PEDU 7206 Foundations of E A P Lecture 4 & 5 The Ontological Foundations of EAP A. Bring the Ontological Foundation Back into the Research of EAP 1. The Critical Realist declarations: a. “Since Descartes (1596-1650), it has been customary first to ask how we can know, and only afterwards what it is that we can know. But this Cartesian ordering has been a contributory factor to prevalence of epistemic fallacy: it is easy to let the question how we can know determine our conception of what there is. And if in a certain respect the epistemic question does seem prior, in another it is secondary to the ontological one.” (Collier, 1993, P. 137) b. “I shall concentrate first on the ontological question of the properties that societies possess, before shift to the epistemological question of these properties make them possible objects of knowledge for use. This is not an arbitrary order of development. It reflects the condition that …it is the nature of objects that determines their cognitive possibilities for us.” (Bhaskar, 1989) 2. Objectivism vs. Constructivism: Antagonism in ontological perspectives: Centuries of controversies among social researchers over epistemological and methodological perspectives have created two deeply divided definitions of the reality of the social world, namely objectivism and constructivism a. Objectivism: Under the domination of the logical-positivism and analytical-empirical science, the prevailing social ontology, which has been characterized as objectivism, stipulates the social world as an objectively fixed and given reality as reality of the natural world. In this ontological perspective, social reality is stipulated as analytical and empirical in form, that is, the social world is conceived as a composition of particles or elements, the structures and operations of which are observable by human senses. Moreover, the social reality has also been stipulated as nomological and causal in structure, i.e. the constitutive particles of social reality are presumed to be structured in causal laws. The law-like structures of the social world can further be defined in terms of their degree of universality and permanence. Accordingly, the “strong” stance within the objectivism would argue that the law-like structures of social realities are universal across locations and permanent over time. Such an ontological stance could be characterized as “objective absolutism”. On the other hand, the “weak” stance of objectivism would assume that the laws governing the social world are only probabilistic laws and their universality and permanence are limited in particular social and historical contexts. b. Constructivism: In opposite to objectivism and more specifically in response to the domination and even assault from the empirical positivists, the social scientists in the historical-hermeneutic tradition have turned to interpretivism and constructivism for havens. By Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 1 interpretivism, it refers to the research approach which emphasizes on the meaning-laden and value-laden nature of the social world. Accordingly, this group of social scientists focuses on the interpretive (i.e. meaning attributing) features embedded in social reality and stresses the uniqueness of each interpretive communities involved as well as the meanings they imputed to the social reality concerned. Moreover, some of these interpretativists would even advocate that the social reality is “a matter of interpretation” and its features and structures are “open to interpretation” as well. By constructivism, it refers to the research orientation which underlines the essential roles of human ideas, believes, and efforts in the constitution of the social world and more specifically its social institutions. Accordingly, it is assumed that realities of the social world are subject to construction by different interpretive communities according to their own ideas, believes or even vested interests. As a result, social realities are conceived to be relative in nature, i.e. relative to the subjectivities and intersubjectivities of the interpretive communities that have power over the respective social realities in point. Such a research approach can be characterized as “constructive relativism”. The “paradigm war” between these two perspectives in social ontology, especially the “dog fights” between extremists of “objective absolutism” and those of “constructive relativism” have left the field of social ontology in complete disarrays if not chaos for decades. On the one hand, there are advocates holding the ontological perspective of “structural determinism”, which insists on the definitude of causal laws at work in social structures. And accordingly human relationship and activities found in these social structures are conceived to be deterministic in nature. On the other hand, there are proponents promoting the ontological perspective of “constructive voluntarism”, which emphasizes the intersubjectivity and forgeability at work in social reality. Caught between the crossfire of these two camps, most of the students in social research are helpless at lost in these ontological, epistemological and methodological labyrinth. 3. The Critical-Realist Movement a. Since the second half of the 1970s, Roy Bhaskar, a British philosopher, has produced a series of work on philosophy of science and social sciences (1975, 1979, 1986, 1989). His work has motivated a line of academic work in varieties of disciplines. As a result, they have together triggered an intellectual movement now known as Critical Realism. b. In the past three decades Critical Realism has gained significant recognition and development in social-science researches; for examples economics (Lawson, 1997), social psychology (Greenwood, 1994), sociology (Archer, 1995; Danermark et al., 2002), geography (Sayer, 2000), management and organizational studies (Ackroyd and Fleetwood, 2000), social research methods (Sayer, 1992), policy studies (Henry, et al. 1998; Pawson, 2006, 2013; Mark et al., 2000), and education (in particular sociology of education (Maton, 2014; Maton & Moore, 2010; Muller, 2000; Moore, 2007, 2009; Scott, 2010; Shipway, 2012; Wheelahan, 2010; Young, 2008a, 2008b). Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 2 4. What is critical realism? a. Realism as doctrine in philosophy or more specifically in the philosophy of science “belief that there is a world existing independently of our knowledge of it.” (Sayer, 2000, P. 2). It assumes that the objects of study in science “is ontologically independent of human mind.” (Niiniluoto, 1990, P. 10) b. Critical realism as a theoretical branch within realism makes several specific theoretical claims: (Collier, 1994, P.6-7) i. Objectivity: It refers to the ontological stance that “what is known would be real whether or not it were known. Something may be real without appearing at all.” (P. 6) ii. Fallibility: It refers to the epistemological stance that knowledge claims made by critical realists are “not about some supposedly infallible or corrigible data of appearance.” Instead, they “are always open to refutation by further information.” (P. 6) Therefore, social researchers must also be vigilant and critical to their research results and knowledge claims. iii. Transphenomenality (going beyond appearance): It indicates that “knowledge may be not only of what appears, but of underlying structures, which endure longer than those appearances, and generate them or make them possible.” (P. 6) iv. Counter-phenomenallity: It refers to the epistemological stance which claims that “knowledge of the deep structure of something may not just go beyond, and not just explain, but also contradict appears. …It is precisely the capacity of science for counterphenomenality which made it necessary: without the contradiction between appearance and reality, science would be redundant, and we could go by appearance.” (P.7) B. Conceptual constituents of Transcendental Realism of Natural Sciences Roy Basher starts his buildup of critical realism first with the analysis of the work and enterprise of natural sciences. One of his initial points of departure is to criticize the validity of empirical realism, which was the dominant approach in scientific research. Instead Bhaskar proposes to replace empirical realism with what he called transcendental realism. It means that the reality of the natural world is not confine its appearances or to what we could have experienced. He claims that there are deeper layers of mechanism and system at work than the mere appearances that we could sensorily experience. (Collier, 1994, Pp. 25-29) 1. Concept of Depth Realism: The first conception of Bhaskar’s Critical Realism is his distinction of reality into three domains: a. Empirical domain: It refers to the aspect of reality which we have experienced with our senses. b. Actual domain: It refers to events which have occurred without our noticing, while we can infer from their effects. c. Real domain: It refers to the properties within entities, which are able to triggers events to take place or to constraint them from occurring. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 3 Domain of Real Domain of Actual ✓ Mechanism ✓ Events ✓ Experiences Source: Bhaskar, 1978, P. 13 ✓ ✓ Domain of Empirical ✓ 2. Features of the domain of the Real: Bhaskar has further differentiated the features of the reality into levels: a. Power and liability: Powers or emergent power, in Bhaskar’s term, refers to the potentials which are able trigger events to take place; while liability are properties which can prevent or constraint events from happening. b. Mechanism: It refers to a set of powers working inter-connectively to set off the occurrence an event or a chain of events. c. Structure of the system: It refers to the interconnections among operative mechanisms, which constitute the underlying structure against which events are taking places. d. Open/closed system: It refers the openness or closure (i.e. boundary) of a given system. According to Critical Realist conception, “no system in our universe is ever perfectly closed.” (Collier, 1994, P. 33) And accordingly both our natural and social world are by definition open systems. 3. Stratification of causation: Taking together these conceptions of the natural world stipulated by the Critical Realists, theories and models of causal explanations formulated by scientists can be categorized into several strata a. Cause-effect explanation b. Explanatory mechanism c. Explanatory structure i. Structure of closed system: Nomological/law-like explanations ii. Structure of open system: Theories of tendency or emergency 4. The work of science: Given all these specifications of the operations of the natural world, Critical Realists contend that the work of natural science is in no way close to the conceptions of experimental work stipulated by empiricism (based solely on sensory observation) and positivism (aimed solely at verifying nomological explanations). Instead, Critical Realists specify the features of the work of experimental science as follows: a. Science as work: Science in essence “is work, not contemplation, not observation, not taking up of some kind of scientific attitude.” “It is an active intervention into nature, made by people with acquired scientific skills, usually using special equipment.” (Collier, 1993, P. 50) And “the ‘product’ is not the new arrangement of matter brought about by the experiment. …It is the deepened knowledge of some mechanism of nature.” (P.52) b. Dr = Da = De coincide: Deepening of knowledge of nature means to penetrate