Law & Literature ISSN: 1535-685X (Print) 1541-2601 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rlal20 Slavery as Contract: Betty's Case and the Question of Freedom Sora Han To cite this article: Sora Han (2015) Slavery as Contract: Betty's�Case and the Question of Freedom, Law & Literature, 27:3, 395-416, DOI: 10.1080/1535685X.2015.1058621 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/1535685X.2015.1058621 Published online: 05 Nov 2015. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 614 View related articles View Crossmark data Citing articles: 22 View citing articles Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rlal20 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 Slavery as Contract: Betty’s Case and the Question of Freedom Sora Han Abstract, This article offers a theoretical reading of the 1857 freedom suit, Betty’s Case, wherein a slave woman, Betty, declared free by Chief Justice Lemuel Shaw of the Massachusetts Supreme Court, returned to Tennessee with her owners. Based on the case’s enduring question of whether the freedom to contract should include the freedom to be a slave, the article argues that this question is foundational for the ever-present jurisprudential problem of negotiating the empirical development of the idea of free will with the transcendental right of freedom in modern contract law. This deeper understanding of slavery as contract deconstructs and builds on critical legal studies of slavery that have largely focused on the legal constitution of the slave as property. Keywords, Slavery, race, contract, property, cultural criticism, American legal history, African American studies, critical race theory, performativity There is no up from slavery. (Anthony Farley1) INTRODUCTION In 1857, Chief Justice Lemuel Shaw of the Supreme Court of Massachusetts declared Betty to be free. Betty, a slave woman, had been brought from Tennessee into Massachusetts by her owners, the Sweets and by virtue of their travel and stay in Massachusetts, the Sweets’ relation with Betty had been legally converted from one of enslavement to one of labor.It was within this latter context that Shaw determined Betty to be a contractual agent with free will. This case, driven in its ruling and circumstances by a question about the legal personality of a slave, would come to be called Betty’s Case.2 Shaw’s ruling was not unusual, as exploiting the natural law of emancipation had become a common legal strategy for abolitionists in the northern states. However, emancipation as a formal legal procedure was dependent on the jurisdiction of free state courts, or the benevolence of southern masters. As a legal strategy, then, emancipation presented little challenge to the general political climate of the time. Law & Literature, vol. 27, issue 3, pp. 395 416. issn 1535-685X, electronic issn 1541-2601. © 2015 by The Cardozo School of Law of Yeshiva University. All rights reserved. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1535685X.2015.1058621. 395 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 Just eight months prior to Betty’s Case, the Supreme Court reasoned in Dred Scott v. Sandford that various state laws recognizing black persons as free did not constitute evidence of their fitness for national citizenship.3 Despite the anemic legal effects of emancipation on transforming the American law of slavery, Betty’s Case is particularly interesting for the question of freedom it raises. As matter of the legal issue of contract at the heart of the case, the law recognized Betty’s free will. But as a matter of the facts surrounding the case, Betty curiously, even unthinkably, asserted and exceeded this legal freedom. For, against the disapprobation and outright hostility of the abolitionists who had successfully brought the case before Shaw in her name, and immediately after Shaw’s declaration of her freedom, Betty decided to return to Tennessee with her owners. In Betty’s Case we find the crucible of mounting national tensions around the issue of slavery, the particular legal issues of contract and property at stake for the parties involved in the case, and the scandal of Betty’s decision to return to slavery. The scandal of Betty’s decision to return to Tennessee continues to be the occasion for retrieving Betty’s Case from an American legal archive with far more doctrinally significant rulings on the status of the slave. And yet, it is precisely because of a certain unthinkability as to Betty’s enactment of legal freedom that the case rises to the surface of the American legal archive to be read and heard again. This occasion is made even more compelling because of the fact that the case was never officially recorded.4 By every measure, this is a marginal case, even as it has been discussed as an example of the agency of the female slave to negotiate a personal domain of autonomy within conditions of legal and social subjection.5 It certainly is possible to understand Betty’s act as the performance of some nominal form of personal autonomy exercised against the slave’s legal status as property. In other words, it is reasonable to read Betty’s Case as evidence of slave resistance to, or incomplete domination by, the legal enforcement of the slave’s property status. But this reading assumes a tension between the law’s recognition of Betty as a contractual agent (in Massachusetts) and as an object of property (in Tennessee). It also assumes a tension between contract law as a mode of subjection through consent and property law as a mode of subjection through possession. Against such an average reading, what I hope to show in the following presentation of Betty’s Case is that today’s property understanding of slavery, through the imputation of a categorical difference between property and contract law, is a theoretical and historical assumption without moor and limits our ongoing efforts to innovate radical critiques of race, violence and freedom. We have only to note recent critical historical studies of slavery documenting that slaves did make contracts, and free blacks lived constantly under the threat of recapture and sale back into to slavery.6 In sum, racial slavery included contracting propertized subjects; and concurrently, legal freedom included repossession of contractual subjects. 396 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT Specifically regarding Betty’s Case, it is clear that Betty represents not simply an exception to this more nuanced historical scene of slavery, but marks the presence of a legal personality that decomposes the very distinction between racial slavery and legal freedom. Thus approaching the case as if Betty exercised some nominal personal autonomy over her legal status occludes the material circumstances of the case. It is pure projection to regard Betty as if she was a proper plaintiff to this case, for she plainly was not: the claim to enforce or nullify Betty’s presumed labor contract with the Sweets was made on Betty’s behalf by local abolitionist groups. Indeed, Betty was compelled before the court by writ of habeas corpus. The case materialized not by Betty’s own efforts or will to claim freedom, but is itself a sign of a constitutive coercion to appear before the law. At the same time, all we can glean from the legal archive is that Betty neither exercised rights entitled to her by contract law, nor did nothing with the freedom of contract given to her. What if, in our attempt to understand the resonance of this case, the enigmatic outline of the legal personality of the slave, appearing as Betty, was not reduced to any one type of legal relation in advance? How might we think this enigma through the language of modern American jurisprudence, while at the same time retaining the uniqueness of its imprint on the legal archive?7 If it is Betty’s Case, more than any other case, that marks the American legal archive with a material question about slavery and freedom, how does something like resistance take form within the specific confines of the law’s language of contract? Exactly what form of “resistance” takes shape at this singular instance where a name, “Betty,” appears as a sign of free will, and as the name, Betty’s Case, of a form of decision at the limit of the law’s idea of freedom? Is it even adequate to call this “resistance”? Why should we not call it “freedom,” as Betty neither accepts nor rejects this declaration made about and for her by the law, and also commits an act in relationship to it? BETTY’S ACT The legal issue in Betty’s Case concerned whether the Sweets were detaining Betty against her will, who held as a slave in Tennessee had become free in Massachusetts by the dictates of natural law. Specifically, as the antislavery activists claimed in their habeas corpus petition compelling Betty and the Sweets before the court, Betty was being held to a labor contract under duress, and thus, they argued that the contract must be invalidated and Betty released from it. In order to resolve this legal issue, Shaw needed to determine whether Betty was a contractual party by duress or consent. And so Shaw set out to personally interview Betty in his closed chambers. He explained this procedure was necessary so “that there might be no restraint or intimidation”8 from the Sweets and “all other persons.”9 By extending the private interview as a common practice of equity courts to emancipation cases, he intended to guard his determination of the nature of Betty’s will not only from