ARGUMENTATION Hello Itchy, are you going to observe Grice’s Principle of Cooperation today? SUCKER Only if you observe the Principle of Charity Argumentation requires at least two people One of these people is arguing for some position about which there is some dispute or controversy This is sometimes called the standpoint. She gives reasons in favour of her standpoint. The respondent may argue against the standpoint, perhaps by offering reasons of his own. Or he may direct critical questions at her reasoning to reveal its flaws. In the argumentation scheme from position to know, some Similar are terminology the argumentation schemes from Topopular be truly opinion analagous, and Critical questions to leave be asked are: Although An arguer Walton may uses deliberately this also, premises hetosuggests unexpressed. that this is persons(s) is in a priveleged position ascertain some This This can befact. a strong from popular practice. These can be summed in the the analogue reasons must 1. How credible is E as an expert witness? When used improperly, this is called the ad verecundiam fallacy. a Sometimes misunderstanding thiscould is the of what thing Aristotle to do, meant since an audience he may the ARGUMENT beright something quite trivial, like when whether it isintroduced raining. argument because ARGUMENT “Everybody so!” “Everybody doing it!” of the same APPEAL 2. Is E anthinks expert in and the field that A iselse in? isconsist FROM the become term.TO suspicious Instead, the if enthymeme the arguer argues properly for should what they be argument identified already can be However, not allEFROM appeals to authority areopinion fallacious. The argumentation scheme from can beofseen as respectively. Used incorrectly it isexpert called the adnumber populum features fallacy. 3. What did assert that implies A? CORRELATION AUTHORITY made to look like one with accept. what But hesometimes callsIt4. presumptive the arguer might hope that Birds the fly, audience, Tweety ANALOGY a special Thearguments, expert expected the facts in the TO CAUSE is used correctly when weisifare justified inknow thinking interrelated that people inisthe Is Ecase. personally reliable as ae.g. source? There are situations where, some facttowere true, some that is widely who a bird, aretherefore probably Tweety adopting flies. a Principle Such arguments of Charity, defeasible fill intrue. the domain their expertise. If some alleged fact isthat not known by are in Is a of strong position to know, just as inare thewill same expert case. as in the 5. A can consistent with what other experts assert? person(s) reasonably be expected to know itway is accepted, even by the thecould expert, itassertion isareasonable toand conclude that it iscannot not a fact. 6. Is E’s based on evidence? premises because in Tweety the way that be they penguin personally find penguins the most convincing. fly. When they are made original domain. respondent. The When someone They can aware of argues a The arguer Any conclusion respondent will try to makes a usually do this AD Used incorrectly contradiction, theyof that if the course drawn from a deny that the cases statement, they by making an which critical ARGUMENTATION ARGUMENT We see that questions aredistinct relevant depends onfallacy the HOMINEM this is the Presumptive are, he claims, from deductive oris are obliged to arguments correlation action she is commit exception to a areFROM really analagous. SIGN as post argumentation scheme. This seems a helpful constraint ARGUMENTS resolve it byisarguments. presumptive inductive “Birds fly” like is intended toformal be a known different recommending themselves to anot general rule hoc ergo propter because the revoking one of their on a Principle of Charity, so or that agreement can As be areached followed, then either premise from birds fly” “Most birds fly”, whole, on the certain set of “All they were correlation may be hoc, or that after commitments. itcommitted will have have a the to argument question actually is. statements. to.what argument is meant be moreinlike a practical syllogism than a accidental. It could this, therefore Individual The respondent Premise: can a has question property the F A sign is something bad result, or it will also be due toof a logical syllogism. that because basis on which the classification is that indicates when have a result that will common cause,this. but ClassificationARGUMENT Premise: For all x, if x ARGUMENT ARGUMENT The answers to those questions should be in the premises. So,itFROM once made, on whether it is merely something else itself lead to a bad This is called the PRINCIPLE then is notis had property F, then x can beOF