States must find their protection from congressional regulation through the national political process, not through judicially defined spheres of unregulable state activity.’). 332 Garcia, 469 U.S. at 566. 333 Id. at 580 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting); see also Stewart, supra note 16, at 971 (National League of Cities may be resurrected.). 334 Closely analogous questions, in which the models are similarly implicated and their equilibrium similarly volatile, arise when a state court accepts jurisdiction over a federal statutory claim but applies procedural rules that are less hospitable to that claim than are the parallel federal procedures. The issue then is whether Congress would have wished to require the state courts to apply federal procedural rules and, if so, whether Congress is constitutionally competent to impose procedural obligations on the states. With respect to the question of congressional intent, when Congress creates federal statutory rights, the legislative history seldom addresses the procedures to be followed in state court adjudications; presumptions therefore are crucially important. Generally, in the absence of indications to the contrary, the Supreme Court imputes to Congress a set of Federalist understandings: it assumes that Congress, respectful of the interests supporting uniform procedures in state courts, would have intended federal law to take state courts as it finds them. See C. Wright, supra note 240, § 45, at 271-73; Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 637-38. Nonetheless, without any express indication of congressional intent, the Supreme Court at least occasionally has reasoned from the competing Nationalist perspective. For example, it has held that state courts adjudicating claims under the Federal Employers Liability Act, 45 U.S.C. §§ 51-60 (1982), must follow federal divisions of responsibility between judge and jury, see Dice v. Akron, C. & Y. R.R., 342 U.S. 359 (1952), that tey must abandon pleading rules that are substantially more burdensome than their federal counterparts, Brown v. Western Ry., 338 U.S. 294 (1949), and that they may not enforce notice requirements that frustrate the ready enforcement of federal rights in § 1983 actions, see Felder v. Casey, 108 S. Ct. 2302 (1988). Besides reflecting the Nationalist position that specific legislative intent need not always be proved in order to hold that state procedural requirements must give way to the interest in enforcing federal rights, these cases reject the Federalist position concerning the scope of congressional power to impose procedural obligations on the states. The cases are few, however, and the fairest summary would probably be that the ongoing competition between the two models gives rise to considerable doctrinal uncertainty, if not instability, throughout the field. 335 S. 210, 96th Cong., 1st Sess., 125 Cong. Rec. 7577 (1979) (Helms amendment); see Gunther, Congressional Power to Curtail Federal Court Jurisdiction: An Opinionated Guide to the Ongoing Debate, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 895, 900 (1984). 336 See Gunther, supra note 335, at 897. 337 Id. at 900. 338 49 U.S. (8 How.) 441 (1850). 339 Id. at 448. 340 See, e.g., Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 231-38; Eisenberg, Congressional Authority to Restrict Lower Federal Court Jurisdiction, 83 Yale L.J. 498, 504-05 (1974). 341 See, e.g., Martin v. Hunter’s Lessee, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 304, 327-29 (1816); Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 231-32; Clinton, supra note 69, at 749-50. 342 See, e.g., Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 11; Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1030-37; Gunther, supra note 335. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 59 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 343 See, e.g., Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1030-31; Gunther, supra note 335, at 912-13. 344 Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1031 (emphasis in original). 345 Id. 346 See Martin, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) at 328-39 (Story, J.). 347 See Sager, supra note 87, at 45-57. 348 See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 231-32. 349 See J. Goebel, History of the Supreme Court of the United States: Antecedents and Beginnings to 1801, at 246-47 (1971); Eisenberg, supra note 340. 350 It has generally been so regarded even by scholars who have advanced versions of the more limited Nationalist claim considered in the text. See, e.g., Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 212; Sager, supra note 87, at 30-36. A distinct but related argument, advanced by Professor Theodore Eisenberg, begins with the premise that article III contemplated the performance by the federal judiciary of functions that include checking the other two branches of government, achieving uniformity of decisions in questions of national concern, and protecting individual rights. See Eisenberg, supra note 340, at 504-13. According to Eisenberg, the framers anticipated that the Supreme Court’s appellate jurisdiction would be adequate to achieve these constitutional ends and therefore contemplated that the need for lower federal courts should be subject to congressional judgment. Today, however, the Supreme Court is no longer capable of providing a federal forum to hear the merits of every case involving a federal question. Under these changed circumstances, Eisenberg argues, the existence of federal courts to pass on at least the most important claims of federal rights have become a constitutional requirement. Despite its ingenuity, Eisenberg’s argument generally has not been accepted by other scholars in the Nationalist tradition. Critics have objected that Eisenberg’s interpretation would strip the provision of article III that authorizes Congress to create exceptions to the Supreme Court’s appellate jurisdiction of virtually all its significance. See, e.g., Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 216-18. 351 See Martin, 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) at 328-39 (1816) (Story, J.); Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 254-59; Clinton, supra note 69, at 753; Sager, supra note 87, at 56. 352 As viewed from a Nationalist perspective, historical as well as textual evidence favors this interpretation. First, the framers viewed the national judiciary as an essential component of a tripartite scheme of government. See, e.g., Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 231-38. If Congress were free to eviscerate the judicial power through its definitions of the bounds of federal jurisdiction, a basic element of the constitutional structure would be undermined. Eisenberg, supra note 340, at 505, 507; Sager, supra note 87, at 57-59. Second, the framers anticipated the possibility of state resistance to national authority, including the danger that state courts, which were dependent on the state legislatures, might prove unreliable as guarantors of constitutional norms. See, e.g., Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 233-38, 248-51; Sager, supra note 87, at 43-57. Despite the supremacy clause, it therefore was generally assumed at the Constitutional Convention that state court judgments should be subject to Supreme Court review. See Sager, supra note 87, at 51. In light of this assumption, Nationalists argue that it would make no sense to allow state courts the last word on questions of fundamental national importance. 353 See, e.g., Yakus v. United States, 321 U.S. 414, 429 (1944); Sheldon v. Sill, 49 U.S. (8 How.) 441, 448-49 (1850). 354 The Court has, however, occasionally upheld legislation that foreclosed jurisdiction by any federal court at all. See, e.g., Lauf v. Shinner, 303 U.S. 323, 330 (1938); Sheldon v. Sill, 49 U.S. (8 How.) 441 (1850). 355 See, e.g., Cohens v. Virginia, 19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264, 420 (1821); Castro, The First Congress’s Understanding of its Authority Over the Federal Courts’ Jurisdiction, 26 B.C.L. Rev. 1101 (1985). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 60 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 356 For a brief and lucid summary of the Act’s provisions, see Bator, Judiciary Act of 1789, in 3 Encyclopedia of the American Constitution 1075 (1986). 357 See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7. 358 Article III, § 2 of the Constitution provides: ‘The judicial Power shall extend to all Cases, in Law and Equity, arising under this Constitution, the Laws of the United States, and Treaties made, or which shall be made, under their Authority;—to all Cases affecting Ambassadors, other public Ministers and Consuls;—to all Cases of admiralty and maritime Jurisdiction;—to Controversies to which the United States shall be a Party;—to Controversies between two or more States;—between a State and Citizens of another State;—between Citizens of different States;—between Citizens of the same State claiming Lands under grants of different States, and between a State, or the Citizens thereof, and foreign States, Citizens or Subjects.’ 359 See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 246-54. 360 The conformity between Amar’s theory of the Constitution’s requirements and the 1789 Judiciary Act is by no means perfect. Under the Judiciary Act of 1789, either the Supreme Court or the lower federal courts were given jurisdiction in each of the three constitutionally enumerated categories of jurisdiction defined by subject matter and with respect to which the judicial power of the United States extends to ‘all Cases’—(i) cases arising under the Constitution, laws, and treaties of the United States; (ii) cases ‘affecting ambassadors, other public Ministers and Consults’; and (iii) cases of ‘admiralty and maritime jurisdiction.’ But in each instance the jurisdictional grant contained apparent gaps. First, in cases arising under the Constitution, laws, and treaties of the United States, the first Judiciary Act failed to provide general federal question jurisdiction in the lower federal courts. There was Supreme Court appellate jurisdiction, which, of course, would suffice to satisfy Amar’s thesis. But it was limited to cases in which a state court rejected a claim of federal right. Thus, in cases arising under federal law in which federal claims were upheld in state court, federal judicial power was not vested in any federal court. Although this omission embarrasses Amar’s thesis to some degree, Amar can argue that it is not inconsistent with the spirit of his account of article III, because, viewed from a Nationalist perspective, the fundamental purpose of the Constitution’s ‘arising under’ jurisdictional category was ‘not . . . uniformity but . . . protecting individual rights’ against government violation. Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 263. Second, although § 13 of the Judiciary Act did provide exclusive Supreme Court jurisdiction in cases against ambassadors, the state courts retained concurrent jurisdiction in suits by ambassadors. If an ambassador chose to sue in state court, there was no removal and no Supreme Court review. Thus the federal judicial power could not reach all cases involving ambassadors. To this objection, Amar can again respond that the purpose of the article III jurisdictional grant was essentially protective—to provide the benefits of a federal forum to any ambassador who wished to claim it. Amar has no such response to the charge of a more minor incompatibility between his theory and the 1789 Judiciary Act. The Act did not contemplate jurisdiction in all cases ‘affecting’ ambassadors—the linguistic formulation of article III—but only over those to which an ambassador was a party. Finally, although the original Judiciary Act provided for federal admiralty jurisdiction, the statute allowed plaintiffs to couch some cases that could have been framed in admiralty as common law actions and thus to litigate their claims in state court. The state decisions were not then reviewable in the Supreme Court. See Amar, Neo-Federalist View, supra note 7, at 253-54. 361 See Ely, Legislative and Administrative Motivation in Constitutional Law, 79 Yale L.J. 1205, 1306 (1970) (‘because the cases are rare and the opinions are muddled,’ it is hard to predict how the Court would reason today). But see Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1031-32 (an ‘unbroken line of authoritative judicial precedent’ supports the claim that Congress enjoys plenary power under article III, and no case can be cited to dispute the asserted power). 362 See Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 383; Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1034. 363 For a survey of this literature, see Gunther, supra note 335. 364 The term comes from Tribe, supra note 72. 365 See id. at 142-46. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 61 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 366 Ely, supra note 361, at 1306-08. 367 See, e.g., Tribe, supra note 72, at 141; Sager, supra note 87, at 74-79. 368 See, e.g., Gunther, supra note 335, at 919-21 (the motive of redrawing jurisdictional lines to express dissatifaction with judicial decisions is not unconstitutional); see also Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1035-37 (a motivational test would be unadministrable and inconsistent with historical practice). A dispute about the relevance of congressional intent echoes through the case law. Compare United States v. Klein, 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 128, 145 (1871) (jurisdictional legislation may not be used as means to achieve an unconstitutional purpose) with Ex parte McCardle, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 506, 514 (1869) (expressing reluctance to inquire into motivation of jurisdiction-stripping legislation). 369 See, e.g., Bator, Congressional Power, supra note 6, at 1034-35; Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 384 & n.34; Gunther, supra note 335, at 918. 370 28 U.S.C. § 1341 (1982). The statute, the Tax Injunction Act, was originally enacted in 1937. 371 28 U.S.C. § 1342 (1982). The statute, the Johnson Act, was initially enacted in 1934. 372 303 U.S. 323, 329-30 (1938). 373 Moreover, Lauf can now be explained on the basis that the underlying right that Congress set out to burden was a substantive due process right that no longer is a ‘right’ at all. See Ely, supra note 361, at 1307 n.305; Eisenberg, supra note 340, at 529. 374 Compare Field, supra note 212 (arguing that federal interests are sufficient to justify the creation of federal common law by federal courts whenever the federal interest is traceable to constitutional or statutory provisions) with Merrill, supra note 301, at 13-19 (arguing that creation of federal common law intrudes on state sovereignty interests and should be sharply limited). 375 28 U.S.C. § 1443 (1982). On the proper interpretation of this Reconstruction statute, compare Amsterdam, supra note 77 (arguing that the Reconstruction Congress that first enacted the statute intended to create a very broad right of removal) with City of Greenwood v. Peacock, 384 U.S. 808, 834 (1966) (narrowly construing the statute and asking rhetorically, ‘Has the historic practice of holding state criminal trials in state courts . . . been such a failure that the relationship of state and federal courts should now be revolutionized?’). 376 The doctrine takes its name from Railroad Comm’n v. Pullman Co., 312 U.S. 496 (1941). The best general survey remains Field, Abstention in Constitutional Cases: The Scope of the Pullman Abstention Doctrine, 122 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1071 (1974). 377 See generally C. Wright, supra note 240, § 52, at 308-19 (discussing other doctrines authorizing federal judicial abstention to permit state court adjudication of matters of central state concern). 378 407 U.S. 225 (1972). 379 427 U.S. 445 (1976). 380 See supra note 304. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 62 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 381 See, e.g., Hilton v. Braunskill, 107 S. Ct. 2113 (1987) (Marshall, J., joined by Brennan and Blackmun, JJ., dissenting) (asserting that, for reasons of comity and federalism, a federal district court should not withhold habeas corpus relief on the basis of state interests more properly weighed by a state court); Fiss, supra note 13, at 1126. 382 See supra note 3. 383 The argument for rhetorical reform applies most powerfully to authoritative declarations of law—especially to majority opinions of appellate courts. But the argument also extends, albeit in attenuated form, to concurring and dissenting opinions by individual judges and to scholarly writing. These types of legal writing also help to shape the legal culture, and they ought to do so in ways that do not exemplify or encourage narrowly partisan or one-sided modes of thought or expression. To apply a uniform standard to majority opinions, judicial concurrences and dissents, and scholarly articles undoubtedly blurs distinctions that might be relevant in other contexts. Scholarly writings, and even judicial concurring and dissenting opinions, frequently have a purpose of provoking thought and shifting the lines of debate. Their aim might not be to identify each of the complex factors relevant to the ‘best resolution’ of a legal problem; it may be, rather, to act as an advocate in a multilateral intellectual debate that, like the adversary process, may be counted on to extract truth through a competition of provocatively overstated claims. Even when measured against this standard, however, the Nationalist and Federalist models have long since lost their provocative characters. Today the familiar pairing of Nationalist and Federalist arguments does nothing quite so much as breed the cynical attitude that there is an argument to be made for every position and no rational basis for preferring one to another. Although claims about the inherent bankruptcy of legal argument and the truth of legal nihilism are somewhat in vogue, see Cornell, Taking Hegel Seriously: Reflections on Beyond Objectivism and Relativism, 7 Cardozo L. Rev. 139 (1985) (discussing legal ‘nihilism’ and ‘irrationalism’), I assume that legal reasoning can be either good or bad, and that the measure of goodness depends on the legal culture and on the standards of argument that the legal community maintains. The argument here is for maintaining appropriate standards. 384 See, e.g., R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986). 385 See supra note 20 and accompanying text. 386 See supra notes 235-37 and accompanying text. 387 See supra notes 230-34 and accompanying text. 388 See Fallon, supra note 24, at 1194-1209, 1237-68 (discussing the reciprocal influences among at least five kinds of factors in constitutional argument). 389 See Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1426 n.9. 390 See Fallon, supra note 24, at 1200-09. 391 See, e.g., Mitchum v. Foster, 407 U.S. 225 (1972). 392 See, e.g., Allen v. McCurry, 449 U.S. 90, 103-05 (1980); Quern v. Jordan, 440 U.S. 332, 338-45 (1979). 393 See Allen, 449 U.S. at 96. 394 See, e.g., Nichol, supra note 68; Saltzburg, supra note 21. 395 See Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1426 n.9. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 63 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 396 This is not to deny that judicial decisions can and should remain ‘neutral’ in other senses of that complex term. See, e.g., Nelson, supra note 23, at 1263-69. 397 Cf. Fallon, supra note 24, at 1247-48 (emphasizing the constraints on the influence of ‘value arguments’ in constitutional interpretation). 398 Cf. id., at 1284-85 (discussing the obligations of a constitutional interpreter to reach normatively troublesome conclusions when the relevant legal materials are sufficiently clear); Nelson, supra note 23, at 1257-59, 1292 (arguing that sometimes there will be only one plausible historical account of the meaning of a constitutional provision, even to a ‘contextualist’ historian who believes that the interests and value judgments of the historian inevitably permeate the search for historical truth). 399 A similar theme is interestingly developed in Werhan, supra note 269, at 500-06; see also Bator, supra note 2, at 621-22 (the Court should seek ‘mediating solutions’ that ensure that state and federal courts ‘will continue to be partners in the task of defining and enforcing federal constitutional principles’). 400 407 U.S. 225 (1972). 401 401 U.S. 37 (1971). 402 See supra notes 89-94 and accompanying text. 403 For a survey, see Taylor & Wills, supra note 92, at 1171-94. 404 See, e.g., Brest, The Misconceived Quest for the Original Understanding, 60 B.U.L. Rev. 204 (1980); R. Dworkin, A. Matter of Principle, 38-57 (1985). 405 See Fallon, supra note 24, at 1254-58 (defending reliance on the framers’ intent as a relevant factor in constitutional interpretation). 406 See R. Dworkin, supra note 384, at 319-31. 407 See Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1011-20. 408 See, e.g., Monroe v. Pape, 365 U.S. 167, 171-87 (1961); Mitchum, 407 U.S. at 231-42. 409 See Mitchum, 407 U.S. at 240-42. 