ANGELES UNIVERSITY FOUNDATION SCHOOL OF LAW ANGELES CITY, PHILIPPINES A COMPILATION OF REPORTS FOR LEGAL PHILOSOPHY Submitted by: AUF-SOL JD 1B Submitted on: December 5, 2024 Submitted to: Atty. Charles B. Escolin TABLE OF CONTENTS Class List i Groupings ii Written Reports 1. Natural Law 1 2. Enlightenment and Renaissance 12 3. Positivism 32 4. Realism 41 5. Marxism 51 6. Feminism 61 7. LGBTQIA+ 67 8. Eastern Philosophy 81 Class List for Legal Philosophy Class (1B) STUDENT NAME STUDENT ID LASTNAME FIRSTNAME MI 1 24-1707-201 ANCHETA JOHN CARLO M 2 24-1764-689 BUAN KATE CYRIL C 3 24-1763-644 CANDA CHELICA KYLE 4 24-1778-425 CASTAÑEDA E-ANNE QAYLAMYLE C 5 11-1254-627 DAVID KEVIN CHRISTOFER G 6 24-1747-424 DE GUZMAN ICONICA REY-VWEN L 7 24-1751-153 GAILAN ROXAN M 8 24-1711-698 GARCIA EDWARD R 9 24-1863-656 HERRERA DOMINIQUE RICCA T 10 24-1742-310 LUGUE JAMEY LYNN P 11 18-2796-773 NABATA CHRISTIN JIREH R 12 24-1839-697 NAGUIT JOCELYN MUTYA G 13 24-1718-973 SANTOS KAYE D 14 24-1821-198 VALES APRIL ANGEL C 15 24-1801-580 VIZCAYNO DEA A i List of Groups and Topics to be Discussed Groups Topics Members ANCHETA, John Carlo Group 1 Natural Law DE GUZMAN, Iconica Rey-vwen GARCIA, Edward Group 2 Enlightenment and Renaissance Group 3 Positivism Group 4 Realism Group 5 Marxism Group 6 CASTAÑEDA, E-anne Qaylamyle BUAN, Kate Cyril CANDA, Chelica Kyle GAILAN, Roxan SANTOS, Kaye VIZCAYNO, Dea NAGUIT, Jocelyn Mutya Feminism VALES, April Angel GARCIA, Edward Group 7 LGBTQIA+ LUGUE, Jamey Lynn NABATA, Christin Jireh Group 8 DAVID, Kevin Christofer Eastern Philosophy HERRERA, Dominique Ricca ii I. NATURAL LAW Reported by: ANCHETA, John Carlo DE GUZMAN, Iconica Rey-vwen GARCIA, Edward I. The Nature and Implications of Natural Law A. How is law linked to the concept of morality? IS- Old English: !lagu” - ordinance, rule prescribed by authority, regulation; district governed by the same laws; right, legal privilege OUGHT - the understanding of actions which are either good or bad. IS-OUGHT PROBLEM IN NATURAL LAW THEORY By arguing that what 'is' the law is based on a higher law dictated by reason and so is also what the law 'ought' to be, positive law is thought to acquire a sanctity that puts it beyond question (Yonjan, n.d.). NATURAL LAW CONSISTS OF THE PRINCIPLES OF OUGHT Natural law notes that the law ought to do more than simply exist the confines of morality, but rather it ought to contribute to the development of moral standards, and it is this morality that we utilize to define what the law is. II. Ancient Philosophy A. Introduction to the Theory of Natural Law: An Ancient Philosophy "An individual who breaks a law that conscience tells him is unjust, and who willingly accepts the penalty of imprisonment in order to arouse the conscience of the community over its injustice, is in reality expressing the highest respect for law... one who breaks an unjust law must do so openly, lovingly, and with a willingness to accept the penalty.” - (Martin Luther King Jr., "Letter from Birmingham Jail”) GOOD AND EVIL IN NATURAL LAW Natural law suggests that there are fundamental moral principles inherent in human nature and the natural world, which can be discovered through reason and observation. These principles are thought to be universal and unchanging, providing a basis for distinguishing right from wrong. NATURAL LAW CONSISTS OF THREE SETS OF PRINCIPLES: 1) Most fundamental - a set of principles directing human choice and action toward intelligible purposes. 2 2) A set of intermediate moral principles which specify the most basic principle of morality by directing choice and action toward possibilities that may be chosen consistently with a will toward integral human fulfillment. 3) Fully specific moral norms which require or forbid certain specific possible choices. CHARACTERISTICS OF NATURAL LAW (Dias and Hughes): 1) Ideals which guide for legal developments and administration 2) Basic moral quality in law which prevents a total separation of ‘is' from the 'ought"# 3) The method of discovering the perfect law 4) The content of a perfect law deducible by reason 5) The conditions are not for the existence of law- unjust law is no law at all When a constitution reserved a particular natural right from the government's power, natural law suggested the degree to which the constitution protected that right, not because natural law was incorporated into the constitution, but because natural rights were understood to be subject to natural law. e.g. • The Bill of Rights prohibited Congress from abridging the natural right of free speech and press, and natural law could be understood to indicate very generally what an abridgement of that right was. III. Stoics: How Should Man Act? Because human beings have the faculty of choice, they will NOT necessarily obey the law... when they act in accordance with reason, however, they will be "following nature." Stoics emphasized on the duty bond concept of law. It is based on the principle of ''do your duty'' but never expect any fruit."## BASIC FEATURES OF STOICISM $ goodness $ truthfulness $ honesty 3 $ cooperation $ support IV. Natural Law Theories in Ancient Period The story of natural law begins with the philosophers of ancient Greece and its true meaning is still a matter of controversy today. It is believed that the Greeks were the first Ancients who discovered the concept of natural law and developed its essentials. During that time in Greece, there was a lot of political instability. This led scholars to think about creating new rules or principles that could prevent unfair or tyrannical behavior by those in power. The Greek philosophers believed that if something is universally true, it must come from nature and should apply to all people, no matter where they are or when they live. Nature, they argued, is beyond human control, making these natural laws fair and unchangeable by any one person or group. A. Socrates (470-399 B.C.) Socrates, a prominent figure among the Stoic philosophers of ancient times, was a great admirer of truth and moral values. He believed that just as there are natural physical laws governing the universe, there exists a natural moral law that guides human conduct. According to Socrates, this moral law is understood through human insight, which gives individuals the capacity to distinguish between good and bad and to appreciate moral values. He famously argued that "virtue is knowledge," meaning that understanding what is virtuous naturally leads one to act virtuously, while ignorance leads to sin. A cornerstone of Socrates' philosophy is the belief that moral truths exist independently of personal opinions or divine commands. In the dialogue Euthyphro, he poses the provocative question: Is something good because the gods command it, or do the gods command it because it is inherently good? This challenge underscores his view that morality is not subject to divine will or human convention but is rooted in objective standards discoverable through reason. This idea resonates with the concept of natural law, which holds that moral principles are inherent in nature and universally accessible through human reason, transcending cultural and individual differences. Socrates also made a distinction between two types of justice: natural justice and legal justice. He asserted that the rules of natural justice are universally applicable, regardless of time or place, while the notion of legal justice may vary depending on the specific laws of a given society. The reasonableness of a particular 4 law, in Socrates' view, is judged by human reason. And, only those laws that align with the principles of natural law and are supported by human reasoning are deemed proper, while those that do not are unjust. Socrates developed a unique approach to discovering truth, known as the Socratic Method, which involves asking a series of probing questions to challenge assumptions and uncover underlying principles. Through this dialectical process, Socrates aimed to clarify concepts like justice, courage, and piety by stripping away false beliefs and refining understanding. The Socratic Method reflects his belief that moral and philosophical truths are not immediately obvious but require deep intellectual engagement to be fully grasped. This method mirrors the natural law tradition, which posits that understanding the moral order of the world requires careful reasoning and introspection. Socrates believed that only through this rigorous examination could individuals come to know and live by the universal moral laws that govern human behavior. In Crito, Socrates examines the relationship between justice, law, and individual duty. He asserts that individuals must generally obey laws to preserve social stability. However, his acceptance of the state's unjust sentence against him reveals a deeper conviction: true justice transcends human laws and aligns with a higher moral order. By honoring his legal obligations despite personal injustice, Socrates demonstrated his belief that justice is an integral part of the natural order. His stance suggests that while the social contract binds citizens to follow laws, those laws must ultimately reflect universal moral principles for society to function justly. Socrates' unwavering commitment to his philosophical principles highlights his belief in a natural moral order that transcends human law and opinion. For Socrates, philosophical integrity meant adhering to these truths as part of a rational, universal order governing human existence. His steadfastness underscores the essence of natural law: living justly requires more than mere compliance with manmade laws—it demands alignment with higher principles of justice and virtue embedded in the moral fabric of the universe. While Socrates did not deny the authority of positive law, he emphasized the necessity of natural law for the security and stability of the community. He was a rational thinker who believed that moral principles represent the higher law, and that individuals should act in accordance with their moral insight. Through this insight, Socrates believed that people are able to cultivate moral values within themselves. His teachings encourage us to use our reasoning to examine our nature and to make decisions that are informed by our moral compass, ultimately promoting a restorative form of justice. 5 B. Plato (427–347 B.C.) Plato is numbered among the most important thinkers in the natural law tradition. Plato's views on natural law, while not explicitly laid out as a systematic theory, are embedded in his broader philosophical work, particularly in his dialogues such as "The Republic," "Laws," and “Crito." For Plato, justice is not merely a social or political construct but a fundamental truth that exists beyond human creation. He ties this concept of justice to the "Good," which he views as the ultimate reality from which all other good things derive their meaning and value. Justice, for Plato, is a reflection of this higher, universal order and is rooted in the nature of reality itself. This idea suggests an early form of natural law, as Plato believes that justice is not dependent on human laws or opinions but is a moral order present in the universe that can be understood through reason. His philosophy implies that justice is something permanent and accessible, not subject to change based on human convention. Plato's view on natural law is deeply connected to his metaphysical ideas about the Forms. According to him, the universe is an orderly system grounded in the metaphysical Forms, particularly the Form of the Good. This Form is the highest reality and the source of all other things; when understood, it leads a person to act wisely. Plato connects the Good with the Beautiful in the "Symposium" and suggests that the ideal community should be established "in accordance with nature" in the "Republic." He emphasizes the importance of a perfect division of labor, where each person performs the role best suited to their capacities. He believed that justice and morality are objective realities that exist independently of human opinions and that laws should reflect these eternal truths. He rejected a subjective understanding of the good, arguing instead that certain things, like knowledge and beauty, are inherently good, independent of human desires or perfection. The pursuit of these goods falls within the realm of natural law as long as they are within human practical possibilities. For Plato, natural law is accessible through reason and is the foundation of a just society. Laws that do not conform to this natural order are not true laws and should be critically examined. In this way, Plato's theory of forms