DISSOCIATION FROM FROM VERBAL stipulated or biased (e.g. persuasive true, e.g a footprint result (the slippery you know the argumentation scheme, you to fill ina the necessarily bad is classified as having property G. know how CLASSIFICATION COMMITMENT definitions), CONSEQUENCES or just vague. a sign that someone slope argument) but an unexpressed premises. These are traditionally called argument, enthymemes. This is called the PRINCIPLE Conclusion: a has property G.OF ASSOCIATION has stood argument from there. sign . SCHEMES This should cause the defender of the standpoint to clarify her reasoning. Clarification could be: i) Adding new reasons that are independent of the ones before. This is convergent argumentation. ii) Filling in unexpressed premises iii) Using an argumentation scheme. iv) Separating into two concepts what was previously just one. v) Combining into one concept what was previously two. ARGUMENTATION STRUCTURES There are more ways than one to argue for a standpoint The arguer has to judge from the audience what needs to be said explicitly and what should be taken for granted, what can be left unexpressed. Redundant argumentation is not merely time-consuming but could actually be seen as suspicious by the audience, with a corresponding fall in the persuasiveness of the argument. Lawyers have to very A and B give different support to C. If ButBy if Aarguing is conclusive on its own, careful what arguments they use and when they use them. the respondent manages to rebut A, then adding B seems like a against an objection, you might suggest that it has more importance then the arguer can still appeal to B. In confession that it is not conclusive. than it really at the the sense that the respondent musthas. Normally, the main arguments are presented In some sense, the more beginning andofrepeated again at the end. Additional support is put in you add, the less rebut two argumentations instead argumentatations middle. This support is weaker (at least for the audience in force each one has. one, this structure isthe stronger. persuasive question) but independent of the main points. The argumentation-structure looks like this. This argumentation-structure is called convergent. ARGUMENTATION STRUCTURES There are more ways than one to argue for a standpoint Deductive argumentation is linked, since the premises A and B only support the conclusion C when combined according to a rule of inference. Usually more than one rule will need to be applied, so the premises only support a subconclusion, which together with the premises supports the standpoint. For instance… The pragma-dialectical view sees linked and Some philosophers consider all linked convergent structures as forms of complex structures to be deductive argumentation, argumentation that can be analysed into single but others like Thomas, and Pinto and argumentations; these are interrelated Blair, allow inductive Thisargumentation. argumentation-structure is called linked ordifferently subordinative. when the premises are interdependent. This argumentation-structure is called serial. ARGUMENTATION STRUCTURES This is not the only way to diagram argumentation. Below we have a diagram illustrating the Toulmin model. One interesting thing to note is that the rebuttal does entail rejection of the claim, but only a qualification of it. Another is the distinction between warrant and backing. The warrant says simply “From this data, you can infer that”. The backing is the grounds of the warrant, the reason for accepting it. This could be more observational data, or it could be something like a legal statute. fallacies dialectics The traditional view of fallacies was that they looked like valid arguments, but were not. Barth and Krabbe took Hamblin’s lead and created a formal model of argumentation. However, many fallacies, e.g., petitio principii, are valid arguments according to classical logic. Influenced by the dialectics of Barth and Krabbe and the critical rationalism of Popper, the pragmadialecticians consider the ability to handle fallacies to be a crucial test of their theory. Others are not arguments at all, e.g., the fallacy of many questions. In 1970, Charles Hamblin wrote a book “Fallacies” that highlighted the inadequacy of classical logic to deal with the fallacies. His work is widely considered to be devastating. Some have considered that logic books and teaching logic should exclude fallacies altogether. Hamblin’s own approach, though, still seems to be essentially logical, although not truth-valued logic. Fallacies were better understood dialogically as something like illegal moves in a game. This led to things like formal dialectics. Their approach