Human Rights and the Priority of the Moral 1. The language of human rights Many philosophers have observed, correctly, that human rights have now become the common language in which an increasing number of important legal and political issues are debated.1 Thus, it is all the more curious that so often this common language is used by them to talk past each other. For example, in discussing human rights some philosophers refer to a particular class of moral rights: those moral rights that all human beings possess “simply by virtue of their humanity.” Others refer instead to a group of norms and principles that form the current international human rights practice, whose primary function is twofold: providing standards for assessing how governments behave, and establishing when responses such as military intervention, economic and diplomatic sanctions, or formal censure are warranted.2 This explains, at least to some extent, the different approaches adopted by the so called “naturalistic” (or “orthodox”) and “political” (or “practical”) approaches to the justification of human rights, with the former primarily interested in the question of which important moral rights can be attributed to human beings simply in virtue of their human nature –call these “moral human rights”– 3 and the latter primarily focusing on the question of how best to make sense of, and bring coherence within, the practice of international human rights.4 What defenders of the political view object to is not the thought that individuals can be said to have certain moral rights simply as a consequence of their status as human beings. (Indeed, this is an idea which prominent defenders of the political view such as John Rawls and Joseph Raz explicitly accept.) What they object to is the idea that this thought can be usefully employed to make sense of the practice of international human rights as we know it, and thus to justify human rights. 1 On the other hand, philosophers who investigate the justification of the moral rights we possess simply in virtue of our human nature do not believe that answering this question automatically gives us an answer to the question of how we should structure the practice of international human rights. For example, John Tasioulas defends the view that simply in virtue of our status of human beings, we have a moral right not to be pinched or to be betrayed by friends, but he denies that these rights should play a role within the current practice of international human rights.5 This is because the question of how this practice should be structured is a separate one and should be informed by a host of different considerations concerning the nature and the functions of political institutions, international organizations, as well as other non-political actors operating at the international level.6 However, the disagreement between naturalistic and political justifications of human rights cannot be reduced to a case of philosophers talking past each other. The disagreement is substantive and concerns the need to appeal to fundamental moral human rights in justifying the international practice of human rights.7 Political justifications argue that we should bypass the question of the justification of moral human rights and start instead with the question of which norms and principles should be adopted to regulate the practice. This is because, as Beitz puts it, “[t]here is no assumption of a prior or independent layer of fundamental rights whose nature and content can be discovered independently of a consideration of the place of human rights in the international realm and its normative discourse and then used to interpret and criticize international doctrine.”8 Naturalistic justifications deny this and claim that a convincing answer to the second question will have to presuppose some answer to the first. An adequate justification of the system of human rights included in the international practice will ultimately have to rely on some appeal to fundamental moral human rights, whose binding force depends neither on their being incorporated into the law nor on their being a suitable object of international concern. 2 This is not to say that there is a one to one relationship between moral human rights and the international rights invoked in the human rights practice, so that our list of international human rights will have to perfectly mirror our list of moral human rights. Naturalistic justifications acknowledge that this is not always the case. For example, they acknowledge that we might justify the existence of an international human right to X, even if we do not have a moral human right to X, provided that implementing an international human right to X is necessary to implement (or at least greatly contributes to the implementation of) an international human right to Y, where it is the international human right Y that is grounded in a human moral right.9 The claim of naturalistic justifications is rather that if the international human right practice is to be justified, there must be a group of fundamental moral rights that the practice ultimately aims to protect, no matter how indirect the relationship between the two is. Call this view the “Priority of the Moral over the Political” (the “Priority of the Moral,” for short).10 To the extent that there is a genuine disagreement between naturalistic and political approaches to the justification of human rights, the disagreement is primarily about whether we should accept this view. In this paper I argue that the Priority of the Moral is harder to dismiss than supporters of political theories of human rights suggest, and that they need to say more in defence of their claim that we can dispense with it. This is because if it is true that human rights play the special role that political theories attribute to them (be that of justifying political legitimacy, limiting state sovereignty or triggering particular responses when violated), there must be something that explains why they can play this role. Naturalistic theories explain this by appealing to the thought that since human rights are grounded in particularly important features of human beings, their protection is urgent and their violation particularly serious. This is why violations of human rights justify interfering with state sovereignty and other forms of international response. Since political theories intend to reject this strategy, they need to say something as 3 to what is instead doing the work within the picture they offer. There must be something special about human rights that explains why their violation triggers reactions that are not warranted when ordinary moral rights are violated or when other wrongs are perpetrated. If it’s not the fact that we have a claim to strong normative protections in relation to particularly important features of human nature, what is it? The paper is in six sections and a conclusion: in the next section, I outline the Priority of the Moral; in sections 3 and 4, I raise a number of objections against political theories of human rights and I argue that it is incumbent upon defenders of these theories to show that they do not surreptitiously appeal to something like the Priority of the Moral. In section 5, I consider the two main objections that seem to have motivated the move from naturalistic to political justifications of human rights. In section 6, I suggest that a variant of naturalistic justification, one that appeals to the notion of basic needs, has the resources to address these two objections. 