The (Multiple) Realization of Psychological and other Properties in the Sciences. By Kenneth Aizawa and Carl Gillett. …we should… not focus on weird cases while we are trying to get things straight about multiple realizability as a matter of methodological concern in science;… Let’s free discussions of realization, reduction, emergence, supervenience and the like from reliance on very far out examples and counterexamples. (Boyd (1999), p.91). …there is nothing intrinsically mentalistic (or social or cultural) about multiplerealizability... Though… [this trait has] been taken by some philosophers to be characteristic of the mental, I would argue that [it is] characteristic of any move from a lower compositional level to a higher one. That goes for the theory of chemical bonding relative to fundamental quantum-mechanical theories of the atom no less than for the relation between the neurophysiological… and the cognitive… (Wimsatt (1994), p.224) Over recent decades, work on ‘realization’ and ‘multiple realization’ has been central in both the philosophy of science and the philosophy of mind.1 However, the views presented in these two areas have been very different, often embodying different notions of ‘realization’ offered in the course of distinct projects.2 The failure to heed such differences has arguably produced a range of problems and in particular some of the most prominent accounts of ‘realization’ and ‘multiple realization’ offered in the philosophy of science have arguably been badly underappreciated and misinterpreted.3 Our primary purpose in this paper is therefore to more clearly articulate the standard view of ‘realization’ and ‘multiple realization’ offered in the philosophy of science, focusing upon a number of concrete examples but examining scientific cases of psychological properties, and their various kinds of realizer, in most detail. What we will term the ‘received’ view of special sciences was defended by writers such as Jerry Fodor, William Wimsatt, and Philip Kitcher.4 The proponents of the received view overturned the Positivist’s jaundiced view of special sciences by looking at real examples from the biological sciences, geology, linguistics, neurophysiology, psychology, and economics, amongst other areas. And central to the received view’s critique was the ontological claim that examples in the special sciences very often involve the ‘multiple realization’ of properties where 2 this phenomenon was then used to establish a range of important results. As our opening passage from William Wimsatt highlights, the claims about multiple realization made by proponents of the received view of special sciences were never intended to apply simply to psychology or psychological properties, for the received view used cases of multiple realization drawn from a wide range of special sciences and offers a general picture of all the disciplines above physics. Our first goal will therefore be, in Part 1, to offer a general account of the realization of properties in the special sciences and then to provide an equally general account of multiple realization. Following the counsel of Richard Boyd in our other opening passage, we focus upon real scientific examples to guide our account. To further sharpen our account of multiple realization in the sciences, in Part 2, we consider an alternative theory recently offered by Laurence Shapiro (2004) and the associated objections that Shapiro levels at our position. We show that Shapiro’s criticisms are misplaced and argue that Shapiro’s own account of multiple realization in the sciences faces grave problems: namely, that it fails to acknowledge all the kinds of scientific explanations that reveal “causally relevant properties” and that it is unable to accommodate the use scientists make of theories from a range of levels to guide or constrain their research. Although presented as part of a fully general view of special sciences, one of the most prominent applications of the received view was to the psychological sciences, with writers, such as Fodor (1968) and Block and Fodor (1972), presenting empirical evidence that they claimed showed psychological properties are multiply realized. Unsurprisingly, recent philosophical work on the neurosciences has examined whether these earlier claims actually hold-up in the face of a more careful examination of empirical results and many of these assessments have argued that current neuroscience challenges the multiple realization of psychological properties. 5 In earlier work, we have replied to the most important negative arguments that purport to show 3 there is no multiple realization of psychological properties in the sciences.6 In the second half of this paper, we therefore focus upon using our framework for scientific multiple realization to assess whether there is positive evidence for the existence of multiple realization of psychological properties in the sciences, focusing first upon evidence from biochemistry, in Part 3, and then neurophysiology in Part 4. Our final conclusion is that it is important to provide more precise frameworks for the nature of compositional relations generally, and for realization and multiple realization in particular, using concrete and mundane scientific cases as Boyd and Wimsatt counsel. For such examples allow us to clearly appreciate when, and why, there is multiple realization across the sciences. Furthermore, following such a strategy, we show that given our present empirical evidence we have strong reason to believe that psychological properties are indeed multiply realized both at the biochemical and neuronal levels. Part 1 - Realization and Multiple Realization in the Sciences. Very little scientific work makes explicit use of the term ‘realization’ in anything like the way in which it has been used by defenders of the received view. Thus, like so much philosophy of science, investigation of the realization of higher level properties by lower level properties constitutes a kind of examination and reconstruction of scientific practice, theorizing etc. To guide our work we will begin by examining some familiar cases from the sciences and to make our discussion of these examples manageable we follow recent debates in using a version of the “causal theory of properties”. This is a variant of Shoemaker (1980)’s account under which a property is individuated by the causal powers it potentially contributes to the individuals in which it is instantiated. On this view, two properties are different when they contribute different powers under the same conditions. 4 The basic features of realization relations can be illuminated by all manner of scientific examples, but for brevity we will begin by considering an example whose details are compact, and widely known. Later in the paper we will then examine a range of less familiar cases. But, to start, consider the extreme hardness of a diamond, in its property of having a Knoop hardness value 10,400 kg/mm2along a cubic face, and the bonding and alignment of carbon atoms.7 Our illustration in Figure 1 highlights some of the mechanisms involved with this case. When the edge of a cut diamond is pressed with force across a pane of glass, in a certain sequence of directions, the diamond’s hardness causes a Z-shaped scratch in the glass. Here we have a causal process, i.e. mechanism, which is grounded by the triggering of one of the diamond’s powers, contributed to the diamond by its property of being very hard, which results in a certain effect – a Z-shaped scratch on the glass. As Figure 1 also roughly captures, the sciences have provided an elegant, and familiar, explanation of this higher level process by illuminating its implementation. For the sciences have shown how the lower-level mechanisms of particular carbon atoms breaking the bonds between, and displacing, specific glass molecules compose, or more specifically ‘implement’, the process of the diamond scratching the glass. Under the relevant background and triggering conditions, the powers of the carbon atoms, to hold each other in close relative spatial relations and to break the bonds between glass molecules when under pressure, are triggered in a host of carbon atoms. The result is a large number of causal processes involving particular carbon atoms each of which cause specific glass molecules to break their bonds with other glass molecules and change their spatial locations. It is worth marking that none of these lower-level mechanisms involving carbon atoms results in an effect that has a macroscopic breadth and depth, or has a Z-shape, or any of the other features of the process of the diamond scratching the glass. Instead, when triggered, the powers of particular carbon atoms each ground a mechanism that causes certain 5 glass molecules to break their bonds and change position. Nonetheless, the many mechanisms involving carbon atoms together implement, i.e. non-causally result in, the qualitatively different process involving the diamond. Against this backdrop, since properties are our primary focus, let us more carefully consider the compositional relations posited in this type of case between property instances and their powers, starting with the latter. A property instance is an entity that makes a difference to the causal powers of individuals, usually by contributing powers to individuals. Most scientific properties are thus individuated by the causal powers they potentially contribute to individuals under certain