MONTCLAIR STATE UNIVERSITY Implicature in Legal Proceedings as a Pragmatic Strategy APLN 605 – LINGUISTICS RESEARCH PROJECT Roger Cunningham 5/7/2014 Advisor: Dr. Longxing Wei Readers: Dr. Susana Sotillo Dr. Fadi Hilani Abstract This paper explores how U.S. Supreme Court justices and lawyers use conversational implicatures in oral arguments about a case to help provide legal content while explaining those contents relationship to the case. They also use implicatures to converse with each other, to float theories about the eventual disposition of the case. It considers whether implicatures used by a justice can generally be related to ideological positions, or signal their final voting position on a case. Two cases were studied and the results initially show positive results. Conversational implicature analysis may be useful as a predictor of judicial voting in a case. It does provide a short-hand means for conveying relevant legal content and theory, which is useful for information-gathering by justices. The results suggest more research could be useful. 1. Introduction This paper observes the discourse between lawyers and justices in transactions at the Supreme Court of the United States (SCOTUS). It applies S. C. Levinson’s Implicature theory to the oral arguments of judges and lawyers in SCOTUS. It assesses if justices use implicature to signal views on a case, as well as manage, questions of Law, facts, subjective positions, aspects of politeness/impoliteness and interactions with other justices. Two recent SCOTUS cases concerning the subject of marriage ( Hollingsworth v. Perry., 570 US, 2013 and U.S. v. Windsor., 570 U.S., 2013), are considered. In these cases, lawyers and justices debated the question of marriage between individuals of the same gender. The paper looks at whether judges speak in a Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 1 legal perspective of neutrality, fact-finding, reasoning or in a judgmental perspective of false-neutrality, ideology and unequal law. 1.1. SCOTUS and the Law Pragmatics has paid much attention to the concept labeled implicature, but little to its applicability to Law, and especially the commentary and decisions of SCOTUS, the United States’ highest court. SCOTUS has a major role in the U.S. Federal Government as its third branch. It plays a significant role in Americans’ daily life because its decisions have far-reaching social effects. Analysts pay attention to SCOTUS’ final written court opinions, but little to the spoken medium of court argument, even though the standard one-hour, per case of oral argument is the only public aspect of SCOTUS’ proceedings. SCOTUS’ functions are otherwise secret, including its decision-making processes. The nine justices are only publically seen together during oral arguments of a case. One would think there are links between the formal, written language of court opinions and the preceding medium of spoken argument. These links are important, although SCOTUS’ justices have offered differing views about the oral argument process. Chief Justice Earl Warren did not see oral argument as important, while one of his successors, William Rehnquist, did. To quote specific instances, Justice John Harlan of SCOTUS wrote: …the job of courts…is to search out the truth, both as to facts and the law, and that is ultimately the job of the lawyers too. And in that joint effort, the oral argument gives an opportunity for interchange between court and counsel which the briefs do not…. (O’Brien, 1997, 100). Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 2 Justice Clarence Thomas of SCOTUS offers another viewpoint: …I don’t see the need for all those questions. I think Justices 99 percent of the time, have their minds made up when they go to the bench…. (Rombeck, 2002, B5). The legal community’s general view is that oral argument in SCOTUS proceedings isn’t critical. Before the time of argument, SCOTUS judges have received the briefs of each side to the case, as well as any amici curiae briefs, and it is commonly believed the justices have carefully studied these and the details of the case . This leads to conclusions such as Justice Thomas’ that the Justices come to this public hearing with individual decisions already made. However, there has been research arguing against this view, e.g. T.R. Johnson’s work using Justice Blackmun’s private papers and evaluations of oral arguments: We further show that the probability of a justice voting for a litigant increases dramatically if that litigant’s lawyer presents better oral arguments than the competing counsel. (Johnson, 2006, 99). The idea that pragmatics offers tools to analyze the use of language in law and such specific institutions as SCOTUS, is a developing one. Lawyers have extensively studied the language of law but in written forms like SCOTUS decisions. In recent decades, linguists and pragmatic analysts have looked at legal issues and proceedings, emphasizing concepts of language, among them, implicature. But they’ve not studied SCOTUS proceedings. Why are inferences important to communication and understanding speech? Because as Levinson puts it: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 3 …language is sketchy….The fastest sustainable speech rate for English is about 7 syllables per second…This encoding bottleneck implies that linguistic coding is ‘expensive’ and inference is ‘cheap’, and the design requirements for human communication are: minimize linguistic coding and maximize inference. (Levinson, 2012, 212). Lawyers use verbal and non-verbal behavior, plus specialized vocabulary, to accomplish their goal of winning a case, using language tactics without necessarily realizing the pragmatic language background. One question becomes, does this create particular implicatures? Certainly legal actions involve pragmatic concepts, such as deixis, implicature, presupposition, or speech acts, that are part of a definition of pragmatics. 1.2. Pragmatics and Implicature Pragmatic theories have been studied in courts and trials lower in the U.S. legal system’s hierarchy than SCOTUS, which is at the pinnacle. Or they’ve been applied in Forensic linguistics to the competing voices and relations found in working trial courtrooms -- for example, the cross-examining lawyer who asks a witness in rapid fire, stressing certain words: a) Did you drink? b) Did you or didn’t you drink some alcohol? The first question implies to a listener (in American English, and context) the liquid of alcohol. In b), the lawyer further presupposes an answer with the use of some (instead of speaking neutral words like “…any alcohol…”). And there is the forceful, accusatory tone used in these yes/no questions – question forms which allow the person answering little leeway in the answer. Cultural context and differences are Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 4 important in law. The English, common-law system emphasizes adversarial relationships, while the Napoleonic system emphasizes the use of trained judges and an inquisitorial approach. These differences also mean there would be important pragmatic differences to consider. This paper tries to determine if certain pragmatic strategies, especially implicature theory, can be used to assess SCOTUS conversations during oral argument, which might provide a new way to understand the actions of, and interactions between, SCOTUS justices. Such pragmatic analysis might also give us better insights into predicting the outcome of cases. Pragmatics is a broad field of linguistics. A short definition is: Pragmatics is the systematic study of meaning by virtue of, or dependent on, the use of language. The central topics of inquiry of pragmatics include implicature, presupposition, speech acts and deixis. (Huang, 2007, 2). The key concepts of implicature are important to communication in terms of what, and how is, meaning actually communicated. Inferences help fill the gaps in our communication, e.g. Where’s my drink? On the top shelf. Here the addressee makes an inferential, logical step to understand the speaker’s intention, +> The drink is on the top shelf. An implicature is found in the remark, I toured Dedham’s square. The courthouse was impressive. Here the inference is a new but logical thought, viz. there is a courthouse in Dedham’s square. This specialized language and knowledge of meaning requires some discussion of concept and its background in the discipline of pragmatics. It has received a great deal of attention over the years since its origin in 1967 with the work of H. P. Grice. Grice’s Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 5 idea has as a primary concept the Co-operative principle, with a subdivision of nine conversational maxims split into four categories. Using Huang’s simplification of these, the key implicature properties of a conversation involve: a. The co-operative principle -- Be co-operative. b. The maxims of conversation – 1) Quality: Be truthful i. Don’t say what is false. ii. Don’t say what lacks evidence. 2) Quantity: i. Don’t say less than is required. ii. Don’t say more than is required. 3) Relation: Be relevant. 