those with an 397 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 immediate financial and personal interest in Betty’s labor, but also from those with a political interest in using Betty’s release from the labor contract as a strategy to emancipate her from a foreseeable future of enslavement upon the Sweets’ return with Betty to Tennessee. His chambers served to shelter the legal determination of Betty’s will from a tumultuous political context in which antislavery activists, starting in the 1830s, had regularly organized protests to physically obstruct judges in the Northern states from hearing fugitive slave cases and ordering black persons back to the Southern slave states.10 Legal historian Aviam Soifer gives us an account of Shaw’s conclusion upon emerging from this closed meeting with Betty: “[I]t appeared to me,” Shaw said of Betty, “that she is twenty-five years old, intelligent and capable of judging for herself.” He also found “that she has a husband in Tennessee and other relatives; that she is much attached to Mr. and Mrs. Sweet; is very well treated by them, and desires to remain and return with them, and this desire she expressed decisively and upon repeated inquiries.”11 According to Shaw, Betty had become emancipated when the Sweets brought her into free territory. But his judgment required him to analyze further not only whether Betty was a slave or a free person, but also if she was a free person, what the law required in recognition of her freedom, including her freedom to contract with the Sweets. He went on to reason: “it was contrary to all the principles of freedom that this [Betty] or any other person should not exercise a free choice in such a matter.”12 The “matter” at hand was Betty’s assertion during his closed interview of her desire to return to Tennessee with the Sweets. Notably, we know from the archival materials only what Shaw represents of Betty’s desires, and other than the fact that Betty decided to remain with the Sweets, we do not have any unmediated reference to statements made by Betty. In the archive, Betty is mute. This is not to say she is absent or illegible, but only to say that her act of returning to the Sweets becomes even more crucial for understanding the significance of the case. As Soifer duly recognizes as the assumptive logic of Shaw’s reasoning, “Rejecting Betty’s decision to remain a slave would have denied her freedom.”13 Or to state this more generally, legal freedom to be freedom must include an unobstructed right to contract, including the right to contract to be a slave. The unthinkable question Betty’s Case presents (and, again, this is not because of Shaw’s ruling, but rather because of Betty’s act in relationship to the ruling) is whether freedom, as constituted by the law’s language of contract, must include the freedom to be a slave. Stated another way, does freedom as understood and developed by law require an unfettered right to contract anything and everything with anyone? Shaw reasoned that it did. The abolitionists reasoned that it did not. But the crucial fact remains 398 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT that Betty’s act does not necessarily reflect a decision on her part that valorizes either of these two interpretations of freedom: the force of her act that carries along her desire and the irretrievable words through which this desire was expressed follow neither. In 1895, the US Supreme Court would unanimously reject Shaw’s reasoning. Justice Brewer’s opinion in Frisbie v. United States14 rejected a challenge to a national statute regulating fees paid to agents acting on behalf of private individuals accessing government pension funds, arguing that “[i]t is within the undoubted power of government to restrain some individuals from all contracts, as well as all individuals from some contracts.”15 He goes on to list several types of government restraint on the “freedom of contract” including restraint on all purchase or sale of lottery tickets, or the minor’s acceptance of obligations, or the transporter’s requirement releasing it from any negligence, or, interestingly, for our purposes, “all engaged in any employment from any contract in the course of that employment which is against public policy.”16 The justification for limiting the freedom of contract, we find, is the government’s obligation to regulate contractual relations “against public policy.” Frisbie’s reasoning obviously reflects the political sentiments of the Progressive Era, in which a burgeoning national middle class successfully advocated for government intervention in the private sector precisely to ensure competition and enterprise. Further, Frisbie’s public policy limit does not introduce a clear standard for the exercise of government authority over the freedom of contract, and only further expands the law’s interpretive powers over the meaning of “public policy.” Still, we find here the law’s recognition of a political need to regulate the freedom of contract in the commercial realm. Notably, this regulatory boundary can be read also to structure contemporary terms of debate about neoliberalism wherein the legal validation of commercial exchange and contracting the scene depicted in Frisbie’s list of particulars is either celebrated (by the political right) or bemoaned (by the political left) as a normative metaphor for resolving social conflicts. Yet, beyond Frisbie’s liberal reasoning justifying government intervention in the commercial realm, it runs into trouble. For if it provides a reason (“public policy”) for regulating the commercial realm (irrespective of whether one is ultimately convinced of this reason or not), it does not provide a reason as to why this curtailed commercial realm does not also curtail the right to freedom of contract. It only offers this flat assertion: “The possession of this power by government in no manner conflicts with the proposition that, generally speaking, every citizen has a right freely to contract for the price of his labor, services, or property.”17 Here Frisbie appears to want to have its cake and eat it too by initially imposing public policy matters onto the private commercial realm, and then by “generally speaking,” affirming the inviolability of the right to freedom of contract. How does government authority not “contradict” this right? As a matter of logic, it cannot. There is, in both Betty’s Case and Frisbie, a curious impasse in the 399 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 development of contract law that cannot establish a clear line of integration between an empirical realm of law’s regulatory power over exercises of individual free will and an absolute right of individual free will. On the one hand, there is the necessarily enclosed development of legal principles in social reality; on the other, there is an a priori right of freedom of contract that must protect itself from the singularity of the individual in order to hold out the promise of freedom. But as a matter of language, government authority can indeed not contradict the absolute right of individual free will. Frisbie and Betty’s Case, each in their own turn, differently overcome this logical challenge: the former by “generally speaking”; and the latter by hypothetically yoking the slave to the legal idea of universal free will. The sovereign regulatory power of the state and the sovereign freedom of the individual do not contradict each other because the two types of sovereignty occupy two different planes of legal language that are broached by generic speech and hypothetical example. In short, two literary forms of abstraction in legal reasoning protect the absolute right of individual free will from within the language of contract law. This might seem like an obvious uncritical statement about legal formalism. However, as we will see in the next section, what is not so obvious about these forms of abstraction is precisely their ideality as a material structure of law that Betty’s Case reveals because Betty’s act carries with it the force of a singular event that disperses like an echo across an interminable determination of freedom. This internally divided language of contract law is variously staged as an aporetic problem of freedom as both contract and absolute right. In that moment of “generally speaking,” the law cannot reason its way from the sphere of calculation to the sphere of foundational promise. Instead it leaps from a pragmatic application of contract law to the social world of commercial dealings to the idea of contract law in an abstracted world of individual freedom. I mark this aporia in order to emphasize a need to analyze more precisely the difference in legal discourses of contract between the law’s drift toward commercialization and the law’s failed logical negotiations of this drift with an absolute right of individual free will. The fact that the law pragmatically submits social conflicts to commercial resolution does not negate its dependence on an absolute right of individual free will. As such, contract law today, in practice and as conceptual metaphor for social relations, marks the law’s impossible attempt to harmonize principles of regulated and regulatory exchange and a categorically abstract realm of freedom. In this precise differentiation, we should attempt to account for how personal sovereignty, recognized by contract law in the legal personality of the individual, is haunted materially at the level of formal legal reasoning by