the empirical world and the actual events and to obtain the mechanism and structure underlying all human experiences. It is Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 4 through scientific experiment, “we can set up a situation in which three domains (Dr, Da, De) coincide — in which a mechanism is actualized, i.e. isolated from its usual codeterminants, so that it can operate as a closed system, and to manifested as an event exemplifying the law to which it corresponds.” (Collier, 1994, P. 45) c. Experiment as closure: “What the experiment does …is to isolate one mechanism of nature from the effect of others, to see what that mechanism does on its own.” (Collier, 1994, P. 33) It is “an attempt to trigger or unleash a single kind of mechanism or process in relative isolation, free from the interfering flux of the open world, so as to observe its details workings or record its characteristic mode of effect and/or to test some hypothesis about them.” (Bhashar, 1986, P. 35; quoted in Collier, 1994, P. 33) d. Theory-led endeavor: “The classical sequence of experimental science is…: first we construct a theory, then we design an experiment to test it, then we receive nature’s answer to our question.” (Collier, 1994, P. 40) This indicates that experimental practice cannot replace theoretical thinking in the work of science. Power of abstraction and theoretical synthesizing is not only the initial point of departure for formulation of problems but also the guiding signposts throughout the path of scientific enquiry. 5. The hierarchy of science: a. In view of the distinct domains, levels and strata specified by Critical Realists so far, the enterprise of science itself can then be further differentiated into “distinct sciences — physics, chemistry, biology, economics etc. — which are mutually irreducible, but which are ordered. Physics is in this sense more basic than chemistry, which is more basic than biology, which is more basic than the human sciences.” (Collier, 1994, P. 107) b. For example, Benton and Craib proposed a hierarchy of sciences as follows. (Benton & Craib, 2011, P. 127) social sciences psychology physiology/anatomy organic chemistry/biological chemistry physical chemistry physics c. Andrew Collier posposes another hierarchy, which he calls “tree of science” (Collier, 1994, P. 132) ? psychological and semiological sciences social sciences biological sciences Molecular sciences ? d. “This way of ordering the sciences could be justified in terms of the mechanisms characteristic of each level are explicable in terms of those of the nest one below it. This corresponds to a view of science as explaining wholes in terms of the parts of which they are composed.” (Benton and Craib, 2011, Pp. 126-127) However, it must Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 5 be underlined that the causal flows can be construed in both directions, that is, “causality can flow down the hierarchy as well as up it.” (P. 128) 6. Intransitive and transitive dimensions of science: a. Intransitive dimension of science: According to the basic tenet of Critical Realism, the natural world exists independently of human minds and knowledge. Hence, this object of science studies — the natural world and with all its substances, mechanisms and structures — constitute the intransitive dimension of the work of science. b. Transitive dimension of science: Scientists, with their concepts and theories, their skills and practices, as well as their communities, associations and rival schools of thought, they constitute the transitive dimension of science. What scientists do is to strive to deepen the existing scientific knowledge of the nature world. c. Accordingly, “the ‘results’ of scientific inquiry at any time are a set of theories about the nature of the world, which are presumably our best approximation to truth about the world….However much science deepens its knowledge of its intransitive object, its product remains a transitive object.” (Collier, 1994, P. 51) d. In light of these distinctions between intransitive and transitive dimensions in science, we can see that Critical Realists take on different stances for their ontological and epistemological foundations. Ontologically, Critical Realists assume its objects of their enquiry are intransitive and real and the products of their enquiry could be truth. However, epistemological, Critical Realists admit that their scientific work and practice at any given in time are only relative to the material, social as well as theoretical configuration of the scientific enterprise, in which they find themselves. D. Distinction between the Natural and the Social Sciences: Conceptual Constituents of Critical Naturalism 1. The debate between the natural and the social sciences has been raging on since the nineteenth century around the issue of the unity of scientific method. Recently Roy Bhaskar reformulates the issue at the beginning of his book The Possibility of Naturalism as follows. “To what extent can society be studied in the way as nature?” (Bhaskar, 1998, P. 1) Two conventional answers to this issue are a. Naturalism: The positive answer to the issue can be summarized under the doctrine, which Bhaskar called naturalism. By naturalism, it refers to the doctrine which asserts that there “is (or can be) an essential unity of method between the natural and the social sciences.” (Bhaskar, 1998, P. 2) With this naturalist camp, subdivisions can further be differentiated i. Reductionism, which claims that “there is an actual identity of subject matter” between the two sciences.” (Bhaskar, 1998, P. 2) ii. Scientism, which “denies that there are any significant differences in the methods appropriate to studying social and natural subject.” (Bhaskar, 1998, P. 2) That appropriate method is of course the scientific method. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 6 iii. Positivism, which claims that the products of studies in both the natural and social sciences are the same, that is, to verify causal laws, which can account for the events under study to the full. (Bhaskar, 1998; Collier, 1994, P. 102-102) b. Hermeneutics and interpretive theory: In opposite to the naturalists positive answer to the issue, social scientists in hermeneutic and interpretive tradition insist that it is impossible to study society in the way as nature! They have argued for centuries that human and social sciences are essentially distinct from natural sciences in terms of their methodology and epistemology, but most importantly in their ontological foundation. (These arguments have been explicate on Topic 2 and 3 in this course) 2. Critical Realists’ stance on the issue of the possibility of naturalism of social science: a. Critical Realists have distanced themselves from the epistemological arguments between positivism and hermeneutics and the methodological arguments between quantitative and qualitative research practitioners; they have chosen a different approach to the issue, by looking into the ontological differences between the natural world and the social reality. They have synthesized a series of concepts, which attempt to build a conceptual framework of social ontology of critical realism. b. Human agents and their agency: Critical Realists assert that one of the major differences between nature and society is that society is made up of human agents, who would not act or behave mechanically to antecedent causes or stimulus. Human beings are “meaning making animals”, who forge ideas, hold believes, adhere identities, plan intentional actions, and carry out projects and agencies. As a result, in accounting for social events, social scientists could not simply look for antecedent causes, in the form of necessary and/or sufficient conditions. They must dig deep into social reality and look for “reasons”. In fact, Critical Realists have argued at length that reasons, which include beliefs, desires, ideas, intentions, should belong to the causal orders in accounting for social events. (Bhaskar, 1998, Pp.80-119; Collier, 1994, Pp. 151-156) c. Activity-dependent structure and Transformational Model of Social Activity (TMSA): One of the fundamental differences between structures of society and nature is that “social structures are maintained in existence only through the activities of agents (activitydependence), whereas this is not true of structures of nature.” (Benton & Craib, 2011, P. 135) More specifically, the continuity and consistency of a given social structure depends mainly on the willingness and capacity of its members to participate and carry out the obligations and duties prescribed to their specific positions within the structure. Therefore, the endurance of a social structure rely on the efficacies of its institutions of production, socialization, social control and reproduction. Bhaskar has named this characteristic of social structure as Transformation Model of Social Activity (TMAS). That is, social Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 7 structures are more likely to transform than structures of nature and their endurance are only relative in nature. d. Concept-dependence and the cultural dimension of social structure: Since the reproduction of social structures are subject to human agents’ participations and actions, they are therefore more fundamentally depending on members’ impressions, perceptions, beliefs, and conception about the respective structures. As a result, social structures are not only built on their material grounds same as the structures of nature, but are also based on their cultural resources, such as linguistic, cultural and social capitals. e. Space-time-dependent and context specific: Unlike the structure of entities found in nature, which are universal across both time and space; social structures constituted by human agents are heavily embedded in the specific contexts, in which particular groups of human agents found themselves. These contexts include historical contexts, socio-cultural contexts, geo-political contexts, naturalecological contexts, etc. f. Impossibility of experimental closure: Incomparable to natural scientists, social scientists are practical impossible to isolate any fragments of social reality and to design an experimental closure, in which they can test their hypothesis about specific causal relations found in society. In fact the openness of the social system is so immense that it is basically unable to control and/or randomize all the other co-determinants confounding the specific cause-effect explanatory models that social scientists are supposed to verify. g. Unsustainability of intransitive-transitive division in knowledge of social science: Unlike knowledge of natural science, in which the distinction between the intransitivity of the natural world and the transitivity of the knowledge produced by particular groups of natural scientists is empirically definitive; the division is practically indistinct. It is because social reality is transitive in nature. They are subject to change with the beliefs and ideas of human agents. Furthermore, they may even transform themselves according to findings and theories produced by social scientists. 