provides a foundation for the concept of natural law, as it offers a timeless and universal standard by which human laws and conduct can be judged. Plato was critical of positive law, which refers to laws created by human societies based on conventions or agreements, particularly when such laws fail to reflect the natural law. He believed that unjust laws—laws that do not align with 6 the eternal moral order—are not true laws at all. For Plato, laws must reflect higher, unchanging standards of justice and goodness to be legitimate. If they do not, they are merely expressions of human will and are not truly binding in a moral sense. This critique emphasizes his belief that laws should be measured against the natural law, which is derived from universal truths, rather than being based solely on societal preferences or temporary conditions. Plato viewed reason as the key to understanding the natural law. Through intellectual reflection and philosophical contemplation, particularly of the eternal forms like the Good, individuals can grasp the true principles that should govern both personal conduct and societal laws. Plato emphasized that reason allows people to discern right from wrong, and by using it, they can create laws that align with the moral order inherent in nature. In Crito, for example, Plato argues that people have a moral obligation to follow just laws because these laws reflect the natural order. Disobeying such laws is seen as opposing the natural law, which has a higher claim to justice than any human-made law. Plato#s philosophy laid the groundwork for the natural law tradition by emphasizing that justice and morality are rooted in an unchanging, universal order accessible through reason. His metaphysical theory of the Forms, especially the Form of the Good, underscores the belief that human laws and societal structures must align with eternal truths to be legitimate. For Plato, justice is not a human invention but a reflection of the natural moral order, and laws that deviate from this higher standard lack true validity. By advocating for reason as the tool to discern these universal principles, Plato championed the idea that both individuals and societies should strive to align their actions and laws with the inherent moral order of the universe. His insights continue to inspire discussions on the relationship between law, morality, and the pursuit of justice. C. Aristotle (384–322 B.C.) Aristotle is considered by many to be the founder of natural law. He argued that what is !just by nature” is not always the same as what is !just by law.” Aristotle believed that there is a natural justice that is valid everywhere with the same force. This natural justice is positive and does not depend on the decisions or laws of any one group of people. Aristotle believed that moral and legal norms should be in harmony with human nature. He argued that the world has a natural order, and as part of this 7 order, humans have an innate nature that shapes their behavior and ethical choices. For Aristotle, the ultimate goal of human life is to achieve eudaimonia, a state of flourishing or "the good life," which is attained by living virtuously in accordance with human nature. He maintained that virtues are qualities that help individuals fulfill their potential and live in harmony with others. This view of human nature as central to moral and legal norms reflects Aristotle's understanding of natural law, where ethical behavior and laws should help individuals live a fulfilled and virtuous life. Aristotle's views on natural law are integral to his broader ethical and political philosophy, though he did not explicitly use the term "natural law." He posited that the entire world is a product of nature and divided human life into two parts: first, that man is a creature created by God, and second, that man is endowed with active reason, enabling him to form his will. Aristotle asserted that the principles of natural justice can be discovered through this reason. Aristotle#s concept of natural justice underscores his belief in a higher, rational order that transcends human-made laws and customs. Aristotle makes a distinction between "natural justice" and "legal justice." Natural justice, he argued, is universal and constant, based on natural law that applies to all people and societies regardless of time or place. It reflects what is inherently fair and right, rooted in the rational nature of human beings. In contrast, legal justice refers to laws created by specific societies, which can vary based on historical and cultural contexts. He argued that what is "just by nature" is not always the same as what is "just by law," suggesting that there is a natural justice valid everywhere with the same force, independent of people's opinions or laws. This natural justice, according to Aristotle, is positive and does not depend on the decisions or laws of any one group of people. While legal justice is changeable and context-dependent, natural justice is unchanging and reflects universal principles of fairness and morality. In one of Aristotle#s works, Nicomanchean Ethics, he illustrated the close link between legal and political philosophy. Aristotle introduced the Doctrine of the Mean, which states that virtue is found in the balance between two extremes. For example, courage is the mean between recklessness and cowardice. This balance reflects Aristotle#s belief that moral virtue is grounded in human nature and can be discovered through reasoned reflection on human experiences. Virtue, for Aristotle, involves using reason to find the right course of action in any situation, avoiding excesses or deficiencies in behavior. He argued that law supports a virtuous 8 existence, advances the lives of individuals and promotes the %perfect community#. He proposed people should employ practical wisdom or active reason in order to behave in a way that is consistent with a virtuous existence. Aristotle defined justice as %a state of mind that encourages man to perform just actions#, %just "#meaning %lawful#, %fair"#and %virtuous#. His Doctrine of the Mean supports the idea that natural law is accessible through rational analysis, as it is through careful consideration that individuals can align their actions with their true nature and the moral order. Aristotle divided %political "#justice into %natural "#and %conventional "#justice. According to Aristotle, the content of %natural "#justice (or %universal"#law) is set by nature, which renders it immutable and valid in all communities. In contrast, %conventional "#justice comprises rules devised by individual communities to serve their needs. Aristotle argued %conventional"#justice is subject to change (depending on the form of government), and is therefore subordinate to %natural "#justice. In Nicomanchean Ethics, Aristotle identified a further two types of justice: distributive and corrective. For Aristotle, distributive justice involves allocating common property proportionally to individuals on the basis of merit. Corrective justice serves to redress any unfairness which may result from private transactions that violate an individual#s property rights or other rights. Whilst distributive justice promotes proportionate equality within society, corrective justice deals with the administration of the law through a judge or mediator. Aristotle placed great importance on reason as the key to understanding and applying natural law. He believed that human beings, through the use of their rational faculties, are capable of recognizing the natural order and making moral decisions based on it. In his work Politics, Aristotle argued that the best political systems are those that align with natural law, as these systems are designed to promote human flourishing and are guided by rational principles. By exercising practical reason and considering real-world experiences, individuals and societies can develop laws and political structures that reflect the natural order and promote the common good. Aristotle was critical of positive laws—those laws created by human societies—if they did not align with the principles of natural justice. He argued that laws should be designed with the aim of promoting human flourishing and virtue, rather than merely serving the interests of particular groups or individuals. Laws that fail to reflect the moral truths derived from human nature are unjust and do not contribute to the common good. For Aristotle, positive law is only valid if it aligns 9 with natural law, meaning it must promote ethical behavior, encourage virtue, and help individuals and society achieve eudaimonia. Laws that do not fulfill this purpose are flawed, as they do not serve the higher goal of fostering a just and virtuous society. V. Greco-Roman Philosophy A. Cicero “Natural Law is right reason, consonant with nature, common to everyman, constant, eternal.” • Cicero is a Roman Statecicero Roman statesman, lawyer, scholar, philosopher, writer and Academic skeptic. In his work he argued that both justice and law originate from what nature has to give to humanity, from what the human mind embraces, from the function of humanity, and what serves to unite humanity. • The principle of mutual benefit. B. Gaius !Every people (populus) that is governed by statutes and customs (leges et mores) observes partly its own peculiar law and partly the common law of all mankind” Civil Law - Law which people established for itself is peculiar for it is called jus civile (civil law) as being a special law of that civitas (State) Law of Nations - Law that natural reason establishes among all mankind is followed by all peoples alike, and is called ius gentium (law of nations, or law of the world) as being the law observed by all mankind. Thus the Roman people observes partly its own peculiar law and partly the common law of all mankind. - !innate in every human being" VI. Middle Ages Philosophy: Thomas Aquinas (1225 – 7.03.1274) Aquinas Argues that God created the world according to natural laws predictable, goal driven systems whereby life if sustained and everything functions smoothly. The Basic Goods 10 1. Life 2. Reproduction 3. Educate One’s Offspring 4. Seek God 5. Live in Society 6. Avoid Offence 7. Shun Ignorance NATURAL LAW THEORY PROHIBITION THE BASIC GOOD POSITIVE INJUCTION DO NOT KILL LIFE PROMOTE LIFE DO NOT PREVENT REPRODUCTION REPRODUCTION PROCREATE 11 II. ENGLIGHTENMENT AND RENAISSANCE Reported by: CASTAÑEDA, E-anne Qaylamyle GARCIA, Wolf Frank I. Contribution and Influence of the Enlightenment Period to Legal Philosophy What is the Enlightenment? The Enlightenment was an intellectual movement that introduced new ways of understanding the world through rationalism and empiricism. To break that down: • Rationalism argues that reason, rather than emotion or external authorities, is the most reliable source of true knowledge. In other words, to achieve enlightenment, you need to focus on rational thought rather than emotional responses. • Empiricism suggests that true knowledge comes from sensory experience and rigorous experimentation. This approach was not entirely new but was developed further during the Scientific Revolution. The Scientific Revolution Empirical and rationalist thinking didn't emerge overnight; they were developed earlier during the Scientific Revolution in Europe during the 16th and 17th centuries. During this period, scientists moved away from religious and biblical authorities and used reason and experimentation to understand the natural world. This led to significant scientific breakthroughs and a better understanding of the universe and human anatomy. The Enlightenment built upon this foundation, extending scientific and rationalist thinking to the study of human society. To clearly see the shift towards the enlightenment period, we remember from the previous discussion the emphasis on the belief that supernatural forces deeply shape the lives of human individuals. For instance, earthquake tremors in Istanbul in 1648 were seen as signs of a sultan’s death a few months later. A century after that, a huge earthquake struck Lisbon, Portugal. Tens of thousands of people died, many from a tsunami that followed the quake. Now, some theologians argued this was punishment from God for the world’s sins, but others pointed out that the earthquake had actually destroyed a lot of churches while sparing a lot of brothels. 