Crime, Punishment and Consumer Protection [DRAFT] © Peter Cartwright* Introduction The criminal law is perhaps society’s most visible instrument of condemnation - its “strongest form of official censure and punishment.”1 Criminal sanctions also, however, play a significant role in dealing with conduct that may not justify such a censorious response. The question of what role, if any, criminal sanctions should play in the protection of the consumer is highly topical in the UK for a number of reasons.2 First, conflicting messages are emerging about the extent to which criminal sanctions is an appropriate tool for dealing with corporate wrongdoing. On the one hand, some commentators have seen evidence of a potential drift towards ‘punitive’ approaches to regulation, with increasing emphasis being placed upon criminal sanctions.3 On the other hand, there appears to be enthusiasm among various quarters for alternatives to criminal law. The Hampton Review, which was set up to consider ways of reducing administrative burdens on business by approaching regulatory inspection and enforcement more efficiently, recommended that a comprehensive review of regulators’ penalty regimes be 1 A Ashworth Principles of Criminal Law (3rd ed) (OUP, 1999) p 17. For a detailed examination see P Cartwright Consumer Protection and the Criminal Law (CUP, 2001). 3 See in particular R Baldwin “The New Punitive Regulation” (1994) 67(3) MLR 351. He sees “a new zest for punitive approaches to regulation” (p 251) which is evidenced by government policy, legislative developments and the approach of regulators. 2 1 undertaken.4 That review is now underway.5 The Government has also shown support for rethinking the role of criminal law in regulation, and accepted the recommendations of the Hampton Report in full.6 A second factor which makes consideration of the role of the criminal law in consumer protection topical is that of the imminent implementation of the Unfair Commercial Practices Directive.7 The precise effect of this implementation remains unclear, but it would appear to have significant implications for many areas of UK consumer protection law that have traditionally fallen under the umbrella of criminal law.8 This paper will suggest that while the criminal law should continue to play a role in the protection of the consumer, it is time to reconsider precisely what that role should involve. It will be argued that criminal law should be used to deal with serious wrongs committed against consumers, although it will also be suggested that few of these wrongs can be classified appropriately as consumer protection offences. The paper will then consider whether criminal law should continue to play a role in dealing with less serious wrongs – those that would fall under the broad category of regulatory offences. This is a more difficult issue. Criminal sanctions have long been established as a tool of consumer protection in the UK, and the removal of some of these offences might be thought to convey an unfortunate message. Furthermore, it will suggested that one can to take issue 4 HM Treasury Reducing Administrative Burdens: Effective Inspection and Enforcement (the Hampton Report) (March 2005) para 2.86. 5 See BRE Regulatory Justice: Sanctioning in a post-Hampton World (undated). Although the Hampton review was concerned primarily with reducing administrative burdens, this did not translate to a call for less stringent penalties (see ibid). 6 DTI A Fair Deal for All (June 2005) para 8.4. My discussions with DTI officials have also revealed an ambivalent approach towards the use of criminal sanctions in consumer protection. 7 Directive 2005/29/EC. 8 See DTI The Unfair Commercial Practices Directive: Consultation on implementing the EU Directive on Unfair Commercial Practices and Amending Existing Consumer Legislation (DTI, December 2005) and the discussion below. 2 with some of the criticisms that have been made of the use of regulatory offences. Nevertheless, significant questions remain about criminal law’s role in protecting consumers. This paper engages with these, and concludes that it may be time to initiate a move away from criminal law and towards alternative mechanisms for punishing errant traders. When is conduct criminal? It is possible to answer the question “when is conduct criminal?” in a formal manner. Lord Atkin argued that the criminal nature of an act can be discovered by reference only to one question: “is the act prohibited with criminal consequences?”9 But might additional characteristics be necessary before we properly classify conduct as criminal? Hart argued that a crime is not “simply any conduct to which a legislature chooses to attach a criminal penalty. It is conduct which, if duly shown to have taken place, will incur a formal and solemn pronouncement of the moral condemnation of the community.”10 This point has been reflected in recent discussions on the role of criminal sanctions in regulation. For example, the Better Regulation Executive’s discussion paper Regulatory Justice: Sanctioning in a post-Hampton World argues that criminal prosecution “attaches a severe moral condemnation and a criminal record to a business or individual”.11 For the purpose of this paper, it will be argued that an act is a crime if it is 9 Proprietary Articles Trade Association v Attorney General for Canada [1931] AC 310 at 324. 10 11 Better Regulation Executive Regulatory Justice: Sanctioning in a post-Hampton World (BRE undated) para 1.28. 3 defined by law as such.12 However, such an approach does not preclude our questioning what criminal law should involve from a normative perspective. It is to this that we turn. What should be criminal? If labelling someone as criminal does involve a significant element of moral condemnation in the eyes of the public, then the willingness (or even enthusiasm) with which states classify conduct as criminal is a matter of great concern. Much liberal criminal justice scholarship sees criminalisation as something that should be a last resort. Indeed, the doctrine of minimal criminalisation has been recognised by Labour governments since 1997. However those administrations have done little to slow the creation of new offences, many of which lack any significant condemnatory character.13 The fear of over-criminalisation has characterised much of the objection to the use of the criminal law. Mill most famously argued that criminal law should deal only where there is harm to others, and while Feinberg and others have found alternative justifications for the use of criminal sanctions (in particular, offence to others) there remains a powerful case for restricting the use of the criminal law. 14 Recently, Ashworth has asked whether the criminal law is “a lost cause”, and in so doing has called for 12 It is helpful to consider the position under the ECHR here. It has been held that if national law defines proceedings as criminal then this will be conclusive. However, proceedings may be found to be criminal for the purposes of the ECHR even where national law does not regard them as such. See e.g Benham v UK (1996) 22 EHRR 293. 13 Lord Williams of Mostyn stated that offences should only be created “when absolutely necessary”, and that when considering whether to create new offences, the Government will take into account whether: “the behaviour in question is sufficiently serious to warrant intervention by the criminal law; the mischief could be dealt with under existing legislation or by using other remedies; the proposed offence is enforceable in practice; the proposed offence is tightly drawn and legally sound; and the proposed offence is commensurate with the seriousness of the offence.” HL Deb vol.602 WA 57 (June 18 1999) cited in Ashworth “Is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause” at 229. 14 See JS Mill On Liberty (1859). J Feinberg Offense to Others (1986 OUP). 