is characterized by the idea that certain rules have to be obeyed for a discourse to aim at the rational resolution of disagreement. Such rules had already been suggested by philosophers such as H.P. Grice and Jurgen Habermas. Fallacies are violations of these rules. When arguers argue fallaciously, they are no longer pursuing a rational resolution of disagreement, but any resolution in which they win. Van Eemeren calls this “strategic maneuvering” Habermas also stresses that language should be used communicatively and not strategically. PRAGMA-DIALECTICS AND FALLACIES Van Eemeren is a critical rationalist. Disputes are to be resolved by rational argumentation, and both protagonist and antagonist must be committed to this kind of resolution. Knowledgeare Standpoints increases by is Every best standpoint when they making bold open advertise to criticial the conjectures and means discussion of their then testing them falsification In the meta-level dispute between pragma-dialectics and other theories of argumentation, the crucial experiment is the handling of the fallacies. PRAGMA-DIALECTICS AND FALLACIES There are 10 rules for critical discussion and fallacies. If the protagonist or antagonist break these rules then they are no longer committed to resolving the dispute rationally, but are engaging in strategic maneuvering. This is reminiscent of Habermas’ distinction between communicative and strategic action, and his rules of discourse. 1. Freedom rule 6. Starting point rule 2. Burden-of-proof rule 7. Argument scheme rule 3. Standpoint rule 8. Validity rule 4. Relevance rule 9. Closure rule 5. Unexpressed premise rule 10.Usage rule Freedom rule • Parties must not prevent each other from putting forward standpoints or casting doubt on standpoints • Violations of rule 1 by the protagonist or the antagonist at the confrontation stage – Placing limits on standpoints or doubts • Fallacy of declaring standpoints sacrosanct • Fallacy of declaring standpoints taboo – Restricting the other party’s freedom of action • Putting the other party under pressure – Fallacy of the stick – Fallacy of appeal to pity • Attacking the other party’s person – Fallacy of depicting the other party as stupid, bad, unreliable, etc. – Fallacy of casting suspicion on the other party’s motives – Fallacy of pointing out a contradiction in the other party’s words or deeds Burden-of-proof rule • A party who puts forward a standpoint is obliged to defend it if asked to do so • Violations of rule 2 by the protagonist at the opening stage – Charging the burden of proof to the other party • In a non-mixed difference of opinion, instead of defending his or her own standpoint the protagonist forces the antagonist to show that the protagonist’s standpoint is wrong – Fallacy of shifting the burden of proof • In a mixed difference of opinion the one party does not attempt to defend his or her standpoint but forces the other party to defend their standpoint – Fallacy of shifting the burden of proof – Escaping from the burden of proof • Presenting the standpoint as self-evident – Fallacy of evading the burden of proof • Giving a personal guarantee of the rightness of the standpoint – Fallacy of evading the burden of proof • Immunizing the standpoint against criticism – Fallacy of evading the burden of proof Standpoint rule • A party’s attack on a standpoint must relate to the standpoint that has indeed been advanced by the other party • Violations of rule 3 by the protagonist or the antagonist at all the discussion stages – Attributing a fictitious standpoint to the other party • Emphatically putting forward the opposite standpoint – Fallacy of the straw man • Referring to the views of the group to which the opponent belongs – Fallacy of the straw man • Creating a fictitious opponent – Fallacy of the straw man – Misrepresenting the other party’s standpoint • Taking utterances out of context – Fallacy of the straw man • Oversimplifying or exaggerating – Fallacy of the straw man Relevance rule • A party may defend his or her standpoint only by advancing argumentation relating to that standpoint • Violations of rule 4 by the protagonist at the argumentation stage – The argumentation has no relation to the standpoint under discussion • Fallacy of irrelevant argumentation – The standpoint is defended by means other than argumentation • Non-argumentation – Fallacy of playing on the sentiments of the audience (pathetic fallacy) – Fallacy of parading one’s own qualities (ethical fallacy) Unexpressed premise rule • A party may not falsely present something as a premise that has been left unexpressed by the other party or deny a premise that he or she has left implicit • Violations of rule 5 by the protagonist or the antagonist at the argumentation stage – Adding an unexpressed premise that goes beyond what is warranted • Fallacy of magnifying an unexpressed premise – Refusing to accept commitment to an unexpressed premise implied by one’s own defence • Fallacy of denying an unexpressed premise Starting point rule • No party must falsely present a premise as an accepted starting point, or deny a premise representing an accepted starting point • Violations of rule 6 by the protagonist or the antagonist at the argumentation stage – Meddling with the starting points by the protagonist by falsely denying that something is an accepted starting point • Fallacy of falsely denying an accepted starting point – Meddling with the starting points by the antagonist by falsely presenting something as an accepted starting point. • Fallacy of making unfair use of propositions in making assertions • Fallacy of making unfair use of presuppositions in asking questions • Fallacy of using an argument that amounts to the same thing as the standpoint Argument scheme rule • A standpoint may not be regarded as conclusively defended if the defence does not take place by means of an appropriate argument scheme that is correctly applied • Violations of rule 7 by the protagonist at the argumentation stage – Using an inappropriate argument scheme • Populist fallacy • Fallacy of confusing facts with value judgments – Incorrectly applying an argument scheme • • • • • Fallacy of authority Fallacy of hasty generalization Fallacy of false analogy Fallacy of post hoc ergo propter hoc Fallacy of the slippery slope Validity rule • The reasoning in the argumentation must be logically valid or must be capable of being made valid by making explicit one or more unexpressed premises • Violations of rule 8 by the protagonist at the argumentation stage – Reasoning that treats a sufficient condition as a necessary condition • Fallacy of denying the antecedent • Fallacy of affirming the consequent – Reasoning that confuses the properties of parts and wholes • Fallacy of division • Fallacy of composition Closure rule • A failed defence of a standpoint must result in the protagonist retracting the standpoint, and a successful defence of the standpoint must result in the antagonist retracting his or her doubts • Violations of rule 9 by the protagonist or the antagonist at the concluding stage • Meddling with the conclusion by the protagonist • Fallacy of refusing to retract a standpoint that has not been successfully defended • Fallacy of concluding that a standpoint is true because it has been defended successfully • Meddling with the conclusion of the antagonist • Fallacy of refusing to retract criticism of a standpoint that has been successfully defended • Fallacy of concluding that a standpoint is true because the opposite has not been successfully defended Usage rule • Parties must not use any formulations that are insufficiently clear or confusingly ambiguous, and they must interpret the formulations of the other party as carefully and accurately as possible. Circular arguments and “begging the question” Van Eemeren Hahn et.al YES Although Walton seems to say that circular arguments are not always invalid, any error in the arguer is trasmitted to the “Beggingalways the question” argument. is a pragmatic error distinct from circular arguments. YES Are these the same thing? NO Walton If the arguer is bad, does this mean that the argument is bad ? Hahn et et al.al. say “the notion Hahn explain the that a poor argument is fallacy using Bayesian pragmatically probability: the‘question posterior begging’ probability of a conclusion is precisely the same labels as the the prior limitations probabilityofofsuch a arguments, conclusion,highlighting or to put it the another consequences of their way, being use in dialog [it] fails provided with. .a. circular to explain poor argument for awhy conclusion arguments poorhow in the does Truncalito not are change first convinced place. . . . The arguer of that too, presumably conclusion a thinker fails only because would be. his or her argument is poor NO They have a number of items in common: • They are both influenced by formal dialectics • They both want a rapprochement between dialectics and rhetoric. • They both see argumentation fundamentally as a dialogue with moves made by “players”. Conclusion • They both see argumentation schemes as logical tools The to regulate the dialogue. “pragmatic” approach of Douglas and “pragma-dialectical” model, • TheyWalton both use thethe “speaker-commitment” approachthe of Van Eemeren et al. are the thus avoiding irritation of having to consider worked