13 Voltaire wrote a famous poem in response to the earthquake that included the lines “As the dying voices call out, will you dare respond to this appalling spectacle of smoking ashes with, “This is the necessary effect of the eternal laws Freely chosen by God?” Religious and Philosophical Shifts One of the key aspects of the Enlightenment was its challenge to traditional religious authority. In Europe, where Christianity had long held significant power, Enlightenment thinkers questioned the role of religion in public life. • From this, the idea of Deism became popular among Enlightenment thinkers. Deists believed in a creator who set the universe in motion but did not intervene in its workings. This view compared God to a clockmaker who created the universe and then stepped back. • Atheism was another response, rejecting religious belief and any notion of divine being altogether. Montesquieu (1689–1755) Montesquieu is a key figure in the Enlightenment. He made significant contributions to legal and political philosophy, particularly through his work "The Spirit of the Laws". Theory of Separation of Powers Montesquieu’s most influential idea is his theory of the separation of powers, which he articulated in "The Spirit of the Laws." He argued for the separation of powers within government as a means to prevent tyranny and protect liberty. In other words, he contended that political power should be divided among different branches of government—executive, legislative, and judicial—to prevent any one branch from becoming too powerful and to protect individual freedoms. This concept profoundly influenced the development of modern democratic systems, including the U.S. Constitution. Political Liberty and the Role of Law Montesquieu explored how laws and political institutions impact liberty. He argued that political liberty could only be safeguarded when power was not concentrated in a single entity. His work highlighted the importance of laws in maintaining a balance between authority and freedom, emphasizing that legal frameworks should reflect the values and needs of the society they govern. 14 Comparative Analysis of Political Systems His comparative method involved analyzing different political systems and legal traditions to understand how they functioned and influenced society. He examined various forms of government, including monarchies, republics, and despotisms, and considered how their structures and laws affected their stability and the freedom of their citizens. This comparative approach provided insights into how legal and political systems could be structured to achieve desired outcomes. Critique of Absolute Monarchy Montesquieu was a critic of absolute monarchy and centralized power. He used historical and contemporary examples to argue that absolute power was inherently corrupting and destructive to liberty. His advocacy for a balanced government with checks and balances was a direct response to the abuses of power he observed in absolute monarchies. Impact on Modern Constitutional Design Montesquieu’s ideas had a lasting impact on the development of constitutional design and legal theory. His concepts of separation of powers and checks and balances became foundational in many modern democracies, influencing how constitutions are drafted and how governments are structured to ensure accountability and protect individual rights. In summary, Montesquieu’s contributions to legal philosophy were pivotal in shaping modern democratic thought. His advocacy for the separation of powers, his analysis of different political systems, and his consideration of cultural and geographic factors in law provided a framework that continues to influence political and legal systems around the world. Voltaire (1694–1778) Voltaire, a leading figure of the Enlightenment, made substantial contributions to legal and political philosophy, although his work was often more focused on critique and advocacy rather than systematic legal theory. Critique of Arbitrary Power and Injustice Voltaire was a fierce critic of arbitrary power and legal injustices. He used his writings to challenge the abuses of authority, particularly in relation to legal and judicial systems. His famous works, such as the "Candide" and various essays, often exposed the corruption, cruelty, and incompetence of established institutions, 15 including the legal system. His criticism was aimed at promoting justice and rational reform. Advocacy for Civil Liberties Voltaire was also a staunch advocate for civil liberties, including freedom of speech, freedom of religion, and the protection of individual rights. He famously defended individuals who were persecuted or wrongfully accused, such as in the case of Jean Calas, a Protestant who was wrongly executed for allegedly murdering his son. Voltaire’s advocacy for Calas and others highlighted his commitment to justice and the need for legal systems to protect individual rights and prevent wrongful persecution. Opposition to Religious Intolerance Voltaire was a vocal critic of religious intolerance and the role of religious institutions in legal and political matters. He argued for the separation of church and state and for a legal system that would not be influenced by religious dogma. His works, including "Philosophical Dictionary," often argued that laws should be based on reason rather than religious beliefs, advocating for a more secular approach to governance and justice. Support for Enlightened Despotism Although Voltaire criticized the existing legal and political systems, he also supported the idea of enlightened despotism—where an absolute ruler would use their power to implement rational and progressive reforms. While this idea might seem contradictory to his advocacy for individual rights and democratic principles, it reflected his belief that meaningful change could sometimes be achieved through the benevolent actions of a powerful ruler. Voltaire’s contributions to legal philosophy were primarily through his critique of injustice and abuse of power, his advocacy for civil liberties, and his calls for legal reform. His emphasis on reason and justice, along with his criticism of religious and political authorities, helped shape modern perspectives on legal and political systems. Denis Diderot (1713-1784) Denis Diderot, though primarily known as a philosopher and a key figure of the Enlightenment, made significant contributions to legal philosophy through his role in compiling the Encyclopédie. 16 The Encyclopédie: Diderot was the chief editor of the Encyclopédie, a monumental work that aimed to compile and disseminate human knowledge. This work included extensive articles on law and governance, reflecting Enlightenment principles and shaping legal and political thought. Rational Critique of Existing Systems: Through the Encyclopédie, Diderot and his collaborators criticized existing legal and political systems. They challenged the traditional, often arbitrary nature of laws and governance and advocated for reforms based on reason and justice. His emphasis on human rights and his critique of societal injustices contributed to the broader discourse on human rights that influenced legal philosophy. His ideas supported the Enlightenment notion that human rights should be fundamental to any legal system. Diderot’s contributions helped shape the Enlightenment’s impact on legal philosophy by promoting ideas of rationality, equality, and justice. His work encouraged a shift away from traditional, authoritarian legal systems towards ones based on reason and human rights. Cesare Beccaria (1738–1794) Cesare Beccaria, an Italian philosopher and legal scholar, made groundbreaking contributions to legal philosophy, particularly through his seminal work "On Crimes and Punishments" published in 1764. Here, Beccaria addressed the principles of criminal law and the justice system with a focus on rationality, fairness, and humanitarianism. His ideas were instrumental in shaping modern criminal justice systems and have had a lasting impact on legal reform. Principles of Penal Reform Beccaria’s work is foundational in the field of penal reform. He advocated for a rational and humane approach to criminal justice, emphasizing that laws and punishments should be designed to prevent crime and rehabilitate offenders rather than simply to punish. • Proportionality: Beccaria argued that punishments should be proportionate to the crimes committed. Excessive or cruel punishments were not only unjust but also ineffective in deterring crime. He believed that the severity of the punishment should be calibrated to the seriousness of the offense, thereby ensuring fairness and justice. 17 • • Deterrence: Beccaria emphasized that the primary purpose of punishment should be to deter crime. He argued that punishments should be swift, certain, and appropriate to prevent future offenses. This concept has influenced modern criminal justice systems, which focus on deterrence as a key objective of criminal sanctions. Abolition of Torture and Capital Punishment: Beccaria was a strong opponent of torture and capital punishment. He believed that torture was both inhumane and ineffective, and that capital punishment was not a deterrent to crime and violated the fundamental rights of individuals. His advocacy for the abolition of these practices contributed to their gradual decline in many legal systems. Legal Certainty and Clarity Beccaria argued for the importance of legal certainty and clarity in laws. He believed that laws should be clear, precise, and publicized so that individuals could understand what behaviors were prohibited and what the consequences would be. This principle supports the idea that laws should be accessible and comprehensible to ensure fairness and accountability. Critique of Arbitrary Justice Beccaria was critical of arbitrary and discretionary justice, which he saw as a source of corruption and inequality in the legal system. He advocated for a system of laws and procedures that would limit judicial discretion and ensure that justice was administered in a consistent and predictable manner. His ideas promoted the development of more formal and structured legal processes. Beccaria’s ideas had a profound impact on the development of criminal law and procedure. His emphasis on rationality, proportionality, and the rule of law influenced legal reforms in many countries. His work laid the groundwork for the modern criminal justice system, including the adoption of legal principles that promote fairness, transparency, and the protection of individual rights. In summary, Cesare Beccaria’s contributions to legal philosophy are significant for their emphasis on rationality, proportionality, and human rights within the criminal justice system. His work on penal reform, the abolition of torture and capital punishment, and the principles of legal certainty and clarity has had a lasting influence on criminal law and legal systems worldwide. 18 John Locke (1632-1704) John Locke’s contributions to legal philosophy were groundbreaking and have had a profound and lasting impact on modern political and legal theory. His work, Two Treatises of Government tried to answer the question who should rule the country and on what legitimate bases. • First Treatise - demolished the spiritual claim that God had created kings • Second Treatise - people possessed a natural right that no ruler can ever take away o He wrote that the people voluntarily consented to cede some of their personal freedom but only as so far to preserve their rights. They could not be expected to give up these rights entirely as that would just defeat the point of joining the society o According to Locke, if a ruler started to act like a tyrant and unfairly deprive their subjects of their freedom of property, the subjects would then entirely within their rights withdraw their consent, overthrow their ruler, and set up a new government Locke is also popular for his concept that our minds from birth is a Tabula Rasa or a blank slate. - This is contrary to prevailing views that our minds are fitted at birth with all sorts of ideas about religion, ethics, morality, and government. - Lock contended that everything that we know, think, or conjecture is derived from experience. Locke made a significant contribution on the Theory of Natural Rights • Locke’s theory of natural rights is central to his legal philosophy. He posited that individuals possess inherent rights to life, liberty, and property. These rights are not granted by any government but are intrinsic and must be respected by all, including the state. • Locke argued that the primary function of government is to protect these natural rights. Governments derive their legitimacy from their ability to secure these rights for their citizens. This idea emphasizes that the state’s authority is conditional upon its respect for individual rights. Social Contract Theory • In Locke’s view, the state of nature is a pre-political condition where individuals are free and equal, but lack a common authority to resolve conflicts and protect rights. This leads to insecurity and potential conflicts over property and rights. 