4 recognition of a principled core of criminal law.15 For Ashworth and others, criminal law is more than merely instrumental. The label “criminal” implies an element of censure that other forms of social control lack. As a result, criminal law should, on this view, be concerned only with serious wrongdoing. To what extent do consumer protection offences reflect this paradigm? It is helpful, first, to consider the role of criminal law in protecting the consumer from serious wrongdoing. Consumer Protection and Serious Crime It is submitted that the first contention in this article is one with which most commentators are likely to agree: that criminal law has an important role in protecting consumers from serious wrongdoing. A distinction is sometimes drawn between crimes mala in se and crimes mala prohibita. Offences mala in se are those that are wrong in themselves: “sins with legal definitions”.16 There is consensus that it is appropriate for the criminal law to be invoked to deal with such conduct. Although there are different ways of assessing seriousness, it is submitted that the main indicators of seriousness are (1) the degree of culpability involved; and (b) the degree of harm (actual or potential) involved.17 Consumers will sometimes be victims of serious wrongdoing and, where they are, it is frequently appropriate for criminal law to step in. For example, if a consumer was killed by a product that its suppliers knew to be dangerous, it is conceivable that a 15 A Ashworth is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause? (2000) 116 LQR 225. Per Lord Devlin at a Holdsworth Club presidential Address. Cited in G Borrie The Development of Consumer Law and Policy: Bold Spirits and Timorous Souls (London, Stevens and Sons 1984) at p 46. 17 It is conceded that this is a very simple account of seriousness. For a far more sophisticated attempt at assessing seriousness see A von Hirsch and N Jareborg “Gauging Criminal Harms: a Living Standard Analysis” (1991) 11 OJLS 1. As Ashworth argues “[t]he task of assessing the seriousness of offences is…as complex and problematic as it is unavoidable and fundamental.” A Ashworth Principles of Criminal Law (3rd ed) p 41. 16 5 prosecution for manslaughter might follow.18 The criminal law should protect consumers from serious harm (and potential harm) caused with mens rea, as it protects individuals when not acting as consumers. But these wrongs are not easily classified as “consumer protection offences.” While manslaughter may in some cases have the effect of protecting individuals when they are acting as consumers, it is not conceived of as a consumer protection measure. In the case of the dangerous product causing death, the victim’s status as a consumer is not relevant.19 Similarly, a conviction for obtaining property by deception might follow from a trader’s dishonestly tricking a consumer about a product the former was selling. Section 15 of the Theft Act 1968 which contains this offence is undoubtedly an example of a serious offence – an offence mala in se, and it may be utilised to protect consumers, but again it is not a consumer protection offence.20 Are there examples of serious wrongs that are properly classed as consumer protection offences? To the extent that seriousness is based on harm, product safety legislation might be a candidate for such a label, but it is submitted that product safety laws are not perceived as real crimes.21 It was noted above that the other main element of seriousness is culpability, normally expressed in terms of mens rea.22 Relatively few offences that would usually be described as “consumer protection offences” require proof 18 I am assuming here that it is appropriate to class manslaughter as an offence requiring mens rea. Even this is questionable. Constructive, or unlawful act manslaughter requires proof of intention to do an act which is unlawful and dangerous, but imposes strict liability as to the causing of death. Death or serious harm need to be foreseeable: see Mallet [1972] Crim LR 260. Manslaughter by gross negligence requires proof of gross negligence, but there is debate about whether it is appropriate to describe any form of negligence as mens rea. See P Brett An Inquiry into Criminal Guilt (Sweet and Maxwell 1963). 19 A manslaughter conviction could equally follow if the victim were a third party, not acting as a consumer. 20 See David CE Roberts “The Use of the Theft Act in Trading Standards Cases” (1992) 9(4) Trading Law 205. 21 Such laws are generally seen as regulatory offences. 22 There is scope for debate about whether mens rea always equates with culpability, particularly where objective standards are applied. 6 of mens rea, but there are some. For example, s.14 of the Trade Descriptions Act 1968 requires the prosecution to prove either that a statement was made recklessly, or that it was known to be false when made.23 Hansard reveals that the mens rea requirement was introduced because of the novelty of using criminal sanctions to deal with false statements about services.24 Parliament wanted to distinguish between goods (where criminal sanctions had previously been used and strict liability imposed) and services, where proof of fault would be required. However, the courts have tended to play down the effect of the mens rea requirement, and so the criminal nature of the provision. In Wings v Ellis, s.14(1) of the TDA was described as “not a truly criminal statute”. In that case, their lordships concluded that such a conclusion was “consistent with the social purpose of a statute in the class to which this act belongs.”25 Therefore, despite the fact that the section required proof of mens rea, it was not viewed as truly criminal.26 Lord Scarman stated in Wings v Ellis that the prime object of the TDA is “not the enforcement of the criminal law, but the maintenance of trading standards.” Such interpretation allowed the House to conclude that the general principles governing the interpretation of criminal statutes did not apply to s.14.27 This adds weight to the view that the offences in s.14 are not part of the mainstream criminal law, despite their requiring proof of mens rea. 23 Although the effect of this mens rea requirement has been watered-down considerably by decisions of the appeal courts. 24 759 HC Deb col 683. 25 [1985] AC 272 at 295. 26 The courts also adopted a broad interpretation of the term recklessness in s.14(1)(b) of the 1968 Act. See for example MFI Warehouses Ltd v Nattrass [1973] 1 WLR 307 per Lord Widgery at 312 and Dixons Ltd v Roberts (1984) 148 JP 513 per Forbes J at 519. For discussion see P Cartwright “Reckless Statements, Trade Descriptions and Law Reform (1996) 47(2) NILQ 171. 27 [1985] AC 272 at 295. This approach contrasts with that taken in other cases under the Act. For example, in Miller v Pickering Bull and Co, McNeil J argued that while the Act is a statute for the protection of consumers “it is also a penal statute: unless Parliament has made it clear that particular conduct is criminal, the courts…should not seek artificial constructions of the statutory words to make it so.” [1981] 3 All ER 265 at 270 7 Two conclusions may be drawn from the discussion above. The first is that there are examples of truly criminal offences, which will sometimes apply in the context of an injured consumer. It is submitted that there is little difficulty with classifying such conduct as criminal, but more difficulty with classifying those measures as consumer protection provisions. Secondly, although there are offences which are appropriately described as consumer protection measures, and which might be viewed as “serious” in the sense that they require proof of mens rea and/or involve serious or potentially serious harm, those offences appear not to be regarded as truly criminal. This suggests that there is a distinction between consumer protection offences and real crime, and that it is not formed solely on the basis of the need for proof of culpability, and/or the need to prove the risk or occurrence of serious harm. It is appropriate now to turn our attention to this class of offences – regulatory offences as they are frequently described – to investigate the extent to which it is appropriate that they utilise the criminal law. Consumer Protection and Regulatory Offences It is possible to contrast offences mala in se, with offences mala prohibita, (sometimes referred to as regulatory offences or quasi crime) which are those “which are not criminal in any real sense, but are acts which, in the public interest, are prohibited under a penalty”.28 Ramsay identifies three principal characteristics of regulatory crime.29 First, it tends to be over-inclusive, imposing strict liability which is tempered by statutory defences. Secondly, it is enforced by specialised bureaucracies which use discretion in 28 Sherras v De Rutzen [1895] 1 QB 918 at 922. I Ramsay Consumer protection: text and materials (Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989) at 183. Other commentators accept the terminology of regulatory offences, but differ in the characteristics they attribute to them. See e.g. N Lacey C Wells and O Quick Reconstructing Criminal Law (3rd ed, Butterworths, 2003) p 645 29 8 the implementation and enforcement of standards. Thirdly, it tends to be implemented by magistrates’ courts, with higher courts developing matters of policy. Other possible characteristics of regulatory