Realist ontology of categories (a work in progress) Paul Thom This is a Powerpoint presentation. You can navigate the slides by using the Browse menu. You can animate the images by clicking anywhere. Contents Basic ontological relationships ab … the beautiful are beautiful by beauty. Phaedo. Thus, for example, the grammarian gets his name from grammar, the brave get theirs from bravery. Categories 1a14-15 ab: is from ab Contents Basic ontological relationships de de: said of de deG: said of as a genus deD: said of as a differentia deG de What is said of a subject has its name and definition predicated of the subject. Categories. Whenever one thing is predicated of another as of a subject, all things said of what is predicated will be said of the subject also. Categories 1b10ff. The genus [is said of] both the species and the individual. Categories 3a39. For footed and two-footed are said of man as subject. Categories 5, 3a22-24. Rule 1. If A de B, whatever is B is A Rule 2. If A de B and B de C, A de C Rule 3. If A deG B, A de B Rule 4. If A deD B, A de B Rule 5. If A deG C and B deG C, either A deG B or B deG A The differentiae of genera which are different and not subordinate one to the other are themselves different in kind. Categories 1b16ff. The Categories formula is equivalent to stating that if two genera have a common differentia (thus a common species), then one genus is subordinate to the other. That formula implies Rule 5. Suppose that both A and B are genera of C. If we assume that two genera having a common species have a common differentia, then A and B have a common differentia. So, by the Categories formula, either A is a genus to B or B is a genus to A. In other words, the Categories formula implies Rule 3, on the assumption that two genera having a common species have a common differentia. Contents Basic ontological relationships in By ‘in a subject’ I mean what is in something, not as a part, and cannot exist separately from what it is in. Categories 1a24-25. in in: inheres in in ab de Rule 6. If A in B and C ab A, whatever is C is B Rule 7. If A in B and A de C, C in B … the individual knowledge-of-grammar is in a subject, the soul … . … knowledge is in a subject, the soul, and is also said of a subject, knowledge-of-grammar. Categories 1a25-26; 1b1-3 Contents Basic ontological relationships ad Relatives are what they are ‘to’ something. Categories. A relation is an accident that is truly and simply one, not requiring a multitude in which it is, but just one thing – only in respect of another…. A correlation is a pair of relations mutually respecting one another. Correlation Kilwardby, De Natura Relationis 16:19-24 co ab ad: stands to co: are a correlation ad Correlatives ab … paternity is not of filiation … but father is stands to son and son to father. A relation, then, … is not relative except through the concrete [being] which it is in…. And so a relation is relative per accidens. Kilwardby, De Natura Relationis 5:22-28. Contents Beings Per se beings, denominatives Definition 1. perse(A) iff for some B [B de A] . Categories. Definition 2. denom(A) iff not perse(A), and for some B: perse(B) and A ab B Paronyms [denominatives] take their name from what they are from but with a difference of ending. Categories. Per se beings Denominatives de ab perse: is a per se being denom: is a denominative Rule 8. If A de B, perse(A) Rule 9. If A in B, perse(A) Rule 10. If A in B, perse(B) Definition 1 implies that if A de B, perse(B) Contents Beings … colour is in a body and therefore also in an individual body. Categories 2b1-2 Universals, individuals Definition 3. indiv(A) iff perse(A) and for no B [A de B] Definition 4. univ(A) iff for some B [indiv(B) and A de B] Things that are individual and numerically one are, without exception, not said of a subject. Categories 2, 1b6-7. Universals … it is necessary that the things predicated in what something is are finite. Posterior Analytics A22, 83a1. univ: is a universal de indiv: is an individual Individuals Rule 11. If A de B, for some C {A de C and for all D [if C de D, D de C]} Rule 12. If A de B and univ(B), B de B Definition 3 implies that if A de B and indiv(B), it’s not the case that B de B Contents Beings Substances, accidents Definition 5. subst(A) iff perse(A) and for no B, A in B Definition 6. subst1(A) iff subst(A) and indiv(A) It is a characteristic common to every substance not to be in a subject…. This is not, however, peculiar to substance; the differentia also is not in a subject. Categories 5, 3a7-8; 21-22. Definition 7. acc(A) iff for some B, A in B Substances Accidents in subst: is a substance de de subst1: is a primary substance acc: is an accident A substance – that which is called a substance most strictly, primarily, and most of all – is that which is neither said of a subject nor in a subject. Categories 5, 2a11-13. in Rule 13. If subst(A) and A de B, subst(B) The species in which the things primarily called substances are, are called secondary substances, as also are the genera of these species. Categories 2a14-17. A particular case of grammatical knowledge would be, for example, the grammatical knowledge that Aristarchus possesses. Porphyry, Categories