19 • • Formation of Government: To overcome the limitations of the state of nature, individuals enter into a social contract. They agree to form a government that will create and enforce laws to protect their natural rights. The social contract is an agreement among individuals to establish a political body that operates with their consent. Consent of the Governed: Locke emphasized that legitimate government is based on the consent of the governed. If a government fails to protect natural rights or acts against the interests of its people, the social contract is broken, and citizens have the right to revolt and establish a new government. Theory of Property • Labor Theory of Property: Locke’s theory of property is based on the idea that individuals gain ownership of property through their labor. According to Locke, when individuals mix their labor with natural resources, they acquire property rights over those resources. • Limits of Property Accumulation: Locke also proposed limits on property accumulation. He argued that one should only appropriate as much property as one can use and that enough resources should remain in common for others. This principle reflects a concern for equitable access to resources. Influence on Constitutionalism • Separation of Powers: While Locke did not explicitly articulate the modern doctrine of the separation of powers, his ideas influenced its development. His work implied the necessity of separating legislative and executive functions to prevent tyranny and protect individual rights. • Impact on Constitutions: Locke’s ideas on government and rights heavily influenced the drafting of foundational documents, including the American Declaration of Independence and the U.S. Constitution. His concept of the right to revolt and the protection of natural rights are reflected in these documents. Legal and Political Philosophy • Rule of Law: Locke’s emphasis on the rule of law is a critical aspect of his legal philosophy. He argued that laws should be designed to protect natural rights and should be applied equally to all individuals. This principle is foundational to modern legal systems. • Limited Government: Locke advocated for a limited government that is accountable to the people. This idea contrasts with absolute monarchy and 20 supports the development of democratic and constitutional frameworks that limit governmental power and enhance individual freedoms. Influence on Liberal Thought • Liberal Democracy: Locke’s ideas are central to the development of liberal democracy. His emphasis on individual rights, representative government, and the importance of consent has shaped the principles of modern democratic states. • Human Rights: Locke’s theories laid the groundwork for later discussions on human rights. His assertion that individuals have inherent rights to life, liberty, and property influenced subsequent human rights movements and international legal frameworks. John Locke’s contributions to legal philosophy include his formulation of natural rights, his development of social contract theory, and his labor theory of property. His ideas on the role of government, the importance of consent, and the rule of law have had a lasting impact on democratic and legal systems worldwide. Locke’s work laid the intellectual foundation for modern constitutionalism, liberal democracy, and human rights, making him a central figure in the evolution of legal and political thought. Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) Jean-Jacques Rousseau, a central figure in the Enlightenment, made significant contributions to legal and political philosophy through his works, most notably "The Social Contract" (Du Contrat Social). His ideas have had a profound and lasting impact on legal and political theory. Theory of the Social Contract Rousseau’s most famous contribution is his theory of the social contract, outlined in "The Social Contract." He proposed that legitimate political authority comes from an implicit contract between individuals in a society. • General Will: Rousseau introduced the concept of the "general will," which represents the collective interest of the people. He argued that sovereignty lies with the people and that the general will should guide the laws and governance. This idea was revolutionary in emphasizing collective decisionmaking and democratic participation. • Popular Sovereignty: Rousseau believed that true sovereignty resides with the people, and that all political power derives from the consent of the governed. He argued that individuals should not be subject to laws they have 21 • not participated in creating, which underscored the importance of democratic legitimacy and active citizen engagement in governance. Freedom and Equality: Rousseau’s social contract theory emphasized that individuals achieve true freedom not by withdrawing from society but by participating in the formation of laws that they follow. His notion of freedom is deeply connected with the idea of equality and collective decision-making, suggesting that individuals are free when they are part of a political community that governs itself through the general will. Critique of Private Property In "Discourse on the Origin and Basis of Inequality Among Men" (Discours sur l'origine et les fondements de l'inégalité parmi les hommes), Rousseau critiqued the institution of private property as a source of social inequality and conflict. He argued that the creation of private property led to the emergence of social hierarchies and the erosion of natural freedom and equality. This critique laid the groundwork for discussions on property rights and social justice in political philosophy. Concept of the Noble Savage Rousseau’s concept of the "noble savage" challenged the prevailing assumptions about human nature and civilization. He argued that humans were inherently good in their natural state but became corrupted by the development of civilization and private property. This idea influenced discussions on the nature of society, the impact of civilization on human morality, and the need for societal reform. Influence on Democratic Theory Rousseau’s ideas on democracy and the social contract influenced the development of modern democratic theory. His emphasis on popular sovereignty, civic participation, and the general will became foundational concepts in democratic governance and republican theory. His work also inspired various revolutionary movements and thinkers who sought to create more participatory and democratic political systems. Impact on Revolutionary Thought Rousseau’s critiques of inequality and his advocacy for popular sovereignty had a significant impact on revolutionary thought, particularly during the French Revolution. His ideas about the general will and the nature of legitimate political authority provided a theoretical basis for revolutionary movements that sought to 22 overthrow existing regimes and establish new forms of government based on democratic principles. In summary, Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s contributions to legal and political philosophy revolve around his theory of the social contract, his critique of private property, his ideas on human nature and education, and his influence on democratic and revolutionary thought. His work continues to be a cornerstone of discussions about democracy, equality, and the role of the state in modern political philosophy. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) In his 1784 essay "What is Enlightenment?", Kant proposed that the defining feature of his era was its growing secularism. While intellectually he welcomed the decline in Christian belief, he was practically alarmed by it. Kant was a pessimist about human nature, believing that we are inherently prone to corruption. This awareness led him to dedicate his life’s work to replacing religious authority with the authority of reason, or human intelligence. In his book "Religion within the Bounds of Reason Alone," Kant argued that while historical religions might have been incorrect in their specific beliefs, they had correctly identified the need to promote ethical behavior—a need that still persisted. This context led Kant to develop what he is perhaps most famous for: the "Categorical Imperative." The Categorical Imperative, first introduced in the notoriously named "Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals," is a principle meant to evaluate the morality of actions. Kant’s idea was to test the morality of an action by imagining it as a universal practice and considering its implications if you were the recipient of such actions. For instance, while it might seem harmless to take a few sheets of paper from work, if everyone did this, it would lead to significant issues. Similarly, while an affair might seem acceptable if kept secret, the Categorical Imperative would reject this if it implies that it would be acceptable for your partner to have affairs without informing you. The principle aims to shift our perspective to recognize the broader implications of our behavior. Kant also proposed a different formulation of the Categorical Imperative: treating individuals as ends in themselves, not merely as means to an end. This idea was intended as a replacement for the Christian command to "love 23 one's neighbor." According to Kant, treating a person as an end means recognizing their own pursuit of happiness and fulfillment, and ensuring justice and fair treatment. The Categorical Imperative, for Kant, represents the voice of our rational selves, embodying the principles our intelligence dictates when we think clearly. Theory of Justice and Rights • Right and Justice: Kant believed that justice involves respecting and protecting individual rights. His concept of right (Recht) is grounded in the idea that individuals have inherent rights that must be respected by all, including the state. This concept underpins modern ideas of legal rights and the rule of law. • Moral Autonomy and Legal Authority: Kant’s notion of moral autonomy implies that individuals are self-governing and must have a say in the laws that govern them. This aligns with democratic principles where laws are created and enforced with the consent of the governed. Principle of Publicity Kant argued that laws should be publicly known and accessible. This principle of publicity ensures that individuals are aware of the laws and can understand how they are applied. It promotes transparency and accountability in legal systems, preventing arbitrary or secretive enforcement of laws. Retributive Justice Kant’s views on punishment are grounded in retributive justice. He argued that punishment should be proportionate to the crime and should serve as a means of moral retribution rather than deterrence or rehabilitation. According to Kant: • Proportionality: Punishments must be proportionate to the seriousness of the crime committed. This reflects his belief in respecting the dignity of individuals and ensuring that justice is fairly administered. • Moral Justification: Punishment, for Kant, is justified morally when it is a necessary response to a violation of the law. It should reaffirm the moral order and respect for the law. Autonomy and the Social Contract Kant’s theory of the social contract is based on the idea that individuals, as moral agents, agree to form a civil society and abide by laws that they collectively legislate. This agreement is grounded in the respect for individual autonomy and the desire to live in a community where mutual respect and justice prevail. 24 Influence on Modern Legal Theory Kant’s ideas have had a profound impact on modern legal theory: • Human Rights: Kant’s emphasis on respecting individuals as ends in themselves has been foundational for the development of human rights theories. His work influenced the formulation of international human rights laws and the protection of individual rights. Legal Formalism: Kant’s insistence on consistency, universality, and respect for individual rights has influenced legal formalism, which emphasizes the application of law according to established principles and precedents. So, those were just some of the philosophers during the enlightenment period who significantly contributed to legal philosophy. From their contributions, we derive the key enlightenment ideas. Key Enlightenment Ideas 1. Individualism: Enlightenment thinkers emphasized the individual as the fundamental unit of society, with progress and personal expansion being key. 2. Natural Rights: The belief that individuals are born with inherent rights that cannot be infringed upon by governments. We remember, John Locke who argued that individuals have natural rights to life, liberty, and property, which are endowed by God and cannot be taken away by any ruler. 