4) Manner: Be perspicuous. i. Avoid obscurity. ii. Avoid ambiguity. iii. Be brief. iv. Be orderly. (Huang, 2007, 26). A common example of Grice’s implicature involves the conjunction but, which joins and additionally implies a contrast between the compound sentence parts. a. He is poor but honest. (Implicature tells us there is some contrast between these two states, i.e. it is surprising that one finds someone poor but also honest.) b. He is poor and honest. (There is no contrast between these states of being and no inference is to be made.) Considering the above, there is a required inferential meaning to be made by the listener hearing the conjunction but; one cannot hear, He is poor but honest, and believe the speaker means there is no distinction between being poor and honest. This ties to certain properties of implicature which Grice spelled out: cancelability, calculability and non-detachability, which are evident in the above examples, e.g. the conjunction but Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 6 involves non-cancelability since the implicature is part of the semantic content of the word, but. Grice’s theories have evolved as pragmatists have advanced them. One main line of revision has been to reduce the numerous parts of Gricean implicature. One main reductionist model has been the Levinsonian theory. Another model is Sperber and Wilson’s Relevance theory, which expands Gricean theory via work in cognitive linguistics, establishing a linguistic theory that considers explicature and implicature; it also revises the approach to how a listener determines the speaker’s intended meaning, the most salient meaning. Both of these theories are discussed in Part III. The remainder of this paper is organized as follows: Part II discusses the research goal in more detail. Part III discusses background on SCOTUS, its oral arguments, and fleshes out pragmatic ideas and implicature approaches. It reviews the SCOTUS data available for research. Part IV covers the SCOTUS cases and deals with implicature examples. The final part provides conclusions and discusses issues of more research. 2. Research Problem and Objective “Objectivity” in law is an essential concept of the American legal system. Of course, defining that term requires some subjectivity since there is no standard or Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 7 universally accepted meaning for “objectivity”. So that becomes the first problem to address. The second problem is to discover if there actually is some sense of subjectivity (i.e. ideology and/or political choice) found in judicial conversation, in the forms of Questions and Answers, or the speech judges and lawyers use, where the Gricean idea of “What is said.” and “What is implicated.” can help us understand the proceedings? Can inferences be found that reflect ideological assumptions that may underlie the eventual court decisions? Possibly implicature can be used to clarify what objectivity/subjectivity factors exist in judicial thinking. Such examination may show that attitudinal factors – ideology – can be found which are more important than the “law” (i.e. the legal principles or doctrines, what the legal text of statutues or Constitutions say ). The two cases studied involve social conflict. While the situations were different, both cases were associated with the notion of same-sex marriage, i.e. legally recognized marriage between individuals of the same gender. The opinion in Windsor (written by Justice Kennedy and joined by four others) concerned the struggle over federal benefits for same-sex couples under the federal Defense of Marriage Act. The majority (five justices) found the statute violated the Fifth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution, thus allowing benefits to be extended. The majority opinion in Hollingsworth (written by Chief Justice Roberts) concerned a federal judicial ruling invalidating a state constitutional amendment in California – Prop. 8 . The majority decided that the petitioners had no legal standing to appeal the ruling. The decision rested on a legal Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 8 technicality of jurisdiction rather than broader legal doctrines. Its effect was to allow California to recognize same-sex marriages. The two 5-4 decisions were issued together, with the Windsor case’s majority made up of Justice Kennedy plus the four justices usually labeled the liberal wing of the court. The Hollingsworth majority, however, was made up of an unusual group of justices, two conservatives plus three liberals. This may reflect the nature of the technical legality involved. These cases, given their different outcomes, offer the opportunity to consider the communications of these judges and their language as they might suggest the outcomes. Looking at Gricean and Relevance theory and, more specifically, the Levinsonian neo-Gricean theory with principles of Q(uantity) – I(nformativeness) – M(anners), this paper investigates how these pragmatic ideas can be used to evaluate the language used in SCOTUS discourse. Especially important is the I-principle, which Levinson states as: Speaker’s maxim: …Say as little as necessary; that is, produce the minimal linguistic information sufficient to achieve your communicational ends…. Recipient’s corollary:…Amplify the informational content of the speaker’s utterance by finding the most specific interpretation, up to what you judge to be the speaker’s m-intended (= meaning-intended) point….Specifically: i. Assume the richest temporal, causal and referential connections between described situations or events, consistent with what is taken for granted. ii. Assume that stereotypical relations obtain…. iii. Avoid interpretations that multiply entities referred to…; prefer coreferential readings of reduced NPs…. iv. Assume the existence or actuality of what a sentence is about….(Levinson, 2000, 114-115). Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 9 Levinson’s I-principle is, simply put, say enough to be informative. For example, if one says, I think he is an intellectual, an I-implicature to be drawn (based on context) is that other people may not think he’s an intellectual. Also note that what is not said, can also be informative. How do Levinson’s principles work? How are they evidenced in SCOTUS discourse? How do the judges and lawyers know their implied meanings will be recovered by their listeners? Two key principles of the Relevance theory interact with this last question: i. …behavior provides evidence of one’s thoughts. It succeeds in doing so because it implies a guarantee of relevance. It implies such a guarantee because humans automatically turn their attention to what seems most relevant to them….and that this fact…makes manifest the intention…. (Sperber and Wilson, 1995, 50). ii. In aiming at relevance, the speaker must make some assumptions about the hearer’s cognitive abilities and contextual resources, which will necessarily be reflected in the way she communicates, and in particular in what she chooses to make explicit and leave implicit. (Sperber and Wilson, 1995, 218). Sperber and Wilson’s theory takes the Gricean notions and expands them to involve two ideas, explicatures, i.e. an inference that enriches the original utterance to a complete proposition; its meaning is explicit, the salient meaning. A sign, for example, minimally says “Student Parking.” Explicature allows the reader to understand the complete proposition of “Only students allowed to park in this location.” Then the idea of Implicature follows, i.e. an inference that details the relevant meaning intended, but is a different logical step, e.g. “Student Parking” infers that no one else can park in the location marked with this sign. Relevance becomes a two-step process: …we will call an explicitly communicated assumption an explicature. Any assumption communicated, but not explicitly so, is implicitly communicated; it is an implicature. (Sperber and Wilson, 1995, 182). Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 10 The SCOTUS context is unique in law; it’s special for pragmatic analyses because: a. The rapid verbal interaction in SCOTUS proceedings exemplifies questioning strategies, with the judges and lawyers using a range of styles in speaking. What do the questions reflect in terms of what’s important in a case? Is there an order to a judge’s questions and does it reflect an order of importance? b. While power relations are clear in SCOTUS, the Question and Answer conversation in SCOTUS proceedings involves a group of equally knowledgeable, elite appellate lawyers and judges; it isn’t the usual asymmetric case of legal professionals and laymen in a courtroom. And speakers can be certain their listeners understand implicit meanings since they are members of the same in-group, with similar knowledge: A speaker who is aiming at optimal relevance must assume that the contextual assumptions required for the interpretation of the utterance are immediately accessible to the hearer. ( Blakemore, 1992, 128). c. SCOTUS justices often interrupt others questioning; what might they be implying with their words or this behavior? Or: …should we recognize…tendentious questioning – questioning that signals a judge’s view of the merits of the case being argued—provides expressive utility to the judge….especially…in the case of the Supreme Court, because the views express by justices in open court are newsworthy…. (Epstein, Landes & Posner, 2010, 437). Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 11 d. The turn-taking aspects of conversation are also different from the usual courtroom’s rigid approach. There is a defined turntaking approach in SCOTUS, but here the verbal exchange is much more like ordinary conversation – judges question lawyers but it is also thought they direct comments to other judges for persuasion, …The hour-long sessions in the ornate courtroom also offer the justices a chance to make their own case – to each other….(Biskupic, 2006, 1). This lends itself to pragmatic analysis. e. SCOTUS is situated at legal hierarchy’s summit, with final interpretative power. It is pragmatic since the account it gives of the meaning of legal terms is not semantic but in terms of authoritative acts determining their content. (Canale & Tuzet,2007, 39). The links between power, ideology and law are important to understanding what SCOTUS language reflects in terms of society’s social or philosophical views. This paper has a narrow focus of exploring these pragmatic ideas in two cases and, therefore, has obvious limitations. But the ideas considered may prove relevant for broader consideration by researchers of SCOTUS. These concepts could also be applied to SCOTUS’ written conversation (majority and minority opinions) as reflected in final rulings. The written conversation could be analyzed in relation to the oral argument. Given SCOTUS’ position in the American legal system, the mysteries behind its decisions, and the fact that SCOTUS decisions sometimes, but not always, follow the expected Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 12 ideological-political expectations, extensive research is assured, by the many who try to understand this court. Linguistic study can undoubtedly contribute to that understanding. 3. Research Background and Literature This paper involves a multi-discipline literature search. It’s focus on applying pragmatics to law means readings will focus on pragmatic concepts, especially Levinson’s. Implicature is an integral part of any speaker’s meaning. It is often context dependent. Implicatures can be created using the Gricean Co-operative principle, or by flouting it (note the use of “+>” to stand for the implicature): I went to the station and bought gas +> I went to a gas station and purchased gas at that station. The detective who asks me, Didn’t you kill your wife in a fit of anger? And I answer, Yup! You’re right! actually meaning, with my sarcasm, the exact opposite. Even sentence meanings, e.g. WH-questions, create implicatures: Who is the Linguistic’s professor at MSU? +> Someone is a linguistic’s professor at MSU. But implicatures are dependent not on just linguistic data but context, background assumptions, participants’ encyclopedic information and perceptions. The implicature made above by flouting the Co-operative principle, for example, might not be recognized if I were speaking to a police detective in Japan. Grice’s implicature framework has been influential, as has Levinson’s expansion of it, in understanding implicature’s role in communication and overcoming the slowness of human speech – the absolute limits on human sound production given their speech Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 13 organs. As Levinson observes about the articulatory bottleneck, …inference is cheap, articulation expensive.... (Levinson, 2000, 29). Levinson also differentiates two forms of implicature, generalized vs. particularized. The latter depends on some particular context assumption, while the former relies on Levinson’s three general principles which relate to Grice’s theory. To illustrate: Speaker A) Did the students’ linguistics’ presentations go well? Speaker B) Some of them got sick. Generalized implicature: Some but not all of the students became sick. Particularized implicature: The presentations about linguistics were not as successful as hoped. The generalized implicature will always arise but the particular one requires a context determined by speaker A’s question. At the same time, law’s language is not everyday language. Law uses specialized technical concepts and jargon, where, for example, everyday words possess different legal meaning. A well known example is “reasonable man”. An example relevant to this paper is “marriage”, which colloquially refers to a socially recognized union of spouses, a cultural and/or religious institution. Marriage is specifically defined in 36 state statutes or state Constitutions (as of 2013) as a legal union between one man and one woman (which is also the definition argued in Windsor, which meant gay couples legally married in certain states would be treated as unmarried under federal laws). Other states do not have a specific legal definition of the word, making a broader definition easily possible – for example, a legal union of a couple regardless of gender. This different language requires exploration, since it may mean peculiar pragmatic issues. SCOTUS provides striking differences from the usual courtroom, and Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 14 also defines legal issues. Studying this should be useful in understanding relationships between law and implicature, as well as assisting in knowing “what is meant.” vs. “what is said.” when SCOTUS participants speak. 3.1. SCOTUS There have been millions of words written about SCOTUS over the years. But one area of its work that’s relatively less studied is the role of oral argument: The oral argumentation process, however, has been largely ignored….Indeed, only a handful of analyses over the last couple of decades address the function of oral arguments at the Court. (Johnson, et. al., 2006, 112). In general, the oral aspects of courtroom activity have not been widely studied. Twentyfour years before Johnson’s work, a researcher wrote: …little systematic effort by social scientists, linguists, or legal scholars has focused on spoken language. …Passing attention is paid here and there to spoken legal language, but there are virtually no attempts to deal directly and extensively with it. (O’Barr, 1982, 23-24). This explains why the spoken interactions of judges, lawyers, clients and other participants in law are worth study. SCOTUS allocated more than its usual one hour of oral argument to each of these two cases on marriage equality (marriage between those of different gender vs. those of the same gender), as it does for some high-profile cases. This creates the impression that argument does matter. Johnson’s, et al study (2006) of SCOTUS oral argument is a recent analysis of such argument, although from a political scientist’s perspective. 539 transcripts of Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 15 SCOTUS oral arguments, along with recently released papers of Justice Blackmun on his grading of oral arguments, were reviewed. These authors concluded: …the judges find oral arguments to be an important part of the Court’s decisionmaking process and that the quality of arguments…affects the justices’ votes. (Johnson, et al, 2006, 112). Following this work, Johnson has found further support to conclude that oral argument at SCOTUS matters, Johnson, et al (2009). Data on SCOTUS oral arguments, as well as decisions, is publically available at the U.S. Supreme Court website: supremecourt.gov/opinions/12pdf/12-144 (Hollingsworth). supremecourt.gov/opinions/12pdf/12-307 (Windsor). supremecourt.gov/oral_argument/argument transcript. The Hollingsworth oral argument is at: http://www.supremecourt.gov/oral_arguments/argument_audio_details.aspx? argument=12-144. The Windsor oral argument is at: http://www.supremecourt.gov/oral_arguments/argument_audio_details.aspx? argument=12-307. Transcripts of the arguments are in this paper’s Appendix. Further, Audio recordings of the oral arguments are available as noted above and will be referred to as appropriate. 3.2. Implicature Gricean theory has evolved since 1967, with the majority of researchers trying to reduce its maxims. Levinson revises Gricean maxims to three propositions, considering the speaker’s and listener’s role: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 16 Q-principle: Speaker’s maxim—Do not provide a statement that is informationally weaker than your knowledge of the world allows, unless providing a stronger statement would contravene the I-principle…. Recipient’s corollary—Take it that the speaker made the strongest statement consistent with what he knows… (Levinson, 2000, 76). Example: The lawyer believes his client is not guilty. +> The lawyer doesn’t know if his client will be found in court guilty or not guilty. I-principle: Speaker’s maxim-- …Say as little as necessary, that is, produce the minimal linguistic information sufficient to achieve your communicational ends(bearing the Q-principle in mind)…. Recipient’s corollary--…Amplify the informational content of the speaker’s utterance, by finding the most specific interpretation, up to what you judge to be the speaker’s m-intended point….