background conditions. We can consequently see that the sciences again illuminate how, and why, the properties and relations of the carbon atoms compose, or ‘realize’, the properties of the diamond. For we have now seen that the powers of the carbon atoms that, as we will put it, comprise the powers individuative of the properties of the diamond. As a result, the sciences explain why if one has the carbon atoms with their properties and relations, then the latter properties will together realize the diamond’s property of hardness. For the carbon atoms’ relations of bonding and alignment together contribute powers that comprise the powers individuative of the property of being very hard and hence non-causally result in, and realize, an instance of the property of hardness in the diamond. Using the causal theory of properties, we can formalize these observations in a ‘thumbnail’ account for the kind of realization we have found in our case in this theory schema:8 (Realization) Property/relation instance(s) of F1-Fn realize an instance of a property G, in an individual s under conditions $, if and only if, under $, s has powers that are individuative of an instance of G in virtue of the powers together contributed by the instances of F1-Fn to s or s’s constituent(s), but not vice versa. Given its abstract nature, we can better illuminate our schema if we now draw out of the diamond case a number of features that all compositional relations share. 6 First, we should mark that relations like realization are obviously a species of determination relation, but are rather different from causal relations. The ‘horizontal’ determination involved with causation is temporally extended, relates wholly distinct entities and often involves the transfer of energy and/or the mediation of force. In contrast, compositional relations are not temporal in nature, since their ‘vertical’ determination is instantaneous, does not relate wholly distinct entities, and does not involve the transfer of energy and/or the mediation of force. Composition is thus a variety of what has been termed ‘non-causal’ determination. Second, scientific composition usually relates qualitatively different kinds of entity. For example, diamonds have properties like hardness, and hardness contributes the power to scratch glass. But no carbon atom has the property of hardness, nor any property that contributes the power to scratch glass. In our case, we thus have individuals that constitute other individuals with which they share no properties, as well as properties that realize other properties with which they share no common powers, and similar points hold for the relevant powers and mechanisms. A quick examination of the compositional relations illuminated by the full spectrum of special sciences shows that this feature is common to all of their findings. Third, and perhaps most importantly, as we noted with realization relations above, we should mark a common feature of scientific composition. For as in the realization of properties, given their interconnections, the entities studied by lower level sciences together compose the qualitatively different entities studied by higher level sciences. The simple secret of compositional relations, and the mechanistic explanations that posit them, is therefore that, although individually the component entities are qualitatively different from the composed entity, nonetheless the components together non-causally result in the composed entity. Compositional relations in the sciences are thus often ‘many-one’ with regard to their relata, with many component entities and one composed entity. This distinctive feature of the compositional 7 relations posited in the sciences consequently allows one to mechanistically explain entities of one kind in terms of entities of very different kinds. For example, what makes for the hardness of a diamond is not the property of any single carbon atom, but the way in which the properties and relations of individual carbon atoms work together. Noting these general features of scientific composition helps illuminate the character, and strength, of our theory schema for realization. Since we can now see that our schema has the merit of accommodating all of these characteristics of scientific relations of composition. The Dimensioned account allows that realization is a non-causal relation that is synchronous, between entities which are not wholly distinct and which does not involve either the transfer of energy and/or mediation of force. Furthermore, our schema accommodates realizer and realized properties that are qualitatively distinct and instantiated in different individuals, like the carbon atoms and the diamond. Finally, the schema embodies the idea that realizer properties together play the causal role of the realized property without directly contributing any of the realized property’s individuating powers. The second and third of these general features of scientific composition also serve to illuminate the underlying nature of multiple realization in the sciences. If we reflect on the implications of combining the characteristic that scientific realization often relates qualitatively different kinds of property with the feature that properties together realize other properties, then we can see why we will have very different realizer properties that, on different occasions, all realize instance of the same property. Putting things crudely, it is because realizer properties, that are qualitatively distinct from other realizers and the realized property, together realize some special science property that we get multiple realization. Since distinct combinations of lowerlevel properties, that are different from each other in the powers they contribute and hence the causal mechanisms that they ground, may nonetheless still together non-causally result in 8 instances of the same special science property. We can use these points to frame a more precise abstract account of such multiple realization: (Multiple Realization) Instances of a property G are multiply realized if and only if, (i) under condition $, an individual s has an instance of property G in virtue of the powers contributed by instances of properties/relations F1-Fn to s, or s’s constituents, but not vice versa; (ii) under condition $* (which may or may not be identical to $), an individual s* (which may or may not be identical to s) has an instance of a property G in virtue of the powers contributed by instances of properties/relations F*1-F*m of s* or s*’s constituents, but not vice versa; (iii) F1-Fn ≠ F*1-F*m and (iv), under conditions $ and $*, F1-Fn of s and F*1-F*m of s* are at the same scientific level of properties. Overall, the theory schema is fairly mundane. Conditions (i)-(iii) simply frame the demand for distinct sets of realizer properties for instances of the same realized property. However, the final condition deserves more comment. Implicitly, philosophers of science have always had something like condition (iv) in mind, but we show later that making this condition explicit has a variety of advantages. To see why one needs (iv), either implicitly or explicitly, consider the following common situation. Properties and relations of carbon atoms realize hardness; but obviously properties and relations of certain fundamental microphysical properties realize the properties and relations of carbon atoms and realize the property of the diamond. But since (the properties and relations of the carbon atoms) ≠ (the properties and relations of fundamental microphysical individuals), then it appears that in such cases if we only use conditions (i)-(iii) then this entails we have a case of multiple realization. Obviously, what is awry is that the two sets of properties are not at the same level and hence are implicitly excluded as even candidates to ground a case of multiple realization. Addition of condition (iv) resolves this problem, though we suggest that all sides implicitly endorse (iv) as a shared background condition. 9 An added advantage of using (iv) is that it combats a common and problematic philosophical practice. The practice in question is that of talking simply about the ‘multiple realization’ of some property, whether psychological, biological or whatever, and saying nothing 9 further. Often, given the context, this may be a harmless way of talking, but we should note how it may be damaging. Suppose that some higher level psychological property G is multiply realized by microphysical properties of fundamental particles and hence multiply realized at the microphysical level. This does not, of course, mean that G is multiply realized in, say, distinct physiological properties. After all, it is logically possible to have G be univocally realized in the physiological properties of two organisms where these physiological properties are themselves multiply realized by the microphysical properties of the fundamental particles that constitute these two organisms. So, our two instances of G might be univocally realized at level X (the physiological level), but multiply realized at, say, level X – 1 (the microphysical level). In such cases simply discussing ‘multiple realization’ of G potentially leads to confusion which is easily avoided by indexing such claims to particular realizers and levels. We will see later that failing to appreciate, or respect, such points has lead to substantive problems. In order to articulate how we intend our account of