3. Critical Realists’ conception of social reality: Given these essential distinctions between natural and social reality, Critical Realists’ conception of social reality may be summarized as follows: a. Relational model of society: Bhaskar suggests that “society does not consist of individuals (or we might add, groups), but expresses the sum of relations within which individuals (and groups) stand.” (Bhaskar, 1998, P. 26) b. Studying the persistence and endurance of relations: Bhaskar further indicates that social sciences in general and sociology in particular are “concerned…with the persist relations between individuals (and groups) and with relations between these relations (and between such relation and nature and the products of such relations).” (Bhaskar, 1998, P. 28-29; my emphasis) c. Duality of objectivity and subjectivity in social structure: i. Durkheimian objective-factual conception of social structure Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 8 ii. Weberian subjective-meaningful conception of social structure iii. Critical Realist synthesis: TMSA and M/M approach d. Duality of individualism and collectivism in social structure: i. Atomic reductionism and methodological individualism ii. Structuralism and methodological collectivism iii. Critical realist synthesis: SEPM and M/M/ Approach e. Duality of stability and change in social structure i. Conception of relativity of persistence and Morphostasis ii. Conception of Morphogenesis E. Margaret S. Archer’s Morphogenetic/Morphostatic Approach 1. Morphogenetic Approach a. Meaning of morphogenesis: i. The prefix ‘morpho’ refers to ‘of or pertaining to form’ and ‘genesis’ refers ‘mode of formation’. Hence, morphogenesis is commonly in biology to mean formation of the structure biological organisms, while in physical geography it refers formation of landscapes or landforms. (Oxford English Dictionary) ii. Margaret Archer uses the word in morphogenetic approach to connote that “the ‘morpho’ element is an acknowledgement that society has no pre-set form or preferred state; the ‘genetic’ part is a recognition that it takes its shape from, and is formed by, agents, originating from the intended and unintended consequences of the activities.” (Archer, 1995, p. 5) iii. The approach can then be construed as an echo of the TMSA in Critical Realism in sociological analysis. It emphasizes both the possibility of transforming the social structure through social actions of the agents, and at the same time underline the relative endurance and resilience of social structures and their conditioning (not determining) effects on the social actions of human agents. b. Morphogenetic approach in structure-agency debate in sociology: Archer allocates her morphogenetic approach against the longstanding structure-agent in the debate on social ontology in sociology. Archer asserts that her approach can address three common “conflations” found in the debate. They are i. The downwards conflation: It refer to those theoretical stances which put special emphasis on the determinacy of the social structure over the agents and their plans of actions (i.e. agencies). They includes “any uncompromising version of technological determinism, economism, structuralism or normative functionalism.” (Archer, 1995, P. 81) As a result, these theoretical stances constitute a kind of “downwards conflation where structure and agency are conflated because action is treated as fundamentally epiphenomenal has many variants….The bottom line is always that actors may be indispensable for energizing the social system.” (Archer, 1995, P. 81) The methodological ground grown out the social ontology of structuralism is commonly known as methodological collectivism. ii. The upwards conflation: It refers to the theoretical stances which is argued for “the primacy of the agent” and underlines that structure Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 9 is but the creation of agency. Social structural are hence reduced to “a series of intersubjectively negotiated constructs”. (Archer, 1995, P. 84) The methodological ground generated from such social ontology is called the methodological individualism. iii. Central conflation: It is “an approach based upon the putative mutual constitution of structure and agency and finds its most sophisticated expression in modern ‘structuration theory’.” (Archer, 1995, P. 87) The structuration theory is called made well-known by the work of Anthony Giddens. However, Archer argues that what has been suppressed (or conflated) in this mutually constituting activity is the historical-temporal thickness of society, more specifically, the enduring institutional practices sedimented over time. In Archer’s own words, “structural properties (defined reductively as rules and resources) are held to be outside time, having a ‘virtual existence’ only when instantiated by actions. In exact parallel, when actors produce social practices they necessarily draw upon rules and resources and the inevitable invoke the whole matrix of structural properties at that instance.” (Archer, 1995, P. 87) Archer therefore criticizes that Giddens has not given adequate treatment to the temporal dimension in the structuration theory. c. Taking time to link structure an agency: In rectifying these conflations found in the structure-agency debate, Archer formulated her theory of morphogenesis by injecting a time dimension into the framework. She underlines that “the distinctive feature of the morphogenetic approach is its time dimension, through which and in which structure and agency shape one another.” (1995, P. 92) i. Three-part cycles of the morphogenesis: “Morphogenetic analysis, in contrast to the three foregoing approaches, accords time a central place in social theory. By working in terms od its three-part cycles composed of (a) structural conditioning, (b) social interaction and (c) structure elaboration, time is incorporated as sequential tract and phases rather than simply as a medium through which events take place.” (Archer, 1995, P. 89) Source, Archer, 1995, p. 76. ii. As a result, Archer claims that her analytical framework has rectified the three prevailing approaches to structure-agency debates in sociological theory. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 10 Source, Archer, 1995, P. 82. d. Structural condition: This part of the cycle represents the structural properties accumulated and passed on from past agencies. It also signifies that this structural property could in fact assert “causal influences upon subsequent interaction.” These influences are working through facilitating the some types of interactions but at the same time constraining some others. In Critical Realists’ terms they impose selectively either “powers” or “liabilities” on human interactions. By focusing mainly if not solely on this part of the morphogenetic process, structuralists are of course confident to endorse the dominance of the structure on the agency and as a result have committed the downwards conflation that Archer has aptly highlighted. e. Social interaction: This tract of the cycle indicates that the causal influences of structural properties on agencies are never deterministic but only conditional and interactive in nature. It is because Critical Realists presume that “agents possess their own irreducible emergent power”. Hence, structural properties and agencies are engaging in mutually “structurating” and “destructurating” interactions. This is the point in time where Giddens theory of structuration comes in. f. Structural elaboration: After the social interactions between the structure and agent in each generation have played out, an elaborated structure-agency relation will emerge. Analytically, this may take one of the following outcomes: i. Morphostasis: It refers to the outcome where the new generation of human agents in a social system are socialized and Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 11 incorporated into the existing structure as well as culture. And the system has practically “reproduced” itself. ii. Morphogenesis: It refers to the outcome where the prevailing structure and culture of a given social system has been elaborated, transformed and to the greatest extent revolted. 2. The integration of Morphogenetic approach into the conceptions of Critical Realism: Source: Archer, 1995, P. 160. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 12 F. Comparative-Historical Method for Institutional Research: In Search of the Methodological Foundations for EAP Studies 1. The limitations of social knowledge: In light of the explications of the ontological and epistemological foundations of policy studies in more generally of the social sciences, we can conclude that social scientific researchers are confront with numbers of limitations in comparison with their fellow researchers in natural sciences. They include a. Social sciences are expected to render causal explanations to social events, that is, to be “explanatory sciences.” (Collier, 1994, P 1611) b. Social sciences are “sciences without closure.” (Collier, 1994, P. 161) More importantly, social scientists are possible to set up experimental closure. c. Social sciences are “sciences with hermeneutic premises.” (Collier, 1994, P. 161) That is they are required to reveal the meanings embedded in social reality. d. The explanations social scientists rendered should be more than immediate causes for empirical events, but must include reasons and intentions attributed by human agents participated in the respective events. e. These explanations should also include contextual factors (including temporal, spatial, and socio-economical contexts) in which the human agents concerned find themselves. f. Last but not the least, social scientists must take into account the transformative potentials embedded in social realities and more importantly the emancipatory powers endowed in human agents. 2. In order to eliminate these limitations, social scientists must transcend the demarcations between the empiricist-positivism and the interpretive-hermeneutic tradition, more specifically, between the quantitative and qualitative methods. One of the cornerstones in bridging these epistemological and methodological chasms is the comparative-historical method. a. Margaret Archer, one of the leading sociologists in Critical Realism, has demonstrated some convincingly the validities of the comparative-historical method in one of her early research work Social Origins of Educational Systems (1979). b. In the study, Archer traces the historical paths of developments of modern educational systems in four European countries in two pairs, namely i. England and Denmark representing Substitutive Model ii. France and Russia representing Restrictive Model 3. Comparative-historical method has a long, if not the longest, tradition in the research of social sciences. It can be traced back to the works of the founding fathers of social sciences, such as Karl Marx, Max Weber and Emile Durkheim. 4. More recently in the past three decades, there are growing numbers of publications on empirical research and methodological discussions. For examples, Collins (1979, 1999), Carnoy & Levin. (1985), Green (1990), Mahoney & Rueschemeyer (2003), Ragin (1987), Schriewer (1990), Skocpol (1979, 1982), Somers (2008), Tilly (1984, 1990), etc. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 13 G. Explanatory Critique Given the specific natures of social reality and the explanatory power realist social sciences characterized above, Bhaskar asserts that Critical-Realist social theorists are equipped with what Bhaskar called “explanatory critiques” in accounting for social phenomena. 