2. The Priority of the Moral Theories that accept the Priority of the Moral typically proceed in two steps: first, they justify moral human rights by explaining why these rights are particularly important and how they are different from other moral rights; second, they justify international human rights by explaining how they help us protect and implement moral human rights. Their arguments normally take the following form: i. Because of their inherent dignity, human beings are entitled to have a minimally decent life; ii. All human beings, qua human beings, have certain distinguishing features; iii. Given the features specified in ii, human beings can have a minimally decent life only if certain conditions are secured; 4 iv. Given i, ii and iii, human beings have moral rights to what is necessary to secure the conditions specified in iii; v. The best way (or a sufficiently good way) to secure the moral rights specified in iv is by incorporating them in the international human rights practice.11 For example, James Griffin argues that the distinguishing feature of being human is the capacity to act as autonomous moral agents (ii), and that in order to act as autonomous moral agents, we need to be able to freely discuss “whatever goes on in society or government that bears on our thinking and deciding autonomously” (iii).12 This explains why, according to Griffin, there is a moral human right to freedom of expression (iv). And since we have a moral human right to freedom of expression, there is a pro tanto reason to include this right in human rights documents and, more generally, to incorporate it in the current human rights practice, insofar as doing so contributes to its protection and its promotion (v). Vice versa, according to Griffin, in order to act as autonomous moral agents we do not need to be able to choose where to live (as long as the place where we are made to live is sufficiently comfortable), and this explain why there is no human rights to freedom of residence.13 Thus, according to this line of thought, international human rights are justified because they are necessary to (or at least significantly contribute to) securing the fulfilment of moral human rights; and moral human rights are justified insofar as they have a distinctive role that explains their special value: the role of protecting human dignity. Two main objections can be raised against the Priority of the Moral. One consists in rejecting the view formulated as stating a necessary condition for the justification of international human rights. Allen Buchanan, for example, argues that while something like the Priority of the Moral is “by far the clearest strand of justification” for human rights,14 there are a number of further different ways of justifying the existence of a given international legal human right without necessarily relying on moral human rights. For instance, we can appeal to 5 the fact that having such a right prevents great social disutility, or that it contributes to economic prosperity or that it promotes social solidarity. To take an example, these are all grounds on which, according to Buchanan, we can justify a legal right to health care, without necessarily invoking the existence of a moral right to health care.15 In response, we might wonder what the point of calling the right to health care a human right is. Many international legal rights are justified in the way Buchanan suggests, after all, and yet we would not consider them human rights. For instance, because of a directive of the European Parliament, I have a legal right to return a product I have bought on line within seven working days and get a full refund.16 Presumably the justification for this legal right is that it contributes to economic prosperity (by facilitating on line commerce) and prevents social disutility (by reducing the number of potential conflicts between on line buyers and sellers), but we would not want to consider this a human right. This suggests that while it is certainly the case that human rights generally do prevent great social disutility, contribute to economic prosperity and promote social solidarity, this is not enough to justify their existence. One way in which we might be tempted to defend Buchanan’s claim is to argue that while the interests protected by the right to health care are particularly important, those protected by the right to return a product bought on line within seven working days aren’t. Thus, the difference between the two is that the former right contributes much more than the latter to reducing social disutility, increasing economic prosperity etc. But the risk here is that we end up with the view that human rights are simply particularly important moral rights. This conclusion would be problematic because when we employ the language of human rights we normally think that we are pointing at moral considerations that have a distinctive character. We are not simply signalling that the rights in question are important.17 Indeed, if human rights were simply reducible to important rights, we could dispense with the notion altogether, as it would be doing no normative work.18 6 The second line of objection to the Priority of the Moral is more radical, in that it denies that human moral rights play any significant role in justifying international human rights. This is the strategy pursued by political theories. While the latter do not necessarily deny that there are moral rights that individuals have simply by virtue of their humanity, nor do they deny that international human rights are a subset of this class of moral rights, they do deny that these rights are what we should focus on in justifying international human rights. In justifying international human rights we should not look at special features that human beings possess and that international human rights are supposed to protect. Rather, we should look at the international human rights practice, and in particular at the role of those norms and principles that set limits to state sovereignty and establish when certain types of response to state misconduct (by way of formal censure, diplomatic pressure, economic sanctions and, if necessary, armed intervention) are warranted. In the next two sections I will focus on this view. 3. Can we reject the Priority of the Moral? Let’s start by granting to defenders of the political view that the distinguishing feature of human rights is that when these rights are violated the responses described by the political view are warranted, whereas they are not when other forms of injustice take place, including violations of ordinary moral rights. The question I intend to raise is this: On which grounds should the appropriateness of these different reactions be established? Suppose, for example, that we agree with Rawls that the relevant response is triggered when the right to life or the right to liberty is violated but not when the right to political participation is. What we need to know is why the former two rights trigger a different response when they are violated than the one triggered by violations of the latter. Why are violations of the right to political participation to be tolerated in a way in which violations of the right to liberty or the right to life are not? A theory that aims to justify human rights by appealing to 7 the special role that these rights play in triggering the responses at hand, will have to tell us what is so special about human rights that enable them to play this role, which is missing from other rights. But since political approaches want to dispense with the idea that this can be explained by pointing at the fact that there are special features of human nature that human rights protect, what can they appeal to? An answer we might be tempted to give along Rawlsian lines is this: as long as states respect rights such as the right to life or the right to liberty, they are to be tolerated, even if they fail to respect rights such as the right to political participation, because they are “member[s] in good standing of the Society of Peoples.”19 But why should we think that in order to be accepted as members in good standing of the Society of Peoples, a state must respect the former two rights, but need not respect the latter? Again, what is so special about rights like the right to life or the right to liberty that explains why they play a role that cannot be played by the right to political participation? Rawls’ answer is that while liberal societies could tolerate non-liberal “decent” societies that violate rights such as the right to political participation, neither liberal societies nor decent societies would accept to tolerate states that violate rights like the right to liberty or the right to life. In the original position employed at the international level to derive the principles of the Law of Peoples, parties would choose to include a principle that allows tolerating the former but not the latter. Why? Because tolerating violations of the right to liberty or the right to life would pose a threat to international stability, given that states that violate, or fail to protect, these rights are “aggressive and dangerous [and] all peoples are safer and more secure if such states change, or are forced to change, their ways. Otherwise they deeply affect the international climate of power and violence.”20 However, this argument has little