crime are fourthly, that defendants will tend to be businesses, or people acting in the course of business rather than private individuals, and fifthly (and importantly) that it tends to carry relatively little stigma.30 It is important to emphasise that the characteristics identified above are merely indicators of whether an offence is likely to be viewed as regulatory; there is no formal category of regulatory offences recognised by the criminal justice system.31 Nevertheless, there is little doubt that consumer protection offences would be classed as regulatory offences. Examples of statutes based wholly or largely on the imposition of criminal sanctions are the Trade Descriptions Act 1968, the Consumer Protection Act 1987 (Part III), the Food Safety Act 1990 and the General Product Safety Regulations 2005. These are paradigms of the regulatory offence. They are enforced, largely through the magistrates courts, by specialised bureaucracies (generally local authority trading standards departments and environmental health departments). They are also enforced by way of compliance strategies.32 They (generally) impose strict liability and are subject to due diligence defences. In addition, they focus on defendants who act in the course of trade or business and carry relatively little stigma. It is helpful now to consider the principal arguments against using criminal law in the form of regulatory offences. In line with the theme of 30 See P Cartwright Consumer Protection and the Criminal Law (CUP, 2001) at 84. This contrasts with jurisdictions such as Germany, which recognises the concept of ordnungswidrigkeiten or administrative offences. There have sometimes been attempts to argue that regulatory offences are not part of the criminal law. See e.g. A Freiberg and P O’Malley “State Intervention and the Civil Offence” (1984) 18 Law and Society Review 373. 32 See below. 31 9 this piece the discussion below is in the context of consumer protection, but many of the arguments also apply in other areas of regulatory criminal law. OBJECTIONS TO THE USE OF CRIMINAL LAW IN REGULATORY OFFENCES Regulatory offences may not always be enforced in a consistent manner The first objection to the use of criminal law is that consumer protection offences may not always be enforced in a consistent manner. Ashworth argues that criminal laws should always be enforced with respect for equal treatment and proportionality. In relation to equal treatment, he opines that “those who commit wrongs of equivalent seriousness in relatively similar circumstances should be subject to censure of a similar magnitude”, and views this as an important principle of criminal law. 33 Other commentators have pointed to the risk of regulatory capture, where the close connections between enforcement authorities are the industries they are charged with regulating lead to the public interest being subordinated to that of the industry.34 Inconsistent enforcement may be a symptom of regulatory capture. Consumer protection offences are enforced by authorities which adopt compliance strategies in preference to formal prosecution.35 A compliance strategy has as its aim “to secure conformity with law by means of ensuring compliance or by taking action to prevent potential law violation without the necessity to detect, process and penalise violations.”36 By contrast, the aim of a deterrence strategy is “to secure Ashworth “Is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause?” op cit at 245. See generally M Bernstein Regulating Business by Independent Commission (Princeton University Press, 1955). 35 See AJ Reiss "Selecting Strategies of Social Control Over Organisational Life" in K Hawkins and J Thomas (eds) Enforcing Regulation (Boston: Kluwer Nijhoff, 1984) 23. 36 Ibid at 23. 33 34 10 conformity with the law by detecting violation, determining who is responsible for the violation, and penalising violations to deter violations in the future, either by those who are punished or by those who might do so were violations not penalised.”37 In some sectors an enforcement agency may adopt a compliance strategy in relation to most types of wrong but a deterrence strategy in particular types of case.38 However, where consumer protection is concerned, it seems that trading standards officers generally adopt compliance strategies, viewing prosecution as something of a last resort. According to Bragg: “[enforcement officers’] normal attitude is to see their major role as one of attempting to acquire compliance with legislation by information and persuasion...in many authorities prosecution is seen as a last resort and, sometimes, even as an admission of failure.”39 It is submitted that some of the concerns with the use of compliance strategies, and the extent to which they produce inconsistent enforcement in practice, may be overstated. First, despite the one-time popularity of capture theory, there are significant doubts about the extent to which it reflects the conduct of enforcement authorities or other regulators.40 Secondly, bargaining and negotiation may simply be the most effective 37 ibid at pp 23-24. See J Rowan-Robinson, PQ Watchman and CR Barker "Crime and Regulation” [1988] Crim LR 211 at pp 216-217. 39 RJ Bragg Trade Descriptions (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1991) p 202. Empirical research, although now somewhat dated, has shown that this strategy is favoured in the context of trade descriptions legislation. See e.g. R Cranston Regulating Business: Law and Consumer Agencies (London, MacMillan, 1979). The General Product Safety Regulations 2005 now provide a statutory requirement that enforcement authorities first seek voluntary action (see reg 10(5)). 40 Makkai and Braithwaite found “little support for the theory that regulatory enforcement is under the hegemony of the private interests from which so many regulators come – or to which they hope to go.” See T Makkai and J Braithwaite “In and Out of the Revolving Door: Making Sense of Regulatory Capture” (1995) 1 Journal of Public Policy 61 at p 78. 38 11 options for the enforcement agency. “Punishment is expensive; persuasion is cheap.”41 Indeed, the cost of regular prosecution may be prohibitive.42 Furthermore, there is some evidence that compliance strategies increase trust between regulators and regulated and this may improve the flow of information between them, which in turn leads to more effective enforcement. Painter has argued that successful enforcement “depends upon goodwill and co-operation between manufacturers, distributors, and enforcement officers. Unless trades people can discuss problems freely, uninhibited by fear of prosecution, the quality of service must suffer.”43 By contrast, a strategy based on punishment may foster “an organised business subculture of resistance to regulation”.44 This view has been expressed in a number of different areas.45 Adopting punishment as a first choice strategy may be seen as “unaffordable, unworkable, and counter productive in undermining the good will of those with a commitment to compliance.”46 Ashworth refutes suggestions that such approaches are effective in the long term, or justified on the basis of being economical.47 In relation to the first point, although it has been suggested that deterrence, or sanctioning strategies, would have the effect of reducing contraventions of regulatory legislation, the evidence on this is inconclusive.48 41 Ayres and Braithwaite Responsive Regulation (OUP, 1992) p 19. Veljanowski found that prosecution was from eight to ten times more time consuming than the typical factory visit. See C Veljanowski “Regulatory Enforcement: An Economic Study of the British Factory Inspectorate” (1983) 5 Law and Pol Q 75 at p 86 42 The issue of cost is discussed further below. 43 AA Painter “Why Prosecute?” (1974) 76 British Food Journal 38 at p 38. 44 Ayres and Braithwaite Responsive Regulation p 20. 45 See Bardach and Kagan Going by the Book. G Richardson, A Ogus and P Burroughs Policing Pollution (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1982) p 126 and R Cranston Regulating Business (1979). 46 Ayres and Braithwaite op cit p 26. 47 Ashworth “Is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause?” at 248. 48 See the less than conciliatory debate on the topic in the pages of the British Journal of Criminology in the form of F Pearce and S Tombs “Ideology, Hegemony and Empiricism” (1990) 30 Brit J Criminol 423 and K Hawkins “Compliance Strategy, Prosecution Policy and Aunt Sally” (1990) 30 Brit J Criminol 444. 