a notion of “free will” that is free precisely because this freedom can be given away. Contract law itself obliquely and explicitly acknowledges the obscenity of the formal abstractness of freedom obliquely in Frisbie, when it recognizes the necessity of state regulatory power over employment contracts; and explicitly in Betty’s Case, when it affirms Betty’s free will. As two cases that bookend the Civil War and the Reconstruction 400 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT period, when the universalization of freedom of contract would become the dominant legal mode of racial subjection for freedpersons, they reveal the dependence of the legal meaning of freedom on slavery. To be clear, this dependence is neither instrumental nor existential. Rather, it is aporetic, meaning the singularity of the case of the slave, internal to contract law, materializes freedom as a necessarily transcendent right. Betty’s act within and against legal freedom is an obscene sign of “free will” that irrupts like the Real on the development of personal sovereignty in contract law.18 This catastrophic nuance retained by Betty’s act in the formal structure of legal reasoning in Betty’s Case holds open the question of a subterranean realm of legal thought about freedom that precedes property understandings of the legal personality of the slave. Betty’s act stages property freed, but so free as to be given away as something that might arrive again as or like property. In such willful crossing of freedom with slavery, that freedom which is given away turns out to be a complete negation of legal freedom, with the arrival again of the slave’s question of the transcendent right to freedom of contract. To be clear on this point, the mise-en-scene of Betty’s Case presents Betty’s free will as a predicate to her property status: Betty’s act spectrally opens up a territory of law where the free will takes the form of giving away or giving up on freedom. The fact that this will would be (re)owned is a contingency, while the freedom of a freedom to give away freedom is unconditional. This is not to promote a voluntaristic theory of enslavement. Rather, it is to present a certain rebus-like territory of law where distinctions between freedom and enslavement appear as effects of a freedom that is there in the law, but not of the law, and thus, obscene.19 THE PRIVATE LAW OF SLAVERY Focusing on Betty’s act, where legal freedom precedes the propertization of the slave, is not to argue that we have been incorrect to trace the production and management of slaves through legal conceptions of property.20 It is rather to suggest that a more fundamental legal relation contract appears through which to read the master/slave property relation. Literary critic, Hortense Spillers observed a problem with our treatment of slavery through the law of property this way: Even though we tend to parody and simplify matters to behave as if the various civil codes of the slave-holding United States were monolithically informed, unified, and executed in their application, or that the “code” itself is spontaneously generated in an undivided historic moment, we read it nevertheless as exactly this the peak points, the salient and characteristic features of a human and social procedure that evolves over a natural historical sequence and 401 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 represents, consequently, the narrative shorthand of a transaction that is riddled, in practice, with contradictions, accident, and surprise.21 If statutory constructions of the slave across the states are the “peak points” of a law of slavery, then we must be able to also read the nadir of this law, or what Spillers in the same article references as the “oceanic”22 of this law that is “riddled, in practice, with contradictions, accident, and surprise.” The question to be asked here is of a peculiar transactional scene of slavery, where who and what is exchanging and being exchanged for the promise of who or what in the future is not determined by any law in advance. That is, Spillers cautions that using legal definitions of the slave as property is a “narrative shorthand” for understanding the centrality of slavery to the emergence of the modern world, suggesting then that other legal definitions of the slave must be explored. Christopher Tomlins’ history of the creation of what he calls an “AngloAmerican law of slavery” also warns that it is not enough to acknowledge that “[s]laves inhabited England’s New World imaginaire from the very outset.”23 Though this is an undertheorized historical fact, reading and analyzing how this inhabitation took form in law is hardly transparent. Indeed, as he elaborates, the “formation of Anglo-American slavery as an institution [required] the creation in each colony of a legal condition of being for a particular segment of the population, qualitatively set apart from and absolutely subordinate to all other social and legal conditions of existence […].”24 Specifically as an institution shaped by law, he encapsulates, slavery in colonial America “began by joining within itself intellectual arguments and justifications from ius naturae and gentium with the peculiarly protean transactional capacities and policing technologies of English common and statute law.”25 The transactional scene of slavery appears again here to stage the problem of approaching something like the law of slavery. We are confronted by a form of legal translation that is “riddled” because “peculiarly protean,” or “peculiarly protean” because “riddled.” Both Spillers and Tomlins are deeply suspicious of positive laws recognizing the slave or slavery, for a positive law of slavery by definition is the consolidation of social practices and antagonisms into what we might call the master’s subject-matter jurisdiction over conflicts of rights between white and black claims of possession over various forms of value inhering in the slave. But this jurisdictional consolidation is created internally, as Tomlins notes, by an aggregation and supplementation of legal traditions and doctrines. As we saw with my framing of Betty’s act, the aggregative effect (i.e., the yoking of the slave to the legal production of universal free will) is precisely that: an effect. At the same time, we also saw that this effect and how it takes place in the law’s language of contract carries with it the aporia of a singular case that ends in an interminable determination of freedom. This provides a point by which an aggregative approach to the law of slavery opens 402 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT up onto the presence of an as-yet latent question: what kind of law underwrites the master’s jurisdiction in the first instance? As I discussed earlier, Betty’s Case suggests not that contract law is one legal mode of domination among others available to the master, but that contract is the condition of possibility for the slave’s property status. It is not because the slave is a priori property that the master uses contractual relations to exercise his power over the slave; but rather, the development of legal freedom is dependent on the slave as a passage between a fundamental split between radically heterogeneous exercises of individual contract rights (within both public and private realms) and a transcendent idea of the free will at the heart of contract freedom. Far from valorizing transcendentalism, contract law reveals a curious moment in which the protection of the transcendental right to freedom of contract is formally bound to the singularity of the case of the slave. Legal freedom, on this view, is not only the operationalization of universal individual freedom; it is also a limitless horizon of the limits of contracts brought into view by a certain transcendental register the slave’s emancipation must work through. At this register, the obscene legal effects of contracts made and broken between master and slave in both market and domestic contexts are factual predicates through which a transcendent freedom in law is materialized. Of course, those effects give rise to relatively empowered or disempowered claims of injury. But continuing to follow Spillers and Tomlins, those positive claims are always already translations, which require literacy in more than one idiom of representational forms if we are to mobilize them toward a knowledge of the law of slavery. The jurisprudential language of contract is one such idiom heretofore missing from predominantly historical, literary, and anthropological approaches to the law of slavery. In fact, legal philosopher and jurist, Theophilus Parsons observed something similar about the production of American law through an internal structure of translation in his treatise, The Law of Contracts (1853).26 In the opening chapter, which remained unchanged for the most part across the nine subsequent editions, he observed, “The law of contract, in its widest sense, may be regarded as including nearly all the law which regulates the relations of human life.”27 He elaborated further, “All social life presumes it, and rests upon it; for out of contracts, express or implied, declared or understood, grow all rights, all duties, all obligations, and all law.”28 Parsons’ idea of contract as the common denominator of legal relations and conflict is accessible from a lay understanding of the law. Without first finding some form of contractual relation between two parties, there is no legal basis to judge