plausibility. As proponents of the political view themselves have noticed, it is by no means obvious that oppressive regimes that violate the 8 right to life and the right to liberty of their subjects, will necessarily behave in an aggressive or dangerous ways toward other states and threaten international stability.21 Indeed, typically these states will have particularly strong self-interested reasons to maintain peaceful relationships with other states, if they want to preserve their capacity to perpetrate their unjust regime without interference. Thus, we still need an answer to our question: assuming that the point of international human rights is to specify when certain responses to state action are warranted, we still need to know why violations of human rights justify such responses, whereas violations of other rights (ordinary moral rights) and other forms of injustice don’t. Saying that human rights “express a special class of urgent rights”22 or that they protect “urgent individual interests”23 is not sufficient, unless we know what makes those rights and those interests particularly urgent. And saying that in the original position representatives of peoples would choose not to tolerate violation of these rights, does not help either because what we need to know is, once again, what is so special about these rights that explains why their violation would not be tolerated, whereas violation of ordinary moral rights would be. In reply, two strategies are open to defenders of the political view. First they could refuse to engage with the question and simply point at the practice. They could say: “it just so happens that the current practice of human rights treats violations of a particular class of rights as triggering the relevant response.” According to this reply, there is no need to engage with the more fundamental question of why this set of rights is treated differently. Indeed, there might be no principled reason that explains this fact. It just so happens that this is what the practice is shaped like, and if we want to make sense of the practice as it is, we’ll have to tailor our justification to its features, whatever they are.24 Alternatively, they could reply that there are principled reasons why a particular group of moral rights warrant the relevant response, whereas other moral rights don’t, but these 9 reasons have nothing to do with the existence of special features of human beings that the former protect, contrary to what the Priority of the Moral suggests. Rather, they have to do with what our best principles of international justice require of us, given the particular geopolitical situation of the world in which we find ourselves to operate. According to this version of the political view, we first use our best political theory (or, perhaps, our best theory of international relations) to establish, say, when interference with state sovereignty is justified, 25 and then we simply label “human rights” whichever rights we have identified as warranting interference and “ordinary moral rights” those that do not.26 Both replies seem problematic. The worry with the first one is that it ties the justification of human rights too closely to the current state of the international practice, thereby severely limiting the critical role that a theory of human rights can play in revising and improving the practice itself. To be sure, a theory of human rights so construed could play some critical role, but this would be limited to challenging the internal coherence of the practice. For example, it could challenge the capacity of its norms to advance the aims of the practice, or question the way in which certain aims of the practice seem to be at odds with others.27 What the theory could not do is challenge the way in which the practice is structured on the grounds of its being unjust, or not sufficiently just. This is because there simply are no external standards by which the justice of the practice can be assessed.28 But isn’t providing this sort of criticism an important role, perhaps the most important role, that a theory of human rights should be expected to play? An adequate theory of human rights should help us in revising international law and the global practice of human rights not only in order to make them more coherent, but also to make them more just when they are unjust (or insufficiently just). However, no theory can play this role if in establishing what human rights are and which role they should play, the practice has the first and the last word.29 10 The second strategy does not have the same problem in that it can appeal to external normative standards to assess the justice of the international human rights practice. These standards are provided by our best political theory and our best theory of international relations, which are used to establish when, say, interference with state sovereignty is permitted and under which conditions. But while an improvement over the first strategy, this formulation of the political view also has its problems, which I will consider in the next section. (Henceforth, I will reserve the expression “political view” to refer to this particular formulation of the view.) 4. The political view Consider a hypothetical country run a by tyrannical regime, where fundamental rights such as the right not to be tortured or the right to freely associate are regularly violated. Suppose that this country (call it “Tirannia”) is also a dangerous nuclear power and that any interference with its sovereignty, including formal censure and diplomatic sanctions, would be unjustified on the grounds that the risk of a devastating retaliation would be too high. Should we conclude that the citizens of Tirannia lack the right not to be tortured or the right to freely associate? I take it that we should not. If an important function of a theory of human rights is that of providing grounds on which we can criticize severely unjust practices and institutions, a theory that fails to justify the existence of such rights in cases like the one described in my example, falls short of what an adequate theory should do. Such a theory should be rejected as inadequate. Here defenders of the political view will object that this example misconstrues their position. As both Raz and Beitz make clear, their claim is that human rights violations constitute pro tanto reasons for intervention,30 whereas the Tirannia example is premised on the claim that human rights violations constitute all things considered reasons for intervention. And once formulated as a view about the existence of pro tanto reasons for intervention, the 11 political view seems to offer a plausible answer to the Tirannia case: pro tanto reasons for intervention can be occasionally defeated by competing reasons, and this is why we might have all things considered reasons not to interfere with Tirannia, without being thereby forced to conclude that there is no human right to freely associate which is being violated there. Tirannia’s citizens have a human right to freely associate because there are pro tanto reasons to interfere with Tirannia’s violations of the interests protected by this right, even if these reasons in this case are overridden. This however, brings us back to the question raised in the previous section: on what basis can we establish that there are pro tanto reasons for intervention when the right to freely associate is violated, but not when ordinary moral rights are? The thought underlying the political view formulated as a view about the existence of pro tanto reasons for intervention seems to be something like this: we should consider the weight of the right to freely associate (or perhaps, the weight of the interests protected by the right) and balance it with the weight of national sovereignty. Once we do that, we will see that while the former is greater than the latter, the weight of ordinary moral rights isn’t. This is why protecting ordinary moral rights does not warrant trumping state sovereignty, while protecting human rights does. The cost of interfering with state sovereignty is such that interference is not justified by the need to protect ordinary moral rights, whereas it is justified by the need to protect human rights. My objection however, is that this view can be defended only if we have a principled way of establishing why the weight of human rights is greater than the weight of ordinary moral rights. If the political view is formulated