multiple realization to be understood, and to further illuminate its nature, we now want to work through some simple scientific examples. Our goal will be to explain both when our account says we do not have multiple realization, as well as when we do. Case I. Take some group of carbon atoms s1-sp. At one time, bonded together in one way, i.e. with one set of bonding and spatial relations, these carbon atoms have properties/relations that realize an instance of the property of having a Knoop hardness value 10,400 kg/mm2along a cubic face –that is, the hardness of a diamond. However, at another time, the very same carbon atoms when bonded together in another way, i.e. with distinct bonding and spatial relations, can realize an instance of the far lower Knoop hardness found in graphite. Our example thus illuminates how differing properties/relations of the same individuals, either at a 10 time or over time, may realize instances of distinct higher level properties. We return to this point below when we consider recent discussions of multiple realization. Case II. Consider two individual diamonds s and s* that contain exactly the same number of carbon atoms in exactly the same relations of bonding and spatial alignment at standard temperature and pressure. Here we have what one might naturally call two numerically distinct realizations of the property having a Knoop hardness value of 10,400 kg/mm2 along a cubic face. This, however, is not an example of multiple realization for the received view, since the instances of the properties involved in this case clearly fail condition (iii) because we do not have instances of distinct realizer properties/relations in the relevant constituents of the two diamonds. Merely having distinct instances of the very same properties does not suffice for multiple realization under the received view or our theory schema. Case III. Consider an example where we have distinct materials each of which have the same Knoop hardness. Diamonds do not provide a clean example, but other cases of materials with the same hardness are easy to find. Thus, to take an example from modern dentistry, we have a variety of Cobalt-Chromium alloys and Palladium alloys that are used as fillings in humans and which instantiate instances of the property of having a Knoop hardness in the range 350-400 kg/mm2. In addition, of course, much sound, unetched human and bovine enamel (i.e. human and bovine teeth) also has the property of having a Knoop hardness in the range 350-400 kg/mm2.10 In such cases, under our schemata we will have multiple realization. For example, assume that we have distinct instances of the property of having a certain Knoop hardness in both a Palladium alloy filling and also in a human tooth. The properties and relations of the constituent atoms and/or molecules that are the realizers in these individuals are obviously distinct, since the bonding relations between the metal atoms/molecules, and the molecules in the enamel, are different. Furthermore, these atoms/molecules, and their bonding relations, are 11 plausibly at the same level of properties. As a result, our theory schemata say that the relevant instances of the property of having this Knoop hardness are multiply realized. To conclude, we now have a better grip on the general features of the compositional relations posited in mechanistic explanations that defenders of the received view focused upon in their work. In particular, we have more precise theory schemata for both realization and multiple realization. Furthermore, following on from Case III, it should also be obvious to the reader that multiple realization will be common in materials science, engineering sciences, and a host of other disciplines. For these areas are replete with distinct substances known and valued, like the Palladium alloy fillings, because they realize common higher level properties, whether having a certain Knoop hardness, density, refractive index, conductance, etc., which are realized by the properties and relations of some other, distinct, material with rather different accompanying features. Whether we also have multiple realization in a still wider range of disciplines, and in particular in the neurosciences and psychology, is an issue which we examine further in Parts 3 and 4. However, in the next section, we turn to objections, and a rival, to our account of multiple realization. Part 2 – An Opposing View and Objections: Shapiro on Scientific Multiple Realization. At this point, it useful to briefly assess our theory schemata and we can do this if we now turn to the important work on multiple realization of Larry Shapiro ((2000), (2004), (Unpublished)). For Shapiro not only offers a contrasting account of multiple realization in the sciences, but also gives voice to some common concerns about our position. We will begin by outlining two opposing objections Shapiro presents to our view (that it is too permissive and too restrictive), briefly respond to these criticisms, and then detail Shapiro’s alternative account of 12 multiple realization, since his challenges to our theory schemata appear most plausible against the backdrop of his own positive view. One common worry about our precise account, and the received view generally, is that it is too permissive and leads to there being too much multiple realization in the sciences and the natural world. This is often argued by critics to be counterintuitive and hence objectionable. In recent work, for example, Shapiro (Unpublished) has argued that our account of multiple realization would mean that a difference in “just one quark” would lead to multiple realization, where the underlying intuition is apparently that this would consequently make the existence of multiple realization far too widespread. Let us call this the ‘Permissiveness Objection’. In response, it is worthwhile to start by emphasizing that we have offered our accounts of realization and multiple realization as parts of the wider project of understanding the compositional concepts used in the sciences. We suggest that the success of such accounts should be judged by how well they do in capturing the features of the concepts actually used in scientific explanations. But what if the resulting account does not accord with some philosopher’s prior expectations about compositional concepts? For example, what if our view entails that realization, and multiple realization, are more widely found than analytic philosophers of mind of an earlier generation assumed? As in so many other cases where the sciences have surprised us, we fail to see why such a conflict with the expectations of philosophers poses a problem for the success of our accounts of realization and multiple realization. Instead, we contend that the success of our theory schemata is, at least to a large measure, a thoroughly empirical matter to be judged, for example, by whether they ascribe, or fail to ascribe, realization and/or multiple realization in accord with our scientific evidence. We have thus seen that the Permissiveness Objection in the bare form Shapiro presents it fails to pose a problem for our account, but we invite those concerned about our view to explore 13 whether the Permissiveness Objection can be made more successfully using a richer range of empirical evidence. In contrast to the latter concern, Shapiro (2004) gives voice to a complaint of exactly opposite kind – namely, that our accounts of realization and multiple realization are far too restrictive in their ascriptions. Let us call this the ‘Restriction Worry’. For example, Shapiro objects that in virtue of our accounts of realization and multiple realization we are: …committed to the claim that, ultimately, every property is realized in the same way. Talk of multiple realizability, on the dimensioned account [of realization], vanishes, for, it turns out, that the same properties that realize, say, a digital watch also realize an analog watch (as well as everything else under – and over – the sun). (Shapiro (2004), p.44) This version of the Restriction Worry appears to be that the same properties and relations of physics, what Shapiro terms a “handful of basic properties” (Shapiro (2004), p.44) will be the realizers of all properties. Again disambiguating the claims of multiple realization at issue here by indexing to particular properties, the Worry is that our account entails that all higher level properties will be univocally realized by the properties and relations of physics which appears highly implausible given our empirical evidence. In response to this concern, it is useful to consider how, for example, someone might object in a similar way that our view of realization and multiple realization is mistaken using the case of hardness. For, such an objector might argue, our account takes the same kind of individual, in carbon atoms, and the same kinds of relation, in bonding and spatial alignment, to be involved in the realization of both the high Knoop hardness of a diamond and the low Knoop hardness of graphite by the properties and relations of materials science. Thus, in an analogous fashion, the objector might conclude that our account is too restrictive by putatively entailing 14 that all instances of hardness, whether of a high or low Knoop value, are all univocally, rather than multiply, realized by the properties and relations of carbon atoms. The obvious point to make in response, highlighted by our discussion of Case I above, is