a claim, no matter what the conflict or injury is, or who or what the parties are. A natural or corporate person can sue a government entity because citizenship establishes a contractual relationship between them. One governmental agency can sue another because federal republicanism establishes a contractual relationship between them. A criminal defendant can sue state agencies because due process 403 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 establishes a contractual relationship between them. And an individual can sue another individual because the social norm not to cause harm to others establishes a contractual relationship between them. These forms of contractual relation are variations of the social contract as a theory of modern political life, but their legal forms (and there are many more like examples of contractual relations that we might reference) are hardly uniform or rational as expressions of the social contract put in action by the law’s language of contract. Legal historian, Roy Kreitner, has described Parsons’ view of contract as an “intermediate” stage in the modernization of contract law.29 Here, Parsons’ treatise marks a midpoint in the development of the common law status-based approach into the classic modern individual will-based approach to resolving contract issues. The common law approach, exemplified in the 18th century best by Blackstone’s Commentaries, reads contractual obligations from community standards of social hierarchy and corresponding expectations and duties. The modern will-based approach, emergent in Parsons’ treatise, finds contractual obligations where there is mutual consent to obligations freely given between individuals. And to the extent that Parsons’ treatise, according to Kreitner, exemplifies an attempt to narrate the emergence of this will-based approach of contract law from status-based approaches, it marks an “intermediate” point at which the universalization of the individual from status-based social groups is as yet incomplete. But perhaps there is a way in which we might read Parsons’ treatise not as a stage in the teleological development of contract law, but as a fundamental articulation of an ongoing process of transplantation and supplementation of various sources of law at the core of American legal modernity. On this view, the dominance of one theory of contract law over another signals the broaching of some internal limit within contract law that is carried along and given new form through varying arrangements and applications of fundamental legal concepts, such as the right to freedom of contract we read across Betty’s Case and Frisbie. The expansive and categorically abstract idea of freedom of contract might be read, then, to have always been the foundation for various applications of theories of contract from statusbased approaches characteristic of early modern legal regimes, to consent-based approaches characteristic of today’s late capitalist legal regimes. Lawrence Freidman’s unparalleled text, Contract Law in America (1965),30 can be read to reflect this reading of Parsons. There he elaborates how the jurisprudential project of formalizing contract doctrine was at the center of modernizing American law in Christopher Columbus Langdell’s wake, even as later scholars have noted the particular resistance of the form of case law to formalization.31 Grant Gilmore, in his own polemical exposition of contract law, focuses on and paraphrases Friedman’s most compelling insight, which curiously echoes Parsons’ general idea: 404 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT “Pure’” contract doctrine is blind to details of subject matter and person. It does not ask who buys and who sells, and what is bought and sold. […] Contract law is abstraction what is left in the law relating to agreements when all particularities of person and subject-matter are removed. […] The abstraction of classical contract law is not unrealistic; it is a deliberative renunciation of the particular, a deliberate relinquishment of the temptation to restrict untrammeled individual autonomy or the completely free market in the name of social policy.32 Gilmore’s instructive interpretation of Friedman’s history of contract concludes that this history is a history of a “residual” legal category, of “what is left over after all the ‘specialized’ bodies of law have been added up.”33 Contract law is both an abstract totality and an empirically residual legal relation, and thus any perception of change in its substantive rules for finding an enforceable contract is only ever a function of historically contingent inclusions and exclusions of other areas of law from an essentially empty core. Further, because of contract law’s essential abstractness, Gilmore observes, “it resisted, and continues to resist, codification long after most, if not all, of the fields of law apparently most closely related to it had passed under the statutory yoke.”34 The crystallization in the late 19th century of this legal terrain of general abstraction through the construct of individual will was nothing short of “a revolution in private law,”35 to use Kreitner’s words. That revolution, captured by Parsons’ theory, posits a form of private law that is the ground from which social relations are reified into specialized rights, duties, obligations and various genres of doctrine (including administrative law, corporate law, labor law, sexual harassment law, environmental law, animal rights law, maritime law, etc.). What is important to emphasize here is that contract law appears as law’s glance toward that which is anterior to socio-legality, and by this glance, we are reminded that positive law as the spatio-temporal mapping of rules and judgments can only ever be an approximation of the totality of law. To extend Parsons’ theory of contract from intellectual legal history to a critical approach to legal freedom, the hybrid contract form he identified presents a conundrum: contract law’s core principle is based in a negation that rends the transcendent right of freedom of contract into the singular material form of the case of the slave. As a philosophy intimately engaged with the law’s language of contract, it draws attention to the formal relation between singularity and totality that contract law represents in the socio-legal operationalization of free will. Perhaps what Spillers describes as “riddled,” or what Tomlins describes as “protean” is, in a critical approach to legal freedom, a negative form of private law that manifests in the 405 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 jurisprudential language of contract as pure abstraction and remaindered legal relations.36 Thus, what I want to call a “private law of slavery” references both substantive genres of positive law where the nature of the master slave relation was litigated (for example, the law of wills and trusts, commercial law, insurance law, employment law, tort law, family law, constitutional law, etc.) and the residual cases between these genres of positive law that were not litigated, and thus, remain as questions for thought and of practice in law.37 The private law of slavery, if it is to be a concept with critical possibility, must be grasped as a “residual” legal practice that endures after all of the social (and necessarily politically contested) practices of slavery have been institutionalized and abolished by law in various areas of property, commercial, criminal, constitutional, etc. doctrines. For these specialized legal doctrines are cannibalized from the essentially empty core of contract in the private law of slavery, which is always there as relatively fragile or relatively robust in the law’s language of contract. Consequently, the slave, as an enigmatic party to various kinds of contractual relations that make up private practice, remains after the various kinds of positive law institutionalizing slavery have been abolished. While we are accustomed to condemning contract law as state legitimization of social Darwinism, my reading of contract law thus far suggests a crucial point that goes unnoticed by reductive approaches to legal discourse. This point is that legal formalism’s dependence on contract law’s circling around a transcendent freedom is also a dependence on the immeasurable presence of the singular case of the slave, irrupting in the legal archive as an obscene form of freedom through which the transcendent right to freedom of contract is spectrally materialized. The problem with legal formalism is not its indifference to the socio-legal reality of racial and sexual violence and inequality, but its drive toward a transcendent freedom that distorts the singularity of the case of the slave as one particular historical injury among others. That is, Betty’s Case is unique in the precise sense that the circumstances surrounding the case, including the circumstantiality of Betty’s act, precipitates what literary critic, Fred Moten, calls a “transcendental clue,”38 that opens onto the private law of slavery. Perhaps it is impossible to not regard Betty’s act as anything but a tragic act. But still, perhaps, this tragic act might be seen to bear an elegiac decision, as a “necessary reaction to the tragic state of affairs that singularity imposes.”39 Specifically, elegy is “the mechanism by which hopelessly fragile singularity, after the fact of the inevitable end it is and brings, is regenerated in the form of a call to the spirit of a totality