3. Social Contract: The idea that societies, endowed with natural rights, should create governments by their own will. The main purpose of these governments is to protect natural rights. If a government becomes tyrannical and violates these rights, people have the right to overthrow it and establish a new one. Effects of the Enlightenment We also derive the profound effects of Enlightenment to the world. 1. Revolutions: Enlightenment ideas laid the groundwork for major revolutions, including the American, French, Haitian, and Latin American revolutions. These revolutions challenged traditional authorities and proposed new ideas about political power. 2. Expansion of Suffrage: Enlightenment principles like liberty and equality led to the expansion of voting rights. And by equality, I mean among males. Initially, only landowning white males were allowed to vote, but over time, suffrage expanded to include all white males, and after that, eventually black males were likewise allowed to vote. 25 3. Abolition of Slavery: Enlightenment thinkers criticized slavery for its disregard of natural rights. This criticism contributed to the abolition of slavery in places like Great Britain, which, while economically motivated, was also driven by ethical considerations. 4. End of Serfdom: The transition from agricultural to industrial economies made serfdom increasingly obsolete. Peasant revolts and Enlightenment ideas prompted the end of serfdom in countries like England, France, and Russia. 5. Women’s Rights: Despite revolutionary movements emphasizing equality, women often did not share equally in the gains. Although not yet fully established during the Enlightenment period, a growing feminist movement emerged, demanding equality in all areas of life, including voting rights. In summary, the Enlightenment period was pivotal in advancing legal philosophy by promoting reason and individual rights as the basis for law and governance. This era laid the intellectual foundation for modern democratic and legal systems, shaping the principles of justice, equality, and human dignity that remain central to contemporary legal and political frameworks. 26 II. Contribution and Influence of the Renaissance Period to Legal Philosophy Introduction The Renaissance, meaning "rebirth," in was a period of cultural, artistic, intellectual, and social revival in Europe that spanned from the 14th to the 17th century. It marked the transition from the Middle Ages to modernity and was characterized by a renewed interest in classical antiquity, particularly the works of Ancient Greece and Rome. The Renaissance is often regarded as one of the most transformative eras in European history, influencing art, science, philosophy, literature, politics, and religion. Historical Context The Renaissance began in Italy, particularly in cities like Florence, Venice, and Rome, before spreading to the rest of Europe. Several factors contributed to its emergence: • Economic Prosperity - The growth of trade and commerce in Italian citystates enabled the rise of wealthy merchant families, such as the Medici in Florence, who became patrons of the arts and learning. • Rediscovery of Classical Texts - After the fall of Constantinople in 1453, many Greek scholars fled to Italy, bringing with them classical manuscripts that had been lost to the West. This ignited a renewed interest in GrecoRoman knowledge. • Humanism - A philosophical movement emphasizing human potential, reason, and individualism, humanism rejected the medieval focus on theology and mysticism. It promoted the study of humanities, including literature, history, and ethics, based on classical models. Key Features of the Renaissance The Renaissance was marked by several defining characteristics that transformed European society: a. Art and Architecture • Renaissance art emphasized realism, perspective, and the human form. Artists such as Leonardo da Vinci, Michelangelo, Raphael, and Donatello revolutionized painting and sculpture by incorporating techniques like linear perspective, chiaroscuro (the use of light and dark contrasts in art to create a sense of volume and three- 27 dimensionality), and anatomical precision. Architecture saw the revival of classical forms, with Filippo Brunelleschi and Leon Battista Alberti pioneering new approaches to design and urban planning. b. Science and Innovation • The Renaissance was a period of scientific inquiry and technological advancement. Nicolaus Copernicus developed the heliocentric theory of the solar system, while Galileo Galilei and Johannes Kepler furthered astronomy and physics. Leonardo da Vinci, a polymath, made significant contributions to engineering, anatomy, and mathematics. The invention of the printing press by Johannes Gutenberg in the mid-15th century enabled the rapid dissemination of knowledge. c. Philosophy and Humanism • Humanism, central to Renaissance thought, sought to revive classical wisdom while focusing on human experience and individual dignity. Thinkers like Pico della Mirandola (author of "Oration on the Dignity of Man") and Erasmus of Rotterdam advocated for educational reform and the study of classical texts. This intellectual movement influenced politics, literature, and religion, moving away from the strict confines of medieval scholasticism. d. Literature • Renaissance literature was marked by the use of vernacular languages and a focus on human experience. • Dante Alighieri ("The Divine Comedy"), Geoffrey Chaucer ("The Canterbury Tales"), and Petrarch were early figures in this literary revival. Later, William Shakespeare, Niccolò Machiavelli (author of "The Prince"), and Miguel de Cervantes (author of "Don Quixote") became central literary figures whose works have had a lasting impact. e. Religion and Reformation • While the Renaissance was primarily secular, it also influenced religious thought, laying the groundwork for the Protestant Reformation. Martin Luther, influenced by Renaissance ideas, challenged the authority of the Catholic Church with his 95 Theses in 1517. The Reformation led to significant religious and political changes 28 across Europe, including the establishment of Protestant churches and reforms within Catholicism. Major Features of the Renaissance 1. Leonardo da Vinci - A quintessential "Renaissance Man," Leonardo was an artist, scientist, and inventor. His works, such as The Last Supper and Mona Lisa, are among the most famous in the world. His notebooks reveal his scientific studies in anatomy, engineering, and mechanics. 2. Michaelangelo Buonarroti - Renowned for his sculptures like David and Pietà, as well as his paintings on the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel, Michelangelo's work embodies the Renaissance ideals of human beauty and strength. 3. Niccolò Machiavelli - A political philosopher and diplomat, Machiavelli's work The Prince became a foundational text in political theory, advocating pragmatic and sometimes ruthless approaches to statecraft. Machiavelli argued that the most effective rulers were those who could balance conflicting interests and respond quickly to new challenges. Overall, Machiavellian statecraft emphasizes the importance of power, adaptability, and ruthlessness in maintaining political control. 4. Raphael - Known for his harmonious and serene depictions, Raphael's School of Athens is a masterpiece of Renaissance art, depicting an idealized vision of intellectual exchange between ancient philosophers. 5. Galileo Galilei - A pivotal figure in the Scientific Revolution, Galileo's work in astronomy (including his defense of the heliocentric model) and physics laid the groundwork for modern science. His conflict with the Catholic Church symbolized the growing tension between science and religious authority during the Renaissance. The Spread of Renaissance Although the Renaissance began in Italy, it quickly spread to other parts of Europe: 29 Northern Renaissance In regions like Flanders, Germany, and England, the Renaissance took on a more religious tone. Artists like Albrecht Dürer and Jan van Eyck introduced oil painting techniques and created detailed works with symbolic depth. Writers such as Thomas More and Erasmus promoted Christian humanism. French Renaissance The French Renaissance was heavily influenced by Italian culture, particularly after King Francis I invited artists like Leonardo da Vinci to his court. Architecture flourished with the construction of châteaux in the Loire Valley. English Renaisance The French Renaissance was heavily influenced by Italian culture, particularly after King Francis I invited artists like Leonardo da Vinci to his court. Architecture flourished with the construction of châteaux in the Loire Valley. Impact of the Renaissance The Renaissance was marked by several defining characteristics that transformed European society: Cultural Legacy The artistic and intellectual achievements of the Renaissance have shaped Western culture, inspiring countless generations of artists, writers, and thinkers. Scientific Progress The period’s emphasis on observation, experimentation, and inquiry laid the groundwork for the Scientific Revolution, which further advanced understanding in fields such as physics, astronomy, and biology. Political Changes Renaissance ideas contributed to the development of modern political theory and the rise of the modern state. The period also saw the decline of feudalism and the rise of centralized monarchies in Europe. 30 Education and Humanism The humanist focus on education, individualism, and critical thinking influenced modern educational systems. The Renaissance also promoted the study of classical languages, literature, and history, which remain core elements of liberal arts education today. Conclusion The Renaissance was a time of extraordinary cultural, intellectual, and artistic achievements. Its emphasis on rediscovering classical knowledge, coupled with innovations in art, science, and thought, shaped the course of Western history. By challenging the boundaries of the medieval worldview, the Renaissance laid the foundation for modernity and continues to inspire contemporary culture, philosophy, and learning. The legacy of the Renaissance is a testament to the power of human creativity, curiosity, and ambition, setting the stage for the transformation of Europe and the world at large. 31 III. POSITIVISM Reported by: BUAN, Kate Cyril CANDA, Chelica Kyle POSITIVISM - APPLIED TO LAW The only legitimate sources of law are those written rules, regulations, and principles that have been expressly enacted, adopted, or recognized by a governmental entity or political institution, including administrative, executive, legislative, and judicial bodies. Legal positivism is a theory of law that claims that laws are a matter of convention. To simplify, there is no ideal or natural law on which conventional laws are based. Laws are simply "posited" by lawmakers, and those are the laws people should obey. Laws are created and enforced by the legislative body of the government or other authority, as opposed to laws that are based on natural rights or moral principles. Legal positivism is characterized by two theses: 1. The existence and content of law depends entirely on social facts (e.g., facts about human behavior and intentions), and 2. There is no necessary connection between law and morality—more precisely, the existence and content of a law do not depend on its merits or demerits (e.g., whether or not it lives up to the ideals of justice, democracy, or morality). The basic question to be asked are: 1. “What is law?” 2. Is it written? 