that although the same very general kinds of property and relation of carbon atoms may be involved in realizing the hardness of diamonds and graphite, nonetheless the specific properties and relations that are realizers in these cases are different in ways outlined by the sciences concerned. Similarly, on a grander scale, though the same very general kinds of property and relation illuminated by fundamental physics have plausibly been shown to be realizers of very many special science properties/relations at the microphysical level, nonetheless the sciences have also shown that the specific microphysical properties and relations involved in realizing various special science properties are usually different – though where, and what form, multiple realization takes at any level is obviously an empirical matter. We can therefore see that Shapiro’s bare version of the Restriction Worry also fails, though again we invite anyone concerned with our position to explore whether a richer base of empirical evidence can bolster such a concern. Shapiro’s objections are offered against the background of his positive account of a certain kind of explanation in the sciences and corresponding views of both realization and multiple realization. The latter account is at odds with our own view and is developed most fully in Shapiro (2004), so let us now turn to this competing position. Shapiro develops his theory of realization, and multiple realization, primarily through the use of his understanding of Cumminsstyle functional analysis. According to Shapiro, a property G, of an individual s, is multiply realizable if there exist distinct functional analyses of G. For example, Shapiro considers whether the property of being a watch is realized by the properties of being, respectively, an analog watch and a digital watch.11 Shapiro then asks what properties of analog and digital watches make them 15 distinct realizations of watch (if they are in fact distinct). His overall way of thinking about the issue of multiple realization emerges when he writes: …I propose to use the name R-property as a label for those properties of realizations whose differences suffice to explain why the realizations of which they are properties [sic] count as different in kind. In short, two types of realization of some functional kind, like corkscrew or watch, count as different kinds of realization if (by definition) they differ in their R-properties… “Which properties of a realization are R-properties?”… Rproperties are those that are identified in the course of functionally analyzing some capacity. It is to functional analysis, I claim, that we should look for the identification of R-properties because it is functional analysis that uncovers those properties that causally contribute to the production of the capacity of interest. (Shapiro, 2004, pp. 52-53). Given these commitments, when Shapiro turns to the question of whether the properties and relations of lower level constituent individuals, such as quarks, electrons, or atoms, can be realizers, Shapiro’s understanding of functional analysis, and his key notion of an R-property, lead him to conclude that such properties and relations are not realizers, and hence not the basis for multiple realization. With two corkscrews made of aluminum and steel, or to vary the example, two objects each with a Knoop hardness of 370 kg/mm2 where one is made of Palladium alloy and the other of unetched human enamel, our account will say we have multiple realizations of the property of being a corkscrew or the property of having a certain Knoop hardness. In contrast, given his understanding of functional analysis and an R-property, Shapiro denies that properties/relations of the relevant atoms/molecules are R-properties at all, hence denies that these are examples of multiple realization (Shapiro (2004), pp. 56-7). This marks one difference between our account and Shapiro’s. 16 A further divergence is that on our view realization is a transitive relation, where under Shapiro’s account realization is not transitive.12 In order to better assess the impact of these differences, and to evaluate the competing accounts of realization and multiple realization, we need to see how they accord with our evidence from the sciences taken in the broadest sense to include not just our scientific findings about particular phenomena, but also the various features of scientific explanations, methodology and more. And although Shapiro’s rejection of the transitivity of scientific realization might appear innocuous, we will now argue that this and other features of his account lead to a couple of crucial difficulties for his view. As Shapiro (2004) outlines in a range of concrete cases, theories and findings in the higher and lower level sciences that respectively investigate realizer and realized properties are often used to guide, constrain or evaluate each other. In fact, it is well documented (Darden and Maull (1977); Bechtel and Richardson (1993)) that working scientists readily look downwards, or upwards, across levels of realizing and realized properties in order to find the explanatory resources to help overcome difficulties. We suggest that one obvious reason for such intertheoretic constraint is that the objects of these theories bear compositional relations, in the shape of realization relations, which are ontological determination relations and that this ontological constraint leads to inter-theoretic constraint. Furthermore, the ready ability to reach downwards, or upwards, across a number of levels of realizing and realized properties also strongly suggests that the relevant ontological determination relations are transitive – for otherwise there is no explanation of why working scientists may move so easily between theories at one or more lower, or higher, levels. As we have argued at length elsewhere, the nature of these scientific practices and the inter-theoretic constraint that underpins them apparently supports the view of realization and multiple realization we have offered.13 For under our account, realization is a transitive 17 ontological determination relation and thus under our view of the nature of scientific realization one may, for example, track realization relations down one, or more, levels of realizer properties in order to inter-theoretically constrain one’s higher level theory of some higher level realized property. Given Shapiro’s rejection of transitivity his account of realization cannot account for this common methodological phenomenon in the sciences which poses a real problem for his theory of realization and multiple realization. Furthermore, we should also note that Shapiro’s limitation of R-properties to properties of the same individual, through his sole focus upon functional analysis, also independently leads to a similar problem, leaving Shapiro’s account of realization unable to explain why scientists may so readily make use of the relations of determination between the properties of distinct individuals at different levels. So far we have focused on difficulties that primarily arise from Shapiro’s rejection of transitivity, though we have seen that Shapiro’s narrow conception of R-properties produces related problems. We can now see that the latter feature of Shapiro’s account leads to another set of difficulties. As we have seen, Shapiro’s exclusive focus is upon just one type of explanation found in the special sciences, namely, explanation by functional analysis as he understands it. However, although functional analysis may be a sub-species of mechanistic explanation it is very plausible that there are very many mechanistic explanations which are not functional analyses. For example, in our earlier case we saw that the hardness of the diamond is mechanistically explained using the properties and relations of the diamond’s constituents. Although it is far from clear that this is an example of functional analysis, such an explanation is clearly a mechanistic explanation. More importantly for our purposes, whether or not one classes such inter-individual mechanistic explanations as “functional analyses”, such an inter-individual mechanistic explanation clearly “uncovers those properties that causally contribute to the production of the capacity of interest” (Shapiro (2004), p.53). Consequently, a thorny dilemma 18 faces Shapiro and appears to establish that, however one resolves questions over the relation of functional analyses and inter-individual mechanistic explanations, his accounts of realization and multiple realization must be mistaken since they conflict with scientific findings and practice. The dilemma proceeds as follows. Either inter-individual mechanistic explanations are functional analyses or they are not. On one hand, if such inter-individual mechanistic explanations are functional analyses, then R-properties can include properties of constituents, like the carbon or Palladium atoms, and we will have realization, and multiple realization, in cases like the aluminum and steel corkscrews or enamel and Palladium alloy fillings. So, in such cases, Shapiro’s stated account of realization and multiple realization is mistaken. On the other hand, if such explanations are not functional analyses, then it is not only functional analysis that, in Shapiro’s words, “uncovers those properties that causally contribute to the production of the capacity of interest”, since inter-individual mechanistic explanations of this type clearly do so. So, again, Shapiro’s account of realization and multiple realization is mistaken. Consequently, it appears that closer attention to all species of mechanistic explanation in the special sciences suggests that Shapiro’s account of realization and multiple realization is, in fact, mistaken. To conclude our discussion of Shapiro’s recent work, we have seen that the theory schemata for scientific realization and multiple realization that we have presented have passed their test against Shapiro’s objections about their scope. Furthermore, we have also found reason to believe that our understanding of realization and multiple realization fits better with scientific methodology and practice than one of its significant rivals in Shapiro’s own account. Given the success of our theory schemata, in the final two sections of the paper we therefore propose to apply our framework to the key question of whether psychological properties are multiply realized at any neuroscientific level of properties. 