12 In relation to the second point, if the justification for compliance strategies were merely that they save money, this would be a matter for concern.49 Certainly, enforcement authorities argue that they are under-funded, and this is a matter which should be addressed. But it is by no means certain that a higher level of funding would necessarily lead to a greater number of prosecutions. This is, however, a matter that needs further investigation. Another point on consistency is that there are measures in place that aim to ensure that enforcement is carried out equally within a particular sphere of activity, for example, co-ordination of enforcement activity on food and trading standards by LACORs.50 This addresses, for example, the risk of inconsistent enforcement of consumer protection offences. Regulatory offences may apply where the harm (if any) is minor Another objection to the use of consumer protection offences is that apply where the harm in question is relatively minor. Ashworth’s argument that the criminal law should only be used to censure persons for substantial wrongdoing has already been noted. He suggests that harmfulness should be judged in terms of its effect upon valued interests, be they individual or collective.51 Consumer protection offences apply where there is no victim and where, even if there were, the harm suffered would be minor. There is strength in the view that the authority of criminal law may be reduced where it is seen to concern itself with trifling matters. It has already been noted that regulatory offences tend, by 49 Some studies assume that the rarity of prosecutions is down to inadequate resources. See Cranston (1979) Regulating Business: Law and Consumer Agencies (London, Macmillan, 1979) and JE Conklin Illegal But Not Criminal (Englewood Cliffs, Prentice Hall, 1977). 50 LACORS stands for the local authorities coordinators of regulatory services. It is a local government body that helps to coordinate the enforcement activities of local authorities’ regulatory and related services. 51 Op cit. Ashworth is concerned not only with the degree of harm, but also the degree of culpability; intention or recklessness would be necessary for the requirement to be met. This would exclude offences of strict liability, even if subject to due diligence defences. This is considered below. 13 their very nature to be over-inclusive.52 In practice, the effects of this over-inclusiveness tend to be minimised by discretion in enforcement. However, some cases may lead the reader to wonder whether a prosecution was really an appropriate response. Examples such as McDonalds Hamburgers v Windle53 and Smedley’s Ltd v Breed54 are illustrative here. It is important to remember that newspaper headlines, and even law reports, seldom reveal the full story behind the litigation. However, the potential for convicting a defendant for minor harm remains and is cause for concern. Furthermore, it might be argued that over - reliance on prosecutorial discretion “puts at risk the rule of law in so far as it leaves the prospect of criminal conviction to the discretion of enforcement officers.”55 Levels of sanctioning may not be appropriate A further concern relates to sanctioning. On the one hand, sanctions may sometimes be seen in some cases to be disproportionate, particularly where the trader lacks any moral fault. It should be remembered that we should consider not only the penalty imposed by the court, but the other costs of being involved in a prosecution. Indeed, from a practical perspective, the main sanctions are likely to be the inconvenience in having to fight a prosecution and the potential negative publicity that might arise from a conviction rather than the formal sanction. As Baldwin recognises “penal effects may extend very considerably beyond the level of any fine imposed.”56 For example, he suggests that 52 See Ramsay op cit. [1987] Crim LR 200 54 [1974] AC 839. 55 Simester “Is Strict Liability Always Wrong?” at p 33. 56 R Baldwin op cit at 371. As noted below, some of these could be argued to be disproportionate in certain cases. 53 14 prosecution may adversely affect reputation, cause operational disturbances and managerial disruptions, worsen relationships between regulator and regulated and adversely affect investor relations.57 However, it may be that more concerning is the risk that the sanction may be insufficient to reflect the seriousness of the offence. There is some evidence that the penalties imposed in regulatory offences are frequently insufficient to act as a deterrent.58 A further problem is that of inconsistency in sanctioning. It has already been noted that the majority of regulatory offences are heard in the Magistrates’ Court. According to the Department for Constitutional Affairs, a typical magistrate will see a health and safety offence once every 14 years, and an environmental offence every 7 years. This may explain why inconsistency arises. 59 To the extent that inconsistency in sanctioning results, this is of concern to those who see consistency as one of the key principles of the criminal law. Regulatory offences are resource-intensive While regulatory offences may not be as resource intensive as the mainstream criminal law, they may, nevertheless, be unsuited to what may be relatively minor infringements. As the Better Regulation Executive argues “[t]he wholesale use of criminal proceedings to sanction regulatory offences…imposes a burden on the court system. This results in long waits for regulators and business in having cases heard. It also prolongs the 57 Ibid. Regulatory Justice found that many regulators believed that “financial penalties, in many cases, did not exceed the financial benefit of non-compliance, creating in effect perverse incentives for businesses not to comply with regulatory obligations.” (para 1.2). 59 Quoted in Regulatory Justice para 1.34. It may also explain why some sanctions appear surprisingly low. It could be argued that given the usual caseload of magistrates, which involves many violent and property crimes, regulatory offences appear minor. 58 15 resolution of the issue for the business.”60 It may be that this, in part, explains why relatively few prosecutions are initiated for regulatory offences. It was noted above that there are several reasons why it might be legitimate for formal prosecution to take place as a last resort. However, if the paucity of prosecution reflects the expense of the court process, and regulators feel unable to prosecute cases where such action is deserved, this is a matter of great concern. Regulatory offences impose strict liability Perhaps the most significant objection to the use of regulatory offences is that they impose strict liability. As a result, they may lead to the punishment of those lacking culpability and so constitute a misuse of the criminal law.61 This relates, of course, to the earlier discussion about what it means for conduct to be “criminal”. To the extent that the label of criminality implies a significant element of censure (if not moral condemnation) we may feel uneasy imposing strict liability for crime that does not involve serious wrongdoing. Fundamental to Ashworth’s conception of criminal law is that it exists primarily as a means of censure: “[m]y conception of criminal law gives primary place to its censuring function”.62 Simester shares some of Ashworth’s concerns, and argues that “the right not to be wrongly censured defeats any instrumental case for strict liability in stigmatic crimes.”63 From Simester’s perspective, the advantages to the prosecution of strict liability offences cannot override the offence caused by labelling someone as guilty 60 Ibid para 3.9. The presumption in favour of mens rea has recently been affirmed, but it appears that this presumption will easily be rebutted (if it applied at all) where the offence is regulatory in nature. 62 Op cit p 250. 63 AP Simester “Is Strict liability Always Wrong?” in AP Simester (ed) Appraising Strict Liability (OUP, 2005) 21 at 37. However, he later argues that elements of strict liability may such a role in limited cases. 61 16 of a serious offence when they lack moral fault. But this approach does not prevent strict liability being imposed in all cases. It allows for the use of strict liability where the stigma usually associated with the criminal law is lacking. This raises questions about the extent to which a distinction can be drawn between stigmatic and non-stigmatic offences. There is some evidence that defendants do care about being labelled as criminals for committing regulatory offences, as well as about the financial consequences of conviction. Borrie has suggested that major companies “are particularly resentful when a local trading standards officer in some part of the country secures a conviction which may be publicised in the local media.”64 More recently, Baldwin has noted that “very many companies find the imposition of a criminal sanction surprisingly shocking.” 