410 This approach to legislative intent closely parallels that of Eisenberg, Section 1983: Doctrinal Foundations and an Empirical Study, 67 Cornell L. Rev. 482, 485-86 (1982). 411 See Nichol, supra note 68, at 964-71, 1000-09 (analyzing the disruptive effects of the routine availability of federal injunctions against state prosecutions under § 1983). 412 The revision was triggered by the Supreme Court’s decision in Toucey v. New York Life Ins. Co., 314 U.S. 118 (1941) (holding that § 265 of the Judicial Code forbids a federal court from enjoining a proceeding in a state court on the ground that the claims had been previously adjudicated by the federal courts). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 64 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 413 Although the statute expressly recognizes three types of exceptions, this is the only one for which most § 1983 actions would qualify. 414 Toucey, 314 U.S. at 118. 415 It has been viewed as such even by commentators who, with respect to closely analogous issues, have adopted a strong Nationalist line. See, e.g., Redish, supra note 91. 416 See Mitchum, 407 U.S. at 243. 417 The Court’s decisions have sometimes, though by no means consistently, reflected this assumption. See, e.g., Leither Minerals, Inc. v. United States, 352 U.S. 220 (1957) (holding that the statute does not apply to suits for injunctions brought by the United States). 418 401 U.S. 37, 53-54 (1971). 419 See, e.g., Zeigler, supra note 76, at 1017-25. 420 See, e.g., Younger, 401 U.S. at 43-54; Bator, supra note 2, at 622 n.49. 421 See Younger, 401 U.S. at 46-49. 422 See Fallon, supra note 118, at 60-71 (noting the relevance of congressional intent to the question when courts should award equitable remedies). 423 If an ideological assumption underlies this conclusion, it would be this: questions of judicial federalism are sufficiently complex, fact-specific, and dynamic so that it is typically undesirable for broad, rule-like solutions to be drawn from uncertain historical materials. 424 The Supreme Court has recognized the relevance of the distinction between pending and nonpending state actions at least in some contexts. Compare Samuels v. Mackell, 401 U.S. 66 (1971) (holding that Younger principles bar a federal declaratory judgment action that could interfere with a pending state criminal proceeding) with Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452 (1974) (holding that Younger principles do not bar a federal declaratory judgment action that is brought prior to the filing of a state criminal action). 425 The Supreme Court seems to have accepted this proposition, even when ordering abstention in civil cases. See, e.g., Judice v. Vail, 430 U.S. 327, 335 (1977); Huffman v. Pursue, Ltd., 420 U.S. 592, 603-07 (1975). 426 Well prior to Younger, the Supreme Court had denied injunctions to plaintiffs seeking relief from threatened future prosecutions where there was no showing of interference with future conduct. See Spielman Motor Sales Co. v. Dodge, 295 U.S. 89 (1935); Fenner v. Boykin, 271 U.S. 240 (1926). 427 See Laycock, supra note 101, 199-222. 428 See Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452, 474-75 (1974). 429 See Shapiro, State Courts and Federal Declaratory Judgments, 74 NW. U.L. Rev. 759, 776 (1979). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 65 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 430 See id. at 770-79. 431 See Laycock, supra note 101, at 219-22. 432 See id. at 199-219. 433 There could, however, be a res judicata or collateral esoppel effect if a federal injunction barring prosecution for future conduct effectively resolved the dispositive isues in a pending state criminal prosecution for past conduct. See Shapiro, supra note 429, at 764. But cf. Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452 (1974) (Rehnquist, J., concurring) (suggesting that a federal declaratory judgment would lack preclusive effect in a subsequent state prosecution). 434 Shapiro, supra note 429, at 770-76. 435 See, e.g., Patsy v. Board of Regents, 457 U.S. 496, 500-12 (1982). 436 See Martinez v. California, 444 U.S. 277, 283 & n.7 (1980). 437 449 U.S. 90 (1980). 438 See Cover & Aleinikoff, supra note 28, at 1046-52. 439 See Bator, supra note 2, at 631-37. 440 The power of the federal courts to make such context-sensitive choices is by no means necessarily precluded by the full faith and credit statute, 28 U.S.C. § 1738 (1982). One route to this conclusion, which was adopted by the dissenting opinion in Allen, is through interpretation of § 1983 itself. See Allen, 449 U.S. at 107-15 (Blackmun, J. dissenting). Professor Burbank has suggested another. See Burbank, Interjurisdictional Preclusion and Federal Common Law: Toward a General Approach, 70 Cornell L. Rev. 625 (1985). Noting that reflexive application of state preclusion rules to federal rights ‘risks the sacrifice of federal substantive policies,’ id. at 627, Burbank argues that § 1738 does not interfere with federal judicial power to develop common law rules governing the preclusion of federal rights. Id. at 638-40. Although a federal court should often choose to apply or incorporate state law in answering preclusion questions, it should reject state preclusion law and apply an independent federal rule when state preclusion law would frustrate federal policy. See id. Because state courts are required to apply valid federal common law rules, the preclusive effect of a prior adjudication of federal rights would, under Burbank’s proposal, be determined under uniform standards in federal and state courts alike. There would, accordingly, be no affront to the language of § 1738. Although § 1738 does require federal courts to give the same preclusive effect to a state court judgment as would a state court, the state courts’ preclusion doctrine may itself be shaped by federal common law. Id. at 639-40. 441 428 U.S. 465, 494-96 (1976). 442 Distinctive treatment of questions of law and questions of fact is now explicitly mandated by statute. See 28 U.S.C. § 2254(d) (1982). 443 344 U.S. 443, 487 (1953). 444 Cf. Hart & Wechsler, supra note 4, at 1487 (‘The rule of Brown v. Allen is usually thought to rest primarily on the assumption that constitutional rights cannot be adequately protected by direct Supreme Court review of state court judgments resulting in detention.’). © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 66 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 445 See Brilmayer, State Forfeiture Rules and Federal Review of State Criminal Convictions, 49 U. Chi. L. Rev. 741, 770-74 (1982); Meltzer, supra note 192, at 1135, 1182. 446 See Meltzer, supra note 192, at 1190-96. 447 See id. at 1186. 448 See Meltzer, supra note 192. 449 See id. at 1208-26. 450 See id. at 1211-26. 451 See id. at 1132-33, 1190-1202. The specific substantive standards that Meltzer proposes are rather modest in scope and intrusiveness. Meltzer argues that the federal common law rules made binding on the states should be no more forgiving than the parallel rules applicable in litigation occurring in the first instance in federal court. See id. at 1203, 1206. In addition, he generally would enforce waivers that were knowingly made either by a client or her lawyer, see id. at 1216-18, and he would strive to accommodate the state’s interest in securing the timely raising of rights that require either prompt enforcement or a repetition of a criminal trial. See id. at 1223-25. 452 See id. at 1195. 453 See Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1466-92. 454 See, e.g., Fletcher, supra note 215, at 1038-88; Gibbons, supra note 20, at 1895-1941, 1998-2002; Shapiro, supra note 238, at 6679. 455 134 U.S. 1 (1890). 456 Not all of the supporting scholarship comes from writers generally associated with the Nationalist camp. See, e.g., Shapiro, supra note 238, at 62. 457 Id. at 62. Professor Werhan develops similar arguments. See Werhan, supra note 269, at 469-505. 458 See, e.g., Tribe, supra note 233, at 695. 459 The argument that Pullman abstention should do much of the work currently assigned to the eleventh amendment is forcefully and persuasively developed in Werhan, supra note 269, at 468-74, 485-505. 460 See supra notes 113-19 and accompanying text (discussing the appropriate scope and limitations of Younger abstention). 461 See Redish & Woods, supra note 286, at 81-108. 462 See, Amar, Sovereignty and Federalism, supra note 7, at 1504-06, 1509-10. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 67 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 463 80 U.S. (13 Wall.) 397 (1871). 464 Requirements that state courts not discriminate against federal claims are not controversial. See, e.g., Testa v. Katt, 330 U.S. 386, 392-94 (1947). 465 See, e.g., Douglas v. New York, N.H. & H.R.R., 279 U.S. 377, 388 (1929). 466 469 U.S. 528 (1985). 467 Id. at 556. 468 See Van Alstyne, Federalism, Congress, the States and the Tenth Amendment: Adrift in the Cellophane Sea, 1987 Duke L.J. 769, 788-89. 469 See Amar, Neo-Federalist view, supra note 7, at 254-59. 470 Saltzburg, supra note 21, at 368. 471 See id. at 368, 382; Redish, supra note 91, at 71-72. 472 See R. Dworkin, supra note 404, at 34-71. 473 See, e.g., Chayes, Justice, supra note 84, at 1029-42; Shapiro, Jurisdiction and Discretion, 60 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 543, 574 (1985) (arguing that courts have traditionally and pervasively assumed a discretionary power to decline jurisdiction granted to them and that, when ‘dealing with an organic law like the charter of federal court jurisdiction, courts may . . . seek to ‘creat[e] the best rule of law in a situation in which [the] statute is said to govern’’) (quoting G. Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of Statutes 215 (1982)). 474 See Chayes, Justice, supra note 84, at 1029-39. 475 See G. Calabresi, supra note 473, at 163. 476 See id. at 213-14 n.29. 477 See, e.g., Brest, supra note 404, at 209-17. 478 See, e.g., Eskridge, Dynamic Statutory Interpretation, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1479, 1524-54 (1987). 479 Cf. G. Calabresi, supra note 473, at 5-6, 163-66 (arguing that old statutes frequently become outdated or dysfunctional and that courts should be able to revise or nullify them when this occurs). 480 See Eskridge, supra note 478, at 1497-1538. 