(Levinson, 2000, 114). Example: Roger entered the court and noise began. +> Roger entered the courtroom and because of that, the noise started. M-principle: Speaker’s maxim--Indicate an abnormal, non-stereotypical situation by using marked expressions that contrast with those you would use to describe the corresponding normal, stereotypical situation…. Recipient’s corollary—What is said in an abnormal way indicates an abnormal situation, or marked messages indicate marked situations….(Levinson, 2000, 136). Example: Roger caused the pistol to be pointed at you. +> Roger had a pistol pointed at someone but done in some unusual way. (This statement is made in a marked way, not the normal – unmarked-- way of saying, Roger pointed the pistol….) Huang states Levinson’s principles more simply – and effectively: Q-principle: Speaker—Do not say less than is required…. Addressee—What is not said is not the case. E.g. Roger is happy. +> Roger is neither sad nor over-joyful. I-principle: Speaker—Do not say more than is required…. Addressee—What is generally said is stereotypically and specifically exemplified. E.g. Roger and Marina bought a car. +> They purchased the car together, not that each one purchased a car. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 17 M-principle: Speaker—Do not use a marked expression without reason. Addressee—What is said in a marked way is not unmarked. (Huang, 2007, 41,47,50). E.g. Roger is not unrespectable. +> Roger has some degree of respectability (in contrast to an unmarked statement, Roger is respectable). The M-principle’s formation seems, in many cases, unneeded to explain what are otherwise I-implicatures. For example, Levinson uses the M-principle to explain these rival meanings: He was reading a book. +> He was reading an ordinary book. He was reading a tome. +> He was reading some massive, weighty volume (Levinson, 2000, 138). The difference above lies in the lexical meaning of the last words, with tome readily lending itself to a stereotype inference, an I-implicature. The I-principle is a main aspect of this paper’s analysis. For this principle to work, it requires shared background knowledge or information. It works because a listener knows the best translation for a speaker’s utterance is the most informative interpretation; it has to be consistent with what the listener believes is true; usually it’s the first interpretation coming to mind. Huang, using Levinson’s work, lays out fifteen types of I-implicatures (Huang, 2007, 47-49), important to this paper’s analysis; a sample follows. a. Specialization of spatial term: State how the knife was in the body? +>…the knife’s sharp-edged blade part was…. b. Coreferential expression: So you say Roger said that he had a drink before driving? +>…Roger said Roger had an alcoholic drink…. c. Adjective interpretation: You said the stop light was green as you approached the intersection? +>…all of the electric light showed green. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 18 d. Possessive interpretation: Now Detective Watson’s theory is that he was put on a stretcher. +>The theory Detective Watson formulated…. e. Inference to stereotype: Do you live with your wife, sir? +>Are you married and do you live with a female? f. Noun-noun compound: The opposition’s same-sex campaign was horrible. +>The opposition’s campaign against marriage by individuals of the same gender…. Levinson lays out rules for the application of these three principles, with a set of priorities to consider: Q>M>I, where “>” means “resolves inconsistency”(Levinson, 2000, 39). Levinson lays out an example of this priority, Q>I: John drank three beers and drove home, if not in the reverse order. (Levinson, 2000, 158). The Q-inference of the second part +>John drove home first and then drank three beers vs. the I-inference of the first part +> John drank three beers and then drove home: The later clausal condition defeats the inconsistency since its inference suspends the earlier I-implicature. Filtering the implicature forms to gain consistency is an important process for the hearer. Others, such as Horn and Sperber/Wilson, took other approaches, reducing the maxims to a dual principle approach. But Horn’s most substantial contribution to implicature involves the idea of scalar implicatures. It evolved out of his two principles, which create a lower and upper bound for implicature meanings. For example: Roger ate many of the cookies. An upper-bound meaning of this statement is, …some if not all of the cookies. The lower bound meaning is, …some but not all of the cookies. Horn scales involve many lexical and grammatical items, e.g. connectives (and, or); quantifiers (some, many, all, most); adverbs (always, sometimes); degree adjectives (hot-warm, good-excellent); verbs (believe, know, think, predict). The scaling comes from lexical meaning, e.g. the semantic differential between some and all, or strong and weak, Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 19 and also from conversational context. For example, the connectives’ lexical meanings can create different understandings: Roger or Marina will come today. +>It is not true that Roger and Marina will come, only one will. But saying, Roger will come today and Marina will not, or Roger will not come today and Marina will come. In the former, or has its usual disjunctive understanding, while in the latter case, it has an inclusive meaning. Note that Levinson’s I-principle, Say as little as necessary…, approximately corresponds to Horn’s R-principle, Make your contribution necessary. Say no more than you must…. Sperber and Wilson’s model uses cognitive processes. They lay out the Relevance thesis with two principles: (1) Human cognition tends to be geared to the maximization of relevance. (2) Every act of ostensive communication communicates a presumption of its own optimal relevance. (Sperber and Wilson, 1995, 260). The thesis uses mental processes to explain speaker-hearer interaction, given the interaction context: …The organization of the individual’s encyclopedic memory, and the mental activity in which he is engaged, limit the class of potential contexts from which an actual context can be chosen at any given time… In verbal comprehension in particular, it is relevance which is treated as given, and context which is treated as a variable…. (Sperber and Wilson, 1995, 138, 142). Levinson challenges many aspects of this theory: …the theory…never quite gets off the ground for two reasons: the first is lack of internal coherence and clarity, and the second uncertainty of external application. (Levinson, 1989, 462). Grundy, on the other hand, states a major strength: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 20 Relevance theory is to be preferred over other accounts of utterance understanding to the extent that it recognizes and can account for the fact that not all utterances are successfully understood, and that a particular utterance may be understood in different ways and to different degrees by different hearers. (Grundy, 2000, 111). Simply put, does one hear what one wants to? Grundy points out other strengths in the traditional views of implicature vs. relevance theories. In the example, Roger arrived and he sat down +>Roger arrived and Roger sat down—a coreferential type of I-implicature is given, so that the pronoun reference is clear. Under relevance theory, the hearer derives the maximization of relevance based on common understanding that a speaker only says what is relevant and true for the hearer – the interpretation of the pronoun is the most relevant. One problem in the theories of implicature, however, is the differing terminology among its models. This confuses the linguistic student, as well as confusing the analysis of the various theories. Levinson demonstrates this in a diagram (Levinson, 2000, 195). 