65 This may reflect the contention that while the distinction between stigmatic and non-stigmatic offences might occur in the minds of those well-versed in regulatory criminal law, it will not be present in the minds of others. Although it has been argued that “most people distinguish in ordinary life between minor, regulatory-type offences and “true” crimes” this will not always be so.66 As a result, conviction may lead to a disproportionate reaction on the part of the public. If consumers regard conviction as implying culpability and consider changing their purchasing habits as a result, it is not surprising that some businesses are liable to feel aggrieved in the way Borrie and others suggest. Any confusion in the mind of consumers as to the extent to which conviction may imply culpability leads to another problem. Not only may strict liability penalise those G Borrie “Law and Codes for Consumers” (1980) JBL 315 at 321. Despite these observations, Borrie has argued elsewhere that some companies will be less concerned, treating the resulting fines as “tiresome pin pricks” (see G Borrie The Development of Consumer Law and Policy: Bold Spirits and Timorous Souls (London, Stevens and Sons 1984) at p 56. 65 Baldwin op cit at 372. 66 AP Simester and GR Sullivan Criminal law: Theory and Doctrine (2nd ed, Hart Publishing, 2003) p 28. 64 17 who are not at fault, but it may not distinguish adequately between those who are highly culpable (for example, acting advertently), those who are less culpable, (for example, acting negligently) and those who are not culpable at all.67 Conviction of the innocent is perhaps the major concern, but there is also a worry that those with a high degree of culpability may escape appropriate censure. Where strict liability is imposed, mens rea is irrelevant to guilt, and therefore inadmissible in evidence. Although it might be relevant to sentencing, this would require a further hearing.68 The result may be, therefore, that the conviction does not accurately reflect the seriousness of the conduct in question. In many cases, the maximum penalty will mean also that the sanction does not reflect that seriousness. Due Diligence Defences It was noted above that virtually all consumer protection offences are subject to due diligence defences. For example, s.39(1) of the Consumer Protection Act 1987 states: “in proceedings against any person for an offence to which this section applies it shall be a defence for that person to show that he took all reasonable steps and exercised all due diligence to avoid committing the offence.” As these defences aim to distinguish between those who are at fault and those who are not, do they help to provide a justification for the use of strict liability regulatory offences? Some commentators remain unconvinced. Ormerod argues that “such provisions are a distinct advantage on unmitigated strict liability; but they are still a deviation from the fundamental principle that the prosecution must prove the whole of their case; and an extensive use of offences of strict liability, 67 68 For these purposes I am treating negligence as a form of culpability. See Newton (1983) 77 Cr App R 13. 18 even when so qualified, is to be deplored.”69 Ormerod’s objection is that such defences offend the principle that it is the task of the prosecution to prove that the defendant is guilty, and not for the defence to prove that he is not.70 But regard must be had to the role of the defence. The point of a due diligence defence is to distinguish between the person who has done all he reasonably could to avoid committing an offence, and the person who has not. In practice it is extremely difficult to prove a negative. This is particularly so when we consider the issues that are likely to satisfy a court that due diligence has been exercised.71 Ormerod is correct to point out that this goes against the usual principles of proving offences, but it produces little injustice. Conceptually, the problem could be avoided by placing a requirement of the prosecution to prove beyond reasonable doubt that (a) the harm etc was committed, and (b) that the defendant had failed in his duty to take all reasonable precautions and exercise all due diligence to avoid the commission of the offence. There are, indeed, arguments that the law should be more willing to punish defendants (in particular corporations) for failing to etc.72 However, it is submitted that due diligence defences do go some towards addressing concerns about the imposition of strict liability. Regulatory offences may not work effectively 69 D Ormerod, Smith and Hogan p 163. It might be argued that strict liability offends the presumption of innocence guaranteed by Article 6(2) of the ECHR. However, that seems unlikely to be accepted. In Salibaku v France, the European Court of Human Rights stated that “in principle, the contracting States may, under certain conditions, penalize a simple or objective fact as such irrespective of whether it results from criminal intent or from negligence.” (1998) 13 EHRR 379. See P Roberts “The Presumption of Innocence Brought Home? Kebiliene Deconstructed” (2002) 118 LQR 41. 71 See for example Tesco Supermarkets Ltd v Nattrass [1972] AC 153. Whether reasonable precautions/steps are taken and due diligence exercised is a question of fact. 72 See e.g. B Fisse and J Braithwaite Corporations, Crime and Accountability (CUP, 1993). 70 19 The question of the effectiveness of consumer protection offences is of central importance. If regulatory offences are viewed purely in an instrumental fashion, then we might be able to find some justification for them on the basis that they work.73 One obvious advantage of strict liability regulatory offences over mens rea offences is that the prosecution does not have the burden of proving mens rea. Even if, in practice, prosecutions are seldom brought in the absence of fault, the removal of the requirement to prove mens rea gives the prosecution a stronger hand. As Richardson notes, “enforcement is conducted against a background of the criminal law and the implicit threat of its invocation.”74 From the point of view of the effectiveness of compliance strategies, therefore, strict liability may bring benefits when compared with mens rea offences. Punishing through the mechanism of the criminal law has several objectives, but the principal objective in the context of consumer protection offences is probably deterrence.75 Wells argues that: “[m]ost corporate crime theory has been deterrent-based, in the sense that the purpose of instituting sanctions has been to discourage violations and encourage good practice”,76 and the Law Commission has suggested that the criminal law could have a strong deterrent effect on corporations because of the publicity that results 73 See e.g. Simester op cit especially pp 25-30. G Richardson "Strict Liability for Regulatory Crime: The Empirical Research" [1987] Crim LR 295 at p 303. 75 The principal aims of punishment are said to be deterrence, incapacitation, rehabilitation, desert and restoration. Deterrence seems the most obvious justification for punishment in the business context, although there may also be room for desert-based theories. See P Cartwright chap 3 and K Yeung Securing Compliance: a Principled Approach (Oxford, Hart, 2004) chap 4. 76 Wells Corporations and Criminal Responsibility p 31. 74 20 from their prosecution.77 There is no doubt that corporations pay close attention to their status and image, and the label of conviction may affect this adversely.78 It has already been noted that many businesses do care about being labelled as criminals for breaching regulatory offences. As Ball and Friedman argue: “the word “crime” has symbolic meaning for the public and the criminal law is stained so deeply with notions of morality and immorality, public censure and punishment, that labelling an act as criminal often has consequences that go far beyond mere administrative effectiveness”. They conclude that “businessmen abhor the idea of being branded a criminal”, and that fear of prosecution is an effective deterrent to business people.79 It is sometimes assumed that business defendants are particularly liable to be calculating, and so particularly responsive to deterrent-based sanctions. In the words of Ramsay:80 “while criminals generally do not carefully calculate the probable consequences of their actions and therefore are often not deterred by the threat of punishment, this cannot be said of the corporate criminal. Since corporate activity is normally undertaken in order to reap some economic benefit, corporate decisionmakers choose courses of action based on a calculation of potential costs and benefits.” This thinking is undoubtedly influential. Economic models have been constructed to try to establish when to prosecute and what sanction to impose, based on assumptions 77 Law Commission (1972) para 88. For a contrary view see Ramsay Consumer Protection: Text Cases and Materials (London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989) p 190 78 C Wells op cit p 37. 