481 See, e.g., Kelman, Trashing, 36 Stan. L. Rev. 293, 319-21 & n.65 (1984) (‘[T]he course on federal courts is best seen as the purest of contentless legalist rituals, in which all ‘policy’ arguments are grounded in funhouse mirror versions of Competence and © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 68 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Federalism whether they can conceivably be brought to bear on particular cases or not.’). End of Document © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 69 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Citing References (161) Title Date Type Depth 1. BRIEF AMICI CURIAE OF WASHINGTON LEGAL FOUNDATION AND JUSTICE FOR SURVIVING VICTIMS, INC. IN SUPPORT OF RESPONDENT Felker v. Turpin 1996 WL 272382, *272382+ , U.S. May 17, 1996 Brief 2. Idaho v. Coeur d’Alene Tribe of Idaho 117 S.Ct. 2028, 2059 , U.S.Idaho Jun. 23, 1997 Case 3. Petitioners’ Reply Brief Mar. 12, 1991 INTERNATIONAL PRIMATE PROTECTION LEAGUE AND ITS MEMBERS, People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals and Its Members, Alex Pacheco, and Louisiana in Support of Animals and Its Members, Petitioners, v. ADMINISTRATORS OF TULANE EDUCATIONAL FUND, National Institutes of Health and the Institutes for Behavior Resources, Inc., Respondents. 1991 WL 11007949, *11007949+ , U.S. Brief 4. PETITIONERS’ REPLY BRIEF International Primate Protection League v. Administrators of Tulane Educational Fund 1991 WL 535313, *535313+ , U.S. Mar. 12, 1991 Brief 5. Brief for the Petitioner on Reargument Aug. 14, 1989 MCKESSON CORPORATION, Petitioner, v. DIVISION OF ALCOHOLIC BEVERAGES and Tobacco, Department of Business Regulation, and Office of the Comptroller, State of Florida, Respondents. 1989 WL 1127315, *1127315+ , U.S. Brief 6. THE IDEOLOGIES OF JUDICIAL SELECTION: EMPIRICISM AND THE 2008 TRANSFORMATION OF THE JUDICIAL SELECTION DEBATE, 39 U. Tol. L. Rev. 551, 590+ Law Review — 1992 Law Review — 2008 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — NATIVE AMERICANS - Federal Courts. Eleventh Amendment barred action by tribe which alleged ownership of state lands and sought declaratory and injunctive relief. ADVOCATES of merit and appointive judicial selection systems contend that the judicial branch must be protected from the majoritarian political process in order to preserve the... 7. PRAYING TO FALSE SOVEREIGNS: THE RULE PERMITTING SUCCESSIVE PROSECUTIONS IN THE AGE OF COOPERATIVE FEDERALISM, 20 Am. J. Crim. L. 1, 78+ C1-3Table of Contents I. Introduction․ 2 A. The Rule Permitting Successive Prosecutions and its Increasing Importance․ 2 B. Survival of the Unfit: Dual Sovereignty in the Age of... 8. ERIE AND PROBLEMS OF CONSTITUTIONAL STRUCTURE, 96 Cal. L. Rev. 661, 697+ Bradford Clark may have drawn more lessons from the Supremacy Clause than anyone in history. For Clark, these few dozen words govern more than federal preemption. They also... 9. TREATISE WRITING AND FEDERAL JURISDICTION SCHOLARSHIP: © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 70 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth DOES DOCTRINE MATTER WHEN LAW IS POLITICS? FEDERAL JURISDICTION. BY ERWIN CHEMERINSKY. BOSTON, TORONTO & LONDON: LITTLE, BROWN AND CO. 1989. PP. XXV, 801. $29.50. FE, 89 Mich. L. Rev. 1499, 1513+ Reviewing books is much harder than the “two thumbs up” approach of Siskel and Ebert. One could merely describe a book, place it within scholarly literature, and evaluate it. Or,... 10. FEDERAL COMMON LAW, POLITICAL LEGITIMACY, AND THE INTERPRETIVE PROCESS: AN “INSTITUTIONALIST”” PERSPECTIVE, 83 Nw. U. L. Rev. 761, 804+ 1989 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 1994 Law Review — 2001 Law Review — 1989 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 1994 Law Review — The Supreme Court, in Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins, rejected the authority of the federal courts to develop so-called general federal common law. Nevertheless, the Court continues... 11. DEMODELING HABEAS, 45 Stan. L. Rev. 575, 644+ L1-2Introduction 576 I. Two Versions of Habeas History․ 582 A. The Institutional Competence (or Jurisdiction Only) Model․ 583 B. The Full Review Model․ 585 II. The Marshall Court... 12. Habeas After the Revolution, 1993 Sup. Ct. Rev. 65, 123+ The past few years have seen a series of Supreme Court decisions dramatically altering the law of federal habeas corpus. Some of these decisions have significantly restricted... 13. THE JURISDICTIONAL LEGACY OF THE CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENT, 61 Tenn. L. Rev. 869, 932+ C1-3Table of Contents I. Introduction․ 870 II. Federal Courts Theories and the Reality of the American South․ 872 A. The Collapse of Republicanism in the American South․ 872... 14. INDIAN TRIBES, CIVIL RIGHTS, AND FEDERAL COURTS, 7 Tex. Wesleyan L. Rev. 119, 155+ I. Introduction․ 119 II. Background․ 122 A. Indian Tribes and Sovereignty․ 122 B. Civil Rights and Indians․ 126 C. Martinez․ 128 D. Getting Around Martinez․ 132 III.... 15. DEPENDENT SOVEREIGNS: INDIAN TRIBES, STATES, AND THE FEDERAL COURTS, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 671, 759+ Introduction I. Creating the Boundaries of Jurisprudential Thought About the Federal Courts A. A Course of Study B. Premises of the Law of Federal Courts II. The Indian Tribes’... 16. UNIFORMITY IN THE FEDERAL COURTS: A PROPOSAL FOR INCREASING THE USE OF EN BANC APPELLATE REVIEW, 54 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 805, 860+ I. Introduction II. Historical Development of En Banc Review III. Increasing the Use of En Banc Review A. Greater Uniformity B. Avoiding Minority Control C. Reducing the Supreme... 17. REREADING “THE FEDERAL COURTS:” REVISING THE DOMAIN OF © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 71 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth FEDERAL COURTS JURISPRUDENCE AT THE END OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY, 47 Vand. L. Rev. 1021, 1054+ I. INTRODUCTION II. THE “FEDERAL COURTS”: AN INSTITUTION IN QUEST OF DEFINITION III. WHAT NEW READINGS BRING IV. THE RICHNESS THAT EMERGES APPENDIX Annette Kolodny tells us that:... 2004 Law Review — 1992 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 2002 Law Review — 23. DEATH-INNOCENCE AND THE LAW OF HABEAS CORPUS, 56 Alb. L. 1992 Rev. 225, 272 Law Review — Law Review — 18. PRINCIPLED MINIMALISM: RESTRIKING THE BALANCE BETWEEN JUDICIAL MINIMALISM AND NEUTRAL PRINCIPLES, 90 Va. L. Rev. 1753, 1847+ Scholars who grapple with the Rehnquist Court’s activism understandably have built upon the work of Alexander Bickel, who grappled with the Warren Court’s activism several decades... 19. REASSESSING THE ALLOCATION OF JUDICIAL BUSINESS BETWEEN STATE AND FEDERAL COURTS: FEDERAL JURISDICTION AND “THE MARTIAN CHRONICLES”, 78 Va. L. Rev. 1769, 1832+ AS is true in most areas of the law, modern standards of federal jurisdiction did not result from a single, collective attempt to fashion a pervasive and coherent structure but,... 20. HISTORY, JURISDICTION, AND THE FEDERAL COURTS: CHANGING CONTEXTS, SELECTIVE MEMORIES, AND LIMITED IMAGINATION, 98 W. Va. L. Rev. 171, 266+ I. Introduction․ 172 II. The Perennial Topic: Federal Judicial Authority․ 176 III. The Challenges of Description․ 187 A. A Four-Tiered House with Many AddOns․ 190 B. The Calder... 21. IS THERE A LAW OF FEDERAL COURTS?, 96 W. Va. L. Rev. 147, 167+ I. Introduction․ 147 II. Constitutional Revolutions․ 148 III. Changing the Landscape in Federal Courts Law․ 151 IV. The Agendas of Federal Courts Law․ 157 V. The Nature of Federal... 22. JUDICIAL REVIEW AND GLOBAL FEDERALISM, 54 Admin. L. Rev. 491, 511 L1-4,T4Introduction 491 I. L3-4,T4The Effect of Supranational Judicial Review on National Sovereignty 494 A. Judicial Review in E.U. Centralization․ 495 B. Shifting Sovereignty in... The legal space between a sentence of death and the execution chamber is occupied by an intricate network of procedural rules. On average, it currently takes between six and... 24. ELEVENTH AMENDMENT IMMUNITY OF A STATE IN BANKRUPTCY CASES: A NEW JURISPRUDENTIAL APPROACH, 7 Am. Bankr. Inst. L. Rev. 269, 334 1999 INTRODUCTION․ 270 A. The Problem․ 270 B. The Thesis․ 271 C. The Intersection of the Eleventh Amendment and Bankruptcy Jurisdiction․ 273 D. Petitions for Certiorari․ 277 I.... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 72 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth 1993 Law Review — 1997 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 2005 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — 31. ABSTENTION AND THE CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITS OF THE JUDICIAL 1991 POWER OF THE UNITED STATES, 1991 B.Y.U. L. Rev. 811, 857 Law Review — Law Review — 25. CONSIDERING THE STATE LAW CONSEQUENCES OF AN ALLEGEDLY IMPROPER BANKRUPTCY FILING, 67 Am. Bankr. L.J. 325, 341 In Gonzales v. Parks the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit held that state courts did not have subject matter jurisdiction to hear a claim that a particular bankruptcy filing... 26. CULPABILITY, MISTAKE, AND OFFICIAL INTERPRETATIONS OF LAW, 25 Am. J. Crim. L. 1, 78 I. Introduction․ 2 II. The Common Law of Entrapment by Estoppel․ 5 Case Law, Commentary, and Model Penal Code․ 6 1. Cases․ 6 Commentary and Model Penal Code․ 13... A. 2. 27. QUALIFIED IMMUNITY IN SECTION 1983 CASES AND THE ROLE OF STATE DECISIONAL LAW, 35 Ariz. L. Rev. 621, 661 Persons bringing damage actions, pursuant to 42 U.S.C. § 1983, against state and local officials for the violation of federal constitutional rights are frequently barred from... 28. THE CONSTITUTIONAL PUZZLE OF HABEAS CORPUS, 46 B.C. L. Rev. 251, 291 Abstract: The U.S. Constitution has always protected habeas corpus. Yet when we consider the Suspension Clause together with three other constitutional principles, we find a... 29. THE DOMESTIC RELATIONS EXCEPTION TO FEDERAL JURISDICTION: RETHINKING AN UNSETTLED FEDERAL COURTS DOCTRINE, 36 B.C. L. Rev. 669, 723 In 1859, Supreme Court dicta disclaimed federal court jurisdiction over “the subject of divorce, or alimony.” This pronouncement, unsupported by either precedent or authority,... 