19 Part 3 - The Scientific Realization of Psychological Properties (I): Amino Acid Sequences and the Multiple Realization of Psychological Properties by Biochemical Properties. We will begin our discussion by using our framework to determine whether our present scientific evidence supports psychological properties being multiply realized by biochemical properties, since this question has recently come to the fore with the pioneering work of John Bickle (2003) on molecular neuroscience. Bickle has presented an empirically informed and sophisticated defense of the claim that psychological properties are univocally realized by biochemical properties, arguing that there exists a psychological process of memory consolidation that is univocally realized across numerous terrestrial species at a single level of neuroscientific structure, namely, the biochemical level. Thus, we have a concrete case of an indexed claim of univocal realization that is putatively grounded in neuroscientific evidence. Aizawa (2007), however, argued that the empirical evidence did not support Bickle’s view, but this argument proceeded without appeal to a well-formalized theory of realization or multiple realization. All that was said in this earlier paper was that realization was supposed to be a non-logical, non-causal determination relation. Here, we can elaborate upon this earlier work by appeal to the framework we have offered in this paper.14 We shall not challenge the scientific evidence or theory to which Bickle appeals. Instead, in combination with our framework for realization and multiple realization, we will dispute Bickle’s analysis by drawing attention to some additional scientific evidence that we believe Bickle fails to take into proper account. For the sake of argument we shall make a number of assumptions. First, we shall follow Bickle in supposing that there is a single cognitive process of memory consolidation that may be found in Aplysia, Drosophila, and mice. Second, by ‘memory consolidation’ we shall understand any cognitive process that enables memories to persist for hours, days, and weeks, rather than 20 merely seconds or minutes. Roughly speaking, memory consolidation is the process of transforming short term memories into long term memories. And, third, we assume, along with Bickle, that this process is implemented by numerous biochemical reactions of the sort we will shortly describe, and that the higher level psychological properties associated with memory consolidation are together realized by the properties of many such biochemical reactions. Turn now to a simplified account of the biochemical level, one boiled down to just the elements that are essential for current philosophical purposes. During electrical activity of neurons, cells come to have increased levels of a secondary messenger, cyclic adenosine monophosphate (cAMP). cAMP molecules bind to molecules of protein kinase A (PKA). PKA is a tetrameric protein containing two regulatory and two catalytic subunits. When cAMP binds to the PKA regulatory subunits, the entire molecule dissociates leaving two free PKA catalytic subunits in the cytosol. As the concentration of PKA catalytic subunits increases in the cytosol, the concentration also increases in the neuronal cell nuclei, where they add phosphate groups to various other molecules farther along in the biochemical cascade. Eventually, this biochemical cascade of reactions leads to the synthesis of more proteins that effect structural changes in the neuronal synapses. These newly synthesized proteins bring about synaptic modifications that are familiar to philosophers of mind and psychology as one of the basic postulates of connectionist theories of cognition. Bickle’s claim is that these biochemical reactions provide the univocal implementation, at this level, of the process of memory consolidation across species – and thus that the higher level psychological properties associated with memory consolidation are univocally realized by the properties of these biochemical reactions. Thus in this case, which has the significant feature of being one of the few where our neuroscience has moved beyond the fledgling stage, Bickle challenges earlier claims that psychological properties are multiply realized across species. 21 The science that Bickle fails to consider, however, is the work that shows that PKA corresponds to distinct amino acid sequences in the different species of organisms that Bickle considers. Bergold, et al. (1992) for example, report differences in the amino acid sequences of the regulatory subunits in Aplysia, Drosophila, and mice. Beushausen, et al. (1988) report differences in the catalytic subunits. Let the regulatory subunit of PKA have the property G of pairing and binding to PKA catalytic subunits, and dissociating upon binding cAMP.15 There are many combinations of amino acids that can be bound into chains that have this property. So, one instance of G might be realized, under normal physiological background conditions $, by a set of properties (such as charge, size, and polarity) and relations (such as being covalently bonded and hydrogen bonded), F1-Fn, of one set of amino acids, s1-sp. Additionally, another instance of G might be realized, under normal physiological conditions $*, by a different set of properties and relations, F*1-F*m, of a distinct set of amino acids, s1-sq. Given the different characters of the relevant amino acids, it is plausible that F1-Fn ≠ F*1-F*m, but that F1-Fn and F*1-F*m are all at the same level. Thus, contrary to Bickle’s claims, once one attends to the evidence about the differing amino acid sequences in distinct species, then it appears we actually have a paradigm case of multiple realization of the properties of the biochemical that Bickle focuses upon and hence of the psychological properties, associated with the process of memory consolidation, that are realized by the properties of such biochemical reactions. Essentially the same kind of story can be told about the catalytic subunit of PKA that has the property of binding to free pairs of PKA regulatory subunits, dissociating from PKA regulatory subunits binding cAMP, and phosphorylating certain additional components of the biochemical pathway. Indeed, essentially the same kind of account could be given for any protein in the relevant biochemical reactions. Thus, for any element of these biochemical reactions a plausible case can be made that the properties of this element will be multiply 22 realized across species. This finding thus squares with the intuitively formulated contention in Aizawa (2007) that the properties of distinct amino acid sequences multiply realize the properties of the biochemical reactions underlying memory consolidation and hence multiply realize the psychological properties associated with memory consolidation. For realization is plausibly a transitive relation. Thus since the properties of Bickle’s favored biochemical reactions are multiply realized at the biochemical level, and given that we are assuming for the sake of argument that the properties of these reactions together realize the psychological properties associated with memory consolidation across species, then the transitivity of realization implies that the psychological properties associated with memory consolidation are multiply realized at the biochemical level across a variety of species. The realization and multiple realization schemata offered here articulate informal notions apparently in play in Bickle, (2003), and Aizawa, (2007). In addition, however, this exchange illustrates some of the features built into the schemata. The example and the schemata are mutually supporting. So, in the biochemistry of memory consolidation, we find that biochemical properties (such as charge, shape, and polarity) and relations (such as covalent and hydrogen bonding) non-causally determine a psychological property. We also find that the realizing properties and relations found in biochemistry are wholly unlike, and hence qualitatively different from, the realized property from psychology. Charge, shape, and polarity are qualitatively different from such properties as dissociating upon binding a cAMP molecule. A third feature is that many biochemical properties and relations together to realize the psychological property. It is not the properties or relations of a single macromolecule that brings about memory consolidation. Finally, there is an implicitly understood level at which the psychological properties are supposed to be univocally, or multiply, realized. 