79 Harry Ball and Laurence Friedman “Use of Criminal Sanctions in the Enforcement of Economic Legislation: a Sociological View” (1965) 17 Stanford Law Review 197 at 216-217. 80 I Ramsay “Developments in the Law: Corporate Crime” (1978-79) 92 Harvard L Rev 1227 at 1231. 21 about how businesses are likely to act.81 Kagan and Scholz divide businesses into different categories such as political citizens, amoral calculators and the organisationally incompetent.82 Amoral calculators are those who are “motivated entirely by profitseeking” and who “carefully and competently assess opportunities and risks.”83 For these businesses, as the authors argue, enforcement should focus on deterrence by prosecution. But many businesses will not be quite so calculating in practice. Some recent empirical research questions the extent to which punitive approaches to regulation encourage compliance on the part of many businesses.84 Baldwin comments as follows:85 “Corporations…will often be confused and irrational about punitive risks; their staff may conflate individual and corporate liabilities; they may be poorly organised to deal with, anticipate or react to punitive risks and the effects of sanctions; their Boards may under-perform in supervising or providing leadership on punitive risk management and they may be poorly placed to assess how they and their staff are performing as risk managers.” This raises a number of issues about the relationship between compliance, deterrence and risk management. In part, it reflects the idea of the business as organizationally incompetent – inclined to obey the law but potentially fallible.86 Ayres 81 See for example G Becker and the simplified example adopted in A Ogus Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory (OUP, 1994). 82 Robert A Kagan and John T Schloz The “Criminology of the Corporation” and Regulatory Enforcement Strategies in Keith Hawkins and John M Thomas (eds) Enforcing Regulation (Kluwer-Nijhoff, 1984) 67 at 67. 83 Ibid. 84 See for example R Baldwin and R Anderson Rethinking Regulatory Risk (London, DLA, 2002). 85 J Baldwin op cit at 370. 86 Kagan and Scholz op cit. 22 and Braithwaite also emphasise the extent to which offences arise from organisational failure on the part of businesses who want to comply.87 In such cases, it is doubtful how appropriate deterrence-based thinking is. It is important to think about the role of strict liability offences in encouraging high standards rather than simply deterring wrongdoing. It has been suggested that “the existence of strict liability does induce organisations to aim at higher and higher standards”, although the evidence on this point is not conclusive.88 It might be argued that due diligence defences play a role here. A defendant who knows that he can escape liability by showing the taking of all reasonable precautions and exercising of all due diligence has an incentive to establish systems to satisfy this requirement.89 This will not only make commission of the actus reus less likely, but will also help to ensure that, should it occur, a defence can be argued. It may be, therefore, that strict liability offences, when coupled with due diligence defences, provide appropriate incentives for businesses to take care. However, the difficulties identified by Baldwin above remain. Deterrence, Stigma and Labelling It was noted above that it could be argued that criminal sanctions operate effectively as a deterrent because they carry stigma. This, however, is problematic. First, it is not clear to what extent regulatory offences are stigmatic. It is submitted that while they may have some stigma attached to them, they carry less stigma that traditional crimes. This may 87 Ayres and Braithwaite op cit chap 2. M Smith and A Pearson "The Value of Strict Liability" [1969] Crim LR 5 at 16. Dickson J has argued that “there is no evidence that a higher standard of care results from absolute liability”. City of Saulte Ste Marie at p 171. He is using the phrase “absolute liability” in the sense that the term "strict liability" is used in this piece. 89 The courts will frequently be influenced by the paper system that the defendant has in place. See Tesco v Nattrass [1972] AC 153. 88 23 reduce the extent to which they are effective as a deterrent. Secondly, it is a cause for concern if the stigma of conviction is being used as part of the sanction by the way it generates adverse publicity. Adverse publicity may not adequately reflect the wrong done – it is determined by the “capricious jury of public opinion” and may be disproportionate to the seriousness of the wrongdoing.90 This is likely to lead to an understandable sense of injustice on behalf of the defendant. Furthermore, to the extent that punishing under the criminal law is justified on the basis of desert, it could be argued that regulatory offences fail to reflect adequately the culpability of the defendant, and the extent to which he or she is deserving of punishment. Looking to the Future: Consumer Protection Offences and their Alternatives The Unfair Commercial Practices Directive and Criminal Law Contrasting signals have been given out recently about the extent to which criminal sanctions will be used in the future in the area of regulatory crime. The need to transpose the Unfair Commercial Practices Directive (hereafter “the Directive”) into UK law by 12th June 2007 has led the Government to consider the role that criminal sanctions will play under a new regime. The Directive applies maximum harmonisation to most laws dealing with business to consumer commercial practices, and will require, at the very least, that some of the UK’s criminal law consumer protection statutes will have to be amended so that they fall into line with the Directive. The DTI’s consultation on implementing the Directive closed only on 8th March 2006, and so it is not yet clear to what extent criminal sanctions will be used to B Fisse “Publicity as a Criminal Sanction against Business Corporations” at 139. Cited in Fisse and Braithwaite at 310. 90 24 implement the Directive. However, early indications are that criminal law will continue to play a role. The DTI has stated:91 “At the time of writing, the Government is not minded to change the current balance between civil and criminal sanctions. This means that, although much existing consumer legislation using criminal sanctions will need amending, their criminal offences will be retained where it is possible and sensible to do so. The Government would similarly aim to retain existing due diligence defences and associated enforcement powers.” It is not proposed to go into detail on the Directive here. It is, however, worth noting the DTI’s view about the role of criminal offences post the Directive’s implementation. The DTI argues that some parts of the Directive, such as the general prohibition in Article 5 and the provisions for dealing with misleading omissions in Article 7 do not lend themselves to being dealt with by the criminal law. However, it considers that there may be scope for creating criminal offences to deal with aggressive commercial practices under Article 8 and Article 9. It also considers that some of the practices listed in annex 1 might be dealt with by the criminal law, while others might not. It is clear from the discussion above that there is some enthusiasm for retaining some consumer protection offences (albeit in an amended form so that they comply with the Directive) and to introduce new offences to deal with conduct that previously was 91 Consultation para 158. 