as a view about the all things considered reasons to interfere with state sovereignty, it bypasses this problem by dispensing altogether with the idea that there is a way of distinguishing between human rights and moral rights before we know which ones trigger international response and which don’t. Within this formulation of the view, we first identify the circumstances in which international interference with state sovereignty is 12 justified, and then we simply label “human rights” whichever rights we have identified as warranting interference and “ordinary moral rights” those that do not. But this is not possible if we need to establish the pro tanto force of human rights and ordinary moral rights before we can establish whether interference is justified. If we need to do that, we are back to the problem of establishing why the class of rights we label as “human rights” are weightier than the class of ordinary moral rights. Once again, the obvious way in which we might be tempted to answer this question is by appealing to the fact that these rights protect especially important features of human beings, but this view is not open to those who intend to reject the Priority of the Moral. Thus, the political view faces a choice. If we understand it as a view about the pro tanto force of the reasons for intervention generated by human rights violations, we need to explain in virtue of what human rights are capable of generating these reasons (whereas ordinary moral rights are not). Alternatively, we can understand it as a view about the all things considered force of the reasons for intervention generated by human rights violations, in which case we avoid this question but are forced to accept the implausible conclusion that the citizens of Tirannia lack human rights not to be tortured and to freely associate. Indeed, there is a deeper problem here. I have thus far granted that the idea of a tradeoff between the value of protecting the right to freely associate and the value of respecting national sovereignty is unproblematic, but things are not as straightforward. This is because the trade-off in question does not take place in a vacuum, but in a specific context, and the features of the context will affect the result of the trade-off. Beitz acknowledges this point when he writes that in establishing whether the protection of a given interest qualifies as a human right, we need to take into account not only the urgency of the interest to be protected, but also “various other considerations such as the likelihood that the threat protected against will actually occur, the feasibility of implementing the protection in typical circumstances, and the 13 likely cost of making the protection effective.”31 But how likely it is that the threat will occur, and how feasible and costly it is to protect against it are contingent features. They are contingent on what we take the “typical circumstances” to be. In a world where Tirannia is an exception, or one of very few exceptions, the typical circumstances are such that the interests in freely associating or in not being tortured are not normally threatened. In such a world, the cost and the feasibility of protecting the right to freely associate or the right not to be tortured are likely to be such that interference with states that violate these rights will be justified, and thus there are pro tanto reasons to interfere with Tirannia’s sovereignty. This is a world where, according to Beitz, individuals can be said to have a human right to freely associate or not to be tortured. But that would not be the case in a world in which most states are like Tirannia and only a small number of states respect the right to freely associate or the right not to be tortured of their citizens. For in this other world, the interests in freely associating or in not being tortured are regularly threatened, and the typical circumstances are such that interference with state sovereignty will be costly and unlikely to succeed (unless perhaps the few states respecting the rights in question also happen to be much stronger than the other states). This would be a world in which, given cost and feasibility constraints, there would be no pro tanto reasons for intervention when Tirannia violates its citizens’ rights to freely associate or their right to not be tortured.32 Suppose now that as a consequence of unpredictable events in international politics, more and more states start behaving like Tirannia, so that we end up living in a world largely composed of Tirannia-like states. Should we conclude that now citizens of Tirannia lack the right to freely associate or the right not to be tortured? My view is that we should not. Once again, if an important function of a theory of human rights is that of providing grounds on which we can criticize severely unjust practices and institutions, a theory that fails to justify the existence of such rights in cases like the one described, falls short of what an adequate 14 theory should do. Indeed, we might think that it is all the more important to acknowledge that these rights exist in a world where they are being regularly violated on a massive scale. But here defenders of the political view could reply along the following lines: “it is a sad fact that given that the geopolitical situation has changed and the ‘typical circumstances’ are now such that no intervention can be justified to prevent, punish, or even simply censure the violations of the rights committed in Tirannia. But since this is the case, what would be the point of saying that those rights are human rights?”33 To be sure, the citizens of Tirannia have moral rights not to be tortured and to freely associate, but why should we want to say that these are human rights? The reason cannot be that doing so would justify any sort of intervention against their violation, since the permissibility of such intervention is ruled out ex hypothesi in the case at hand. Why should we care then, about the fact that those rights are classified as human rights? The first thing to notice here is that saying that the typical circumstances in the world described are such that interfering to protect the interest to freely associate or not to be tortured will be too costly or unlikely to succeed, is not of course saying that there are no contexts where interference would be cost-effective and likely to succeed. Suppose that the UK also violated the right not to be tortured or to freely associate of its citizens, and that the UK was one of the very few states where interference would indeed be cost-effective and likely to succeed (because the UK, unlike Tirannia, would not retaliate in an uncontrolled way). It now looks as if we cannot say that those committed in the UK are human rights violations, even if they could be successfully addressed by some kind of international response such as economic or diplomatic sanctions. We cannot say that because in establishing whether the protection of the interest not to be tortured and to freely associate qualify as human rights, we need to take into account the feasibility and the costs of implementing the protection of these interests in typical circumstances. 15 This result seems undesirable. If the value of invoking the language of human rights is that of triggering international intervention, “disabling the defence ‘none of your business’,” 34 we should regret that our theory does not allow human rights to play this role in those circumstances in which they could successfully do so. How much of a problem is this for the political view? Perhaps not much. After all, defenders of the political view typically accept that violations of human rights are a defeasibly sufficient ground for intervention.35 They normally do not claim that they also are necessary conditions for intervention.36 If so, we could say that as long as the theory allows for interference with British sovereignty in order to prevent violations of the right to freely associate or the right not to be tortured committed there, we should not care much about the fact that such intervention is not justified in the language of human rights. But then we might wonder whether we really need the language of human rights at all. Why not simply say that all we need is a good theory of international relations that will tell us when interference with state sovereignty is justified? If nothing of moral significance is lost in dispensing with the language of human rights