that is no longer, that has perhaps never been, one. The elegiac response to the end that is of singularity is the invocation of totality’s ghost.”40 A critical approach to legal freedom contained in contract law reveals something of this totality as the cold calculus of spreading the collective cost of social life, or as a humanist protest against the infinite designs of legal formalism. But even more crucial than these near misses with totality, when we read Betty’s 406 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT Case as a “transcendental clue,” it invokes precisely “totality’s ghost”: the always present (im)possibility of enacting a freedom that is also freedom’s end; a promise of freedom that simultaneously exercises and gives away the freedom the law would recognize in the slave but for the law’s fundamental dependence on her to continue promising freedom. THE FORCE OF NONPERFORMANCE If Betty’s Case recognized Betty as party to the social contract, it is nonetheless unclear what, if any, kind of promise Betty made to whom as an exercise of legal freedom. The recognition of Betty’s freedom by virtue of finding in her “free will” neither implies a mutual promissory relationship, nor the possibility of finding some form of breach of that promissory relationship by either party. Herein lies the ultimate stake of my reading of the private law of slavery: How, as a matter of the law’s language, to rethink the relation between promise, breach, and freedom raised by the slave as a figure of contract? While it is accurate that the law’s facilitation of the historical shift from slavery to segregation worked through innovations of contractual relationships (not only of labor, but also of kinship, citizenship, and selfhood), my reading of the intellectual history of modern contract law suggests that this legal development is symptomatic of a deeper jurisprudential problem rather than a moment of progressive reforms to the laws of chattel slavery. In this sense, Betty’s act faces another order of ethics what we might call an ethics of the obscene. Her decision is neither her submission to slavery, nor her permission to the state to enforce her legal freedom. It is a remnant legal act, or an unconditional responsibility to freedom a redoubled and redoubtable materialization of freedom that is otherwise known only in its relationship to the transcendent right of freedom driving modern law. The decision of unconditional responsibility shows up, at least on my reading, as a reveling in an enacted threat of a freedom against freedom that haunts any and every promise of freedom the law both makes and guards. Her decision is an a priori fugitivity to becoming a fugitive of the law of slave and free states.41 The force of this fugitivity is what we might reference as blackness, a performative against all performances of freedom and unfreedom dependent on the historical dilemma of a lack of meaningful distinction between freedom and slavery.42 The distinction here between performances of (un)freedom and a form of freedom in and as the performative of blackness is crucial. The latter arrives at a form of freedom dependent on, but in excess of, not only rules distributing the right to freedom of contract (which is contract law’s primary occupation), but also, on the radical adherence of the law’s language to the transcendent idea of freedom through the case of the slave. And while this performative is displayed in plain sight with Betty’s Case, it is buried, but no less present, in contract law. 407 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 In what is perhaps the irony of all legal ironies raised by Betty’s Case, we find that the formalization of what I am calling the performative of blackness is generally referred to in contract doctrine as “nonperformance.” Nonperformance in contract doctrine generally designates the failure of one party to a legally enforceable promise to fulfill her obligation to the other party. Black’s Law Dictionary defines nonperformance as the “the breach of a contract and the failing to carry out the terms of the agreement.”43 Nonperformance takes many legally actionable forms, including intentionally or unintentionally failing to keep a promise, or the judicial disposition of the excesses of promising as either “material breach” or “gift.” Stated another way, nonperformance claims are based both on omissions of acts expected to fulfill a promise, and positive acts which reveal the impossibility of meeting the expectations arising from what was a foreseeable future when the promise was made. This scene of contract encompasses nonperforming parties performing willed refusal, fraud, bad faith, or protest. But even more complicated than these performances, contract law also addresses nonperforming parties performing assent, good faith, accommodation, and commitment after any practicable conditions or moral justifications for the enforcement of the contract cease to exist by virtue of the fact of the future’s unforeseeability. This second form of nonperformance pokes a permanent hole in contract law’s disciplinary function. Here perhaps is the jurisprudential analog to Spillers’ and Tomlins’ notations of a “riddled” and “protean” law of slavery. For while we can imagine a contract law so punitive it might manage to effectively deter intentional breaches of contract obligations, it is harder to imagine a contract law unburdened by nonperformance resulting from wholly unforeseeable changes in conditions that render the expectations and enforceability of the contract impossible. “Nonperformance” is the promise of the material threat of chance that appears obscene only to the extent that the delusion of contract enforceability is maintained against the totality of circumstances in any given situation. It is a futurity that is radically indeterminable, and that is formally and uniquely structured into the temporality of the promise.44 Nonperformances of acts or intent make of contracting parties either competitors or crooks, but the legal idea of nonperformance also makes of the contract a way out for the contracting parties from their expectations’ hold on the future. This way out, an always present fugitivity, or the performative of blackness as nonperformance, is the horizon of slavery as contract. The idea of blackness as a performative in and against law then, is nonperformance, in this precise legal sense of a form of pure performativity that Moten would call “improvisation.”45 Improvisation, notably, is that which cannot be specifically contracted, nor performed against a contract, but is nonetheless a legal form contract law might refer to as nonperformance. We might say that improvisation is the kernel around which contract law’s recognition of nonperformance circles, and that which it attempts to defend the promise against. 408 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT This idea of nonperformance allows a deeper engagement with Spillers’ observation of the New World natal alienation of African captives that produces the “property/kinless constellation” of the slave. She specifies: In the context of the United States, we could not say that the enslaved offspring was ‘orphaned,’ but the child does become, under the press of a patronymic, patrifocal, patrilineal, and patriarchal order, the man/woman on the boundary, whose human and familial status, by the very nature of the case, had yet to be defined. I would call this enforced state of breach another instance of vestibular cultural formation where ‘kinship’ loses meaning, since it can be invaded at any given and arbitrary moment by the property relations.46 Spillers brushes up against nonperformance in contract law here in two ways. First, the processes by which property relations “invaded” forms of black kinship forged despite the law’s refusal to recognize and protect them occurred through what I have called the private law of slavery. The most common example is the slave family that is broken up by financial and disciplinary imperatives of the master to sell away a family member. However, Spillers’ specific reference to black kinship as an “enforced state of breach” gestures to the private law of slavery where all the conjugations of the abstract realm of contract law (what Parsons identified as “all rights, all duties, all obligations, and all law”) could be enforced against black kinship. In this particular example, the “property relations” are invasions cum conjugations of contract: to be more precise, changes in the names of the master with title to the exchanged slave. The invasive property relation is mere example for a general condition of slavery as contract, which must include all variable obscene forms of fulfilled promises. Notably, though Spillers references specifically the “property relation” as that which interferes with otherwise established (however precarious) legal relations of black kinship, in Betty’s Case, it is not the property relation, but the legal freedom of contract, which invades. Second, and the more important point for my discussion, this “enforced state of breach” is itself a reference to contract, but by promises that are known only by their inherent brokenness. The temporality of the promise represented by Spillers’ phrase, “enforced state of breach,” is not of future satisfaction or fulfillment foreclosed, but a condition in which compromise with any future called forth by the promise of human kinship is impossible (which is not to say