25 dealt with inadequately by consumer law. This may not be surprising when it is considered that the Labour administrations since 1997 have created a large number of regulatory offences. However, this must be considered against an apparently widespread recognition that criminal sanctions may not always be the best method for protecting the consumer. There is enthusiasm in some quarters for examining alternatives to regulatory offences. Reference has already been made to the Better Regulation Executive’s discussion paper Regulatory Justice: Sanctioning in a post-Hampton World, which argues that criminal prosecution “attaches a severe moral condemnation and a criminal record to a business or individual”, and therefore sees it as important to limit the extent to which criminal sanctions are used in regulation.92 Regulatory Justice builds upon the conclusions of the Hampton Report (hereafter “Hampton”). A variety of regulatory techniques are available, and it is not possible to consider them all.93 However, the regulatory techniques that could most obviously be used in place of criminal sanctions will now be considered. Statutory Notices Regulatory Justice draws a distinction between statutory notices and administrative penalties. Statutory notices require businesses either to do specific things, or to refrain from doing specific things. Examples include improvement notices; prohibition or suspension notices; works notices and enforcement notices. Failure to comply with such a 92 Better Regulation Executive Regulatory Justice: Sanctioning in a post-Hampton World (BRE undated) para 1.28. 93 See e.g. R Baldwin and M Cave Understanding Regulation (OUP, 1999) chap 4; S Breyer Regulation and its Reform (Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1982); A Ogus Regulation op cit chaps 5 and 7-12. For discussion of the principal regulatory techniques for delivering consumer protection see P Cartwright op cit chap 2. 26 notice is generally a criminal offence, with the enforcement authority having to go to court to secure a sanction. Examples of statutory notices in the consumer protection field include improvement and prohibition notices that can be imposed for breach of food safety legislation, and safety notices that can be served under the General Product Safety Regulations 2005.94 For example, under the 2005 Regulations, enforcement authorities are empowered to serve a variety of safety notices, namely suspension notices, requirements to mark, requirements to warn, withdrawal notices and recall notices.95 These are subject to appeal.96 Breach of a safety notice gives rise to criminal liability. Statutory notices are a useful additional tool for regulators. In some cases, they more directly tackle the harm in issue than prosecution. For example, if a product is dangerous because it could pose a risk in certain conditions, the most appropriate response might be to serve a requirement to mark, which ensures that a product is marked in accordance with specific information warning of the risks that it might present. 97 A producer who has placed a dangerous product on the market may also be prosecuted for such, if the enforcement authority considers it appropriate, but the authority is likely to be more concerned to ensure that in the future, such products are appropriately marked. Administrative or Civil Penalties Statutory notices can be contrasted with administrative (sometimes called civil) penalties. Administrative penalties are defined by Regulatory justice as “penalties imposed by a regulator without the intervention of a court, although usually with a right to appeal to a 94 Over 4500 improvement notices and 190 prohibition notices were served by local authorities in the 200304 financial year (Regulatory Justice table 1.1). 95 See in particular regulations 11-15. 96 Regulation 17. 97 This could be achieved using regulation 12(1)(a). 27 court or similar independent tribunal.”98 It is believed that 15 UK regulators currently use administrative penalties, and they fall into two main types: fixed administrative penalties and variable administrative penalties. Fixed administrative penalties are used normally where there has been a technical breach of a regulation. Although the regulator may have some discretion whether to impose them, they are relatively inflexible, the legislation prescribing precisely when the infringement has taken place and what sanction will be imposed. It has been suggested that such penalties “are usually suited to minor, highvolume breaches, involving strict or absolute liability and therefore, little or no forensic enquiry.”99 Appeal can be either to a court or to a specialist tribunal. Variable administrative sanctions are also imposed by the regulator, but that regulator has significant discretion as to the level of sanction that can be imposed. To some extent, administrative penalties may operate in a similar manner to regulatory offences. Once the offending conduct is proved, the defendant is subjected to a financial penalty. These may present similar difficulties to fines; they need to be high enough to deter undesirable conduct, but not so high as to put traders out of business. Where they are too low they are likely to be treated as little more than a business expense. Fixed administrative penalties may be criticized as inadequate from the perspective of deterrence. Variable administrative penalties can sometimes be criticized as too low, but also have the potential to be disproportionate. 98 Hampton para 2.83. Baldwin and Cave refer to administrative sanctions which are sanctions that operate without recourse to the courts. However, they classify improvement and prohibition notices under this heading (p 112). 99 Regulatory Justice para 3.22. 28 There are, however, differences between administrative penalties and criminal sanctions. First, enforcement authorities may be more willing to take action under a civil penalties regime that a regime based on criminal sanctions. Administrative penalties would, arguably, remove the stigma associated with a criminal conviction.100 Would this make them less effective as a deterrent? There is some reason to think that it might not. First, the financial penalty may exceed any penalty that would be imposed by way of fine by criminal courts.101 Therefore, to the extent that deterrence is based on the level of fine imposed, civil penalties might work more effectively. Secondly, if enforcement authorities were more willing to impose civil penalties than they are to seek conviction (and it is submitted that they would be) this would increase to the likelihood of the sanction being imposed.102 Thirdly, administrative penalties would not be subject to the same procedural limitations as regulatory offences, and this would improve the chance of enforcement action being successful. For example, under the Financial Services and Markets Act 2000 the Financial Services Authority has the power to impose significant sanctions upon firms (or individuals) if it is satisfied on the balance of probabilities that there has been a contravention.103 Khanna argues that civil sanctions is likely to have as strong an effect upon deterring corporate misconduct as criminal sanctions are. 104 What administrative penalties generally lack is the element of condemnation associated with conviction, but if the wrongs in question are not deserving of such condemnation, this should be welcomed. 100 See D Tench Towards a Middle System of Law (London, Consumers Association, 1981). The FSA regime provides a good example of this. Shell was fined £17m for market abuse in 2004. 102 It is assumed that the rational amoral calculator will weigh up the likelihood of being punished and the level of likely punishment on the one hand with the potential benefits from the violation of the other. 103 Sanctions include not only financial penalties in the form of fines, but also restitution orders or even bans from the industry. 104 Vikramaditya S Khanna “Politics and Corporate Crime Legislation” (2004) Spring Regulation 30 at 31 and “Corporate Criminal Liability: What Purpose Does it Serve?” (1996) 109 Harvard Law Review ??? 101 29 Hampton demonstrated strong support for the use of administrative penalties, arguing that they should be introduced as “an extra tool for all regulators.” 105 In particular, Hampton saw administrative penalties as playing an important role in deterring wrongdoing by making it easier to ensure that offenders do not keep the economic benefits of their illegality.106 Ashworth too has supported alternative approaches to the criminal law, which he would call civil violations or administrative offences, and which he sees as providing quick and effective justice. These would generally be punished by way of fine, and would not attract a custodial sentence. Although they would be subject to simple procedures, there would remain minimum rights for defendants, such as access to a criminal court.107 The close relationship between civil penalties and the use of fines for breach of regulatory offences has been noted. Commenting on regulatory offences in the context of Canadian law, Dickson J stated that:108 “although enforced as penal laws through the utilization of the machinery of the criminal law, the offences are in substance of a civil nature and might well be regarded as a branch of administrative law to which traditional principles of criminal law have but limited application.” In some countries there are formal procedural distinctions between criminal law and regulatory law. For example, the concept of the administrative offence was created in 105 Hampton para 2.86. Ibid. 107 Ashworth “Is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause?” p 255. Hampton recommended that administrative penalties should make provision for appeal to magistrates’ courts (Hampton para 2.86). 