in the example just discussed, why not also dispense with the language of human rights altogether, even in a world in which the typical circumstances are such that interference will not be too costly and unlikely to succeed? Alternatively, defenders of the political view might wish to argue that there is some distinctive work that the notion of human right is supposed to do, in addition to telling us when certain international responses are justified. In that case, it’s not clear what that work is. Most importantly, we should worry that whatever that work is, it is not being done in the scenario where the right to freely associate is violated in the UK and the world largely consists of Tirannia-like states. A second reply can be offered to the challenge that if the typical circumstances are such that interference with state sovereignty will be too costly and unlikely to succeed, there is no 16 point in calling the rights violated in Tirannia “human rights.” This consists in rejecting the claim that the value of human rights is exhausted by their capacity to trigger the sort of responses described by the political view. More generally, we should reject, I think, the claim that the value of human rights can be reduced to the instrumental role they play in protecting important interests of their holders. To be sure, this is an important component of their justification, but not the only one. In addition to that, human rights are justified because of their non-instrumental value: they express the value of right holders as beings of a certain sort. As Thomas Nagel puts it, they “express a particular conception of the kind of place that should be occupied by individuals in a moral system–how their lives, actions, and interests should be recognized by the system of justification and authorization that constitute morality. … They embody a form of recognition of the value of each individual.”37 Elsewhere, I develop this suggestion by appealing to Jean Hampton’s idea that certain actions ‘morally injure’ their victims by treating them in a way which is precluded by their value.38 These actions represent the value of their victims as less than the value that they possess, because the actions in question deny the entitlements which are generated by that value and which expresses its presence. This is what violations of human rights do. Not only do they harm their victims by setting back important interests of theirs, but they also deny that the victims possess the status of human being, to the extent that they treat them as if they did not have the basic protections that go with possessing that status.39 If this is correct, there is a point in wanting the rights violated in Tirannia to be recognized as human rights even if, given the contingent circumstances of the geopolitical situation in which they are perpetrated, their violation cannot justifiably trigger the sort of response invoked by the political view. To acknowledge that the citizens of Tirannia have human rights and that those rights are being violated, is to mark the fact that they do have the moral status of human beings, and that this status is being disrespected. Failing to attribute 17 human rights to them is failing to acknowledge this important fact, thereby failing to recognize their value. This wrong is additional to the one produced by the fact that certain urgent interests of theirs have been set back. 5. Two problems with the naturalistic approach I have argued that in order to assess the plausibility of the political approach to the justification of human rights, we need to know how this approach can justify the claim that human rights can play the special function that is commonly attributed to them, without relying on the idea that these are moral rights that protect (and give expression to) particularly important features of human beings. It is incumbent upon defenders of the political approach to offer an argument of this sort in order show that they do not surreptitiously appeal to something like the Priority of the Moral. My own view is that the naturalistic approach is more promising. Not only does it offer a straightforward answer to the question of why human rights can play the special function that is commonly attributed to them, but it seems better placed to account for the link between human rights and human dignity, which plays a crucial role in many of the most important human rights documents. To name but a few, the Preamble of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights famously refers to the “inherent dignity and … equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family,” stating that “[a]ll human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights,” whereas both the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) explicitly make the point that that human rights “derive from the inherent dignity of the human person.” Of course, I am not suggesting that these observations are enough to conclude that the practice of human rights is consistently organized around the idea of natural rights that human 18 beings possess simply by virtue of their humanity and that protect their dignity. Preambles to human rights documents are often seen, no doubt with good reason, as rhetorical exercises, whose wording and content is largely conditioned by political pressure and the need for compromise.40 But it would be hard to deny that the idea of human dignity does play a significant role within the practice of human rights, and thus it’s hard to see how this idea can be easily dismissed by the political view, given that the main motivation of the latter is to be faithful to the practice. Similarly, it is puzzling that a view which aims to be faithful to the international practice of human rights would tie the existence of these rights to the presence of reasons for intervention, be those reasons pro tanto or all things considered. When human rights activists campaign against violations of the right to free-speech in North Korea, they take their actions to be justified by the fact that there is a human right to free-speech; they do not believe that the human right exist because their actions are justified.41 These observations seem to support, at least to some extent, the picture of the justification of human rights articulated by naturalistic theories that adopt the Priority of the Moral. We might wonder then why so many philosophers tend to reject the naturalistic approach. A number of objections have been raised against the latter, but two in particular seem to have motivated the move toward the political view. One is the thought that grounding human rights in human dignity, and in the natural rights that are supposed to protect human dignity, inevitably ties the justification of these rights to a set of controversial metaphysical and moral assumptions about human nature. This is considered problematic because human rights should not be the expression of a particular conception of the good. If they were, it would be harder to resist the objection that the human rights discourse is ultimately a way of imposing Western liberal values on cultures that subscribe to alternative, but equally reasonable, conceptions of the good. 19 For example, if like James Griffin, we ground the justification of human rights in the value of moral autonomy, our account will be unacceptable to non-liberal cultures that do not attribute to this value the importance which is accorded to it within liberal societies. Rawls for one, seems to be moved by this sort of considerations in developing his version of the political view.42 The second main objection that has prompted some philosophers to adopt the political view concerns the potentially over-inclusive character of naturalistic accounts with respect to the content of our list of human rights. Raz, for example, points out that there is no reason to expect the human right that we have simply by virtue of our humanity to be necessarily important rights.43 The right not to be pinched, or the right not to be betrayed in personal relations seem to be universal moral rights that all human beings have in virtue of their humanity, 44 but they lack the importance typical of human rights. If naturalistic theories were committed to the conclusion that these are genuine human rights, they would be incapable of accounting for the common view that only important rights can be human rights. Defenders of the naturalistic approach have tried to address these objections, but with mixed results. For example, in addressing the first problem, Griffin has defended his claim that a distinctively human life is one in which we can act as autonomous moral agents by arguing that “[a]nyone who thinks seriously about the value of our status as normative [i.e. autonomous] agents … will recognize that … [it is] highly important;” and that “[e]veryone, on pain of mistake, has to admit that autonomy [is] highly valuable.” 