3. Where does it come from? “The Command Theory” “Dura lex, sed lex” - The law is harsh, but that is the law. “Whatever pleases the prince has the force of law” In applying it to the law, what the law “posits” by the authority given to the State or by socially accepted rules is known as “the command theory,” positivism highlights obedience of the law with the principle “dura lex, sed lex” and the connotation that whatever pleases the prince has the force of law. English political thinkers John Austin and Thomas Hobbes articulated the command theory of law, which stood for the proposition that the only legal authorities that courts should recognize are the commands of the sovereign, because 33 only the sovereign is entrusted with the power to enforce its commands with military and police force. Legalism Thomas Hobbes - “laws cannot be unjust because these are promulgated by one authorized with sovereign power.” According to him, for the principle of just and unjust to take place, there must be some coercive power to compel men to the performance of their covenants. Hobbes thought that laws cannot be unjust because these are promulgated by one authorized entity with the sovereign power. While positivism is “the rule of law,” — legalism — is “rule by the law,” where there is no need for precedents, rules of procedure, or processes that the lawmaker himself must abide by. What he stressed is that “to the care of the sovereign belongs the making of good laws.” Furthermore, he concludes that “all that is done by such power is warranted and owned by every one of the people, and that which every man will have so, no man can say is unjust.” John Austin held that the relationship between law and morality is only accidental and that the law is its own criterion. Law ushers its own majesty and command without need for moral reference. This developed a legal system wherein, unqualified allegiance is paid as a mark of an independent state system. As a separate science, it will be enough to cite the law. The existence of law is one thing; its merit or demerit is another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different enquiry. A law, which actually exists, is a law, though we happen to dislike it, or though it varies from the text, by which we regulate our approbation and disapprobation. Austin defined law by saying that it is the “command of the sovereign”. He expounds on this further by identifying the elements of the definition and distinguishing law from other concepts that are similar: in his theory, “Commands” involve an expressed wish that something be done, and “an evil” to be imposed if that wish is not complied with. Rules are general commands, as contrasted with specific or individual commands. The “sovereign” is defined as a person who receives habitual obedience from the bulk of the population, but who does not habitually obey any other person or institution. Austin thought that all independent political societies, by their nature, have a sovereign. 34 The existence of a legal system in a society can be inferred from the different structures of governance present, and not on the extent to which it satisfies ideals of justice, democracy, or rule of law. The laws which are in force in a certain system depend on what kind of social standards its officials recognize as authoritative. They may be legislative enactments, judicial decisions, or social customs. Based on Austin, the fact that a policy is just, wise, efficient, or prudent is never a sufficient reason for thinking it is actually the law; and the fact that it is unjust, unwise, inefficient or imprudent is never a sufficient reason for doubting it. The Pedigree Thesis - asserts that legal enforceability and legitimacy is due to certain social facts. Austin says that a command backed by sanction is all that law is limited to. Any external analysis of law is speculative and lies outside the domain of ‘Real Law’. The primary function of the state is to use force to impose sanctions. But modern democracies have governments that serve the people and are elected by them to ensure their safety and prosperity, not use force on them. The force used by the state is not the power of the state but the willingness of the people to obey the same. Austin’s ideas are not applicable to International law because it has no Sovereign. Modern democracies are found in a constitution, in which rests the source of all the political powers of the state. Therefore, the true Sovereign in a democracy are the people, whose rights the constitution upholds. Jeremy Bentham called the natural law “nonsense upon stilts” and laid down the groundwork of Positivist legal philosophy with the Sovereign at its helm. Jeremy Bentham called the natural law as “nonsense upon stilts,” or that it is nonsense for claiming rights not prescribed in the laws of the state, and distinguished the “expositors” of the law (those who explain the law for what it really is) from the “censors” (those who criticize the law in relation to non-legal notions). Law was not meant to be discussed, criticized or debated but rather explained and obeyed. Hans Kelsen - Pure Positive Law is characterized as a “pure” theory of law because it aims to focus on law alone. It only describes the law and it also attempts to eliminate or set aside anything that is not law. 35 The pure positive law theory also distinguishes the “is-statement” from the “ought-statement.” The “is-statement” that something is, or something is not done is expressive of a simple reason for action. As for the “ought-statement” that something should be, or something should be done, or something should not be done is expressive of a higher kind of reason for action. The law according to Kelsen is a system of norms. The pure law theory takes into consideration only the norms created by the acts of human beings, not norms which come from other superhuman authorities. For illustration purposes, here is an example: Why should the people pay taxes on time? As stated above, there are two ways or reasons for complying with the legal norm of paying taxes, specifically the “is-statement” and the “ought-statement.” The response of the person that he pays his taxes on time because the legal norm commands him to do it is an is-statement. Another way of answering or reasoning is that the people should pay their taxes on time because the legal norm should be obeyed. In this example, there is a higher justification for action, which is to discharge an obligation without any thought of getting away from it which is the “ought-statement.” The Hart of the Law - Separation Thesis Herbert Lionel Adolphous Hart, separation thesis is the essence of legal positivism. The main point or essence of this is that the law and morality are conceptually distinct. In order to know what your legal rights are, you need to look at what laws your society has. In order to know what your moral rights are, you need to figure out what is the true morality. It is possible for a person to have legal rights that the true morality says he should not have, and the society might also deny a person’s legal rights that the true morality dictates one must have. In inclusive positivism or also known as incorporationism or soft positivism, it is possible for a society’s rule of recognition to incorporate moral constraints on the content of law. Contrary to this is the exclusive positivism or also called as the hard positivism, in which it denies that a legal system can incorporate moral constraints on legal validity. 36 The rule of recognition, say, via a Constitution, is its own measure. It is like a standard meter, which provides the ways for supplying legal validity. The law is valid as long as it satisfies the criterion of being characterized as law. The law is “open-textured,” or there is room for discretion only as the law says so. However, the positivist approach has been criticized for its tendency to legalism, formalism, and uncritical obedience to authority, which served dictatorial regimes and an example would be the Nazi regime, laws were passed to exterminate the Jews, and the Nazis would raise the defense that they were only following what was then valid official law. Ronald Dworkin - Discretion Thesis “The set of these valid legal rules is exhaustive of ‘the law’, so that if someone’s case is not clearly covered by such a rule then that case cannot be decided by ‘applying the law.’ It must be decided by some official, like a judge, ‘exercising his discretion,’ which means reaching beyond the law for some other sort of standard to guide him in manufacturing a fresh legal rule or supplementing an old one (Dworkin 1977, p. 17).” This thesis asserts that in the practise of law, there will inevitably arise a situation in which an issue would lie outside the established principles of law and there would be no law to govern the said issue. In this case, the discretion thesis asserts that it is up to the judges, the jurists and the legislators to form a new rule to decide on said problem, which would involve leaving the domain of law and exercising their discretion of commanding law. The discretion thesis is not a central tenet of Legal Positivism but is still considered in consonance with it. Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., wrote that the “prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law”. Holmes made a description of what positive law is in the realm of the courts. In making this statement, Holmes was suggesting that the meaning of any written law is determined by the individual judges interpreting them, and until a judge has weighed in on a legal issue, the law is ultimately more than an exercise in trying to guess the way a judge will rule in a case. The Law and the State = The Supreme Political Superior 37 The state is perceived as the creator and enforcer of the law who is therefore vested with the power to “inflict an evil or pain in case its desire is disregarded. Therefore, the law is the expression of the will of the state laying down the rules of action upheld by force. But this does not mean that the state can do no wrong in the expression and enforcement of its will, however, even if a wrong is done by the state, no right can be claimed against it. From the concept of law of the positivists, the supreme political superior is the state, as a collective legal association under the rule of the majority. The legal doctrine of non-suability was derived from this concept. But it must be remembered that the exercise of the will of the supreme political superior by the government is not absolute. When there is a deliberate and unrelenting disregard of the will of the supreme political superior in the exercise of governmental powers, the majority members of the society may blunt, curb, or even deny by response the adverse governmental challenges. Positivism = “Conventionalism” Law is purely a product of human will, not of some natural law or divine will. Laws are made out of explicit or implicit agreements, treaties, or conventions in society. Positivism is also referred to as “conventionalism.” Positivists state that the law is purely a product of human will, not of some natural law or divine will. Laws are made out of explicit or implicit agreements, treaties, or conventions in society, not due to some extra-legal reality like natural rights, divine providence, etc. although the agreement may mention these concepts. There is no underlying substance, principle, or content that the law must conform to. It need only be procedurally correct to be valid. Jurists who classified principles of justice as law did so because the principles were widely embraced, or because local customs authorized these jurists to make new law. When the legality of a rule or principle is based on precedent, prior judicial recognition, or law-making authority, judges appreciate the importance of making these explanatory connections explicit and are adept at doing so. Analytic jurisprudence “Lex lata” - law is simply “what it is” 38 Positivism is “analytic jurisprudence” that studies and recognizes law simply for “what it is” (lex lata). No ifs or buts or referents to judge the law other than the law itself. For positivists, all the other approaches to law (natural law, sociological, pragmatic) are wrong for confusing “what ought” with “what is,” which positivists describe as the “overlap thesis” or “is- ought fallacy.” Until nullified or amended, one cannot dismiss the law based on what it should be according to some non-legal standards — for being immoral, inefficient, irrational, imprudent, or impractical. Thus, when lawyers make or unmake legal arguments, they can only cite the law, and citing the Bible or non-legal authorities will not gain merit. MAIN CRITICISM OF POSITIVISM The most influential criticisms of legal positivism all flow from the suspicion that it fails to give morality its due. The law has important functions in creating harmony and peace in our lives, advancing the common good, in securing human rights, or to govern with integrity and yet it has no relevance with our morals. However, the explanation to this is that Judges who invoked the ‘laws of justice’ were aware that moral principles aren’t really law. Their pretense was aimed at promoting justice while keeping up the façade of strict obedience to law. Since such talk among jurists is insincere, it is entirely compatible with the true grounds of legality being social. But judges, while deciding cases, cannot apply rules without seeking guidance from certain legal principles which are conventionally considered extralegal by positivists. For Dorkin, the actual cases were too ambiguous and full of detail which cannot be adequately captured in rules. To decide on a matter judiciously, one needs guidance from eternal principles which help the judges decide. Dorkin’s viewpoint was met with much opposition from the positivists, who thought that law could not consist of anything apart from objective, definite rules and principles were primarily subjective and metaphysical in nature, which was contrary to their assertion that law is an absolute science. REFLECTING ON THE LEGACY AND RELEVANCE OF POSITIVISM IN TODAY'S WORLD In the legal positivists point of view, the body of legal rules should exist without conscious regard for the norms of morality, although the latter’s influence is not completely denied. There are legal rules that do not measure up to moral law but do not cease to be legal rules. 