3.3. Legal Pragmatics and Implicature While courtroom action is a subject of sociolinguistics, pragmatic issues in law’s language are common: …In the context of a court trial the process of inferencing and …implicature might constitute useful tools both for the interrogators in asking questions and for the interrogated in providing or evading answers…. (Kryk-Kastovsky, 2006, 15). An example is the trial lawyer’s infamous question, When are you going to stop beating your wife? reflecting the pragmatic issue of presupposition. Or consider the common problem in law – and language – of ambiguity: A speaker says, Men and women who are Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 21 62 years old or older are entitled to Social Security benefits. There is an ambiguity created by the sentence’s conjunction and phrase …and…who are…. The speaker can correct this by drawing a syntactic tree; but a listener resolves the ambiguity by pragmatically thinking of the implicature, created by the I-principle (conjunction buttressing, in Levinson’s labeling), as well as the speaker’s likely phonological stress markings, so that the referent is to both genders. Or consider the fact that SCOTUS decisions are final; they are the interpretative acts of a court at the top of the judicial hierarchy and therefore pragmatic as respects SCOTUS’ authoritative role. Inference and its complexity in law is further illustrated by contract law, where the idea of “contract” requires certain key elements be found. Among these is the idea of “promise.” At a garage sale, where a sign, “Vehicle for $10,” hangs on the garage building, with a bicycle standing in front of the back of a car, someone says, I promise to buy the vehicle for $10.00. There are a number of inferences in this statement: a vehicle is for sale; someone can legally sell it; I have a duty to buy it; Jones has an expectation that I will buy the vehicle, and that I have or can get ten dollars. The “contract” made in this statement is based on some context, which lawyer A and lawyer B can treat differently: “vehicle” is a vague term and its reference is ambiguous; maybe the speaker’s understanding that it was the car was wrong; maybe the bicycle was meant, which maybe should have been understood because of the requested price. The legal process allows two lawyers to argue the contract’s validity, with the concept of “vehicle” giving rise to various sets of inferences. A judge decides the correct Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 22 inference, one that is also the definitive legal pragmatic content. The interactions of the original parties, the lawyers, and the judge may all be different, but all are arguing the concepts of contract and property within a context, within a general legal view of such concepts, and in the American legal style of an adversarial system of law. Verbal interactions in a court, especially SCOTUS, reflect the law’s complex language, a range of speaking styles, questioning strategies and pragmatic strategies that depend on inferences. Law’s particular rigid language use can be demonstrated by the legalistic concept of a “leading question”, e.g. the lawyer who articulates, All right. So you say you beat your wife Monday night? Another lawyer will object because the question becomes a leading question, i.e. the first sentence in conjunction with the second sentence’s use of, So you say… suggests the answer. Courtroom discourse, unlike everyday discourse, also carries more of a social sense and therefore creates social and/or moral inferences, which need to be controlled, such as the leading question just discussed. In another example, Tannen reviews a case of assault and rape, and how a lawyer uses questions to make the facts appear different from the victim’s alleged portrayal, e.g. one question was: …But not before, according to you, he took two ten-dollar bills out of his pocket and handed them to you, true?... Per Tannen, “According to you” implies “even you admitted this.” “But not before” implies she made sure to get paid – the latter inferring greed and/or immorality. (Tannen, 1998, 139). The lawyer inferred moral issues by the question’s word choices. In SCOTUS, the Constitutional claims of citizens are decided. Social and moral interests come to the forefront in such discussions and decisions. Emotional factors are Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 23 obvious, where implication can be used to avoid or lessen emotional debate among the judges and lawyers – an important interface between implicature and law. This paper explores this in two recent cases on same-sex marriage. 4. SCOTUS Cases and Implicature This section considers two aspects of implicature: 1. The kinds of implicature found in two SCOTUS cases involving issues of constitutional law, emphasizing types under Levinson’s I-principle. 2. The question of whether or how implicature might provide guidance about SCOTUS Justices’ intent on a case’s decision. Constitutional law is a legal realm where interpretations are of major importance. SCOTUS, in these two cases, made very different decisions about the question of marriage equality. In both cases, SCOTUS spent much time in oral argument on the question of standing, i.e. whether a plaintiff is a proper party to be involved in a case, or whether the court has jurisdiction to decide the case. Were there indications in oral arguments of these cases that they would be decided differently? In Windsor, the court reached a decision based on the case’s merits even though it spent much of the advocacy time on the question of standing rather than the merits. But in Hollingsworth, the court decided that plaintiffs had no standing, after spending much of the advocacy time on that question; it did not reach the case’s substantive issues. 4.1. Levinson’s I-principle at Work Implicature examples in the oral arguments under review range from the simple, straightforward kind, e.g. an I-implicature of noun-noun compound: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 24 The issue of same-sex marriage certainly implicates profound and deeply held views.…(Windsor, 55, line 22-23). The compound noun, “same-sex marriage” implicates: +> marriage between two humans of the same gender, in contradistinction to marriage between two heterosexuals. The word, marriage, also implies, in law and common understanding, certain features – one, in America, being a legally binding, enforceable contract between two people. And implicature can range to more complex, legalistic forms. Lawyers are not known for a simplistic way of saying things. They seem, to the layman, to purposefully use language in unusual and unclear ways. An excellent sample of this, and implicature, is found in the Hollingsworth case, where attorney Cooper, arguing for the petitioners, said about marriage and older people: …It’s designed…to make it less likely that either party…to that marriage will engage in irresponsible procreative conduct outside of that marriage….Society has an interest in seeing a 55-year-old couple…that intends to engage in a prolonged period of cohabitation to reserve that until they have made a marital commitment….(Hollingsworth, 26, lines 16-21). The speaker’s beginning, It’s, refers to the idea of marital norm (see below), while Cooper’s remark, with its verbiage, …irresponsible procreative conduct outside of that marriage…., illustrates Levinson’s M-principle, Do not use a marked expression without reason, Apparently because of the SCOTUS setting of seriousness, of argument that borders on the philosophical, this attorney thought it too colloquial to directly talk about affairs, adultery and out-of-wedlock children. Instead, he used an unusual turn of phrase to indirectly communicate the idea of older men having affairs with younger Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 25 women outside of marriage and the possible consequences thereof. Cooper’s arresting phrase implies sexual conduct outside of marriage, which Cooper argues throughout this case is a societally sanctioned conduct in marriage, whose purpose is the responsible creation of children. Leading into this exchange, implicature is also found in Cooper’s statement: …the marital norm which imposes upon that couple the obligation of fidelity…. (Hollingsworth, 26, lines 9-10). +> the norm of marriage of heterosexual fidelity ,monogamy … An I-implicature using inference to stereotypes is evident in the words, marital norm, which in American society implies fidelity, monogamy, a union of two people of different genders, children, and various responsibilities to the children as well as between the two parties. And for the religious , the term implies cultural concepts relating to God and beliefs. Even within this inference, there are further implications, e.g. the idea of “gender” which we think of as an innate quality of sexuality – male/female. Examples, in addition to those mentioned, of straightforward I-implicature forms follow (using Huang’s classification of types, with the I-type’s label beginning the example): Adjective interpretation: …I see my red light is on….(Hollingsworth, 58, lines 1718). +> the whole surface of the light changed color to red…. “My red light” is a general statement; but it implicates a more specific meaning via the common knowledge of speaker (the attorney) and listener (Chief Justice) that the entire light in front of speaker —not just part of it -- became fully red; and it also tells (metaphor’s implication) the speaker, and recipient of his words, that speaking time is finished. Coreferential interpretation: …to think that the State is going to delegate to people who don’t have a fiduciary duty to them [sic], that it’s going to delegate the responsibility of representing…. (Hollingsworth, 7, lines 23-25). +> …to think Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 26 that the State is going to delegate to people who don’t have a fiduciary duty to the State, that the State is going to delegate the responsibility of representing…. There is an inference in …to think that the State… that makes essential the assignment of the following pronoun references to the preceding referent, State, for understanding. Conditional perfection: …If you’re not dealing with this as a class question, then why would you say that the Government is not free to discriminate against them?... (Hollingsworth, 15, lines 18-20). +> If and only if you’re not dealing with this as a class question and only a class question, then …. The If conditional clause implicates ideas of a single class in question, or possibly the opposite idea “If you were dealing with this as a class question, you would say….” Conjunction buttressing: …The governor…frequently appoints an attorney where there’s a perceived conflict of interest…and that person would have a responsibility for the State and might have responsibility for attorneys’ fees….