45 This answer however, can be hardly considered satisfactory. No matter how sensitive we are to the importance of moral autonomy, the claim that anyone who chooses to structure his life around the importance of non-liberal traditions and values, rather than around autonomy, thereby fails to live a distinctively human life, seems too extreme.46 In addressing the second objection, John Tasioulas bites the bullet and acknowledges that 20 we do have human moral rights not to be pinched and not to be betrayed in personal relationships, but he hastens to add that there are obvious reasons not to have corresponding legal human rights for them. In the case of the former, because the right not to be pinched is not sufficiently important to warrant legal recognition; in the case of the latter, because human rights documents “include only those human rights that are genuinely under threat and regarding which preventative and remedial action by the state is both legitimate and potentially effective.”47 However, this move also seems unpersuasive, since what is implausible (and what critics of the naturalistic view correctly object to) is not only the idea that the right not to be pinched or the right not to be betrayed could be legal human rights, but also the idea that they could be moral human rights. While the view that all human beings, qua human beings, have a moral right not to be pinched or not to be betrayed does not seem necessarily implausible, the view that these are human rights does, as we normally think that only particularly important moral rights should qualify as human rights. In order to be convincing, a formulation of the naturalistic view will have to be able to address these two problems. It must show that it does not rely on the adoption of values that belong exclusively to a particular conception of the good, and it must show that it is not overinclusive with respect to the content of the list of human rights that it generates (i.e. that it does not classify as human rights moral rights that all human beings have simply by virtue of their humanity, but that are not sufficiently important). In the next section, I will outline a variant of the naturalistic view that seems promising on both counts. 6. The basic-needs view Recall the formulation of the naturalistic view introduced above: 21 i. Because of their inherent dignity, human beings are entitled to have a minimally decent life; ii. All human beings, qua human beings, have certain distinguishing features; iii. Given the features specified in ii, human beings can have a minimally decent life only if certain conditions are secured; iv. Given i, ii and iii, human beings have moral rights to what is necessary to secure the conditions specified in iii. v. The best way (or a sufficiently good way) to secure the moral rights specified in iv is by incorporating them in the international human rights practice. My aim here is to consider the justification of moral human rights, so I will focus on the first four steps of the argument. The question is how best to account for the relationship between the notion of human dignity, the idea of a minimally decent life and the distinctive features of human beings that need to be protected in order to have a minimally decent life. Probably the most influential answer to this question is the one that appeals to the idea that the main constituent of human dignity is the capacity to act as autonomous moral agents. According to this view, whose most prominent defender is James Griffin, the distinctive feature of human beings on which we should focus in order to make sense of the idea of a minimally decent human life is the capacity to autonomously choose a plan of life and successfully pursue it. Thus, human rights are to be justified by appealing to the thought that they protect the capacity to act in this way by protecting the conditions necessary to form and successfully pursue a plan of life. We have already seen that one problem with this view is that it struggles to account for the idea that human rights should not be the expression of a particular conception of the good. The view however, also presents a second crucial problem, namely its being under-inclusive 22 with respect to the class of human rights bearers. The problem here is that insofar as human rights are justified by appealing to the idea that they protect the capacity to act as autonomous moral agents, whoever lacks such capacity, for example children or the severely mentally disable, cannot be said to have human rights. This conclusion however, is problematic for two reasons. To begin with, there is an issue of internal coherence. Insofar as the view is meant to ground human rights in our nature of human beings, it is puzzling that some human beings would be left out. As Raz puts it, “one abandons the idea that human rights derive from our humanity once one says that babies or people with Down’s syndrome do not have (certain) human rights.”48 Moreover, the view seems inadequate insofar as common sense morality as well as the law unequivocally assume that both children and the severely mentally disable do have human rights. Indeed, not only do both groups regularly appeal to the human rights listed in human rights documents such as the ICCPR and the ICESCR, but there are also special documents, such as the Convention on the Rights of the Child and the Declaration on the Rights of Disabled Persons, which are meant specifically to protect the human rights of these two groups. Of course the fact that the autonomy-based view fails to account for the existence of these rights would not be a problem if a convincing case could be made as to why children and the severely mentally disable should not have human rights, but no such argument is offered by the view. The only reasons to exclude these subjects from the class of human rights bearer seems to be that the rationale identified by the autonomy-based view is not able to justify their inclusion. A more promising formulation of the naturalistic view is the one that instead of appealing to our capacity to act as autonomous moral agents, grounds human rights in certain basic needs that we have as human beings. By “basic needs” I mean things like food, air, water, shelter, a minimum level of health and a minimal level of social interaction. The sense in which 23 these needs are basic is that having the opportunity to meet them is the bare minimum required in order to function as human beings, whereas failing to have this opportunity normally compromises our capacity to have a minimally decent life. The basic-needs account and autonomy-based accounts share two central premises: first, human dignity is respected when the conditions for a minimally decent life are not undermined; second, the function of human rights is to protect the conditions for a minimally decent life, thereby protecting human dignity. But while for the autonomy-based account a minimally decent life is one in which we can act as autonomous moral agents, for the basic needs account a minimally decent life is one in which we have the opportunity to fulfil a core group of biological, psychological, as well as social needs. Thus, while for autonomy-based account, the justification of human rights consists in the fact that they protect the capacity to act as autonomous moral agents, for the basic needs account it consists in the fact that they protect the opportunity to have these basic needs met.49 One advantage of this account is that it avoids the objection of being under-inclusive with respect to the class of human rights bearers. For while some human beings lack the capacity for autonomous agency, all human beings, including children and the severely mentally disabled, have the basic needs listed above. But the basic needs account also avoids grounding human rights on a set of controversial metaphysical and moral assumptions about human nature. The claim that human beings need things like food, shelter, a minimum level of health and