30. PRAGMATISM WITHOUT POLITICS-A HALF MEASURE OF AUTHORITY FOR JURISDICTIONAL COMMON LAW, 1991 B.Y.U. L. Rev. 767, 810 My paper for the symposium considers the propriety of independent lawmaking by federal courts about their own power. There has been much debate. Figuratively, most participants... The federal courts have by now firmly established a variety of doctrines by which they decline to exercise jurisdiction vested in them by Congress. The constitutional validity of... 32. DEALING WITH YOUNGER ABSTENTION AS A PART OF FEDERAL COURTS REFORM-THE ROLE OF THE VANISHING PROPOSAL, 1991 B.Y.U. L. Rev. 987, 1004+ 1991 Should Congress take action to deal with Younger abstention, perhaps by altering the doctrine, perhaps by abolishing it? That intriguing set of © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 73 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth questions is raised by President... Law Review — 2008 Law Review — 1999 Law Review — 36. JUDICIAL FEDERALISM AND THE ADMINISTRATIVE STATES, 87 Cal. 1999 L. Rev. 613, 702 Law Review — Law Review — 2005 Law Review — 2010 Law Review — 2004 Law Review — 33. ALTERED STATES: THE ARTICLE I COMMERCE POWER AND THE 1991 ELEVENTH AMENDMENT IN PENNSYLVANIA v. UNION GAS, 56 Brook. L. Rev. 1413, 1442 The enduring debate within the Supreme Court and among scholars about the “proper” constitutional relationship between the article I commerce power and the eleventh amendment was... 34. REPRESSING ERIE’S MYTH, 96 Cal. L. Rev. 595, 660 Some cases are not just cases; they are icons. Built of more than ordinary facts and holdings, at least three decisions stand as cultural pillars of our legal architecture: Marbury... 35. POLYPHONIC FEDERALISM: STATE CONSTITUTIONS IN THE FEDERAL COURTS, 87 Cal. L. Rev. 1409, 1468 Introduction․ 1411 I. Federal Courts Doctrine and State Constitutions․ 1418 A. Siler: Avoiding Federal Constitutional Claims․ 1418 B. State Forum for Certain State Issues․ 1418... Introduction․ 616 I. Federal Courts and the Pre-Administrative States․ 620 A. Federal Judicial Review of Pre-Modern “Agencies”: Scrutinizing Local Government Power․ 620 1.... 37. COEUR D’ALENE AND EXISTENTIAL CATEGORIES FOR SOVEREIGN 1998 IMMUNITY CASES, 86 Cal. L. Rev. 879, 917 Individuals may sue state officers in federal court according to a simple rule most closely associated with Ex Parte Young and Jordan: plaintiffs may sue for prospective relief... 38. FEDERALISM’S FALLACY: THE EARLY TRADITION OF FEDERAL FAMILY LAW AND THE INVENTION OF STATES’ RIGHTS, 26 Cardozo L. Rev. 1761, 1865 Introduction․ 1762 I. Making, Breaking, and Ignoring Federalism Rules․ 1769 II. The Inherited Tradition of Domestic Relations Law․ 1777 III. Domestic Relations in the National... 39. REMAKING THE MOLD: PURSUING FAILURE-TO-PROTECT CLAIMS UNDER STATE CONSTITUTIONS VIA ANALOGOUS BIVENS ACTIONS, 110 Colum. L. Rev. 1294, 1347 If a state child-welfare agency does not remove a child from his father’s custody, despite documented evidence of abuse and its exclusive ability to do so, is it partly responsible... 40. UNDER THE LAW OF FEDERAL JURISDICTION: ALLOCATING CASES BETWEEN FEDERAL AND STATE COURTS, 104 Colum. L. Rev. 1211, 1279 One of the primary functions of the law of federal jurisdiction is to allocate cases between state and federal courts. Commentators agree that the law of © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 74 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth allocation is troubled,... Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 43. CHALLENGING THE HART AND WECHSLER PARADIGM, 27 Conn. L. 1995 Rev. 833, 847 Law Review — Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 1997 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 48. BUSTING THE HART & WECHSLER PARADIGM, 11 Const. Comment. 1994 557, 586+ Law Review — 41. APPLYING THE SUSPENSION CLAUSE TO IMMIGRATION CASES, 98 1998 Colum. L. Rev. 1068, 1102 Notwithstanding “plenary power” and “public rights” doctrines that have traditionally left aliens with less protection against administrative detention than American citizens... 42. SOME CONFUSIONS ABOUT DUE PROCESS, JUDICIAL REVIEW, AND CONSTITUTIONAL REMEDIES, 93 Colum. L. Rev. 309, 373 Due process doctrine subsists in confusion. The disarray partly reflects the terrain that due process covers. The Due Process Clause generates rights, among other things, to... In 1932, a prescient Herbert Wechsler noted that Felix Frankfurter’s new Federal Courts casebook “conditions the method which an instructor can adopt, as surely as it does the... 44. TRANSCENDING CONVENTIONAL SUPREMACY: A 1992 RECONSTRUCTION OF THE SUPREMACY CLAUSE, 24 Conn. L. Rev. 829, 891 Judging from the numbers alone, the Supremacy Clause has become a primary battlefield for demarcating the boundaries of the federal regulatory state. Over the past four Terms,... 45. COEUR D’ALENE, FEDERAL COURTS AND THE SUPREMACY OF FEDERAL LAW: THE COMPETING PARADIGMS OF CHIEF JUSTICES MARSHALL AND REHNQUIST, 15 Const. Comment. 301, 324+ In a decade that is witnessing a resurgence of law’s development and application to government entities around the world, in newly emerging democracies and in multi-national... 46. WHO’S AFRAID OF HENRY HART?, 14 Const. Comment. 175, 207+ No law book has enjoyed greater acclaim from distinguished commentators over a sustained period than has Hart & Wechsler’s The Federal Courts and the Federal System. Indeed, the... 47. COMPARING FEDERAL COURTS “PARADIGMS”, 12 Const. Comment. 3, 19 In a recent article, Professor Michael Wells attacks what I had characterized as “the Hart and Wechsler paradigm” for analysis of Federal Courts issues. To summarize crudely, Wells... Federal Courts law was once a vibrant area of scholarship and an essential course for intellectually ambitious students. Now its prestige has diminished so much that scholars... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 75 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth 2008 Law Review — 2003 Law Review — 1996 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 2001 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 55. CHISHOLM, THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT, AND SOVEREIGN 2001 IMMUNITY: ON ALDEN’S RETURN TO CONFEDERATION PRINCIPLES, 28 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 605, 648 Law Review — Law Review — Law Review — 49. STATE COURTS UNBOUND, 93 Cornell L. Rev. 501, 554 We may not think that state courts disobey binding Supreme Court precedent, but occasionally state courts do. In a number of important cases, state courts have actively defied... 50. EXAMINING THE POWER OF FEDERAL COURTS TO CERTIFY QUESTIONS OF STATE LAW, 88 Cornell L. Rev. 1672, 1749+ Attracted by the perception that certification accords with norms of federalism and comity, federal courts have applied certification without serious examination of its... 51. THE INTEGRATION OF STATE PRIVATE LAW IN FEDERALIZED FIELDS OF LAW: THE CASE FOR FEDERAL COMMON LAW, 74 Denv. U. L. Rev. 207, 264 I. Introduction․ 208 II. Federal Preemption․ 214 A. The Relevance of Background Assumptions to Preemption Jurisprudence․ 214 B. Federal Preemption: From Conflict to Field... 52. PARITY REVISITED: THE USES OF A JUDICIAL FORUM OF EXCELLENCE, 44 DePaul L. Rev. 797, 810 Longer ago than I wish to acknowledge, I urged judges and legislators to consider qualitative differences between state and federal systems in drawing jurisdictional lines in... 53. NARRATIVES OF FEDERALISM: OF CONTINUITIES AND COMPARATIVE CONSTITUTIONAL EXPERIENCE, 51 Duke L.J. 223, 287 The dramatic title of the conference for which this Essay was written raises the question, what is the Constitution “in exile” from? The “Constitution in Exile” might refer to an... 54. NAKED POLITICS, FEDERAL COURTS LAW, AND THE CANON OF ACCEPTABLE ARGUMENTS, 47 Emory L.J. 89, 162+ When lawyers debate Federal Courts issues, they rely on a familiar cluster of policy arguments. Much is made, for example, of the need to respect institutional competence, to... I. L2-3,T3Introduction 605 II. L2-3,T3The Chisholm Decision 606 A. Doing Justice․ 607 B. Becoming Part of the Union․ 612 III. L2-3,T3The Passage of the Eleventh Amendment 617 A.... 56. FIGHTING FEDERALISM WITH FEDERALISM: IF IT’S NOT JUST A 2006 BATTLE BETWEEN FEDERALISTS AND NATIONALISTS, WHAT IS IT?, 74 Fordham L. Rev. 2081, 2121 There are many ways to promote federalism. The most recent federalism revival, for example, protects states differently than earlier efforts by the United States Supreme Court to... 57. TYING THE BRAID OF SECOND-PARENT ADOPTIONS-WHERE DUE 2005 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 76 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth PROCESS MEETS EQUAL PROTECTION, 74 Fordham L. Rev. 1425, 1473 Victoria and Laura, same-sex partners, both held legal, parental custody of each other’s biological children, Maya and Tessa. The parental relationships of Victoria and Laura had... 1998 Law Review — 59. HANS, AYERS, AND ELEVENTH AMENDMENT JURISPRUDENCE: ON 2001 JUSTIFICATION, RATIONALIZATION, AND SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY, 10 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 251, 291 Law Review — 2009 Law Review — 2003 Law Review — 1990 Law Review — 2004 Law Review — 1994 Law Review — 58. STATUTORY INTERPRETATION OF FEDERAL JURISDICTIONAL STATUTES: JURISDICTION OF THE PRIVATE RIGHT OF ACTION UNDER THE TCPA, 66 Fordham L. Rev. 1895, 1937 [Courts’] use of legislative history [is] the equivalent of entering a crowded cocktail party and looking over the heads of the guests for one’s friends. From 1960 to 1995, the... Over the past several years, the Supreme Court has expanded the breadth of the Eleventh Amendment protections accorded to the states, making it increasingly difficult for a citizen... 60. SPLITTING THE ATOM OF PROPERTY: RIGHTS EXPERIMENTALISM AS OBLIGATION TO FUTURE GENERATIONS, 77 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 1411, 1477 The Framers split the atom of sovereignty. It was the genius of their idea that our citizens would have two political capacities, one state and one federal, each protected from... 61. THE SUPREMACY CLAUSE AS A CONSTRAINT ON FEDERAL POWER, 71 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 91, 130 It is . . . not entirely unworthy of observation, that in declaring what shall be the supreme law of the land, the constitution itself is first mentioned; and not the laws of the... 62. WHEN FEDERALISM AND SEPARATION OF POWERS COLLIDERETHINKING YOUNGER ABSTENTION, 59 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 114, 156 What would the Rehnquist Court do if faced with a conflict between its vision of federalism and its commitment to the separation of powers? A case can be made that the abstention... 63. FEDERAL COURTS, STATE COURTS AND CIVIL RIGHTS: JUDICIAL POWER AND POLITICS REVIEW OF DANIEL R. PINELLO, GAY RIGHTS AND AMERICAN LAW, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS, 2003, PP. 349. $23.00 (HARDCOVER), 92 Geo. L.J. 941, 980 With Lawrence v. Texas, in which the Supreme Court struck down a Texas law prohibiting same-sex sexual acts, and Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, in which the... 64. Empiricism, Gender, and Legal Pedagogy: An Experiment in a Federal Courts Seminar at Georgetown University Law Center, 83 Geo. L.J. 461, 524 Over the last decade, the organized bench and bar have drawn on the insights of feminist legal theory and sociolegal research techniques to create a fascinating movement. The... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 77 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth 1994 Law Review — 66. FELIX FRANKFURTER: THE ARCHITECT OF “OUR FEDERALISM”, 27 1993 Ga. L. Rev. 697, 788 Law Review — 2000 Law Review — 1996 Law Review — 2000 Law Review — 70. PARITY REVISITED: AN EMPIRICAL COMPARISON OF STATE AND 1999 LOWER FEDERAL COURT INTERPRETATIONS OF NOLLAN V. CALIFORNIA COASTAL COMMISSION, 23 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 233, 293 Law Review — 2009 Law Review — 72. CONSTITUTIONAL LAW - STATE SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY - FIFTH 2004 CIRCUIT BARS CHALLENGE TO STATUTES’ CONSTITUTIONALITY IN INTERLOCUTORY APPEAL REVIEWING DENIAL OF STATE SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY. - MCCARTHY EX REL. TRAVIS V. HAWKINS, 381, 118 Harv. L. Rev. 786, 793 Law Review — Law Review — 65. AN ASSESSMENT OF PAST EXTRAMURAL REFORMS OF THE U.S. COURTS OF APPEALS, 28 Ga. L. Rev. 863, 912 My nomenclature needs explanation by way of introduction. This Article will evaluate reforms designated here ‘extramural‘ or ‘structural.‘ Although the distinction between... Until we have penetrating studies of the influence of [Supreme Court Justices], we shall not have an adequate history of the Supreme Court, and, therefore, of the United States.... 67. THE SUPREME COURT’S “NEW” FEDERALISM: AN ANTI-RIGHTS AGENDA?, 16 Ga. St. U. L. Rev. 517, 572 In recent years, the United States Supreme Court has developed a “new” federalism doctrine. The Court’s “new” federalism seeks to elevate the power of state governments over that... 68. POPULAR JUSTICE: STATE JUDICIAL ELECTIONS AND PROCEDURAL DUE PROCESS, 31 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 187, 221 Popular election and retention of state judges have been integral components of the American legal and political systems since the early nineteenth century. Despite the... 69. ALDEN TRILOGY: PRAISE AND PROTEST, 23 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 323, 409+ I. Introduction․ 324 II. The New Federalism--A Creature of the 1990s․ 328 III. The Alden Trilogy: The Holdings, Interpretive Frameworks, and Unresolved Questions․ 336 A. Alden v.... I. Introduction․ 234 II. Jurisdictional Foundations․ 239 A. Constitutional Role of the State Judiciaries in the Adjudication of Federal Questions․ 239 B. State Court... 71. FEDERALISM AND THE GENERALITY PROBLEM IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION, 122 Harv. L. Rev. 2003, 2069 Ever since the concept of state sovereign immunity entered the constitutional realm, courts have struggled to balance the “sovereign interests of the State” with “the supremacy of... 73. EX PARTE YOUNG DOCTRINE., 111 Harv. L. Rev. 269, 279 1997 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 78 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth Since the time of Edward the First, the common law has conferred immunity from suit on the sovereign. In contrast, officers and agents of the Crown were accountable in both law... 74. NEW LAW, NON-RETROACTIVITY, AND CONSTITUTIONAL REMEDIES, 104 Harv. L. Rev. 1731, 1833 1991 Law Review — 1990 Law Review — 1990 Law Review — 2003 Law Review — 1990 Law Review — 1989 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 2004 Law Review — Introduction I. The Supreme Court’s Treatment of New Law as a Basis for Denying Relief in Constitutional Cases A. Retroactivity in Criminal Cases 1. The Warren Court’s Approach... 75. UNCONSTITUTIONAL STATE TAXES - FEDERAL STANDARD FOR REMEDIES IN STATE COURT, 104 Harv. L. Rev. 188, 198 In declaring state taxes unconstitutional, the Supreme Court’s practice has been to defer to state-court determinations of the appropriate remedy. This deference has left the... 76. CLARIFYING COMITY: STATE COURT JURISDICTION AND SECTION 1983 STATE TAX CHALLENGES, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1888, 1908 State taxes are frequently challenged as violating the commerce clause, the establishment clause, the equal protection clause, or other provisions of the federal Constitution. The... 77. CONSTRICTING REMEDIES: THE REHNQUIST JUDICIARY, CONGRESS, AND FEDERAL POWER, 78 Ind. L.J. 223, 310 I. L2-4,T4From the Rehnquist Court to the Rehnquist Judiciary 224 A. L34,T4Developing New Norms 224․ B. L3-4,T4Sources of Judicial Authority, Exercised Individually and... 78. SYMMETRIES OF ACCESS IN CIVIL RIGHTS LITIGATION: POLITICS, PRAGMATISM AND WILL, 66 Ind. L.J. 1, 52 Introduction I. The Will Case II. Will as a Political Decision A. Three Nonpragmatist Approaches to Interpreting Section 1983 1. Intentionalism 2. Plain Meaning and Political... 79. LETTING GO OF THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT, 64 Ind. L.J. 601, 615 In Pennsylvania v. Union Gas Co., the Supreme Court must decide whether a private party can claim damages against a state in federal superfund litigation. The case involves some... 80. PRINTZ AND TESTA: THE INFRASTRUCTURE OF FEDERAL SUPREMACY, 32 Ind. L. Rev. 111, 140+ Professor Martin Redish and Steven Sklaver make an elegant argument that state courts are competent to adjudicate federal claims not because they are in “parity” with federal... 81. CONSTITUTIONAL REMEDIES FOR STATUTORY VIOLATIONS, 89 Iowa L. Rev. 355, 441 I. Introduction․ 357 II. Two Private Right of Action Doctrines․ 364 Preemption Cases and Violation Cases․ 365 B. Other Possible Explanations․ 369 III. Federal... A. © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 79 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth 1994 Law Review — 83. AMERICAN AND AUSTRALIAN CONSTITUTIONS: CONTINUING 1997 ADVENTURES IN COMPARATIVE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW, 30 J. Marshall L. Rev. 627, 698 Law Review — 2001 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 1989 Law Review — 1992 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — 82. FAMILY LAW, FEDERALISM, AND THE FEDERAL COURTS, 79 Iowa L. Rev. 1073, 1126 Whether family law belongs in the federal courts under diversity jurisdiction is somewhat contested within federal court jurisprudence. Although neither the Constitution nor the... The chief virtue of a comparative study . . . is [not] . . . in generalisations that emerge from it, but in the deeper insight that it offers [all participants] into their own... 84. ENFORCING FEDERAL CIVIL RIGHTS AGAINST PUBLIC ENTITIES AFTER GARRETT, 28 J.C. & U.L. 41, 96 [T]he [C]ourt’s doctrinal realignment of the federal-state structure is of little interest to most Americans. It recalls memories of dreary high school civics classes, and for the... 85. MULTIPLE SOVEREIGNTIES: INDIAN TRIBES, STATES, AND THE FEDERAL GOVERNMENT, 79 Judicature 118, 125 Although often unrecognized, three entities within the territory that constitutes the United States--Indian tribes, states, and the federal government--have forms of sovereignty.... 86. NO FINAL VICTORIES: THE INCOMPLETENESS OF EQUITY’S TRIUMPH IN FEDERAL PUBLIC LAW, 56-SUM Law & Contemp. Probs. 105, 121 If Professor Laycock senses a “segregationist spirit” in some attitudes about keeping equity distinct and intact, I hear a note of triumphalism about the scope and approaches of... 87. FEDERALISM’S FULL CIRCLE: RELIEF FOR EDUCATION DISCRIMINATION, 35 Loy. L. Rev. 13, 110 Today’s unsettled federalism doctrine dictates a shift in view and strategy regarding the effective remedial approach to current social and political challenges. Recent Supreme... 88. BARGAINING IN THE DARK: THE NORMATIVE INCOHERENCE OF LAWYER DISPUTE BARGAINING ROLE, 51 Md. L. Rev. 1, 104 INTRODUCTION I. BARGAINING AS STRATEGIC INTERACTION II. THE PRACTICAL NEED TO COOPERATE A. Cordial Bargaining B. Principled Bargaining C. Problem-Solving Bargaining D. Coordinated... 89. WANTED: A FEDERAL STANDARD FOR EVALUATING THE ADEQUATE STATE FORUM, 50 Md. L. Rev. 131, 212 C1-3Table of Contents Introduction․ 132 I. The Heightened Scrutiny Model: Adequate State Grounds․ 135 II. Negligible Scrutiny: A Pending State Proceeding as an Adequate Forum․ ... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 80 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title 90. ENVISIONING A GLOBAL LEGAL CULTURE, 25 Mich. J. Int’l L. 1, 76 Date Type Depth 2003 Law Review — 2010 Law Review — 2002 Law Review — 1989 Law Review — 2007 Law Review — 2001 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 2010 Law Review — 2008 Law Review — “To truly know a man, you must walk a mile in his shoes.” Introduction․ 2 I. Emerging Global Institutions and the Forces That Will Shape Their Laws․ 6 A. Present and Future... 91. THE TAX INJUNCTION ACT AND FEDERAL JURISDICTION: REASONING FROM THE UNDERLYING GOALS OF FEDERALISM AND COMITY, 108 Mich. L. Rev. 795, 821 States routinely contest federal jurisdiction when a state tax is challenged in federal district court on federal constitutional grounds. States argue that the Tax Injunction Act,... 92. SUSPECTING THE STATES: SUPREME COURT REVIEW OF STATECOURT STATE-LAW JUDGMENTS, 101 Mich. L. Rev. 80, 178+ At the Supreme Court these days, it is unfashionable to second-guess states’ fealty to federal law without real proof that they are ignoring it. As the Court declared in Alden v.... 93. A REVISIONIST THEORY OF ABSTENTION, 88 Mich. L. Rev. 530, 602 There is a widespread perception that the forum of litigation may be as outcome-determinative as the underlying merits. This perception accounts for the importance of the... 94. STATE HABEAS RELIEF FOR FEDERAL EXTRAJUDICIAL DETAINEES, 92 Minn. L. Rev. 265, 322 I. The Rise and Fall of State Habeas Relief for Federal Prisoners․ 270 A. From the Nation’s Birth to the Wisconsin Rebellion: The Ascendancy of State Courts’ Powers․ 270 B.... 95. THE STRUCTURE OF JUDICIAL OPINIONS, 86 Minn. L. Rev. 447, 496 A judicial opinion tells many stories and speaks with many voices. It is less a single and anonymous utterance of the law than a condensed quarrel, less a line than a knot. It is... 96. REMOVAL, REMANDS, AND REFORMING FEDERAL APPELLATE REVIEW, 58 Mo. L. Rev. 287, 333 On January 13, 1992, the United States Supreme Court denied certiorari to a decision of the Fifth Circuit in Castillo v. Shell Oil Co., over the dissent of Justice White. About... 97. DID THE MADISONIAN COMPROMISE SURVIVE DETENTION AT GUANTÁNAMO?, 85 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 535, 586 This Essay takes up the Court’s less-heralded second holding in Boumediene v. Bush--that a federal habeas court must have the institutional capacity to find facts, which in... 98. THE UNCONSCIONABILITY GAME: STRATEGIC JUDGING AND THE EVOLUTION OF FEDERAL ARBITRATION LAW, 83 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1420, 1490 This Article uses recent developments in the enforcement of arbitration agreements to illustrate one way in which strategic dynamics can drive © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 81 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth doctrinal change. In a fairly short... 