(Hollingsworth, 31, lines 2-9). +> The governor…appoints an attorney…and thereby that person would have responsibility…. the sequence of events is conjoined by implication; the succession inference, the governor…appoints…and that person (thereby)… connects the thoughts for the listener. Conjunction buttressing: …but I think the most apt of the doctrines, although they are overlapping and reinforce each other, the most apt is standing… (Windsor, 13, lines 11-13). +> …although the doctrines are overlapping and therefore reinforce each other…. There is a coreferential I-implicature in this statement, as well as a conjunction, “and,” that implicates the information that one action necessarily involves a next action – the two thoughts are joined together by the listener. The conjunction is, semantically, inclusive Frame-based reference: …Unless there are other questions, I will sit down…. (Windsor, 52, lines 22-23). +> Unless there are other questions, instead of standing I will sit… In this instance, the speaker implies what must be an existing fact and a perceived framework of being upright on feet, i.e. “…I will stop standing and sit down….” Indirect speech act: …I’m sorry?... (Windsor, 30, line 24). +> I don’t understand. Could you elaborate…. Here the speaker uses an idiom commonly understood to imply, based on context, a request for more information. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 27 Negative raising: …I don’t know why you don’t mention some concrete things…(Hollingsworth, 19, lines 5-6). +>I know you do not mention some concrete things but you should…. Certain verbs convey opinions, attitudes or states of knowledge; “know” is an example of this and implicates that the speaker is thinking, in fact telling the listener, …I know you could mention some concrete things…. Possessive interpretation: …the House’s prerogatives aren’t at stake here…. (Windsor, 38, line 4). +>The prerogatives belonging to the U.S. House of Representatives…. Rather than using the of-construction, the speaker uses the briefer contraction form, “…the House’s…” to imply a close relationship between the “owner” and the owned properties. The two possessive forms, formal and informal, allow a speaker to convey information in the most relevant way to the speaker. Possessive interpretation: …There’s $300,000 that’s going to come out of the Government’s treasury… (Windsor, 14, lines 15-16). +> There’s $300,000 that’s going to come out of the treasury of the U.S. Government…. Besides the notes above, the possessive contraction form lets the speaker present a more positive inference than the formal approach. Saying …that’s going to come out of the treasury of the U.S. Government… almost raises Levinson’s M-principle as a “marked expression” and a different speaker’s intent Proper name narrowing: …that Congress couldn’t specify members of Congress in that context even where the measure depleted or diminished powers of Congress…. (Hollingsworth, 32, lines 4-6). +> that the House of Representatives and the Senate of the United States couldn’t specify… Based on common, shared knowledge, a general term is used which a listener, through implications, both maximizes and narrows to more specific meanings, e.g. “Congress” implies the two parts of one branch of the U.S. Government. Proper name narrowing: …In Chadha, the Court was…(Windsor, 16, line 25). +>In a previous case that came before SCOTUS, called Chadha.… “Chada” must be narrowed if it is to have meaning for the speaker and listener. Based on shared knowledge of legal cases and their facts that have applicability to the Windsor case being debated, the parties use the abbreviated reference to convey a complete legal reference. This is a legal convention in trials. Systematic ambiguity: …if there were a way to cabin the arguments that are being presented to you to California, then the concerns about defining marriage in California could be confined to California….(Hollingsworth, 20-21, lines 25 and 1-3). +> …if, and only if, there were a way to cabin the arguments that are being Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 28 presented to you to the entire state of California (i.e. not to districts of the state, and not to other states of the U.S.)…. There is a lexical issue in …cabin the arguments…to California…; how is the term “California” to be understood? Implicature solves this by common knowledge, and a listener’s understanding that the speaker’s inference is to the whole territory of that political-governmental entity and just that entity. This speaker intent is clearly understood in the Justices’ prior and later references …to states other than California… (Hollingsworth, 20, line 9). or …There are some 40,000 children in California…. (Hollingsworth, 21, line 12). 4.2. The I-principle at Work in Legal Practice Unlike the preceding I-implicatures, complex implicature forms, where a legal understanding and meaning is implied, are found throughout legal cases. They often involve the noun-noun compound form (e.g. Due Process Clause, Right to Bear Arms, Cruel and Unusual Punishment), probably because of the law’s predilection for labeling, and longhand rather than shorthand expressions. Some examples of complex implicatures follow. In the Windsor case, there is much discussion of constitutional theories. One example is: …But that has never been your approach, especially under rational basis or even rational basis-plus… (Windsor, 74, lines 19-21). The noun-noun I-implicature of “rational basis” would certainly be understood in normal terms, +> But…using a special basis of reasoning or even a strengthened basis of reasoning…. But there is a special legal meaning to rational basis, which the lawyer saying this knows all his listeners - know, i.e. a constitutional standard applied by courts to legislative acts which presumes their constitutionality. This standard means there Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 29 should be minimal judicial review and requires plaintiffs to overcome the constitutionality presumption. To mention an example of Levinson’s Q-type implicature involving this idea, found later in the argument: …Rational basis, Mr. Clement – is a problem in your briefing. You seem to say and you repeat it today that there is[sic] three tiers, and if ….(Windsor, 111, lines 710). +> …and you repeat it today that there is three (not more or less) tiers… The Q-type involves number words such as “three” and relates to Horn’s idea of scalar implicatures. In the SCOTUS context, all parties realize that the legal notion of “rational basis” involves three levels of form for judicial review, with “rational basis” being the least onerous form. The other two forms (see below) are considered more stringent, and relate to other phases of constitutional review as noted below. The lawyer, Mr. Clement, goes on to say, …This Court, even when it’s applied more heightened scrutiny….(Windsor, 74, lines 22-23). The implicature of this compound suggests a court uses different standards of judicial review and could be read as, +>Even when this Court’s review has been closer, more searching…. But again, in constitutional law, the concept of heightened scrutiny is understood to refer to levels of “intermediate” or “strict” scrutiny in judicial review of constitutional questions – which further implies that a plaintiff’s case can be potentially determined by the level of constitutional review that a court determines to use. The structure of the tiers of scrutiny is an important characteristic of another constitutional idea, Equal Protection analysis, discussed below. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 30 Complicated legal referencing and inferencing is found in Justice Kagan’s remarks, … or do we think that Congress’s judgment was infected by dislike, by fear, by animus, and so forth….