a minimal level of social interaction does not depend on some controversial metaphysical view about human nature, nor does it depend on the adoption of a particular conception of the good. Far from it, having the option to meet our basic needs is a precondition for the pursuit of any conception of the good. Thus, the basic needs view avoids the first of the two main objections raised against naturalistic approaches. The view however, is also well equipped to deal with the second 24 objection, namely the alleged incapacity of naturalistic approaches to account for the fact that only important moral rights can be human rights. Given that the basic needs view grounds the justification of human rights on those needs which we must have an opportunity to fulfil in order to have a minimally decent life, this automatically rules out any candidate whose importance does not meet this threshold. According to this view, neither the right not to be pinched, nor the right not to be betrayed in personal relationships are plausible candidates for human rights. Obviously, more needs to be said to develop the basic needs view.50 My aim in this section was only to show that the view has the resources to address the two main worries raised against naturalistic theories of human rights. If I am right, some of the pressure to move toward a political justification of human rights will be removed. 7. Conclusion The aim of this paper has been to articulate the view I have labelled the “Priority of the Moral”, whose adoption is the main point of contention between naturalistic and political theories of human rights. I have argued that this view is harder to dismiss than political theories suggest, and that before we can assess the plausibility of these theories, they need to say more in defence of their claim that they can do without it. It is incumbent upon political theories of human rights to show that they do not surreptitiously appeal to something like the Priority of the Moral. I then considered the two main objections that seem to have motivated many philosophers to abandon the naturalistic approach to the justification of human rights in favour of the political one. I have suggested that a variant of naturalistic justification, the basic needs account, has the resources to address these objections. If so, the basic needs account warrants further examination as a promising model for the justification of human rights. 51 25 1 John Tasioulas, “The Moral Reality of Human Rights,” in Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor?, ed. Thomas Pogge (Oxford: OUP, 2007), 75; Charles R. Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights (Oxford: OUP, 2009), ix; Joseph Raz, “Human Rights Without Foundations,” in The Philosophy of International Law, ed. Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas (Oxford: OUP, 2010), 321. 2 Allen Buchanan notices this ambiguity in his recent book The Heart of Human Rights (Oxford: OUP, 2013), 10- 11. 3 James Griffin, On Human Rights (Oxford: OUP, 2008); David Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice (Oxford: OUP, 2007); David Miller, “Grounding Human Rights,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15 (2012): 407–27; John Tasioulas, “On the Foundations of Human Rights,” in Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, ed. Rowan Cruft, S. Matthew Liao, and Massimo Renzo (Oxford: OUP, 2015), 45-70). 4 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 2002); Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights; Raz, “Human Rights Without Foundations”; Joseph Raz, “Human Rights in the Emerging World Order,” Transnational Legal Theory 1 (2010): 31–47; Joshua Cohen, The Arc of the Moral Universe and Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2010), chap. 9, 10. It is worth mentioning that Rawls does not focus so much on the practice of international human rights, but on the way in which the foreign policy of liberal societies should be organized. 5 See below, pp. __ 6 Some draw the distinction between naturalistic and political justifications of human rights in a different way. According to Pablo Gilabert, naturalistic justifications are those that identify human rights with claims that individuals have against each other, whereas political justifications are those that that identify human rights with claims that individuals have against specific institutional structures, such as governments or states (Pablo Gilabert, “Humanist and Political Perspectives on Human Rights,” Political Theory 39 (2011): 439–467, at pp. 439-440). According to Allen Buchanan, naturalistic approaches are interested in the justification of moral rights, whereas political ones are interested in the justification of international legal rights (Allen Buchanan, “Human Rights,” in The Oxford Handbook of Political Philosophy, ed. David Estlund, (New York: OUP, 2012), 279–97, at pp. 2801). Both these characterizations seem to me misleading. In response to Gilabert, it is worth noticing that defenders of the naturalistic approach do sometimes subscribe to the view that human rights are primarily held not against individuals but against states or governments (e.g. Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice). In response to Buchanan, we should notice that political approaches are not exclusively interested in the question of legal 26 rights. They are open to the idea that certain human rights are justified because they trigger specific responses by given agents operating at the international level, but should not become legal rights. As Beitz makes clear, the “repertoire of strategies of action that might be open to these various agents is heterogeneous, ranging from the legal to the political and from the coercive to the persuasive and consensual” (Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, 198. See also pp. 38-41). 7 Remember that I am here using the expression “moral human rights” as a term of art to refer to important moral rights that can be attributed to human beings simply in virtue of their human nature. 8 Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, 102. 9 James W. Nickel, Making Sense of Human Rights (Malden, MA; Oxford: Blackwell Pub., 2007). 10 Buchanan calls this the “mirroring view” (Buchanan, The Heart of Human Rights; Allen Buchanan, “Why International Legal Human Rights?,” in Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, ed. Cruft, Liao, and Renzo, 244-262). I prefer to avoid this label because it suggests that our list of human rights will have to mirror our list of moral rights. This is not true for the reasons mentioned in the text. I should stress that Buchanan is aware of the problem and does not intend to invite this misunderstanding. However, the label he chooses seems to encourage it, as do some of Buchanan formulations (for example, his referring to the existence of a “corresponding moral right” when discussing a particular human right). 11 This is how theories that subscribe to the Priority of the Moral normally proceed. However, accepting the Priority of the Moral does not commit one to accept i-v. The Priority of the Moral simply states that human rights are ultimately grounded in a group of fundamental moral rights that individuals possess simply by virtue of their humanity. 12 Griffin, On Human Rights, 240. 13 Ibid., 195–6. 14 Buchanan, “Human Rights,” 281. 15 Buchanan, “Why International Legal Human Rights?” 16 Directive 97/7/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council of 20 May 1997 on the protection of consumers in respect of distance contracts. 17 As Griffin correctly points out, matters of justice can be important without thereby being matters of human rights. His example (which he brings up in the context of his discussion of fairness) is that of two top executives who are equally competent and efficient, but receive different pay in virtue of the fact that one of them is related 27 to the company’s CEO. While a significant injustice, this does not seem to be a human rights violation (Griffin, On Human Rights, 41–2). 18 Of course, saying that the notion of human rights should be abandoned by philosophers is not saying that it should also be abandoned by human rights activists, lawyers and politicians. To the extent that appealing to the rhetoric of human rights helps these actors to prevent serious harm and further the cause of justice, they are justified in doing so, but the existence of human rights could not be vindicated in this way any more than the existence of the tooth fairy could be vindicated by appealing to the value of tooth fairy talk for the well-being of children. 