108 R v City of Saulte Ste Marie (1978) 40 CCC (2d) 353 at 357. 106 30 Germany by the Act of Administrative Offences in 1968. Violations can be penalized by regulators where they are insufficiently serious to warrant a prosecution.109 The criminal courts play a role, but mainly in dealing with appeals. Although the term regulatory offence is frequently used in the UK, such offences are formally part of the criminal law. The more widespread use of administrative penalties would appear to address many of the concerns expressed at the use of criminal law in the area of regulation. Mens Rea Regulatory Offences? An additional point to consider is whether there is an argument for the retention of criminal sanctions where a defendant can be proved to have acted with a degree of culpability, but where the offence may not be viewed as truly criminal. It is submitted that the criminal law should continue to play a role in dealing with the most serious forms of wrongdoing. It was suggested above that few, if any, consumer protection offences could be classed a offences mala in se. On those few occasions where mens rea is necessary, the courts have tended to limit its effect. There may, however, be a strong argument for ensuring that enforcement authorities are able to use the criminal law where traders cause serious harm with mens rea. In some cases, this can be done with the criminal offences that exist. For example, corporate manslaughter, while difficult to prove, is recognised. It may be necessary to look at the creation of new offences where it is felt that conduct is deserving of a high degree of censure.110 As mentioned above, the 109 Sanctions are however significant, with fines reaching up to 500,000 euros. There is evidence of some regulators using mainstream criminal offences in order to ensure that the “right message” is given out. For example, the Food Standards Agency has been known to pursue some cases using the law of conspiracy. There have also been examples of trading standards officers using the Theft Act 1968 where consumer protection offences appeared inadequate. See David CE Roberts “The Use of the Theft Act in Trading Standards Cases” (1992) 9(4) Trading Law 205. 110 31 present Government has shown a willingness to use the criminal law in the area of consumer protection, but has tended to create offences which impose strict liability. It is submitted that there is a strong argument for having criminal sanctions existing alongside administrative penalties. If these sanctions required proof of mens rea, and operated in addition to a regime of administrative penalties, this would address the principal concerns considered above. Consistency and Regulatory Structure An additional concern set out above is that regulatory offences are sometimes enforced in an inconsistent manner. One reason for this may be the extent to which enforcement is carried out locally.111 Although there is some coordination of enforcement in the area of consumer protection, it has been argued that this could go much further. Hampton recommended that there should be a new central authority which would take lead responsibility for trading standards at a national level. Local authority trading standards departments would still exist, but the new body would endeavour to “deliver a more coherent enforcement network and …improve performance in local authorities around the country.” The Government recently consulted on the establishment of the new body (the Consumer and Trading Standards Agency, or CTSA). A summary of the responses the Government received was published in March 2006. Before this, however, the Chancellor of the Exchequer announced that the Government would be establishing a Local Better Regulation Office (LBRO), which will not take on the role of a regulator, but will “work in partnership with local authorities and the national regulators to deliver a risk-based 111 There are, for example, 203 trading standards departments and 408 environmental health departments. 32 approach to business inspection and enforcement.”112 As a result, it seems that LBRO will take on some of the roles originally envisaged for CTSA, but will apply these to a broader range of activities. Other roles envisaged for CTSA will be undertaken by the Office of Fair Trading, with the OFT becoming “the Champion for consumer enforcement issues.” Detail is currently very thin, and it is difficult to comment on the proposals at this stage. Suffice it to say that there is the potential for the new structure to address some of the concern about inconsistent regulation identified above. Conclusions The UK has a long history of using regulatory offences to protect consumers, and there is a strong case for using criminal sanctions where traders are guilty of substantial wrongdoing. However, while consumer protection offences may be prosecuted where substantial wrongdoing exists, few of these offences require proof of such wrongdoing before the defendant can be convicted. Consumer protection offences bear the hallmarks of regulatory offences: they impose strict liability, are subject to due diligence defences, are enforced by specialist agencies which make extensive use of compliance strategies, target businesses and carry relatively little stigma. The use of regulatory offences raises concerns. First, there is concern that they may not be enforced consistently. It is submitted that this can be overstated, and that mechanisms exist, for example coordination under the home authority principle and by LACORS, that minimises the effect of this. Nevertheless, there are legitimate concerns here. Secondly, regulatory offences apply where harm is minor. This is undoubtedly so, and there are strong arguments that criminal sanctions should not be used in such cases. 112 Reducing admin burdens para 13. 33 Thirdly, levels of sanctioning may not be appropriate. This concern is multi-layered. The principal concern appears to be one of inconsistent sanctioning. Occasionally sanctions appear disproportionate, more frequently they appear unduly lenient. However, it should be noted here, as Baldwin recognises, that “the effects of penal sanctions may extend very considerably beyond the level of fine imposed.”113 Fourthly, regulatory offences can be resource-intensive, posing considerable burdens on the court system, as well as on regulators and business. Fifthly, regulatory offences tend to impose strict liability. Even if we accept that regulatory offences may not carry the same stigma as more mainstream offences, there is doubt about the appropriateness of imposing criminal liability without proof of fault. Put simply, strict criminal liability looks, feels, and may be, unjust, even with safeguards of prosecutorial discretion and due diligence defences in place. Finally, regulatory offences may simply not work effectively, particularly as a deterrent. It is frequently assumed that traders “choose courses of action based on a calculation of potential costs and benefits” and this is used to justify optimal deterrence based approaches to enforcement.114 However, it should be remembered that many offences are not committed in so calculating a manner. Some of these concerns can be addressed by alternatives to regulatory offences, in particular administrative penalties. An appropriately constructed and enforced regime of administrative sanctions would still provide effective deterrence, while reducing the scope for inappropriate labelling. Where there is compelling evidence of culpability, criminal sanctions should still be able to be invoked, but the criminal label would be restricted to such conduct. It is doubtful that Parliament will go this far. However, it is 113 114 Op cit. See Ramsay op cit. 34 submitted that a two-pronged regime of administrative penalties where moral fault may be lacking, and criminal liability where it is present would protect the effectiveness of consumer law, and the integrity of criminal law. 35