(Windsor, 72, lines 15-17). There is an I-implicature of possessive construction in this, +> the judgment of members of the U.S. Senate and House of Representatives (“Congress”) – the specific interpretation we automatically make. But there is also an inference we might overlook when Justice Kagan says, “animus”. This word’s legal semantic meaning implicates specific understanding in constitutional law, which the participants in Windsor recognized; consider Chief Justice Robert’s later comment: …So that was the view of the 84 Senators who voted in favor of it and the President who signed it? They were motivated by animus? (Windsor, 91, 14-16). Roberts takes for granted listeners’ understanding of the last word. Animus is an Iimplicature example of lexical narrowing. It’s a specific but unclearly defined term of art in constitutional assessments. SCOTUS narrowly defined it, in Romer v. Evans, as a…bare desire to harm a politically unpopular group. Other SCOTUS cases have more broadly defined it, looking at mindsets involving fear, stereotype or bias, which create laws with distinctions between societal groups – or laws which lack a rational basis (discussed above). Also consider a remark in Hollingsworth’s oral argument. “Animus” isn’t mentioned or discussed in this case; however, the plaintiff’s lawyer implicitly raises the idea when discussing if traditional marriage definitions reflect an unconscious bias and …a bare desire to harm (Hollingsworth, 13, line 9). Because of the lawyers’ preparation for these constitutional cases, the phrasing was no doubt recognized, even if no comment was made: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 31 …that the traditional definition of marriage insofar as – insofar as it does not include same-sex couples, insofar as it is a gender definition is irrational and can only be explained, as a result of anti-gay malice and a bare desire to harm…. (Hollingsworth, 13, lines 4-9). The expression, “animus,” can closely relate to ideas found in other constitutional concepts, such as “rational basis”, where the idea can be used to find a law unconstitutional, no matter its “rational basis.” In fact, constitutional interpretation uses a finding of the absence of “rational basis” in a statute to imply the existence of “animus.” Also note the implicature in Justice Kagan’s use of a rhetorical question, when the Justice discussed the question of animus: …Is that what happened in 1996?.... (Windsor, 74, line 15). +>The speaker believes or at least expects the answer is yes. Here is an indirect speech act whose tone, when listening to the argument, of positive assertion implicates an answer of Yes. One also finds the doctrine in Equal Protection analysis and the Equal Protection Clause, oft mentioned in Windsor’s case: …told the Executive Branch to comply with the Equal Protection Clause….(Windsor, 9, line 16-17). …The equal protection analysis in this case should focus on two fundamental points….(Windsor, 80, line 19). …I think the question under the Equal Protection Clause is .…(Windsor, 96, lines 17-18). The noun-noun compound could be read, +> In this case, the analysis of protections that are equal. But the reference is to a legal analysis about fairness, discrimination and the U.S. Constitution’s 14th amendment (where the Equal Protection Clause is found). Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 32 SCOTUS has deemed Marriage a fundamental right (Turner v. Safley, 1987). These two cases concerned whether same-sex couples had equal, fundamental rights to marriage. In Windsor, the Equal Protection issue was DOMA’s provision defining marriage, for the federal government, to exclude same-sex marriages. In Hollingsworth, an amendment to a state’s constitution defining marriage to exclude same-sex couples, after the state’s Supreme Court decision that the state Constitution’s Equal Protection proviso allowed same-sex marriage, was at issue. Equal protection analysis will also implicate automatically, in lawyers’ thinking, previously discussed concepts, such as “heightened scrutiny.” 4.3. Discussion of Implicature at Work What the preceding analysis further evidences is a SCOTUS speaker makes assumptions about the audience – assumptions about their constitutional law knowledge relative to the cases argued, and knows implicatures will be understood because: There is a regularity of association and interpretation in constitutional law between, for example, noun-noun compounds and their semantic legal meanings; In the context of constitutional law and for the expert participants at SCOTUS, the phrases possess associations with pragmatic inferences. We’re in a legal setting, using legal words and language, which has a “restricted code” that registers with these experienced lawyers and judges. All the parties share the Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 33 same knowledge of what is important to understanding the concepts in a speaker’s reference. The participants automatically, systematically process references which have preferred and precise interpretations, evident, for example, in the back-andforth discussion about Chadha in the Windsor case. The interplay among the components of constitutional doctrines and their inferences are an inherent part of the exchanges among the Justices and lawyers, as well as relevant to the interpretation of constitutional law which SCOTUS decisions determine. Are there hints of the ultimate SCOTUS decisions in oral arguments, of how justices perceive the case? In Windsor, unlike Hollingsworth, there are many comments by the Justices about the rapidly changing societal attitudes toward questions of marriage equality and LBGT individuals, which might suggest a concern with how constitutional issues apply to these individuals. Justice Scalia says, in talking about the number of states allowing a gay couple to marry, …Nine. And…and so there has been this sea change between now and 1996….(Windsor, 107, lines 3-4). +>…and so there has been this substantial change in the number of states permitting same-sex couples to marry… Of course, in listening to the oral argument, one might conclude that Scalia’s remark, “sea change,” is said with some sarcasm; it’s intended to highlight only nine states in 17 years had changed laws to allow such marriages. By intonation as well as the choice of words, the Justice makes another implication, one of doubt that the citizenry is ready to approve redefining “marriage”. Chief Justice Roberts later remarks: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 34 …I suppose the sea change has a lot to do with the political force and effectiveness of people representing, supporting your side of the case?... (Windsor, 107, lines 17-20). and still later: …As far as I can tell, political figures are falling over themselves to endorse your side of the case….(Windsor, 108, lines 12-14). +>…people in politics are quickly endorsing your opinion of the arguments about this case, i.e. endorsing samesex marriage…. The Chief Justice implies there is real and significant change happening. Consider attorney Kaplan’s remarks (for plaintiff): …the Federal Government has always handled that and has never before…separated out a class of married gay couples solely because they were gay….(Windsor,101, lines 11-14). …and you’re having discrimination for the first time in our country’s history against a class of married couples.…(Windsor,104, lines 11-14). The Justices are hearing about social changes and acknowledging in their remarks the changes underway. In these remarks and implications, one could hear both suggestions of previously inconceivable constitutional interpretation, i.e. in 1996, a question before SCOTUS of civil rights for LBGT individuals wouldn’t be thought possible by the majority of Americans, and that the court might reach the merits in Windsor. This latter suggestion is also implied in various Windsor discussions about the doctrine of federalism. Justice Kennedy says succinctly: …The question is whether or not the Federal government, under our federalism scheme, has the authority to regulate marriage….(Windsor, 76, lines 14-16). Earlier, he said: …in our society means that the Federal government is intertwined with the citizens’ day-to-day life,…you are at …real risk of running in conflict with what Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 35 has always been thought to be the essence of the State police power, which is to regulate marriage….(Windsor, 59, lines 20-25). The attorney for the defendant argues that the Federal government does have an interest in defining marriage: …the basic principles of federalism suggest that as long as the federal government defines those terms solely for the purposes of Federal law….(Windsor, 56, lines 7-11). Justice Ginsburg weighs in later: …as Justice Kennedy said…so you are really diminishing what the State has said is marriage. You’re saying, no, State did two kinds of marriage, the full marriage and then…skim-milk marriage. (Windsor, 71, lines 11-16). In this sequence of conversation, implicatures abound and suggest concerns with important constitutional distinctions that some of the Justices want to address, i.e. do the states alone decide marriage definitions and issues, or is there a federal role. To review some of these implicatures: …the Federal government (I-type, proper name narrowing) infers …+> the government of the U.S. constituted by the fifty states, consisting of three branches, etc.; …State police power (I-type, noun-noun compound/lexical narrowing) infers +> the authority of states in the U.S. under the 10th Amendment to the U.S. Constitution to decide and regulate societal behaviors, such as marriage; … full marriage and then…skim-milk marriage.