19 Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 67. One way to challenge the claim that respect for human rights is the criterion for membership in the Society of People is to point out that Rawls does not grant membership to what he calls “benevolent absolutisms,” i.e. regimes where human rights are respected out of the benevolence of the rulers, but not legally guaranteed. (Thanks to Yann Allard-Tremblay for pressing this point.) Different strategies can be employed to resist this challenge. Some argue that the exclusion of benevolent absolutisms is unwarranted: to the extent that benevolent absolutisms respect human rights, they should be recognized as members in good standing of the Society of Peoples, alongside liberal and decent societies (Kok-Chor Tan, Toleration, Diversity, and Global Justice (Penn State Press, 2010), 38.). Others explain the fact that benevolent absolutisms should be treated differently by appealing to the idea that what warrants membership in the Society of Peoples is robust respect for human rights, i.e. respect “guaranteed by stable institutional constraints” (Laura Valentini, Justice in a Globalized World (Oxford: OUP, 2011), 82). These complications can be bracketed for the purposes of this paper, but see David Reidy, “Political Authority and Human Rights,” in Rawls’s Law of Peoples, ed. Rex Martin and David Reidy (Blackwell, 2006), 169–88, for an interesting discussion of the problem. 20 Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 81. 21 Charles R. Beitz, “Rawls’s Law of Peoples,” Ethics 110 (2000): 669–696, at p. 685. 22 Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 79. 23 Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, 110. 24 At least at times, Beitz seems to be taking this view (Ibid., 10–2, 104–6). 25 As I mention above, the role that political approaches attribute to human rights within the international practice is not limited to justifying interference with state sovereignty. It might be argued that the distinctive role of human rights is rather to set conditions for the legitimate authority of states. (According to this view, states lose their power to create moral obligations for their subjects when they violate or fail to protect human rights). In the rest 28 of the paper, I will focus on the role of human rights as triggers for international intervention but my arguments will apply mutatis mutandis to views that understand them as benchmarks of political legitimacy. 26 Raz defends a version of this view. 27 Ibid., 103. 28 Beitz seems aware of this problem and makes clear that we should not simply assume that the human rights practice should be treated as morally binding. Whether we have reasons to treat it in this way is a question to be examined in its own right (Ibid., 11). 29 But see Andrea Sangiovanni, “Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality,” Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (2008): 137–164, for an interesting attempt to defend the idea of a critique “immanent to the practice,” one that does not presuppose the existence of pre-institutional standards of justice. 30 31 32 Raz, “Human Rights Without Foundations,” 328; Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, 109, 115–20. Ibid., 110, italics mine. For a discussion of how the presence and the strength of pro tanto reasons can be identified in this context, see Andrea Sangiovanni, “Beyond the Political-Orthodox Divide: The Broad View,” in Human Rights: Moral or Political?. ed. Adam Etinson (Oxford: OUP, 2015). 33 I am grateful to Joseph Raz for pressing this point in conversation. 34 This is how Raz characterizes the political view in his “Human Rights Without Foundations,” 322. 35 Ibid., 328. 36 Particularly if we follow Raz and Beitz (as I think we should) in understanding human rights as triggers not only for military intervention but also for weaker responses (such as diplomatic sanctions and acts of formal censure), the view that violations of human rights are a necessary condition for such responses seems implausible. Suppose, for example, that Italy decided to allow the torture of non-human animals, or the destruction of all its art collections. If so, international intervention by way of formal censure would be permissible, although no human rights would be violated. 37 Thomas Nagel, “Personal Rights and Public Space,” in Concealment and Exposure (New York: OUP, 2002), 31–52, at pp. 33-4. The view that rights can have this sort of non-instrumental value is also defended by Frances Kamm and Warren Quinn (F. M. Kamm, Intricate Ethics (New York: OUP, 2007), chap.7.8; Warren Quinn, Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), chap. 7). 38 Jean Hampton, The Intrinsic Worth of Persons (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007), chap. 4. 29 39 Massimo Renzo, “Human Needs, Human Rights,” in Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, ed. Cruft, Liao, and Renzo, 570-587. In this paper, I defend the view that human rights in addition to having instrumental value, also have non-instrumental value. John Tasioulas pursues a similar strategy, since his justification for human rights appeals both to interests (though these interests for Tasioulas are not limited to the opportunity to fulfil basic needs) and to the importance of human status; John Tasioulas, “Human Rights, Legitimacy and International Law,” American Journal of Jurisprudence, 58 (2013): 1-25, at 53-6. 40 The different roles that the notion of human dignity can play as a foundation of human rights are examined in Jeremy Waldron, “Is Dignity the Foundation of Human Rights?,” in Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, ed. Cruft, Liao, and Renzo, 117-137. 41 I should make clear that in my view, naturalistic accounts are also constrained by the requirement of being sufficiently faithful to the practice of human rights as we know it. However, these accounts can be more revisionary given that the practice does not play a central role in how they approach the questions of the nature and the justification of human rights. Since the practice plays such a role within the political view, it is particularly troubling for this view when its implications are at odds with the practice. 42 Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 68. 43 Raz, “Human Rights Without Foundations,” 323. 44 I borrow these examples from John Tasioulas, “On the Nature of Human Rights,” in The Philosophy of Human Rights Contemporary Controversies, ed. Gerhard Ernst and Jan-Christoph Heilinger (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2012), 17–59. 45 Griffin, On Human Rights, 133. 46 Renzo, “Human Needs, Human Rights,” 575-6. 47 Tasioulas, “On the Nature of Human Rights,” 40. 48 Raz, “Human Rights Without Foundations,” 323. 49 The reason why the basic needs account require that we have the opportunity to have our basic needs met, as opposed to requiring that those needs are actually met, is that people can decide not to avail themselves of the opportunity without failing for this reason to have a minimally decent life. To see this point, contrast the case of someone who decides to join a religious order that requires her not to live a certain building with the case of someone who is forced not to leave the same building against her will. 50 I further defend the basic needs view in my paper “Human Needs, Human Rights.” The philosopher who has done most to develop the view is David Miller (Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice, chap. 7; Miller, 30 “Grounding Human Rights”). The view overlaps to some extent with the capabilities approach defended by Martha Nussbaum (Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011) and Amartya Sen (“Elements of a Theory of Human Rights,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32 (2004): 315–56). 51 I am grateful to Alejandro Chehtman, Rowan Cruft, Pablo Gilabert, Simon Hope, Carmen Pavel, Andrea Sangiovanni, David Schmidtz, Laura Valentini and two anonymous referees for very helpful comments. Thanks also to audiences at Oxford, McGill, Carleton, Monash, and at the workshop organized by Social Philosophy and Policy for stimulating discussions. Part of the work on this article was conducted at the School of Philosophy of the Australian National University. 31