Commentary 76,1. Rule 14. If acc(A) and A de B, acc(B) Rule 15. An individual accident inheres in exactly one individual substance Contents Derived ontological relationships Definition 8. A in2 B iff for some C [A ab C and C in B] [Denominatives] are in a subject secondarily, i.e., through their forms, which are primarily in subjects. Garlandus, Dialectica 18:3-4 Definition 9. A was B iff for some C, D [A ab C and C de D and B ab D] ‘All moving things are changing’ is not to be taken to mean that this is so absolutely, but rather while the substance of the moving thing is moving. Avicenna, Pointers 265. Definition 10. H sus C iff for some B [H in B and B in C] ab in2: inheres in secondarily (Garlandus) was: wasfi predication (Avicenna) sus: sustenation (Abaelard) was de ab sus in in2 in Contents Ontological dependencies Among per se beings For if one is to say of the primary substance what it is, it will be more informative and apt to give the species than the genus. Categories 2b8-10 de For example, animal is predicated of man and therefore also of the individual man; for were it predicated of none of the individual men it would be predicated of man at all. Categories 2a36ff. Rule 16. If a per se individual exists, a specific per se universal (which is said of it) exists Rule 17. If a per se universal exists, it is said of some per se individual Contents Ontological dependencies Among relatives Those relatives are said to be essential whose being depends on the correlative. Correlation ab Both correlatives essential Kilwardby, De Natura Relationis 18:21-22 ab ad Correlatives Rule 18. If A ad B and A exists, B exists Rule 19. If A ad B and B exists and both correlatives are essential, A exists Contents Ontological dependencies Inter-category All the other things are either said of the primary substances as subjects or in them as subjects. This is clear from an examination of cases. Categories 2a34-36 Cf. Marenbon, The Philosophy of Peter Abelard p.120-122 ab de He does not say that it is incapable of existing separately from what it was in, but that ‘it is incapable of existing separately from what it is in’. The smell is capable of being separated from what it is in; but it cannot exist separately and on its own. Porphyry in Cat. 79,23-34 Rule 20. An individual accident inheres in at least one individual substance Contents Knowledge Kilwardby’s account, Notulae Relative de de de Knowable and known ad ad Knowledge Knowable but not known Contents Knowledge Kilwardby’s account, De Natura Relationis Quality Relative de de Knowledge de de ad ab Knowable de de Knower ad Medical knowledge Known Contents Extreme conditions Different denominatives, same accident ab ab Contents Extreme conditions Aequiparentia (different relatives, same relation) Correlatives that agree in name and definition respect one another by a relation that is one is species but two in number. Kilwardby, De Natura Relationis 18:10-12 ad de in de in Contents Extreme conditions A relation is a substance Here is an alternative argument. Subst(A) iff for some B, B de A. Reln(A) iff for some C,D, C a A and C ad D. Thus, Subst(A) and Reln(A) iff for some B,C,D, B de A and C a A and C ad D. The constructive problem is to show that this is a possibility. … paternity is not of filiation … but father is stands to son and son to father. A relation, then, … is not relative except through the concrete [being] which it is in…. And so a relation is relative per accidens. Kilwardby, De Natura Relationis 5:22-28. A B de a ad C D Kilwardby’s argument is flawed. It is relatives, not relations, that are ‘ad aliquid’. So, the most the argument could show is that a relative may be a substance. However it can’t even show that, because a relative, being a denominative, is neither substance nor accident. And it is to be said that substance and accident differ in this, that a substance subsists through itself and an accident through a substance in which it inheres. Hence accident has this property that it inheres. Relation however, as such, has this property, that it respects another. So where these two (inhering and standing toward something) concur, relation is an accident – not because it stands towards something but because it inheres, since this (namely that it inheres) is the nature of accident. So take away the inhering and leave the standing towards something, and you have taken away the nature of accident. Leaving the nature of relation, but taking away the nature of accident, you necessarily leave the nature of substance. And so a substance can stand toward something and be a relative or relation, because this is not repugnant to it. Kilwardby, De Natura Relationis 34:14-24. Contents The Trinity Augustine’s account … every being that is called something by way of relationship is also something besides the relationship; thus a master is also a man, and a slave is a man …. So if the Father is not also something with reference How can theisthree relations nothing inhere in God? is said of with reference to something else. to himself, there absolutely thereNothing to be talked What are these three relations? Boethius of GodVII.i.2 accidentally. So relations can inhere in God only