3/PH/SB Quantum Theory - Week 8 - Dr. P.A. Mulheran BELL’S INEQUALITY AND THE NATURE OF REALITY 8.1 Introduction The nature of reality can be tested through the correlations between results of measurements performed on pairs of particles that are part of a coherent system. This was first suggested by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (EPR) in 1935 who hoped to demonstrate the inadequacies of quantum theory and the Copenhagen Interpretation. Consider first the story told by John Bell about Bertlmann’s socks as an example of everyday correlation. Bertlmann always wore odd socks so that if you see that one of his socks is red than you know immediately that the other is blue. Of course there is absolutely no mystery here because we believe in local realism in classical physics. On that particular day Bertlmann’s first sock was always red and the other always blue, regardless of when or how we observe them. However were the observation of socks a quantum phenomenon then we might start to get worried. Before seeing his feet, our knowledge of the socks is completely uncertain and the wave function describes a linear superposition of the possible outcomes of the experiment. Furthermore upon observing that the first sock is red, the wave function instantaneously collapses to the appropriate eigenfunction of the sock-operator (!) which means the second sock is now definitely blue. In other words observing sock number one determines instantaneously the nature of sock number two, despite the fact that they are spatially separated onto different legs! This is precisely the sort of “spooky action at a distance” that EPR were worried about. Surely the Copenhagen Interpretation must be wrong; real socks do not behave like that and so neither should the quantum equivalent. Perhaps what is wrong is that there is something missing from quantum theory. Could there be hidden variables that we cannot detect but which nevertheless determine from the outset the results of all experiments? Surprisingly Bell in the 1960’s showed how experiments could be devised to rule out the possibility of local hidden variables dictating the results of these experiments. These experiments are based on correlated results on the spin of particles or the polarisation of photons rather than the colour of socks (of course!). Subsequently many experimental tests, including those by Aspect in the early 1980’s, confirm the predictions of the standard quantum theory and rule out local hidden variable theories. Therefore it seems that there is no local realism in real world experiments performed on systems governed by quantum mechanics. It implies that “spooky action at a distance” which violates relativity is real, and that the classical view of physics as an objective science of local reality is fundamentally wrong. 1 3/PH/SB Quantum Theory - Week 8 - Dr. P.A. Mulheran 8.2 Measuring the spin of coherent pairs: the correlation coefficient Consider pair of spin-half particles (e.g. protons) moving apart (along the y-axis as usual) after a scattering experiment where the total angular momentum of the system is strictly zero (these conditions can be constructed in real experiments). Then if one particle is measured to have a z-component of spin up, the other must be z-down and vice versa. Now imagine that we measure the spin of the first particle with an SGZ apparatus, so finding Z1-UP or Z1-DOWN at random. Immediately afterwards we measure the spin of the second particle with a Stern-Gerlach apparatus SG which lies in the x-z plane and is oriented at an angle to the z-axis. Using quantum theory we can easily calculate the probability that if the first result is Z1-UP the second result is 2-UP: PUU sin 2 2 . Similarly we can calculate the probabilities PUD for observing Z1-UP and 2DOWN, PDU for Z1-DOWN and 2-UP, and PDD for Z1-DOWN and 2-DOWN: PUD cos 2 2 , PDU cos 2 2 , PDD sin 2 2 . We can now calculate the correlation coefficient between the two results, that is 4 S Z 1 S 2 , using these probabilities: 2 1 PUD PDD PDU cos . 2 the average value of the product 1 CQT PUU 2 2 3/PH/SB Quantum Theory - Week 8 - Dr. P.A. Mulheran 8.3 A Local Hidden Variable Theory Let us construct a simple (but ultimately wrong) local hidden variable theory for the spins which preserves classical notion of realism. We assume that the spin of a particle is a real vector oriented in space at random, and if its zcomponent is positive then a measurement of Sz results in +1 (in units of /2). Similarly if it is measured by an SG apparatus it gives a result +1 if its spin vector makes an angle between and with the z-axis. Then for this hidden variable theory PUU and so , PUD 1 , PDU 1 , PDD . 1 1 2 C LHVT PUU PUD PDD PDU 1. 2 2 This result is very different to that of the standard quantum theory, CQT CLHVT , and an experiment could in principle be performed to rule out this particular hidden variable theory. However Bell realised that by considering the correlation between sets of experiments one can rule out all possible local hidden variable theories! 3 3/PH/SB Quantum Theory - Week 8 - Dr. P.A. Mulheran 8.4 Bell’s Inequality Let us suppose that there is some local hidden variable(s) that determine beforehand what the result of the spin measurements will be. In this way we can preserve the classical idea of realism. Then the result of measuring Sz for particle number one is merely a function of the hidden variable, S Z1 , and likewise the result of measuring S for particle number two is another function of the hidden variable S 2 . The hidden variables can take a range of possible values which follows a normalised frequency distribution p(). We are free to choose what this distribution is and furthermore what functions S Z1 and S 2 we use. They can be made to reproduce the results of individual measurements, but as we shall see they cannot be made to reproduce the results of certain correlation experiments! Under these rules the correlation coefficient becomes CB SZ 1 . S 2 . p . d , where SZ1 and S2 take values of 1 (in units of /2). We can now derive Bell’s inequality which concerns the correlation coefficients between three separate experiments performed with (SGZ and SG), (SGZ and SG), and (SGZ and SG-): CB CB CB 1 . This means that the correlation coefficients calculated using all possible local hidden variable theories must obey the above inequality. Recalling now the correlation coefficient calculated using quantum theory, CQT cos , we see that if we choose = 2 the left hand side of Bell’s inequality becomes cos cos 2 cos 1, 0 2 . In other words Bell’s inequality is clearly violated for many experimental set-ups according to standard quantum theory. Therefore careful experiments can in principle be used to distinguish between the standard quantum theory and any local hidden variable theory. In fact experimental tests clearly confirm the predictions of quantum theory and thus rule out all local hidden variable theories! 4 3/PH/SB Quantum Theory - Week 8 - Dr. P.A. Mulheran 8.5 The Aspect Experiment Experimentalists typically perform the correlation tests suggested by Bell’s inequality and its variants using pairs of photons with perpendicular polarisation, because photon detectors are more efficient than the Stern-Gerlach apparatus. The Aspect version from 1982 switches the photons between pairs of polarisers on both sides of the experiment, so in total four different correlation coefficients are measured. The experiments clearly show that the appropriate version of Bell’s inequality for this series of experiments is violated by 10%, and the results agree with the quantum theory predictions to within the experimental error. The Aspect experiment also changes the polarisers at such a high rate that no possible signal travelling with a speed below that of light could pass the information about the precise set-up between the photons at either side of the apparatus before they are measured. The conclusion that quantum systems cannot possibly be described by a local hidden variable theory seems inescapable. However the experimental results are consistent with the Copenhagen Interpretation: our knowledge changes after the measurement of the first photon’s polarisation and so the wave function instantaneously collapses thereby dictating the result of second experiment. This action at a distance violates the relativistic speed limit, and can therefore conflict with causality. Event 1 does not necessarily precede event 2 to an observer in an inertial reference frame that is moving at a constant speed with respect to the experiment. However no-one has yet managed to communicate information faster than light using these correlations. We conclude that Einstein’s “spooky action at a distance” appears to be real, and our classical notion of physics as an objective science describing a universe that “really exists”, with every object really located in a small region of space-time, appears to be false. Clearly this is not the end of the story, and we must wait for further experimental and theoretical progress to clarify what physics is really about! 5