that promises of some other kind of relation are not forged). We must retain this nuance. On my reading of it, Spillers is not arguing that the law of property denies the slave the capacity to promise, for some form of contractual relation (kinship) must exist to be “invaded.” Instead, she is arguing the reality of a “state of breach,” which through its phrasing, implicitly introduces the need for a specific understanding of the nature of the 409 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 promise, on the side of the slave, in a context where both legal unfreedom and freedom are enforcements against a radically indeterminable futurity invited by the legal idea of nonperformance. Thus, as she states, the contractual relation of “‘kinship’ loses meaning,” which is to say neither that whatever Betty might have promised no longer exists, nor that the reality of unkeepable promises forecloses the futures contained in those promises. Rather, we are on the terrain of a relationality based in an unnotarizable promissory note, already breached because unfulfillable. The performative of blackness as nonperformance opens up onto a form of intimacy that registers only in an obscene form of consent to being bound through such promises.47 CONCLUSIONS Caught somewhere between positive and natural legal theories of American modern law, slavery as a foundational national value is not ever fully present, except by a certain opacity of rights and principles necessary for developing a legal language of freedom within an American liberal political tradition. The natural law of freedom is first expressed in the classic judgment of Lord Mansfield in the 1772 Somerset v. Stewart case (issued three years before the start of the American Revolution), that ruled that the air of England was too pure to be breathed by a slave, and that therefore a slave voluntarily brought to England from Virginia by his master immediately became free.48 Somerset would then be directly translated into the 1836 case, Commonwealth v. Aves, also decided by Chief Justice Shaw, who declared that in the absence of a positive law commanding slavery, natural law required that a slave brought into Massachusetts’s free territory would become free.49 However, and as many of the judges of free states like Shaw would acknowledge, this natural law of freedom would inevitably conflict with the equally authoritative constitutional provision favoring the slave states’ interest in guaranteeing to owners the return of their escaped slaves. Still, the slave’s status as either free or bonded was never philosophically or constitutionally determined by positive law. In this way, the slave was always a kind of afterlife, a form of legal being that was neither birthed by law, nor extinguished by law, but nonetheless present in the law. Against the assumption that slavery’s abolition in 1865 with the 13th Amendment to the US Constitution marked the formal death of the institution, after which the Civil War Amendments and their Civil Rights legislations and principles came to represent slavery’s “afterlife,”50 the theoretical reading of contract law I have presented through Betty’s Case reveals that perhaps slavery’s afterlife is law’s condition, not its effect. For Betty’s freedom is a performative precipitated by both complete subjection to and mediation by legal protocols that leave traces of a form of disappearance that can only be known through a desire that persists in monstrous conditions of forced choices. Betty’s freedom is that which remains uncontracted in contract law. This 410 HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT commitment of freedom, then, has two valences of truth: freedom as a prison, and freedom as obscene fidelity. Where these two valences rub up against each other in the case of the slave, we have the performative of blackness as nonperformance, or the shadow image of the oft-noted legal fact that the slave as a completely subjected legal being was not ever given positive form by law. Here we are given the tremulousness of the words of law. Why has the property metaphor come to dominate our analysis and understanding of slavery, such that we tend not to think deeply about the irreducibility of the slave to property? If we are to be more precise, the metaphorical relation of property is materially given in the slave as a referent of a specie of contractual documentation called title. Perhaps it is stating the obvious to argue that the slave is not reducible to the object of a title document. But what is not so obvious is that this irreducibility is given not because the slave is recognized as a subject in other areas of or outside the law, but because title, far from fixing the fact of the slave as property, is and must remain a form of contract. And as we have seen, contract as a matter of form is and has always been beset by nonperformance, or the radical splaying of the question of who or what is promising who or what to who or what. This is the terrifying truth we know by Betty’s act. The law’s universal promise of freedom is not false, as Shaw demonstrated upon his emergence with Betty from his chambers. The law’s universal promise of freedom is a perverse wish. We domesticate this insight when we treat the case of the slave as an artifact, instead of as law on the perverse order of drives, that is, what Moten gestures toward as “a freedom drive that is expressed always and everywhere.”51 Indeed, here we have the slave’s “strange arrival,”52 in whatever may be the case before us. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The author would like to thank Colin Dayan, David Lloyd, Dylan Rodriguez, Fred Moten, Atef Said, M. NourbeSe Philip, Laura Harris, J. Kameron Carter, and David Marriott for their comments on this article. FUNDING This research was supported in part by the Beatrice Bain Research Group at the University of California Berkeley. 1. Anthony Farley, “Perfecting Slavery,” Loyola University Chicago Law Journal 36 (2005): 221 51 (237). 2. 20 Monthly L. Rep. 455 (Massachusetts, November 9, 1857). 3. 60 U.S. 939 (1857). 4. I thank Aviam Soifer, in particular, for his encouragement to think more deeply about Betty. See his discussion of Betty’s Case in Aviam Soifer, “Status, Contract, and Promises Unkept,” Yale Law Journal 96 (1987): 1916 59. 411 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 5. Edlie Wong has uncovered some interesting historical details about Betty’s Case. Specifically, we learn that “Betty, […] who refused to accept her liberty, […]took passage upon the under-ground railroad, and safely escaped to Cincinnati, where she was joined by her husband, who is a free man”; Edlie Wong, Neither Fugitive Nor Free (New York: New York University Press, 2009), 102 (quoting The Liberator, William Lloyd Garrison’s anti-slavery newspaper). Wong argues based on this “epilogue to Betty’s case” that Betty “took advantage of northern law and geopolitics […] to emancipate herself on her own terms”; ibid. The case, a “counter-intuitive freedom story reveals one of the myriad ways that slave attendants negotiated the predicaments that the law of freedom created [… through] seemingly contradictory legal reasoning”; ibid. Wong’s conclusions about Betty’s Case might be convincing, except that she refers to the case as “Betty’s case” and not Betty’s Case. This slip erroneously suggests that Betty had legal standing and that the litigated case was Betty’s, whether as a matter of legal procedure or history. My discussion of the case throughout this article is based on extending the theoretical significance of the formal difference between the proper name of a case, “Betty’s Case,” to which Betty is not a named party, and the proper pronoun, “Betty” in the name of the case, which references both the singularity and anonymity of the slave as a legal personality. Betty’s lack of legal and historical standing is symbolized in the unrecorded name of the case, Betty’s Case, a lack which would not have been symbolically inscribed if the proper name of the case had been “Betty v. the Sweets,” for example. Wong’s conclusions are also unconvincing given the fact that this “epilogue” appears in The Liberator, which further mediates, and does not factually clarify, Betty’s decisions and desires. My reading of Betty’s Case does not attempt to interpret Betty’s decisions or desires, but instead traces their force, as neither a “counter-intuitive freedom” nor proof of a certain reality of slave kinship, but as a form of freedom upon which legal freedom and its various and changing antonyms are predicated. In short, while Wong would contain her reading of Betty’s Case to “legal and literary hermeneutics,” I am interested in the case of that which escapes such hermeneutics. 