1. Models of explanation in social sciences: So far we have covered three methodological approaches and epistemological perspectives, it is revealed that each of them apply different modes of explanation to account for the social phenomena under study. a. Nomological causal explanation: It refers to the explanatory models, which aim to provide law-like explanation in the form of antecedent cause and subsequent effect causation to the social phenomena under study. To a less extent, it substantiates at least probabilistic covariance connection between two variables under study. b. Teleological explanation: it refers to the explanatory models, which attempt to provide intentional explanation to human actions. It intends not to trace antecedent causes for human action but motives and intentions at work behind given action aiming to the future. Under the working assumption that humans are rational actions, this explanatory models has been modified into what is now commonly known as rational-choice model. Furthermore, there is also another kind of explanatory model generally called quasi-teleological explanation in use in social sciences, which render explanations for social actions in macroscopic scale in the formats of functional and institutional accounts. c. Explanatory critique: As critical social scientists, they have employed yet another kind of explanatory model, which the critical realists named “explanatory critique”. 2. What is explanatory critique? a. As formulated by Critical Theorists, such as Horkheimer and Habermas, they are not contented with verifying causality or/and revealing meanings, intentions and values in accounting for social activities; they intends to go beyond the regularities and persistence found in social structures and/or belief-systems and look at the possible systemic biases, injustice, and false believes (i.e. ideologies) at work behind these social regularities. b. Having revealed the systemic biases and ideologies, critical social scientists would feel obliged to criticize the “incorrectness”, injustice, and social ills found in the phenomena under study. c. Lastly, in order to justify their critique, critical social scientists must elevate their explanatory tasks from empirical-causal explanations and/or interpretive-intentional/functional explanations to the level of “explanatory critique”, i.e. to provide explanations for their critiques. 3. In search of the evaluative ground for the critical social science: a. In the last section of the concluding chapter of the two-volume work The Theory of Communicative Theory, Jurgen Habermas underlines that “In this work I have tried to introduce a theory of communicative action that clarifies the normative foundation of the critical theory of society.” (Habermas, 1987, P. 396-7) Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 14 This quotation underlines that one of the essential “task of a critical theory” is to provide “the normative foundation of the critical theory of society.” And the normative foundation that Habermas renders for his own critical theory is exactly the theory of communicative action, rationality and ethics. (Habermas, 1984 & 1987) b. Accordingly, in reviewing any critical theories and the explanatory critiques they provided, one must look for the normative foundation on which the explanatory critiques and evaluations are based. For examples, c. Marx’s normative foundation of explanatory critique: Karl Marx builds his explanatory critique of capitalism on the normative foundation that the mode and relation of production of capitalism has generated i. the extreme inequality of economic distribution biased in favor of the bourgeoisie against the proletarian, which is the causal result of the exploitative nature of the relation of production; ii. the ever accelerating process of commodification, which has not only alienated and reified the process of production, but also the labor process as well; iii. the contradictions between the infrastructure and the superstructure of the capitalism, most notably the hegemony of the ideology of the capitalists over the culture of the whole society. d. Weber’s normative foundation of explanatory critique: Max Weber builds his explanatory critique on the normative foundation not only on the economic sphere of capitalism but also on the bureaucratization of the modern state. Weber underlines that the expansion of the instrumental rationality into various human organization has produced the “iron cage” in which humans have loss both the meanings and freedom in lives. e. Habermas’ normative foundation of explanatory critique: As cited above, Habermas has indicated that the normative foundation of his critical theory of society is the theory of communicative action. By the theory of communicative action, it refers to “the theory…aims at the moment of unconditionality of processes of consensus formation. As claims they transcend all limitations of space and time, all the provincial limitations of the given contexts.” (Habermas, 1987, p. 399) However, Habermas argues that in modern society the money steering apparatus of the market and the power-steering apparatus of the state have proliferated to such a great extent that the primary operating ground of communicative actions, i.e. the Lifeworld, has practically been colonized. (to be explicated in details on Topic 6 & 8) 4. Critical Realists’ normative foundation of explanatory critique: a. Critical realists, in particular Bhaskar and Collier, approach the issue of finding the normative ground or in their terms “evaluative language” for their explanatory critique from another perspective, namely from methodological an epistemological perspectives rather than from the substantive theoretical perspective as Marx, Weber and Habermas. They approach the issue by addressing one of the fundamental debates in social research, namely the entanglement between fact and value. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 15 b. The fact and value aporia in social research: In natural-scientific research, fact and value are two separate domains, which should not be conflated in any ways. However, within the tradition of social research and sociological research in particular, the relation between fact and value has been one of the most controversial topics annoying its practitioners. On the one hand, social researchers are supposed to observe the code of “value-free” in the investigation as suggested by Max Weber, yet on the other hand, the same Weber has also advocated that social actions are laden with subjective meanings and values. As a result, bridging the gap between objective fact and subjective value has been one of the aporia confronting social researchers for generations. c. One of the manifestations of the fact-value aporia in social research is on the issue whether the objects of study, i.e. social phenomena are embodied with values or should they be treated as objective facts. Bhaskar approaches the issue with an example from put forth by Isaiah Berlin, “that of the following four statements about what happened in Nazi Germany: ‘the country was depopulated’, ‘millions of people died’, ‘millions of people were killed’ were massacred’, ‘millions of people were massacred’——the fourth is both the most evaluative and the most precise and accurate; it gives more truth than the others. That is so, but the evaluative force arises entirely out of the factual content. It is not that by bringing values into the discourse one makes it a fuller statement of the truth, but that that by making a fuller statement of the truth one implies more value.” (Collier, 1994, P.178) This example in fact reveals that it is a common feature in social phenomena to proceed from factual statements to value statement and more importantly such a proceeding will practically bring out “more truth” about the social phenomenon in point. d. This example has also revealed another issue involved in research in the critical social science in general and explanatory critique in particular, that is what type of truth has the explanatory critique brought out in their investigation? i. First of all, the critique on Nazi’s act of massacred is built on the normative foundation that it is morally wrong to kill people in large scale. ii. Based on factual evidences generated from investigations, social researchers may and even can infer from “depopulated” to “massacred”. As a result, the argument has in fact elevated from factual statement to value judgment/conclusion. iii. With the normative foundation and the evidence-based inference, social researchers can substantiate their critique on the social phenomenon under study as structural biased, ideological false or simply morally wrong. Taking together this line of criticism, we can see that the kind of truth that critical social scientists is pursuing is quite different from the objective truth of the analytical-empirical scientists and the practical truth of the hermeneutic researchers, it can be characterized as the normative truth, which is based with a strong normative foundation or Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 16 even conviction and at the same time supported with explanatory critiques. 5. Typology of explanatory critiques: Bhaskar has outlined different types of explanatory critiques, but they are to be developed into substantive theories by means of “realistic” social researches in various social domains. a. Explanatory critique on “cognitive ills” (i.e. cognitive deceptions) and “communicative ills” (i.e. communicative distortions) in social reality, i.e. ideology b. Explanatory critique on “practical ills” in social reality, i.e. institutional injustice, illegitimate power and systemic bias c. Explanatory critique on “ethical ills” in social reality, i.e. psychopathological acts and irrational agencies 6. Explanatory critique and normative truth in educational research In light of the precedent discussions about the meanings of explanatory critique and normative truth, we can see that educational research in general and studies of educational administration and policy in particular are in essence a critical science. a. The emancipatory and critical nature of education: Education as a human and social science and practice aiming at developing the potentials of every members of a given society to the full, it is therefore by definition an emancipatory project working for the betterment of human possibilities and potentialities. On the contrary, educators must be critical to any systemic biases and distortions which may restraint or suppress the developments of human potentials. This is in fact the very normative foundation of education. b. Explanatory critique in educational research: In light of the above normative foundation or even conviction, education researchers are obligated to render explanatory critiques, which can provide evidences in criticizing any form of restraints and suppression of the developments of human potentials. In more positive sense, educational researchers should also provide explanatory critiques, which can improve the current institutional structure and belief in educational system, i.e. for the betterment of the status quo. c. In defense of the normative truth of education: Based on the normative foundation and conviction of helping every human to develop their potential to the full, and built on the evidences substantiated from concrete educational research and the substantive explanatory critiques concluded, educational researchers come to the position to defend the normative and educational truth they are obligated to defend. They may be in the forms of educational inequality and injustice institutionalized in particular educational organizations and/or policy institutions. They may also appear in the forms of false believes and ideologies about educational practices which in fact produce distorting, detrimental or even suppressive effects to the development of school-children’s potentials. Pang & Tsang Foundations of EAP 17