39 Positivism laid out the basic notions which are still prevalent in modern legal systems. Even in modern democracies, we see the flow of law emanating from political superiors to the people, we also see the importance of statutes, rules and regulations along with the discretion of jurists. The Separability thesis, however, is more or less proved to be wrong. Our struggles throughout history have proven that law needs to have an ethical direction for it to remain just, fair and not devolve into tyranny. Ethical concerns are now central to any promulgation, rule or legislation. Laws everywhere are becoming less arbitrary, more inclined towards ensuring freedom and liberty. The focus of legal institutions is shifting from being a system of commands and sanctions to a system which aims to ensure prosperity in the people it governs. It can be concluded that Legal Positivism provides a unique perspective towards understanding our legal systems, and while it is not without its flaws, it still holds a lot of academic importance. Positivism in Essence ● Law is a command by a human sovereign. ● Law is separate from morality and has no identifiable ethical concerns. ● Law should be studied positively i.e. “What is law?” and not normatively i.e. “What should the law be?” ● Study of Legal concepts is separate from historical or sociological analysis. ● Legal system is self-sufficient, to make decisions, it does not need to have social concerns. ● Precedence of facts over moral judgements. CONCLUSION Life itself has rules, and we call them law. We follow the law because it is the law. This is what the positivist school maintains. 40 IV. POSITIVISM Reported by: GAILAN, Roxan SANTOS, Kaye Abstract The two grand theories of judging – legal realism and legal formalism - have their differences set around the importance of legal rules. For formalists, judging is a rulebound activity. In its more extreme versions, a judge is seen as an operator of a giant syllogism machine. Legal realists, in contrast, argue that legal rules, at least formal legal rules, do not determine outcomes of cases. Legal realism has been misunderstood almost everywhere outside its birthplace – the United States. Continental legal theory, for one, views legal realism as practical, down-to-earth, hard-nosed school of thought which is opposed to the more “scientific” theories. Legal Realism, a movement that arose in 1920s and 1930s in the US, challenged the prevailing view that judges are rational decision-makers, who apply only legal rules found in law books to the facts of the case. Realists were a sundry group: there were more differences between some realists then between some realists and formalists. Overall, however, realists asserted that often judges make up their mind about the outcome even before they turn to legal rules; often they will use policy principles and make new law; some realists asserted that judge’s personality has more impact than legal rules. After making a decision, judges will justify it with formal legal rules. I. Legal Realism: Birth and Development A. Introduction to Realism Legal realism was arguably the most important and controversial theory of judging in the history. And in general as well, there were few intellectual developments in law that have been as influential, controversial, and misunderstood. Its influence went far beyond as a theory of adjudication. As one legal theorist notes, even contemporary legal positivism owes much of its renewal to legal realism. Realism is a diverse school of thought and any attempts to homogenize it will distort more than simplify. When it comes to judicial decision-making, realists had two general theses. First, judges have a preferred outcome of a case even before they turn to legal rules; that preferred outcome is usually based on some non-legal grounds – conceptions of justice, attributes of litigating parties (government, poor plaintiff, racial group, etc),ideology, public policy preferences, judge’s personality, etc. Second, judges usually will be able to find a justification in legal rules for their 42 preferred outcome. This is possible because the legal system is complex and often contradictory. Of course, occasionally a judge will come across a preferred outcome that just “won’t write”, but these are rare. Normally, however, judges will find some cases, statutes, maxims, canons, authorities, principles, etc, that will justify their preferred outcome. II. Holmes, Cardozo, and other Predecessors of the Movement A. Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. The birth of legal realism is largely credited to the jurist who probably would not consider himself a realist – Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. Holmes famously wrote that “the life of law has not been logic; it has been experience that changes in law (at least judge-made law) were not due to logic or pre-existing law; instead, policy preferences or personal experiences of judges mattered more. Holmes also famously stated in his dissenting opinion that “general propositions do not decide concrete cases”. Many commentators consider this statement as his realist position that general rules of law will never decide actual cases. It seems, however, that this may have been an exaggeration as Holmes himself believed that specific legal propositions can determine how judges decide their cases. It is probably fair to say that Holmes’ views were not iconoclastic by the later standards. It might be also true that many of his ideas were voiced by a previous generation of jurists. However, his prominence as a scholar and the Justice of the US Supreme Court helped to spread his ideas in all legal circles. B. Benjamin Cardozo Like Holmes, Benjamin Cardozo was not only an outspoken legal commentator but also a prominent judge. Thus, his position probably gave his views additional credibility. Compared to later realists, Cardozo was far from a revolutionary freethinker. His main treatise published in 1921 - The Nature of the Judicial Process – shows that most of his views rather moderate. He observed that in most cases, there are clear legal principles, which dictate the outcome. Yet, often a clear legal answer does not exist; in such cases, Cardozo thought, the judge should promote social ends; and here, Cardozo admitted, a judge may be tempted to substitute his view for that of the community. Grant Gilmore observed that “Cardozo’s hesitant confession that judges were, on rare occasions, more than simple automata, that they made law instead of merely declaring it, was widely regarded as a legal version of hard core pornography. Gilm ore probably 43 exaggerated Cardozo’s impact, but we should not make the opposite mistake of underrating Cardozo’s impact. C. Other Predecessors In addition to Holmes and Cardozo, there were a number of smaller contributions to the emerging legal realism. Theodore Schroeder, for example, was one of the first to analyze the psychology of judicial decision-making. He noted that “judicial opinion necessarily is the justification of the personal impulses of the judge” and that “hat the character of these impulses is determined by the judge’s life-long series of previous experiences, with their resultant integration of emotional tones”. While his observations would not impress contemporary psychologists, at that time this was a novel outlook on judicial decision-making. Max Radin, already in 1925, argued that judges do not process facts and legal rules logically or rationally. Essentially, he argued that judges respond to the clusters of fact situations (the so-called situation type of judging) - judges make instant decisions once a “generalized situation of this sort is in the judge’s mind and is immediately called up” He further remarked that judge’s mind works like that in great many situations and could hardly work otherwise. In his subsequent writings, Radin noted that how judges classify events depends on “their training, their prejudices, their conscious or unconscious interests, their philosophy, their aesthetic learnings, or even by the chance circumstances surrounding the particular learning. ”Of course contemporary scholars of judgment and decision-making would depart from Radin’s model; and yet, his observations came very close to what contemporary research psychologists know about intuitive judgment and heuristic processing. III. Birth of the Movement: Hutcheson and Frank A. Hutcheson In 1929, Joseph Hutcheson, a federal judge, published a seminal article in which he explained his own judging model. As other realists, he loathed formalistic model where a judge determines the relevant facts and then consults lawbooks (statutes or cases) to determine the outcome. Hutcheson argued that judges first make up their mind about the outcome and only then turn to law books to look for justification of their decision. In essence, judges use “hunches” or intuitive decisionmaking first, and only then look for justifications in the statutes or caselaw. Although Hutcheson’s contributions to the field were scanty, the view of judicial44 decision making as an intuitive process of hunches became a signature of judicial decision-making in the realistic tradition. B. Jerome Frank One year after Hutcheson’s article appeared, Jerome Frank published his “Law and the Modern Mind”. If there ever was a radical version of legal realism, then Jerome Frank was it. Like other realists, Frank doubted judges’ ability to make decisions based on general categories or general rules. Like many other eminent realists, Frank himself was an eminent federal judge. Frank thought that troubled psychological development is responsible for legal formalism. According to Frank, the judge’s preferred outcome precedes the inquiry into legal rules: “Judicial judgments, like other judgments, doubtless, in most cases are worked out backward from conclusion tentatively reached”. Frank was also one of few realists who was preoccupied not only with “legal rules realism”, but also with “fact finding realism” – a judge will usually accept only that evidence which will support his or her preferred outcome: “A judge, eager to give a decision which will square with his sense of what is fair, but unwilling to break with the traditional rules, will often view the evidence in such a way that the facts’ reported by him, combined with those traditional rules, will justify the result which he announces” Frank was also the only major realist who thought that judge’s personality plays a more important role than legal rules. Legal rules, for Frank, were in general not important. Furthermore, he considered that rational element in law is an illusion. Frank argued that judicial outcomes depend on many factors, most of which can be extra-legal: judge’s personality, political preferences, mood, racial views, etc. On the other hand, Frank pointed out that a judge, after arriving at the conclusion, can consult with the general rules and principles to see if it is acceptable. So in a sense, Frank did not say that legal rules do not matter; instead, his point was that they were not leading to the decision, but they could provide guidance to a conscientious judge as a check-up. Frank and later realists have been ridiculed by saying that how a judge decides a case depends on what “the judge had for breakfast.”(Frank himself, apparently, never said such thing Of course, this ridicule sets up realists for a straw man fallacy. Frank and other realists never maintained that it all comes down to what “the judge had for breakfast”. Yet, he wouldn’t deny that it might influence the decision. Although later criticized for his attachment to psychoanalytic school (and he also argued that judging ability would be greatly enhanced if judges underwent extensive psychological treatment), his views were well-known and to some extent influential. 