99. FINALITY OF JUDGMENTS IN CLASS ACTIONS: A COMMENT ON EPSTEIN V. MCA, INC., 73 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1149, 1166 1998 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 2002 Law Review — 2001 Law Review — 2000 Law Review — 2000 Law Review — In this Response, Professor Allen contends that in arguing that plaintiffs in state court proceedings are unable to fairly and effectively bargain for the release of exclusively... 100. “NATURALLY” WITHOUT GENDER: WOMEN, JURISDICTION, AND THE FEDERAL COURTS, 66 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1682, 1767 For many years, women who work (or who have tried to work) with law and in courts have understood that their gender was relevant to that work. However, until recently, those who... 101. MORE THAN “SLIGHTLY RETRO:” THE REHNQUIST COURT’S ROUT OF HABEAS CORPUS JURISDICTION IN TEAGUE v. LANF, 18 N.Y.U. Rev. L. & Soc. Change 537, 635 A. The Court’s New Rule Defining New Rules 1. The Evolution of the Court’s New Rule on New Rules 2. The Court’s New Rule on New Rules Applied: Three Paradigmatic Situations B. A... 102. THE IDEOLOGIES OF FORUM SHOPPING-WHY DOESN’T A CONSERVATIVE COURT PROTECT DEFENDANTS?, 71 N.C. L. Rev. 649, 720 In this Article, Professor George Brown identifies a seeming inconsistency in the Supreme Court’s treatment of federal-state private law forum shopping and state-state private law... 103. FIFTY YEARS (MORE OR LESS) OF “FEDERAL COURTS”: AN ANNIVERSARY REVIEW, 77 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1083, 1120 For some time now, legal scholars have treated doctrinal analysis in the field of Federal Courts as taking place within the “Hart & Wechsler” paradigm. Named after the casebook... 104. UNCONSTITUTIONAL POLITICS, 76 Notre Dame L. Rev. 519, 641 Introduction․ 520 I. The Dilemma Posed․ 527 A. New York v. United States․ 528 B. The Districting Requirement․ 530 C. Initial Implications․ 531 II. New York v. United States... 105. A DIALOGIC DEFENSE OF ALDEN, 75 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1161, 1182 I find myself in the odd position of arguing that Alden v. Maine is right, or at least not wrong. Do not misunderstand--I do not like the result in Alden any more than the next... 106. ELEVENTH AMENDMENT SCHIZOPHRENIA, 75 Notre Dame L. Rev. 859, 918 Running through the opinions of the Justices who comprise the current Supreme Court majority on Eleventh Amendment immunity have been two distinct and conflicting analytical... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 82 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth 1999 Law Review — 108. INTERDISCIPLINARY ASPECTS OF SEMINOLE TRIBE V. FLORIDA: 1997 STATE SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY IN THE CONTEXT OF ANTITRUST, BANKRUPTCY, CIVIL RIGHTS AND ENVIRONMENTAL LAW Introduction: Seminole Tribe and the Creeping Reemergence of “D, 23 Ohio N.U. L. Rev. 1393, 1401 Law Review — Law Review — 1992 Law Review — 1996 Law Review — 112. THE FEDERALIZATION OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE: AN EXERCISE IN 1996 COOPERATIVE FEDERALISM OR A MISALLOCATION OF FEDERAL JUDICIAL RESOURCES?, 48 Rutgers L. Rev. 1139, 1191 Law Review — 1997 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 107. JUDICIAL FEDERALISM IN THE TRENCHES: THE ROOKERFELDMAN DOCTRINE IN ACTION, 74 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1085, 1128 One little-noticed side effect of the litigation explosion in this country is the exponential growth of federal doctrines designed to simplify complex litigation. Many of these... This Mini-Symposium was originally conducted as a live program at the Annual Conference of The Association of American Law Schools, January 7, 1997, in Washington, D.C. The... 109. FEDERAL QUESTION DOCTRINES AND AMERICAN INDIAN LAW, 14 1989 Okla. City U. L. Rev. 263, 389 A. The “Classical” Historical Period: 1789-1876 B. The Complications of Original and Removal Jurisdiction: Searching for a Unifying Approach 1. Inconsistent Requirements, Statutory... 110. FEDERAL COMMON LAW AND THE ROLE OF THE FEDERAL COURTS IN PRIVATE LAW ADJUDICATION -- A (NEW) ERIE PROBLEM?, 12 Pace L. Rev. 229, 261 A. Introduction This year the Federal Courts Section of the Association of American Law Schools addresses questions of legitimacy and limits in the fashioning of common law by... 111. BALANCING, JUSTICE, AND THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT: JUSTICE STEVENS’ THEORY OF STATE SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY, 27 Rutgers L.J. 563, 604 I.․ Introduction 564 II.․ The Context of Justice Stevens’ Position on State Sovereign Immunity 566 III.․ Evolution of Justice Stevens’ Eleventh Amendment Jurisprudence 568 A. First... Domestic violence is one of this country’s most pernicious and persistent social problems. Like cancer, it is egalitarian, affecting every stratum of American life. No class,... 113. CONSTITUTIONAL LAW-SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY-CONGRESS’S ARTICLE I POWERS MAY NOT ABROGATE STATE SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY GRANTED BY THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT AND EX PARTE YOUNG IS INAPPLICABLE TO SUITS BROUGHT UNDER THE INDIAN GAMING RE, 27 Seton Hall L. Rev. 806, 835 The concept of sovereign immunity predates the formation of a federal government in the United States. Initially founded on the belief that the King enjoyed immunity from all... 114. A CATALOGUE OF JUDICIAL FEDERALISM IN THE UNITED STATES, 46 S.C. L. Rev. 835, 875 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 83 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth I. Introduction․ 835 II. Court Structures and Organization․ 836 III. Principles of Judicial Federalism․ 841 IV. Jurisdictions and Procedures․ 846 A. Diversity․ 846 B. Federal... 2005 Law Review — 2005 Law Review — 1993 Law Review — 1990 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 120. WHY AND HOW TO TEACH FEDERAL COURTS TODAY, 53 St. Louis 2009 U. L.J. 693, 727+ Law Review — 121. TAKING COMITY SERIOUSLY: HOW TO NEUTRALIZE THE ABSTENTION DOCTRINE, 46 Stan. L. Rev. 1049, 1114 1994 Law Review — 2007 Law Review — 2002 Law Review — 115. THE DECONSTRUCTION AND RECONSTRUCTION OF HABEAS, 78 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1125, 1220 I. INTRODUCTION․ 1126 II. THE PARADIGMATIC CONSTRUCT․ 1134 A. The Construct Itself․ 1134 B. The Underlying Doctrines․ 1139 C. The Construct’s Vision of Judicial Federalism․ ... 116. CONSTITUTIONALISM IN THE STREETS, 78 S. Cal. L. Rev. 401, 456 This Article embarks on a reconstruction of constitutionalism in the early American Republic through a microhistorical case study of United States v. Peters, the first Supreme... 117. HABEAS CORPUS JURISDICTION: THE LIMITS OF MODELS, 66 S. Cal. L. Rev. 2507, 2531 It is a pleasure to have the task of reacting to two such interesting and insightful articles. I have always thought there are two rules for commentators. First, discuss the... 118. ONE HUNDRED YEARS OF FOLLY: THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT AND THE 1988 TERM, 64 S. Cal. L. Rev. 51, 104 The eleventh amendment has become a great battleground of constitutional federalism. Although phrased as a limited restriction on federal jurisdiction, the amendment has been read... 119. TWO VISIONS OF JUSTICE: FEDERAL COURTS AT A CROSSROADS, 11 St. John’s J. Legal Comment. 63, 71 For some time now, the conservative legal movement has waged a concerted campaign to exalt a doctrine it refers to as ‘judicial restraint‘ and to demonize that which it terms... The abstention doctrine prohibits a federal court from deciding a case within its jurisdiction so that a state court can resolve some or all of the dispute. The purported rationale... 122. PRIVATIZING BANS ON ABORTION: EVISCERATING CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS THROUGH TORT REMEDIES, 80 Temp. L. Rev. 123, 199 State governments have devised a new means to evade the Constitution. Their new means is to enact tort statutes that, in effect, ban constitutionally protected conduct. In... 123. ACTIVISM AS RESTRAINT: LESSONS FROM CRIMINAL PROCEDURE, 80 Tex. L. Rev. 1057, 1115 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 84 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth Much has been made in recent years about the puzzling chasm that separates constitutional law, on the one hand, and criminal procedure, on the other--what one leading commentator... 2000 Law Review — 125. FEDERAL COURT PRACTICE AND PROCEDURE: A THIRD BRANCH 1999 BIBLIOGRAPHY, 30 Tex. Tech L. Rev. 909, 1108 Law Review — 1994 Law Review — 1992 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 2006 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 131. THE FUTURE OF STATE AND FEDERAL CIVIL RIGHTS 1994 PROSECUTIONS: THE LESSONS OF THE RODNEY KING TRIAL, 41 UCLA L. Rev. 509, 608+ Law Review — 124. THE FIGURE IN THE CARPET, 78 Tex. L. Rev. 1731, 1770 In Henry James’s story, a prolific novelist confides to a literary critic that his books share a common theme. That theme is integral to the nov-els, lending them meaning in the... This effort may seem to be as futile as it is ambitious: to compile a comprehensive bibliography of books and articles dealing with the various aspects of the federal courts and... 126. A BIBLIOGRAPHY FOR THE UNITED STATES COURTS OF APPEALS, 25 Tex. Tech L. Rev. 335, 378 If we are to keep our democracy, there must be one commandment: Thou shalt not ration justice. This Bibliography was compiled for a book by the present author entitled, Rationing... 127. SOME PRELIMINARY THOUGHTS ON LONG-RANGE PLANNING FOR THE FEDERAL JUDICIARY, 23 Tex. Tech L. Rev. 1, 15 The hardest strokes of heaven fall in history upon those who imagine that they can control things in a sovereign manner, as though they were kings of the earth, playing Providence... 128. THE CURTAILMENT OF FEDERAL COURT JURISDICTION: SEMINOLE TRIBE OF FLORIDA V. FLORIDA, 24 T. Marshall L. Rev. 109, 147 “The ‘degree of confusion following a splintered decision ․ is itself a reason for reexamining that decision’.” The Eleventh Amendment, since its adoption and ratification in 1798,... 