6. For example, on contracts, or “passes,” made between slaves and masters, see Stephanie Camp, “I Could Not Stay There: Women, Men and Truancy,” in Closer to Freedom: Enslaved Women and Everyday Resistance in the Plantation South (Chapel 412 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2004), 35 59; and on the legal system of fugitive slave rendition, see Christopher Lasche, “Fugitive Rendition,” North Carolina Law Review 92 (2013): 149 235. These questions echo what I understand to be the vocation of M. NourbeSe Philip’s long poem, Zong! (2008). In the poem’s concluding “Notanda,” if Philip articulates a desire for a poetics of “Breaking and Entering” the text of the infamous case, Gregson v. Gilbert (1783), then she simultaneously asks of law and language, or law as language and language as law, whether: “Words break into sound, return to their initial and originary phonic sound grunts, plosives, labials is this, perhaps, how language might have sounded at the beginning of time?”; ibid., 200, 205. Philip’s question suggests for me that the Constitution, and in the widest sense, laws of various forms of constitution, open up onto the basest of bases where libidinal fragments of and as force are the inviolate surpluses of violence. Soifer, “Status, Contract, and Promises Unkept,” 1923 (quoting Shaw). Ibid., 1922 (quoting Shaw). Soifer provides a gripping account of the courthouse scene; ibid., 1921 3. Indeed, the highly charged political scene, and the growing trend among judges in the free states to abstain from issuing judgment in cases involving slaves, is the very same context that links Betty’s Case with the 1842 case, Prigg v. Pennsylvania, 41 U.S. 539, declaring the Fugitive Slave Law of 1793 to trump a Pennsylvania state law making it a felony to take a “negro or mulatto” back to slavery. Not only is this case a central doctrinal statement on the constitutional principles of American federalism, but also it is the legal backdrop for Toni Morrison’s Beloved (New York: Knopf, 1987). Soifer, “Status, Contract, and Promises Unkept,” 1923. Ibid., 1924. Ibid. 157 U.S. 160, 165 (1895). Ibid. Ibid., 165 6. Ibid., 166. Alenka Zupancic defines the Real, developed by Lacan through the category of duty in Kantian moral law, as an ethics of desire “in which our own death or a general catastrophe begins to function as the ultimate horizon of our desire”; Alenka Zupancic, Ethics of the Real: Kant, Lacan (London: HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. Verso, 2000), 237. The experience of the Real, manifest in a certain “preservation of fundamental lack that introduces a gap between the Thing and things,” is given in “‘something’ […] which appears only in the guise of the encounter, as something that ‘happens to us’, surprises us, throws us ‘out of joint’, because it always inscribes itself in a given continuity as a rupture, a break or an interruption”; ibid., 235, 240. The word “obscene” is derived from the Latin obscaena, meaning “offstage,” and conceptually captures what is at stake in this critical reading of Betty’s Case. For my theoretical orientation toward the “obscene,” see, generally, Georges Bataille, Eroticism (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 2001), 17-18. There he briefly glosses a definition: “Obscenity is our name for the uneasiness which upsets the physical state associated with self-possession, with the possession of a recognised and stable individuality.” The scholarship on this score is voluminous. Critical work includes: Angela Y. Davis, “Reflections on the Black Woman’s Role in the Community of Slaves,” The Massachusetts Review 13 (1972): 81-100; Robert Cover, Justice Accused (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1984); Hortense Spillers, “Mama’s Baby, Papa’s Maybe: An American Grammar Book,” Diacritics 17 (1987): 64 81; Cheryl I. Harris, “Whiteness as Property,” Harvard Law Review 106 (1993): 1707 91; Saidiya Hartman, Scenes of Subjection (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); Ariela Gross, Double Character (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000); Paul Finkelman, ed., Slavery and the Law (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001); Mark Tushnet, Slave Law in the American South: State v. Mann in History and Literature (Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 2003); Adrienne Davis, “Slavery and the Roots of Sexual Harassment,” in Directions in Sexual Harassment, ed. C. MacKinnon and R. Siegel (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2013), 457 78; Colin Dayan, The Law is a White Dog (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011). Spillers, “Mama’s Baby, Papa’s Maybe,” 78. Ibid., 72. Spillers is analogizing here Freud’s metaphor for the unconscious as “undifferentiated identity” to the “Middle Passage.” Christopher Tomlins, “Transplants and Timing: Passages in the Creation of an Anglo-American Law of Slavery,” Theoretical Inquiries in Law 10 (2009): 389 421 (391). Ibid. Ibid., 392 (the underlined emphasis has been added). 26. Theophilus Parsons, The Law of Contracts (repr. Charleston: Nabu, 2010). This chance encounter between Parsons and Betty’s Case is crucial, for the real aporia manifest in Betty’s Case is philosophically manifest in Parsons’ treatise, which would become the most popular legal treatise on contract in American jurisprudence in the several decades following the Civil War. The rebus of law as both real circumstance and philosophy amplifies a fundamental legal problem of contract and freedom that, in fact, predated this moment when freedom suits became an anti-slavery legal tactic. For the will-based idea of contract these two texts elevate can be traced back to the 17th century. Hobbes, for example, would work through his idea of the social contract predicated on a civil society structured by “voluntary obligation” or what we might call private law and custom; Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. R. Tuck (Oxford: Cambridge University Press, 1996). Amy Dru Stanley, in laying the philosophic ground for her history of the rise of contract freedom in the age of emancipation, notes that the “intellectual roots of contract freedom extended back to antebellum debates over slavery, twisting along the paths of the common law to the liberal political thought of the seventeenth century”; Amy Dru Stanley, From Bondage to Contract: Wage Labor, Marriage, and the Market in the Age of Emancipation (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 4. Indeed, one of the most prominent of freedom suits recovered by legal historians, Elizabeth Key’s Case, was brought to court by a mulatto slave woman, Elizabeth Key, in the colonial state of Virginia in 1656, and would include evidence of individual religious belief and practice in her claim that she was free; Case of Elizabeth Key. Northumberland County Record Books (Virginia, 1655), in Old Dominion in the Seventeenth Century, ed. W. Billings (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1975). Taunya Lovell Banks rightly observes that Key won her case based on theories of English subjecthood, and not on the court’s recognition of Key’s free will evidenced by her religious faith; Taunya Lovell Banks, “Dangerous Woman: Elizabeth Key’s Freedom Suit Subjecthood and Racialized Identity in Seventeenth Century Colonial Virginia,” Akron Law Review 41 (2008): 799 837. However, the fact that such evidence was presented indicates that both status- and will-based approaches to contract comingled in the early American law of slavery. Where in Key’s Case evidence of free will is buried under more dispositive evidence of status, in Betty’s Case evidence of free will is no longer 413 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 414 buried but takes center stage. We might say that within the history of freedom suits from the 17th to the 19th century, the question of the slave’s free will as a matter of contract law is more or less apparent depending on how it has been spotlighted on the stage of American legal modernization, and not a matter of whether it was lit at all. Ultimately, this suggests that the freedom suits litigated with increased frequency in the mid-19th century were not simply a sign of historical change, but a more complex recitation of a foundational jurisprudential problem of contract law predicated on the aporetic relation between a transcendent right to freedom of contract and the always present and undecidable case of the status of the slave. The historiographic question of the agency of slaves, in particular, female slaves, is one not of whether (female) slaves had agency, but one of a certain difficulty with encountering the complete (which is not to say over-determined) mediation of that agency by law, history, and culture. For critical historiographic studies of female slaves, see, for example, Brenda Stevenson, Life in Black and White (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997); Stephanie Camp, Closer to Freedom: Enslaved Women and Everyday Resistance in the Plantation South (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2004); Jennifer Morgan, Laboring Women: Reproduction and Gender in New World Slavery (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2004); Sara Clarke Kaplan, “Black Feminism and the Politics of Reading (Un)representability,” Black Women, Gender & Families 1 (2007): 94 124; and Stephanie Li, Something Akin to Freedom (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2011). Parsons, Law of Contracts, 3. Ibid., 3 4. Roy Kreitner, Calculating Promises (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2007), 20. Lawrence Friedman. Contract Law in America (Madison: Wisconsin University Press, 1965). Kreitner, Calculating Promises, 42 67. Grant Gilmore, The Death of Contract (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1974), 6 7 (quoting Friedman). Ibid., 7. Ibid., 8. I note, as does Gilmore, that there have been codifications of certain areas of contract law, as in the Uniform Commercial Code. But again, we mistake the jurisprudential problematic of contract law by conflating it with specialized substantive doctrinal areas, like labor law, or community property law, or insurance law, wills and trusts, or various kinds of social welfare legislation. Indeed, the preeminent legal minds of the 19th century who had grappled with the issue of contract law, like Joseph Story, Christopher Columbus Langdell, and Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., each in their own way recognized the impossibility of codifying all contractual relations. As a matter of history, this impossibility of codification becomes a defining feature of contract law despite and because of each of their efforts. 