23 As well as supporting our earlier findings about realization and multiple realization generally, the foregoing considerations potentially also support a much stronger conclusion about multiple realization at this level in particular. Proteins are major components of all neurons, and indeed all cells in all known cognitive agents. Certain cellular components, such as water, sodium ions, potassium ions, and calcium ions, will be the same across many distinct types of organisms, but the proteins will vary. Even homologous proteins will differ to a greater or lesser degree in their amino acid sequences, so that they will differ to a greater or lesser degree in their physico-chemical properties. These different amino acid sequences will contribute different properties and relations toward the realization of higher level properties. Thus, insofar as any given psychological property is realized, in part, by the properties and relations of such proteins then that property will evidently be multiply realized at the biochemical level. This appears to hold for both cognitive and qualitative properties, suggesting that all psychological properties may be multiply realized across a range of species at the biochemical level. Obviously a full evaluation of these claims requires one to consider a range of interesting suggestions about why the latter reasoning is too quick and does not suffice for multiple realization at the biochemical level. Since one of us has carefully examined many of these responses in detail elsewhere the natural thing to do is to look at a somewhat higher level of neuroscience to see whether there is a better chance for univocal realization at that level.16 In the next section we will therefore consider this question in more detail by focusing on empirical work at the neuronal level. Part 4 - The Scientific Realization of Psychological Properties (II): Neuronal Plasticity and the Multiple Realization of Psychological Properties by Neural Properties. 24 We contend the existence of multiple realization of psychological properties by neuronal properties can be supported using recent neuroscientific research on a variety of different cognitive processes, whether neuroanatomical studies of primates and other mammals or neuroimaging work with human subjects. Elsewhere we have reviewed some of this evidence, but for our illustrative purposes here we wish to focus on one particular example drawn from more recent scientific research.17 In this case, in contrast to what we contend the biochemical evidence shows, we defend a less sweeping conclusion on the basis of some very recent in vivo microscopic work on neurons. What we think this work strongly suggests is that any psychological property that depends on the electrical activity of excitatory neurons, across distinct regions of the cortex, will turn out to be multiply realized by neuronal properties/relations. What the work actually shows is that certain neurons in the adult cortex change the structure of their dendritic spines. This, however, suggests that there will be regular fluctuations in the excitatory electrical signaling properties of these neurons. And this, in turn, strongly suggests that these neurons and their dendritic spines have properties that multiply realize many higher-level psychological properties. The current position in recent research, and our claims about multiple realization at the neuronal level built upon it, should be much clearer following a review of some of the principal empirical findings. The orthodox view in contemporary neuroscience is that neurons are the principal information processing elements in the brain and that they are responsible for many dimensions of psychological processing.18 Neurons, of course, have dendrites, axons, and cell bodies. The dendrites are tree-like structures that primarily receive information from other neurons by way of synaptic connections to them. The cell body contains much of the cellular apparatus for metabolic maintenance of the cell. The axon connects the neuron to other neurons by way of 25 further synapses. The topic of our neuroscience discussion here focuses on a sub-structure of the dendrites, namely, dendritic spines. Dendritic spines appear in many distinct forms as roughly finger-shaped or mushroomshaped extensions on the shafts of neuronal dendrites (see Figure 2). These forms vary in the size of the neck, spine length, spine volume, head volume, and size of a region called the “postsynaptic density area”. (See Figure 3 for data on dendritic spines in the hippocampus.) Each of these properties of a dendritic spine has a plausible role to play in shaping the electrical signaling properties of neurons and will thus plausibly have a role to play when the properties of neurons together realize psychological properties. For example, individual dendritic spines can serve as extensions that can add additional connections between more distantly placed neurons (see Figure 4A) and they provide for structures that facilitate modulation of the effects of one presynaptic terminal on the dendrite of a cell (see Figure 4B). Consider now some recent findings regarding the plasticity of dendritic spines. Techniques have recently been developed that enable scientists to insert genes that code for a green fluorescent protein (gfp) into the part of the genome coding for neurons.19 Individual neurons containing gfp can be reliably reidentified day after day through microscopy. In addition, scientists can track changes in individual dendritic spines over the course of hours, days, and weeks. What they find is that, although much of the structure of the dendritic tree is constant over many days, there are nonetheless individual variations over time. Given the plausible role of the properties of dendritic spines in the realization of psychological properties, the implication of these findings about the neuroplasticity at the dendritic spine level is that we will likely have multiple realization of psychological properties at this level. Although this is not the final word on this form of neuroplasticity, it does provide some evidence for the contention that the central nervous system is highly labile and that a given 26 type of psychological process is in fact often associated with a variety of distinct neurological structures.20 Our accounts of realization, and multiple realization, nicely capture what appears to be emerging from this research in neuroscience. Let G be any psychological property, such as remembering the location of a food source, that scientific and philosophical investigation discovers is realized by the properties/relations F1-Fn of the individual neurons n1-np in a neural network s under standard physiological conditions $. On our view of realization, this means that scientific and philosophical investigation have found that, under standard physiological conditions $, the neural network s has the psychological property G in virtue of the powers together contributed by properties (such as releasing certain neurotransmitters, binding certain neurotransmitters) and relations (such as synapsing upon), F1-Fn, of the constituent neurons n1np. What makes for the multiple realization of G is the plasticity of the dendritic spines, the changes in the patterns and strengths of synaptic connections. Although the individual neurons realizing G may, or may not vary, it appears that the manner in which they are interconnected and the strengths of these interconnections vary over periods of hours, days, and weeks. That is, the initial properties F1-Fn of the relevant neurons will likely change over time, to be replaced by other properties F*1-F*m, where clearly F1-Fn ≠ F*1-F*m and where these properties are at the same level. But in such cases it appears that the subject often continues to instantiate the same psychology and thus continues to have the same psychological property G. Thus, we apparently have a textbook case of multiple realization of the psychological property at the neuronal level within the same individual over time. As with the biochemical example, this neuronal case and our theory schemata are mutually supporting. Our earlier, more philosophical, discussion of the general nature of scientific composition makes the present scientific case look mundane, for recall that the compositional relations posited in mechanistic explanations in the sciences often relate 27 qualitatively different entities. The key to such relations is that although components, such as realizer properties and relations, are qualitatively distinct from the entity they compose, such as a realized property, the component entities together non-causally result in the qualitatively distinct composed entity. But this feature of composition underpins, as we noted earlier, the prevalence of multiple realization, for it means that differing realizers may together non-causally result in instances of the same realized property. And this is apparently what we find with neurons, for although their relevant properties and relations change over time it is often none the less the case that preceding and succeeding properties and relations of the same neurons, although diverse, each contribute powers that together non-causally result in, and hence realize, instances of the same psychological property. At the biochemical level, we argued for the multiple