129. INTERSECTIONS OF STATE AND FEDERAL POWER: STATE JUDGES, FEDERAL LAW, AND THE “RELIANCE PRINCIPLE”, 81 Tul. L. Rev. 283, 329 Over the same time span that the Rehnquist Court has established substantive limitations on state and local regulatory power, this Article argues that it wavered far less often in... 130. FEDERALISM AND THE FAMILY RECONSTRUCTED, 45 UCLA L. Rev. 1297, 1400+ Introduction․ 1297 I. Arguing from History for Localism․ 1301 A. History Marks Family Law as the Lodestar of Localism․ 1302 B. The Unexplained Elevation of History․ 1306 C.... Introduction․ 510 I. ‘The Rodney King Case’․ 516 A. The Beating․ © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 85 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title 516 B. Procedural History․ 524 Prosecuting Civil Rights Cases․ 534... Date C. Type Depth Impact of the Case․ 533 II. 2010 Law Review — 2002 Law Review — 1989 Law Review — 135. TWO CHEERS FOR FEMINIST PROCEDURE, 61 U. Cin. L. Rev. 1201, 1993 1207 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 2005 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 1995 Law Review — 132. PREVENTIVE ADJUDICATION, 77 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1275, 3334 This Article identifies, justifies, and explains the parameters of a largely ignored but important category of cases—what is here called “preventive adjudication.” In this category... 133. THE “CONSERVATIVE” PATHS OF THE REHNQUIST COURT’S FEDERALISM DECISIONS, 69 U. Chi. L. Rev. 429, 494 This Article broadly examines the conservative Rehnquist Court’s federalism doctrines and, in doing so, explores the connections between judicial conservatism and a commitment to... 134. MARBURY, SECTION 13, AND THE ORIGINAL JURISDICTION OF THE SUPREME COURT, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 443, 499 In this year marking the Bicentennial of the Judiciary Act of 1789, and in a symposium designed to commemorate that Act, it might seem perverse, if not downright gauche, to begin... When I first told my wife, who is also a lawyer, that I was going to be on a panel about feminism and civil procedure, she asked me who else was going to participate. When I read... 136. AN UNWELCOME STRANGER: CONGRESSIONAL INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS POWER AND FEDERALISM, 44 U. Kan. L. Rev. 61, 101 The United States Supreme Court’s two recent decisions concerning the availability of federal remedies against private organizations that obstruct access to abortion clinics... 137. JURISDICTION STRIPPING, CONSTITUTIONAL SUPREMACY, AND THE IMPLICATIONS OF EX PARTE YOUNG, 153 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1677, 1708 On July 22, 2004, the House of Representatives passed the Marriage Protection Act of 2004, a bill that would strip the federal courts of jurisdiction over cases challenging the... 138. FORUM SHOPPING FOR ARBITRATION DECISIONS: FEDERAL COURTS’ USE OF ANTISUIT INJUNCTIONS AGAINST STATE COURTS, 147 U. Pa. L. Rev. 91, 203 “The facts of this case demonstrate the quagmire into which federal courts frequently have been thrust in arbitration disputes in which the parties have involved both state and... 139. FEDERALISM AND FAMILIES, 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1787, 1888 Introduction ․ 1788 I. The Localist Strand in Constitutional Federalism ․ 1794 A. Localism Under Dual Federalism ․ 1796 B. The Paradigm of Procedural Federalism: Process and... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 86 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title 140. THE TWO-TIERED STRUCTURE OF THE JUDICIARY ACT OF 1789, 138 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1499, 1567 Date Type Depth 1990 Law Review — 1990 Law Review — 2008 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — 2009 Law Review — 2002 Law Review — 1994 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — 1991 Law Review — What limits (if any) does the Constitution impose on congressional efforts to strip federal courts of jurisdiction in controversial areas— abortion, flag burning, or what have... 141. THE HISTORY AND STRUCTURE OF ARTICLE III, 138 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1569, 1632 In his present article and two that preceded it, Akhil Amar takes issue with what has come to be regarded as the traditional view of article III—that Congress has plenary authority... 142. CONGRESS, EX PARTE YOUNG, AND THE FATE OF THE THREEJUDGE DISTRICT COURT, 70 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 101, 153 In 1908 the Supreme Court held in Ex parte Young that a federal judge could enjoin a state attorney general from enforcing an unconstitutional state statute, notwithstanding... 143. RETHINKING EXCLUSIVE FEDERAL JURISDICTION, 52 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 383, 434+ Two centuries ago the first United States Congress provided that certain actions could only be litigated in the then newly created federal courts, not in the existing state courts.... 144. EX PARTE YOUNG: SOVEREIGNTY, IMMUNITY, AND THE CONSTITUTIONAL STRUCTURE OF AMERICAN FEDERALISM, 40 U. Tol. L. Rev. 843, 888+ THE U.S. Supreme Court’s recent state-immunity jurisprudence requires reconsideration. The call for reconsideration does not stem from an absolutist rejection of all forms of... 145. JUDICIAL RESTRAINTS ON ILLEGAL STATE VIOLENCE: ISRAEL AND THE UNITED STATES, 35 Vand. J. Transnat’l L. 73, 149 This Article examines the role of courts in controlling state violence in the United States and Israel. The Author considers how U.S. federal courts should respond to illegal... 146. REFLECTIONS ON THE HART AND WECHSLER PARADIGM, 47 Vand. L. Rev. 953, 987+ I. INTRODUCTION II. THE HART AND WECHSLER PARADIGM A. Stances Toward Hart and Wechsler 1. The Unmet Challenge of Brown? 2. The Puzzling Persistence of Hart and Wechsler B. Sources... 147. PRIVACY IN THE FIRST AMENDMENT: PRIVATE FACTS AND THE ZONE OF DELIBERATION, 44 Vand. L. Rev. 899, 923 I. INTRODUCTION․ 899 II. THE CLASSIC DEMOCRATIC MODEL OF THE FIRST AMENDMENT: MEIKLEJOHN REVISITED․ 902 A. Meiklejohn, New York Times v. Sullivan, and the Democratic Model․ ... 148. EXPLORING A SECOND LEVEL OF PARITY: SUGGESTIONS FOR DEVELOPING AN ANALYTICAL FRAMEWORK FOR FORUM SELECTION © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 87 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth IN EMPLOYMENT DISCRIMINATION LITIGATION, 44 Vand. L. Rev. 641, 688 I. INTRODUCTION II. THE YELLOW FREIGHT DECISION AND ITS IMPLICATIONS A. Prior Decisions B. The Seventh Circuit’s Rejection of Valenzuela C. The Supreme Court’s Finding of... 1992 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 1999 Law Review — 2000 Law Review — 2005 Law Review — 1998 Law Review — 155. ARTICLE III CASES, STATE COURT DUTIES, AND THE MADISONIAN 1995 COMPROMISE, 1995 Wis. L. Rev. 39, 197 Law Review — Law Review — 149. THE CONSITUTIONALITY OF SECTION 27A OF THE SECURITIES EXCHANGE ACT: IS CONGRESS RUBBING LAMPF THE WRONG WAY?, 37 Vill. L. Rev. 1213, 1328 I. Introduction II. Historical Background of Statutes of Limitation in Rule 10b-5 Litigation A. Statutes of Limitation and Statutes of Repose in General B. Statutes of Limitation... 150. IN PRAISE OF THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT AND SECTION 1983, 84 Va. L. Rev. 47, 82 AS everyone knows, the Eleventh Amendment is a mess. It is the home of selfcontradiction, transparent fiction, and arbitrary stops in reasoning. Any hope of doctrinal stability... 151. MUST COURTS RAISE THE ELEVENTH AMENDMENT SUA SPONTE?: THE JURISDICTIONAL DIFFICULTY OF STATE SOVEREIGN IMMUNITY, 56 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1037, 1078+ Table of Contents I. Introduction․ 1038 II. The Love-Hate Relationship of the Eleventh Amendment and State Sovereign Immunity․ 1040 A. The Love․ 1040 B. The Hate․ 1041 III. How... 152. PRINCIPLES OF FORUM SELECTION, 103 W. Va. L. Rev. 167, 203 i. L2-3,T3Introduction 167 ii. L2-3,T3Venue 170 A. Venue Statutes․ 170 B. Forum Non Conveniens․ 172 C. Transfer of Venue․ 175 D. Personal Jurisdiction․ 178 iii. L2-3,T3Federal... 153. THE FUTURE OF PARITY, 46 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1457, 1497 In the dual enforcement of constitutional norms in the United States, state governmental institutions, and particularly state courts, are entrusted with adjudicating federal... 154. STATE JUDGES, STATE OFFICERS, AND FEDERAL COMMANDS AFTER SEMINOLE TRIBE AND PRINTZ, 1998 Wis. L. Rev. 1465, 1545 Introduction․ 1466 I. The Eleventh Amendment and State Sovereign Immunity․ 1474 A. The Eleventh Amendment: Text and History․ 1476 Precedent․ 1485 1. Constitutional... B. Traditional federal courts scholarship holds that state courts are empowered to hear, and that they have certain duties to hear, Article III cases and controversies. Support for... 156. SAYING WHAT RIGHTS ARE-IN AND OUT OF CONTEXT, 1991 Wis. L. Rev. 929, 968 1991 © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 88 THE IDEOLOGIES OF FEDERAL COURTS LAW, 74 Va. L. Rev. 1141 Title Date Type Depth In this Article, Professor Althouse examines the role of “context” in the lawmaking process. Specifically, she concentrates on the Supreme Court’s new habeas corpus doctrine, and... Law Review — Law Review — 1996 Law Review — 1997 Law Review — 161. ALTERING THE COURSE OF THE CONSTITUTIONAL CONVENTION: 1990 THE ROLE OF THE COMMITTEE OF DETAIL IN ESTABLISHING THE BALANCE OF STATE AND FEDERAL POWERS, 100 Yale L.J. 765, 783 Law Review — 157. WHY ALIENAGE JURISDICTION? HISTORICAL FOUNDATIONS AND 1996 MODERN JUSTIFICATIONS FOR FEDERAL JURISDICTION OVER DISPUTES INVOLVING NONCITIZENS, 21 Yale J. Int’l L. 1, 66 I. Introduction․ 2 II. The Origins․ 6 A. The Constitutional Convention and Ratification․ 6 1. Historical Context․ 6 2. Debate over the Alienage Provisions of Article III․ ... 158. AFTERWORD: FEDERALISM’S OPTIONS, 14 Yale J. on Reg. 465, 503 1996 I. The Fixtures of United States’ Legal Federalism․ 465 II. Alternative Conceptions: The Permeable Boundaries of Judicial Federalism․ 479 III. Federalism and Physicality: The... 159. AFTERWORD: FEDERALISM’S OPTIONS, 14 Yale L. & Pol’y Rev. 465, 503 I. The Fixtures of United States’ Legal Federalism․ 465 II. Alternative Conceptions: The Permeable Boundaries of Judicial Federalism․ 479 III. Federalism and Physicality: The... 160. THE COMMON LAW ORIGINS OF CONSTITUTIONALLY COMPELLED REMEDIES, 107 Yale L.J. 77, 164 C1-3Contents I. Diversity Jurisdiction and Federal Questions․ 84 A. ‘General Law’ and Diversity․ 85 1. The Origins of Diversity Jurisdiction․ 85 2. Use of Diversity to... The Committee of Detail, comprised of five delegates from the Constitutional Convention, produced the first draft of the Constitution. Yet most constitutional scholars have... © 2011 Thomson Reuters. No claim to original U.S. Government Works. 89