35. Kreitner, Calculating Promises, 1. 36. Brenna Bhandar has recently explored how legal interpretations of an autonomous will through property relations work through modes of abstracting material and immaterial things (bodies, land, ideas, etc.) from time and space. See generally, Brenna Bhandar, “Property, Law, and Race: Modes of Abstraction,” University of California Irvine Law Review 4 (2014): 203 18. The abstraction in contract law that I am interested in developing here is abstraction as an a priori knowledge of law, as well as abstraction as a form of art radically separable from its content. If Bhandar’s analysis of abstraction and property law is a critique of the metaphysics of modern liberal subjectivity, mine is an analysis of abstraction and contract law as a critique of the transcendental right of freedom. That said, and not completely unrelated to my general argument in this article, Bhandar’s analysis is unconvincing. The crux of Bhandar’s analysis is the legal figure of the slave as a “hybrid juridical form” between “object and human”; ibid., 206. For Bhandar, “this blurring of boundaries [in the figure of the slave] between thing and person reflects the same conflation of self with property that justifies private property ownership for John Locke and Jeremy Bentham,” and raises a more fundamental question of “being and having” as central to theorizing race and law; ibid. This theoretical examination is not a problem as much as the arbitrary terms that Bhandar imposes on her reading of law and philosophy in order to make the argument that racialization is in part a legal procedure of abstraction necessary for producing the modern liberal subject. The primary work of the article, indeed, is to read analogical connections between what she describes as the “materialization of the abstraction of the Black or Negro in the body of the slave” and the “materialization of the abstract sovereign subject whose very self is constituted through his ownership of things”; ibid. We must note that this similarity Bhandar projects onto the sovereign subject and HAN SLAVERY AS CONTRACT the slave in her analysis pivots around a small but profound error that should lead us to regard the rest of her critiques and interpretations with some suspicion, especially her engagement with Harris’s “Whiteness as Property” (cited in note 20); ibid., 206 13. This error is in the relation she poses between the terms “the Black or Negro,” “the body,” and “the slave” in her above formulation, which reduces “the Black or the Negro” to the metaphysical slave. This reduction of “the Black or the Negro” then further allows the comparisons Bhandar makes with various other legal figures to appear logical, including: the metaphysical master, or what she calls the “sovereign subject,” and later on, “the native,” “the savage,” and commodity and money forms, including finance capital; ibid., 208 16. This reduction further underwrites Bhandar’s reading of an Amiri Baraka poem that is unconcerned with its poetics; ibid., 217 18. As her analogical framework limits her legal critique, so too does it limit her literary critique: where Baraka’s “Negro,” on my reading, references at least five coterminous and entangled variations of a self in “himself” as reflexive pronoun and intensive pronoun; and “hisself” as “self as object,” “self/object,” and vernacular selves Bhandar finds only one, that is, a fraudulent self; ibid., 218. Like Wong’s containment of the language of the law to hermeneutics, Bhandar contains the language of the law to Marxist political economic critique. Each differently avoids encountering how the obscene rationality of the law singles out the non-singleness of “the Black or the Negro.” As an alternative to Bhandar’s analogical analysis of slavery and capitalism, I would argue instead that transatlantic racial slavery materialized the abstraction of the slave in the body of the Black or Negro, such that both “the body” and “the Black or Negro” are irreducible to “the slave.” 37. Adrienne Davis’s study of slavery through the concept of “sexual political economy” outlines how private and public law protected demands made on enslaved black women for various forms of sexualized labor. See generally, Davis, “Slavery and the Roots of Sexual Harassment” (cited in note 20). To the extent that Davis’ discussion examines private causes of action available to masters during slavery, she is analyzing a form of what I call the private law of slavery, but only in the former sense of the term. 38. Fred Moten, In the Break: The Aesthetics of the Black Radical Tradition (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2003), 99. 39. Ibid. 40. Ibid. 41. Stephen Best’s exploration and analysis of fugitivity, though it offers a nuanced critique of legal formalism as a philosophical approach, nevertheless rests on an uninterrogated legal formalism structuring his very definition of the fugitive. One might say in this regard that Best’s critique re-enslaves the fugitive through a form of law as critique that would see the running slave as running away from enslavement and toward emancipation. See, generally, Stephen Best, The Fugitive’s Properties: Law and the Poetics of Possession (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004). Against this move, I understand the idea of blackness as a performative through the specific form of fugitivity developed by Stefano Harney and Fred Moten, “Blackness and Governance,” in The Undercommons: Fugitive Planning and Black Study (New York: Autonomedia, 2013), 50 1. There we encounter the time of a “violent and cruel re-routing” precipitated by a certain inseparability between the “work of blackness” and the “violence of blackness”; ibid., 50. By implication, then, my understanding of the performative here departs from the general Austinian sense of the performative exemplified by the form of an oral promise wherein speech and act the utterance of the promise and the act of promising are one and the same. The legal determination of whether expectations mutually created by a contract, or those things promised by each of the parties, have been fulfilled is a derivative and wholly separate matter with respect to the Austinian performative of the promise. Determining whether the parties have made good on whatever the promise substantively references for the future does not negate a certain correspondence, or mutual fulfillment, between speech and act (promissory, either bilateral or unilateral) that binds two parties through language. However, I prefer Harney and Moten’s articulation of the performative because it does argue a correspondence between speech and act, but pointedly insists, within this plane of correspondence, on “the internal difference of blackness,” between its work and violence, as another form of promise in “a willingness to break the law one calls into existence”; ibid. 42. Judith Butler meditates on performances of freedom and unfreedom as “dispossession,” which is not necessarily incorrect as a matter of a sociolegal critique of liberal political community, but is necessarily superficial as a matter of a radical 415 LAW & LITERATURE VOLUME 27 NUMBER 3 43. 44. 45. 46. reading of law as a philosophic paradox of founding violence; Judith Butler, Dispossession: The Performative in the Political (Cambridge: Polity, 2013). Black’s Law Dictionary, online version, http://thelaw dictionary.org/letter/n/page/48/ (accessed February 11, 2015). This is in contrast to, for example, constitutional law, which is a derivative form of contract. The formalization of a radically indeterminable futurity in constitutional interpretation is foreign if not antithetical to the idea of democracy instituted by law, even if the text of national constitutions can be made to insist otherwise. Moten, In the Break, 13 14. Spillers, “Mama’s Baby, Papa’s Maybe,” 74 (the underlined emphasis has been added; the italics are Spillers’ own). 47. Moten writes of “the document or music,” what I take to be an apposite understanding of Betty’s act as something we might call a fugitive promise, or a fugitive note, that which is unnotarizable, or a mark on a score that in its form admits the impossibility of recording freedom; Moten, In the Break, 227. The legal documents that together constitute Betty’s act in and against the history of freedom have the force of a signature to some other kind of contractual relation that Spillers recognizes in slavery as an “enforced state of breach.” 48. Somerset v. Stewart, 98 ER 499 (1772). 49. Commonwealth v. Aves, 35 Mass. 193 (1836). 50. Saidiya Hartman, “Venus in Two Acts,” Small Axe 12 (2008): 1 14. 51. Moten, In the Break, 7. 52. Fred Moten, “Knowledge of Freedom,” CR: The New Centennial Review 4 (2004): 269 310 (286). Sora Han is Assistant Professor of Criminology, Law & Society and the Ph.D. Program in Culture & Theory at the University of California Irvine. She can be reached by email at: sora.han@uci.edu. 416