(a M-type implicature, using metaphor as well as marked expression ) infers +> a marriage that is fully and legally recognized vs. one that is partially and not fully recognized in law. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 36 In Windsor, five SCOTUS Justices agreed to decide the substantive, constitutional issues; but the mixture of Windsor Justices changed in the decision about Hollingsworth -- and its constitutional issues were not decided. Instead, the technical question of standing, i.e. the defendants of California’s Proposition 8 (who were sponsors of that initiative) lacked standing, decided the case. Under today’s constitutional procedure, there must be a showing by and of harm for the plaintiffs – that they have something to lose in the case; without this demonstration of “injury”, SCOTUS dismisses a case. This decision was presaged in Hollingsworth’s oral argument when certain Justices questioned whether the court should have agreed to hear the case: …Have we ever granted standing to proponents of ballot initiatives?... (Hollingsworth, 3, lines 24-25). +> (I-type, membership categorization) Ballot initiatives have supporters and have they been previously allowed by SCOTUS to argue the merits of the case before it? …the problem with this case is that you’re really asking…for us to go into uncharted waters…. (Hollingsworth, 47, lines 20-22). Implied is a problem, and Levinson’s M-principle is evident in the metaphor, +> If you were really asking us to go into charted waters, there would be no problem. …If the question is letting the States experiment and letting the society have more time to figure out its direction, why is taking the case now the answer?... (Hollingsworth, 64, lines 5-8). This is a clausal implicature, Levinson’s Q-principle. +> For all the speaker knows, accepting the case for decision now may be bad, because society needs more time to figure out its direction. Do conversational implicatures reflect the ideological positions of SCOTUS judges? Judicial decisions must be seen in the context of their facts, time periods, and social context, as must oral arguments and implicatures. This is certainly evident in Windsor where the attorney argued: Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 37 …back in 1996 people did not have the understanding that they have today….It was based…an incorrect understanding that gay couples were fundamentally different than straight couples, an understanding that I don’t think exists today….(Windsor, 106, lines 7-17). The implicature is clear that +>… in 2013 people understand gay couples. And earlier remarks regarding “sea change” show Justices’ attitudes and responses to social context. Considering Windsor further, Justice Kennedy led the federalism discussion in oral argument, but said nothing during the discussion of “rational basis” or “animus.” Yet in Kennedy’s written decision for the majority, these two concepts, in addition to federalism, play a major role in the opinion. Kennedy listened and understood and wrote about the linkages among constitutional ideas, even if the oral arguments don’t specifically reflect his involvement in all of them. 5. Conclusion This paper addressed an objective of assessing implicature in verbal interactions at SCOTUS. Does implicature: a. offer a means for more research that might lead to a better understanding of the U.S.’s highest court? b. tell us anything about Justices’ intentions? SCOTUS lawyers aim to make their advocacy appealing and persuasive to the judges. They couch their message in not just relevant facts, information and precedent, but also in implicatures. Justices can ask the lawyers questions using implicatures. Understanding this may allow analysts to highlight what is significant in oral arguments and justice’s intentions. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 38 As noted, implicatures can be context-sensitive and assume speakers’ and listeners’ mastery of relevant legal concepts. The inferences raised in oral argument will differ from case-to-case because the facts and legal issues differ. This poses the question of, on a general basis, how useful the concept of implicature might be in assessing issues of fact-finding, ideology and equal treatment in law. The concept may be useful for reviewing or finding significant factors in a specific case, for elaborating the pragmatic content of legal phrases in advocacy. But it is difficult to accept it as a way to articulate broader clarifications of law. However, more in-depth analysis of this aspect of oral argument may be feasible. A promising framework of implicature use might be found in a program underway, called the Oyez Project (see http/www.oyez.org), which is compiling SCOTUS audio tapes, back to 1955, into a searchable database. This will allow researchers to consider SCOTUS transcripts in conjunction with Justices’ expressed tones or attitudes and might provide a further means to assess whether an oral argument and its spoken – implied advocacy was influential to a decision, or even if there are general patterns to implicature use. Implicature study might also lead to a way to help measure the salience of issues in a specific case. Nevertheless, a core question about SCOTUS oral argument and its dynamic will remain, i.e. how influential oral argument is for any SCOTUS Justice? A Justice might be deeply influenced by some point made or implied at oral argument but without any reference to that point in the final written decision, without citation or even reference Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 39 to the argument in which the point was made, the linkage between speaking and listening, between advocacy and decision is indeterminant. Intuitions may suggest relationships. But ultimately, to correlate SCOTUS decision-making and the processes leading to it, as well uses of implicature, will require access to Justices’ personal papers, if not to Justices themselves. References Biskupic, J. (2006, Oct. 5). Justices make points by questioning lawyers. USA Today. Retrieved from www.usatoday.com/news/washington/judicial/2006-10-05-oralarguments_x.htm. Blakemore, D. (1992). Understanding utterances. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Canale, D. & Tuzet, G. (2007). On legal inferentialism. Toward a pragmatics of semantic content in legal interpretation? Ratio Juris, 20(1), 32-44. Dennis Hollingsworth, et al v. Kristin M. Perry, et al, 570 U.S._(2013). Epstein, L., Landes, W. & Posner, R. (2010). Inferring the winning party in the supreme court from the pattern of questioning at oral argument. Journal of Legal Studies, 39, 433-467. Grundy, P. (2000). Doing pragmatics. 2nd ed. London: Arnold. Huang, Y. (2007). Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Horn, L. (1984). Toward a new taxonomy for pragmatic inference: Q-based and Rbased implicature. In D. Schiffrin, (Ed.), Meaning, Form and Use in Context: Linguistic Applications (pp. 11-42). Washington D.C.: Georgetown Press. Johnson, T., Wahlbeck, P., & Spriggs, J. (2006). The influence of oral arguments on the U.S. supreme court. American Political Science Review, 100(1), 99-113. Johnson, T., Black, R., & Wedeking, J. (2009). Pardon the interruption: An empirical analysis of supreme court justices’ behavior during oral arguments. Loy. L. Rev., 55, 331. Kryk-Kastovsky, B. (2006). Legal pragmatics. In K. Brown (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics (2nd ed. Vol. 7, pp. 13-20). Amsterdam: Elsevier Ltd. Levinson, S. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 40 Levinson, S. (1989). [A Review of relevance]. Journal of Linguistics. 25 (2), 455-472. Levinson, S. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press. Levinson, S. (2012). H.P. Grice on location on Rossel island. In Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Berkley Linguistic Society, (Vol. 25, No.1, 210-224). Liptak, A. (2013, June 27). Justices extend benefits to gay couples; Allow same-sex marriages in California. New York Times, pp. A1, A20-A21. O’Barr, W. (1982). Linguistic evidence. Language, power and strategy in the courtroom. San Diego, CA: Academic Press Inc. O’Brien, D. (1997). Judges on judging. Views from the bench. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House Publishers. Rombeck, T. (2002, Oct. 30). Justice takes time for q&a. Lawrence Journal-World, p. B5. Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S._(1996). Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1995). Relevance: Communication and cognition. 2nd ed. London: Arnold Publishing. Tannen, D. (1998). The Argument culture. Moving from debate to dialogue. New York, NY: Random House Inc. United States v. Edith Schlain Windsor, in her capacity as executor of the estate of Thea Una Spyer, et al., 570 U.S._(2013). Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 41 MONTCLAIR STATE UNIVERSITY Implicature in Legal Proceedings as a Pragmatic Strategy APLN 605 – LINGUISTICS RESEARCH PROJECT APPENDIX (Refer to SCOTUS website for Windsor & Hollingsworth transcripts.) Roger Cunningham 5/7/2014 Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 42 Apln 605 research paper implicature in scotus RC Page 43