if De Trinitate mentions filiation and paternity; (i) these relations are not accidents, or (ii) they are … the substance of the Father and the Son is one. presumably the third is giving. But all these inseparable from their subject and inherences are There is at least no doubt that God is substance …. are accidents that can come and go in a De Trinitate V.i.4. inseparable, sometimes or (iii) these relations are [The– Holy Spirit] as he is subject whereas God insofar has no such De Trinitate V.i.3 accidents said of God or (iv) are identical with God. properlyaccidents. or peculiarly called the Reply: Definitions 3 & 4 exclude (ii). Rule 2 excludes (iii). Reply: It would to name the Holy Spiritbeisbetter so called relationshipAugustine excludes (ii). relations as divine or preeminent filiation wise, being referred to both Father So (i) and (iv) are the remaining possibilities. (filiation*), divine paternity (paternity*) and anddivine Son,giving since the Holy Spirit is the (giving*). God Spirit of the Father and of the Son. De Trinitate V.iii.12. “Yet when you ask ‘Three what?’ in human speech labors under a great of words. So we and say of three He dearth is the gift of the Father the Son a persons, not in order to say that … . So when we say ‘the gift of the giver’ ad precisely, in order not say to be and ‘the giverbut of the gift’, we each with Father giver Father, Gift (Holy Spirit) reduced to silence.” “… for God even being born is Son giver reference to the other. Son, Trinitate V.ii.10. everlasting, so that the Son can be De De Trinitate V.iii.12. “Even though some modifications are coeternal with the Father.” called inseparable … like the color De Trinitate VI.i.1. God, though, blackWith in a crow’s feather,nothing … the is said modification-wise, because there is nothing changeable with him. Andityet not everything is said moment ceases to be that that animal or of him is said substance-wise. Some things are said with reference How can two correlatives have a to something else,oflike Fatherthat with reference to Son and Son with reference to Father. that feather … it loses courses Son and giver are different relatives; similarly, Father single subject (if the corresponding De Trinitate V.i.6. color….relations So there is no modification in and giver. So there seem to be five or six relatives, are asymmetrical)? God because there is nothing in him not three. Reply: Father and giver may be different Reply: Paternity* is not Thus the Father is God and the Son is God and the Holy Spirit is God, and no-one that person. this is said substance-wise …. that can be changed or subject lost.” De asymmetrical. Every that considered as notions, but they denies are the same De stands Trinitate V.ii.9 in the relation to something Trinitate V.i.5. (viz. God) stands in the relation to itself. Contents The Trinity Kilwardby’s account God a = Filiation* Spiration* Paternity* a ad Holy Spirit Son* = spirator* Father* = spirator* … potius vocatur Spiritus Sanctus quam donum, Sicut Filius potius vocatur Filius quam Verbum. … Cui enim imponitur ‘Spiritus Sanctus’, est hypostasis rationalis, sed cui imponitur ‘donum’, infinitae substantiae quae dari potest, unde et nomen doni communius est de prima impositione quam nomen Spiritus Sancti. Kilwardby, Sent. 1 q.42:16-24. … gignens, genitus et procedens sunt relativa, sed relationes non sunt accidentia, sed substantia. … Qualiter autem relatio possit esse substantia, patet illis qui noverunt quomodo prima principia substantiae compositae ad invicm referuntur, scilicet materia et forma, quomodo etiam creatura Relativa ad creatorem. Potest autem hoc esse tali ratione: Relatio accidens aliunde est accidens et aliunde relatio; accidens enim est unde inest, relatio unde ad aliquid extra se respectum habet. Tolle ergo hoc ipsum inesse et tulisti accidens. Quod ergo remanet, substantia erit. Ubi ergo Nihil est inhaerens, non est accidens. Et tamen bene potest inesse respectus ad aliquid, et ille erit substantia. Kilwardby, Sent. 1 q.35:303315. Contents The Trinity Aquinas’s account Since the Word is the Son when God understands and loves himself, which Word is uttered by the Father, we must infer that the Holy Ghost, who is of the love whereby God is in himself as th beloved in the lover, proceeds from the Father and the Son. God understands and loves himself. Moreover, his understanding and his loving are identical with his being. Compendium Theologiae 49 A thing as understood in the mind is, as it were, a word of mind – for what we signify by an outward word of speech is what we have understood within. Therefore, within God we set down the existence of a Word. Compendium Theologiae 37 God =,de God’s knowledge ad Divine Known, i.e. Word a God’s love ad Divine Divine Knower, Lover Loved i.e. Father i.e. Holy Spirit … the manner whereby God is in himself as beloved in lover is described by the terms breath or spirit. Compendium Theologiae 46 Compendium Theologiae 37 When the mind understands itself, the word conceived is related to mind as offspring to father. Therefore in dealing with God’s understanding, the Word should be compared to God, of which it is the Word, as son to father. Compendium Theologiae 39