talked about, whattwo themost speaker may out, havemost meant to say and arguably the best theories of • They are both concerned with the argumentation currently out fallacies. there. Whose is the best, or are they equals? Walton refers to fallacies as illegitimate shifts from one dialogue type to another. But it is only by some very creative theorizing that some argumentation (e.g. in advertising where the audience cannot question) can be construed as dialogues at all. Is it really reasonable then to think that we can determine what particular type of dialogue is being engaged in without antecedently identifying the fallacies? Do dialogue shifts explain fallacies, or do fallacies explain dialogue shifts? Is there any sharp boundary between one dialogue type and another? Like Van Eemerens “strategic maneuvering” the addition of dialogue types to the core theory of argumentation schemes poses more questions than it answers. Can we tell just from what somebody says (i.e. their commitments) what type of dialogue they take themselves to be involved in and what their communicative goals are? Couldn’t a speaker pursue more than one communicative goal at once, e.g. to persuade his interlocutor and to reassure himself of his correctness? Whereas who sees suchis rules In suchHabermas, maneuvering agent only Van Eemerenthe identifies the as trying constitutive of rationality, can say to win, yet we may suppose fallacies as violations of rules that thatheviolators are simply no longer that says exactly the same things regulate specifically rational “arguing”, Van Eemeren has to try to as he might otherwise, thus discussion.his bring commitments in “strategic maneuvering” are the same. Rhetoric came to be separated from dialectic and treated with suspicion, partly because of Plato’s criticisms of the Sophists. Rhetoric seems concerned with persuasion rather than truth. Not only would Sophists argue fallaciously, but they would do so not accidentally but with the express purpose of persuading irrespective of rationality. Dialectic consists of the canons of logic and is concerned with how you should reason, for which it sets up purely objective and rational standards. By correct reasoning you can reach the truth, and it seems to be further assumed that by communicating that reasoning, another rational being should be equally convinced of the truth. Argumentation is thus viewed by the dialectician is persuading by the best reason and to argue using fallacies is anathema. Civic or political man, loyal to the state Logic is the art of thinking; grammar, the art of inventing symbols and combining them to express thought; and rhetoric, the art of communicating thought from one mind to another, the adaptation of language to circumstance. Another description is: Logic is concerned with the thing as-it-is-known, Grammar is concerned with the thing-as-it-is-symbolized, and Rhetoric is concerned with the thing-as-it-iscommunicated. In medieval universities, the trivium comprised the three subjects taught first: grammar, dialectic, and rhetoric. The word is a Latin term meaning “the three ways” or “the three roads” forming the foundation of a medieval liberal arts education. Walton seems to be the most amenable to rhetoric because he says that not everything normally described as a fallacy represents bad reasoning or incorrect argumentation I think that the “flexibility” of Walton’s approach is actually a problem. It is vulnerable to the same kind of criticisms that Popper aimed against psychoanalytic theory of not ruling anything out and explaining too much. Although he talks about different contexts and values, he fails to explain how these are to be modelled using a purely dialectic system that operates with speaker commitments. Any such analysis will necessarily ignore the aspects of performance that are central to rhetoric. Arguing rhetorically is not so much a question of what you say as of how you say it. He endorses value-based argumentation, where one can argue differently to different audiences by taking into account what is important to them, what they value most. Van Eemeren’s theory has the advantage of being obviously wrong, but wrong in ways that are potentially revealing. In particular, I think it shows the inadequacy of the speaker-commitment model. It also assumes too readily that the best argument from a dialectical perspective will also be effective rhetorically; he doesn’t seem to have much to say if “bad” arguments are more effective other than that higher-order conditions are not being met, such conditions presumably meaning that argumentation is no longer taking place at all. This seems to me a fairly empty consolation.