realization of psychological properties across individuals of different species. However, we should mark that the evidence we have just offered for multiple realization at the neuronal level supports such multiple realization within the very same individual over time. Such evidence the claims of earlier writers, such as Horgan (1993) or Endicott (1993), who contended that psychological properties are multiply realized by neuronal properties even within a single individual. Although the recent work on the plasticity of dendritic spines offers a promising defense of the multiple realization of psychological properties by neuronal properties, we should close this section with a note on some limitations of this argument. There is, of course, the empirical possibility that changes in dendritic spines will simply turn out not to be relevant to any psychological properties at all. Less dramatically, there could be some properties of some psychological processes or states, such as moods, that do not depend on the structure of dendritic spines. Perhaps moods and their properties are entirely a matter of the amounts of particular neurotransmitters perfusing the neurons and perhaps dendritic spines will have nothing to do 28 with this. If so, then the properties of such psychological processes or states will not be shown by the foregoing considerations to be multiply realized at this level. This shows that, over and above an account of realization and multiple realization, it is always primarily a matter of scientific inquiry to determine what realizes what, whether multiply or univocally. However, we should also again emphasize that a diverse range of other evidence in addition to that we have briefly outlined here, for example from both neuroanatomical and neuroimaging studies, can also be used to support such multiple realization of psychological properties at the neuronal level. Conclusion Our opening passage from Boyd encouraged an approach to scientific realization and multiple realization, amongst other issues, that focuses squarely on real, well-confirmed cases from the sciences themselves, rather than the weird and wonderful thought experiments that guided much of the last generation of discussions of multiple realization. Our work in this paper confirms the utility of Boyd’s approach. For by starting with well-confirmed scientific examples we have provided a better understanding of compositional relations in the sciences generally, as well as precise theory schemata for realization and multiple realization. Furthermore, when taken together our case-studies focused on biochemistry and dendritic spines suggest that psychological properties are multiply realized at the biochemical and neuronal levels.21 For we have argued that the amino acid sequences of the relevant proteins vary across species and the properties of these sequences plausibly contribute the powers relevant to the realization of higher level properties. Thus psychological properties are plausibly multiply realized at the biochemical level. We have also given some reason to believe that many psychological properties (those that depend on the electrical signaling properties of neurons) are 29 also multiply realized at the neuronal level given our evidence about changes in the properties of dendritic spines over time. Obviously, the evidence we have offered for these specific multiple realization hypotheses at particular levels is empirical and these hypotheses are thus defeasible. However, we have used scientific evidence, from a range of disciplines, to confirm the suggestion of our other opening passage, from Wimsatt, that multiple realization is not special to the case of psychology. We have shown that, as the defenders of the received view of special sciences argued, multiply realized properties are to be found in a range of scientific disciplines, from materials science and biochemistry to the neurosciences and psychology. Given the success that apparently results from following Boyd’s advice, we suggest that more writers on multiple realization, as well as scientific realization and other topics, would do well to focus on concrete, well-confirmed accounts from the sciences in crafting their views.22 30 References. Aizawa, K. 2007: “The Biochemistry of Memory Consolidation: A Model System for the Philosophy of Mind”. Synthese. v. 155, pp. 65-98. Aizawa, K., and Gillett, C. Under Review: “Multiple Realization and Methodology in the Neurological and Psychological Sciences”. Aizawa, K. and Gillett, C. Forthcoming: “Levels, Individual Variation and Massive Multiple Realization in the Neurosciences”. In Bickle (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bechtel, W. and Mundale, J. 1999: “Revisiting Multiple Realization”. Philosophy of Science, v.66, pp.175-205. Bechtel, W. and Richardson, R. 1993: Discovering Complexity. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Bergold, P. J., Beushausen, S. A., Sacktor, T. C., Cheley, S., Bayley, H., & Schwarz, J. H. 1992: “A Regulatory Subunit of the cAMP-Dependent Protein Kinase Down-Regulated in Aplysia Sensory Neurons During Long-Term Sensitization”. Neuron, v. 8, pp. 387-397. Beushausen, S., Bergold, P., Sturner, S., Elste, A., Roytenberg, V., Schwartz, J. H., & Bayley, H. 1988: “Two Catalytic Subunits of cAMP-Dependent Protein Kinase Generated by Alternative RNA Splicing are Expressed in Aplysia Neurons”. Neuron, v. 1, pp. 853864. Bickle, J. 2003: Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account. Boston: Kluwer. Block, N. and Fodor, J. 1972: “What Psychological States are Not”. Philosophical Review, vol.81, pp.159-181. Reprinted in Block (1981). (All references are to the 31 reprint). Boyd, R. 1999: “Kinds, Complexity and Multiple Realization: Comments on Millikan’s ‘Historical Kinds in the Special Sciences”. Philosophical Studies, 95, pp.67-98. Churchland, P.S. 1986: Neurophilosophy: Towards a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Cotrina, M. L., Lin, J. H.-C., López-Garcia, J.C., Naus, C. G., & Nedergaard, M. 2000: “ATPMediated Glia Signaling”. Journal of Neuroscience, v. 20, pp. 2835-2844. Darden, L. and Maull, N. 1977: “Interfield Theories”. Philosophy of Science, v.44, pp. 43-64. Endicott, R. 1993: “Species-specific Properties and More Narrow-Reductive Strategies”. Erkenntnis, v. 100, pp. 591-603. Endicott, R. 2005: “Multiple Realizability”. In The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd Edition. New York: Macmillan. Fodor, J. 1968: Psychological Explanation. New York: Random House. Fodor, J. 1974: “Special Sciences”. Synthese, v.28, pp. 97-115. Reprinted in Fodor (1981b). (All references are to the reprint). Fodor, J. 1981a: “Introduction”. In Fodor (1981b). Fodor, J. 1981b: Representations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gillett, C. 2002: “The Dimensions of Realization: A Critique of the Standard View”. Analysis, v. 62, pp. 316-23. Gillett, C. 2003: “The Metaphysics of Realization, Multiple Realizability and the Special Sciences”. Journal of Philosophy, v. 100, pp.591-603. Gillett, C. 2007: “A Mechanist Manifesto for the Philosophy of Mind: The Third Way for Functionalists”. Journal of Philosophical Research. Gillett, C. Unpublished: “Making Sense of Levels in the Sciences: Powers, Realization, 32 Constitution and Implementation”. Gillett, C. Forthcoming: “Piercing the Poisonous Fog of ‘Functionalism: An Argumentative Guide for the Perplexed”’. In Hunneman (ed.) Functions: Selection and Mechanisms. Dordrecht: Synthese Library. Grutzendler, J., Kasthuri, N., & Gan, W. 2002: “Long-term dendritic spine stability in the adult cortex”. Nature, v. 420, pp. 812-816. Holtmaat, A., Trachtenberg, J., Wilbrecht, L., Shepherd, G., Zhang, X., Knott, G., and Svoboda, K. 2005: “Transient and Persistent Dendritic Spines in the Neocortex In Vivo”. Neuron, v. 45, pp. 279-291. Horgan, T. (1993). “Nonreductive Materialism and the Explanatory Autonomy of Psychology”. In S. Wagner and R. Warner (eds.), Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 295-320. Kitcher, P. 1984: “1953 and All That: A Tale of Two Sciences”. Philosophical Review, v. 93, pp. 335-73. Putnam, H. 1967: “Psychological Predicates”. In W. Capitan and D. Merrill (eds.) Art, Mind and Religion. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh Univ. Press. Reprinted as “The Nature Of Mental States” in Putnam (1975b). (All references are to the reprint). Putnam, H. 1975a: “Philosophy and our Mental Life”. In Putnam (1975b). Putnam, H. 1975b: Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers Vol.2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shapiro, L. 2000: “Multiple Realizations”. Journal of Philosophy, v. 97, pp. 635-654. Shapiro, L. 2004: The Mind Incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Shapiro, L. Unpublished: “Multiple Realization, Seriously”. Paper presented at the Conference on “Mind-Body Realization”, Lafayette College, October 2006. 33 Shoemaker, S. 1980: “Causality and Properties”. In Van Inwagen (ed) Time and Cause. Dordrecht: Reidel. Sorra, K. E., & Harris, K. M. (2000). Overview on the Structure, Composition, Function, Development, and Plasticity of Hippocampal Dendritic Spines. Hippocampus, v. 10, pp. 501-511. Trachtenberg, J., Chen, B., Knott, G., Feng, G., Sanes, J., Welker, E., & Svoboda, K. 2002: “Long-Term In Vivo Imaging of Experience-Dependent Synaptic Plasticity in Adult Cortex”. Nature, v. 420, pp. 788-794. Wimsatt, W. 1974: “Reductive Explanation: A Functional Account”. In R. Cohen et al (eds.) PSA Proceedings 1974. Dordrecht: Reidel. Wimsatt, W. 1976: “Reductionism, Levels of Organization and the Mind-Body Problem”. In G. Globus, I. Savodnik, and G. Maxwell, (eds.), Consciousness and the Brain, pp. 199267. New York: Plenum. Wimsatt, W. 1994: “The Ontology of Complex Systems: Levels of Organization, Perspectives and Causal Thickets”. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, supp. v. 20, pp. 207-74. Zuo, Y., Lin, A., Chang, P., & Gan, W. 2005: “Development of Long-Term Dendritic Spine Stability in Diverse Regions of Cerebral Cortex”. Neuron, v. 46, pp. 181-189. 34 Figure 1. The higher and lower level processes involved in the implementation of the process of a diamond making a Z-shape scratch in glass. 35 Figure 2. A 3D Reconstruction of Dendritic Spines (from Sorra & Harris, 2000). Ranges in Dimensions of Hippocampal Dendritic Spines and Their Synapses Dentate Gyrus Area CA3 Area CA1 Neck Diameter (μm) 0.09-0.54 0.20-1.00 0.038-0.46 Spine length (μm) 0.20-1.78 0.60-6.50 0.160-2.13 3 Spine volume (μm ) 0.003-0.23 0.13-1.83 0.004-0.56 Head Volume (μm3) 0.003-0.55 3 Postsynaptic density area (μm ) 0.003-0.23 0.01-0.60 0.008-0.54 Figure 3. Variation in Functionally Significant Properties of Dendritic Spines (from Sorra & Harris, 2000) 36 Figure 4. Possible Functions of Dendritic Spines (from Sorra & Harris, 2000). A: Spines increase connectivity between more distantly placed neurons. The gray dots represent synaptic vesicles containing neurotransmitters. The black bars represent so-called postsynaptic densities which appear to have a functional role in the uptake of neurotransmitters. B: Dendritic spines allow structures in which synaptic connections can be modulated by other neurons synapsing on their necks. C: Sizes and shapes of dendritic spines allow for the modulation of the effects of a given synaptic connection and for associative connections between adjacent spines. D: Dendritic spine heads localize the effects of synapses making them more effective at inducing postsynaptic potentials. E: Dendritic spines facilitate the localization of proteins synthesized for modifications of the postsynaptic structures. 37 Notes. 1 Philosophers of mind have often discussed multiple realizability, rather than multiple realization. Here we limit our attention to multiple realization, since it allows us to sidestep issues about the proper modality, it simplifies discussion, and once multiple realization is established then multiple realizability simply follows. 2 See Endicott (2005) for a survey of some of main varieties of the concept of realization. Given how often writers fail to realize the varieties of such concepts, and hence confuse them, it is worth briefly noting three kinds familiar to philosophers. First, there is a group of semantic notions that we term ‘Linguistic’, or ‘L’, realization and which hold between entities in the world and some set of sentences. Famously, for example, the work of David Lewis on topic-neutral Ramseyfication and theoretical terms uses a notion of L-realization. Basically, on Lewis’ view of ‘realization’ it holds between entities in the world and the set of Ramseyfied sentences putatively defining some theoretical term ‘F’ – crudely put, an entity X realizes ‘F’, in this sense, when the entity X satisfies the relevant Ramsey sentences for ‘F’. Second, there is a kind of computational or mathematical relation commonly referred to as ‘realization’, and used in both the sciences and philosophy, we term ‘Abstract’, or ‘A’, realization. Very crudely, X is taken to A-realize Y if the elements of X map onto, or are isomorphic with, the elements of Y. This notion of ‘realization’ is commonly utilized with formal models and hence with work utilizing such models, for example in computational accounts of cognitive processes. Note that here the relata of such ‘realization’ relations are largely unconstrained because A-realization simply holds in virtue of a mathematical mapping, or isomorphism, which can obviously hold between all manner of entities. Finally, the third class of ‘realization’ relations are what we may term ‘CausalMechanist’ or ‘M’ realization. The latter contrast with L- and A-realization by having as relata causally individuated entities in the world, often (though not exclusively) property instances. M- 38 realization has been the focus of many writers, but in particular philosophers of science have been especially interested in such relations which they take to be posited in so-called ‘mechanistic’ explanations in a range of the special sciences. In our discussion, for obvious reasons, we focus exclusively on M-realization when we discuss ‘realization’. 3 For a detailed discussion of how these problems impact our understanding of the metaphysical forms of ‘functionalism’, and their associated concepts of a ‘functional property’, ‘realization’, ‘causal role’ etc, see Gillett (2007) and (Forthcoming). 4 See, for example, Fodor (1968), (1974), and (1975); Kitcher (1984); and Wimsatt (1974), (1976) and (1994), amongst many others. 5 See, for example, Bechtel & Mundale, (1999), Bickle, (2003), and, to a lesser degree, Shapiro, (2004). 6 See Aizawa & Gillett, (under review). 7 The reader should note that due to limits of the test method, the Knoop hardness value of a diamond is not so reliably known. 8 This ‘thumbnail’ account is defended in Gillett (2002) and (2003a). A full account of the ‘Dimensioned’ view of realization, as a part of integrated view of the compositional relations posited in the sciences between ‘packages’ of powers, properties, individuals and mechanisms, is offered in Gillett (Unpublished). 9 Some readers may be concerned that adding (iv), and the notion of a ‘level’, leaves us with what many regard as the vague notion of a ‘level’. However, there are reasonably clear scientific notions of a ‘level of entities’, under some condition, as entities that do, or can, participate in the same causal mechanisms under those conditions (or which participate in processes that together implement other processes). Furthermore, elsewhere one of us has outlined a precise definition 39 of this notion of a ‘level’. See Gillett (Unpublished) for a detailed formulation and defense of the nature and coherence of this notion of ‘level’. 10 There are examples of both types of alloy and enamel that fall outside of these ranges, but all we need is that some forms of these substances fall within the range to run our example. 11 To take another example, Shapiro considers whether the property of being a corkscrew is multiply realized, respectively, by the properties of being a waiter’s corkscrew and a doublelever corkscrew. 12 Shapiro’s denial of transitivity for realization appears to be in conflict with his own assumption that realization relations are determination relations (Shapiro, 2004, p. 39). At least initially, it appears plausible that if A determines B, and B determines C, then A will determine C. This need not be the case, but it appears reasonable to ask for some reason why this is not the case, as Shapiro appears to claim. 13 See Aizawa and Gillett (Under review). 14 Aizawa, (2007), also argued that Shapiro’s, (2004), account of realization does not do justice to the implicitly understood multiple realization involved in the biochemical case. Insofar, however, as our theory schemata for realization and multiple realization do justice to the intuitively understood features of this case, we have further support for the value of our theory schemata. 15 Nothing of philosophical significance changes if we treat the regulatory subunit of PKA as having three properties (pairing together, binding to pairs of PKA catalytic subunits, and dissociating upon binding cAMP) or simply one property (i.e. the combination of those properties). 16 See Aizawa (2007) for an extended treatment of various important objections to these claims. 17 See Aizawa and Gillett (Forthcoming) and Aizawa and Gillett (Under Review). 40 18 Some recent neuroscientific work has suggested a neuromodulatory role for glial cells (see, for example, Cotrina, Lin, López-Garcia, Naus, & Nedergaard, (2000)), but nothing of philosophical import will be lost by setting aside this complication. 19 Grutzendler, Kasthuri, & Gan, (2002), Holtmaat, Trachtenberg, Wilbrecht, Shepherd, Zhang, Knott, and Svoboda, (2005), Trachtenberg, Chen, Knott, Feng, Sanes, Welker, & Svoboda, K. (2002), and Zuo, Lin, Chang, & Gan, (2005), use this and related techniques. 20 Cf., Block & Fodor, (1972). 21 Here our focus has not primarily been to assess the extent of the multiple realization of psychological properties by the properties studied by the neurosciences. However, as the reader may have guessed from some of our comments we think that such multiple realization is very extensive. In fact, elsewhere we have defended what we term the ‘Massive Multiple Realization’ hypothesis: the claim that, within a given species, instances of many psychological properties, are multiply realized at many neuroscientific levels. See Aizawa and Gillett, (forthcoming), for evidence that supports this hypothesis. 22 We would like to thank the audiences for their comments at the 2006 Wisconsin Workshop on Special Sciences, in Madison, and at the 2007 conference of the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology, where we presented versions of this paper. We owe special thanks to Fred Adams, Tom Polger, Larry Shapiro, and Elliot Sober.