45 IV. Birth of the Movement: Pound & Llewellyn A. Roscoe Pound If Hutcheson and Frank presented more radical views of judging, Pound and Llewellyn could be considered centrists. Roscoe Pound, like Holmes, scorned the strict reliance on logic, legal rules, and scientific law which is characterized by certainty and reason. He thought that such notions of law are responsible for fixed conceptions where premises become stiff. Like Holmes, he argued that courts should develop law by relying on public policy preferences. Already in his notable 1908 article, he assaulted the notion of “mechanical jurisprudence” (and it was he who coined that term in the same article) In his address to the American Bar Association in 1906, Pound disdained mechanical application of legal rules: “The most important and most constant cause of dissatisfaction with all law at all times it be found in the necessarily mechanical operation of legal rules.” So for Pound, in addition to legal rules, policy reasons and techniques for deriving doctrines play equally important role. B. Karl Llewellyn Karl Llewellyn was arguably the most influential realist. He also presented the version of legal realism that perhaps could lay claim for an established theory of law and judging. Like other realists, Llewellyn scoffed at the idea that judging is a rulebound activity, where a judge proceeds downward from legal rules to the outcome of the case: “[With a decision already made, the judge has sifted through these ‘facts’ again, and picked a few which he puts forward as essential - and whose legal bearing he then proceeds to expound”. For Llewellyn, formal rules – “the paper rules” or “pretty playthings” - have little effect on what judges actually do. Llewellyn, however, argued that judges do use some rules in their decision-making, only these rules are largely non-formal rules. These are the rules that judges would not find in a law book. Such general rules could be policy preferences like “maximize efficiency”, “let win the poorer party in a civil litigation” or “uphold any outcome which fosters free market competition”. In addition to policy preferences, other factors determine the outcome: legal knowledge, legal indoctrination, approval of peers, the collaborative nature, institutional constraints. Unlike Frank, Llewellyn did not deny that there is a rational element in law. Llewellyn also disagreed with Frank that judge’s personality plays a crucial role in judging. Llewellyn’s one of the most famous contributions to the legal realism was to 46 demonstrate the ambivalence of legal rules. Llewellyn used a fencing metaphor: “thrust” and “parry” of dueling cannons - for every canon of interpretation that said one thing, there was a “dueling” canon that said just the opposite. For example, the canon of in pari materia says that statutes dealing with the same subject should be interpreted so as to be consistent with each other, but another canon provides that later statutes supersede earlier ones. One canon provides that extrinsic aids to interpretation, such as legislative history, are irrelevant when the language of the statute is clear on its face; another canon, however, says that even the plain language of a statute should not be applied literally if such an application would produce a result divergent from what the legislation intended. In his later years, Llewellyn seems to have adopted even more moderate position. In “The Common Law Tradition”, he noted that judges do follow accepted doctrinal techniques, provide a right legal answer, and achieve just results. They also want to earn approval of their legal audience. Moreover, he observed that institutional factors, like collegiality, also minimize individual inconsistencies. V. Novel Contributions of Legal Realists Some scholars argue that legal realism brought nothing new to the understanding of judicial decision-making. For example, some scholars noted that preceding legal generations made similar observations about judging even before realists came to the scene. But almost all major scientific discoveries or ideological movements were preceded by “observations” similar to the new theories. Likewise, it is true that preceding generations of lawyers made similar observations as the legal realists; however, observations are not enough. It even might be that the genius of the realists was not in the discovery of their doctrinal and philosophical outlooks, but in their crystal articulation. Whatever it is, it is easy now to underrate their contribution. One can only wonder then, if the movement brought nothing new, why the awareness of the legal community and general public was so much different than before. VI. Legal Realism in the Philippines Although legal realism movement started in the US and was eventually became popular in Europe, its principles were also seen in some of the jurisprudence or landmark cases decidbe by our Supreme Court in the Philippines. 47 A. Judicial Activism in Social Justice Case In some cases, Philippine courts, particularly the Supreme Court, have adopted a proactive role in protecting rights guaranteed under the Constitution, such as in social justice or human rights cases. This reflects legal realism, as the courts sometimes interpret the Constitution in ways that go beyond the literal wording of the law, considering the social realities and impacts of their rulings. For example, in cases related to agrarian reform or labor disputes, courts have sometimes made decisions that promote social justice over strict adherence to formal rules. For instance, the case of Association of Small Landowners v. Secretary of Agrarian Reform** (G.R. No. 78742, July 14, 1989) expanded the scope of land reform policies, showing that the court was willing to adapt the law to address real-world inequities. B. Flexible Interpretation of Rights The Constitution guarantees several fundamental rights, but how these rights are interpreted in specific cases often reflects a legal realist approach. Judges have the discretion to balance conflicting rights and interpret the law in a way that aligns with social or political needs. In Imbong v. Ochoa (G.R. No. 204819, April 8, 2014), which challenged the constitutionality of the Reproductive Health (RH) Law, the Supreme Court made a nuanced decision. It upheld the law’s constitutionality but struck down certain provisions that it deemed inconsistent with the freedom of religion and conscience. This illustrates how the Court balanced constitutional rights based on a pragmatic consideration of the social and moral context of the country. C. Constitutional Interpretation in Emergency Powers During times of national crisis or emergency, the courts often interpret the Constitution in a flexible manner, considering the prevailing political and social realities rather than applying a rigid reading of constitutional provisions. During President Ferdinand Marcos’ martial law regime, the judiciary often upheld the expansive powers of the president under the guise of national security. This shows that the courts were influenced by the political context, reflecting legal realism in their decision-making. Lateron, however, the post48 martial law era saw a shift, with courts becoming more protective of civil liberties, as seen in cases like Olaguer v. Military Commission No. 34 (G.R. No. L-54558, May 22, 1987). D. Intervention in Environmental Protection The application of environmental laws in the Philippines also highlights the influence of legal realism. Courts sometimes interpret constitutional provisions on environmental protection in a way that accounts for the country’s unique environmental challenges. In Oposa v. Factoran (G.R. No. 101083, July 30, 1993), the Supreme Court recognized the right to a balanced and healthful ecology under the Constitution as a basis for standing in court, even for future generations. The Court's decision reflected a forward-looking, socially conscious approach, illustrating how legal realism shapes constitutional interpretation. E. Influence of Public Opinion Legal realism suggests that judicial decisions can be influenced by public opinion or the societal context. In high-profile cases, such as those involving political figures or controversial issues, Philippine courts have occasionally been seen as taking into account the public's perception when interpreting the Constitution. In the case of Republic of the Philippines v. Sereno (G.R. No. 237428, May 11, 2018), where the Supreme Court removed Chief Justice Maria Lourdes Sereno through a quo warranto proceeding, there were widespread debates about the influence of politics and public opinion on the decision, as it deviated from the usual process of impeachment. These examples demonstrate that Philippine courts, influenced by legal realism, often consider more than just legal texts when interpreting the Constitution, taking into account the broader social, political, and moral context in their rulings. 49 Conclusions In conclusion, the theory of legal realism, regardless how diverse the legal realists are, had a twofold claim. First, legal rules, at least formal legal rules, do not determine outcomes of cases. Most realists agreed that legal rules play some role in judicial decision making, but all realists argued that other rules and factors play a much more important role. And a judge, influenced by other rules and other factors, will decide before consulting law books. In essence, judges act like attorneys who first determine their client’s position and then look for legal materials to support that position. Second, after deciding on other grounds than solely legal rules, judges will be able to justify the decision with formal rules because one can usually find competing legal grounds for almost any position. For example, if a judge experienced the same facts in a certain case, legal realism claims that this influences the judge to decide based on this experience. In the Philippines, the application of legal realism principles can be seen in cases previously enumerated which emphasize that the law can be uncertain, and decision may be based on its overall societal context. 50 V. MARXISM Reported by: VIZCAYNO, Dea OVERVIEW This module talks about Marxist idea and perception on law. It discusses Marx’s ideas of law which he mentioned in the book he co-authored with Fredrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto and in the essay “On the Jewish Question”. He talks about how the concept of law, state and human rights are influenced by the Bourgeoisie and how it is used against the Proletariat. There are three basic assumptions in the Marxist theories of law, first, that law is the product of economic forces; secondly, law is considered to be the tool of the ruling class to maintain its powers over the ruling classes; finally, that law will wither away in the future communist society. However, according to Engels, state in the future will disappear. The third assumption has been repudiated and a novel concept is evolved that of ‘socialist legality’. However, in different communist countries, either the first or the second of the words in ‘socialist legality’ has been stressed. KARL MARX Karl Heinrich Marx (1818-1883), born to Heinrich and Henrietta Marx, was a famous German economist, revolutionary and a social philosopher of the nineteenth century who propounded the theory of Marxism. Born in a wealthy middle class family, Marx studied at the University of Bonn and University of Berlin. He received his Doctorate degree from the University of Jena for his thesis ‘On the difference between the Natural Philosophy of Democritus and Epicurus’. After his studies, he started writing for a newspaper in Cologne where he began working on his theory of dialectical materialism. Later, when he moved to France, he met Friedrich Engels, a young German businessman. The two of them were the founding fathers of the theory of Classical Marxism. He then went to London and produced works of his own such as ‘The Class Struggle in France’ (1850), ‘The 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte’ (1852), and ‘Contributions to a critique of Political Economy’ (1859). He also published some short articles and essays like ‘The Introduction to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Law’ and ‘The Essays on The Jewish Question’. One of his most famous works was the book was called ‘Das Kapital’ which was published in three volumes in 1867, 1885 and 1894. INTRODUCTION “Law, morality, religion, are to [the proletariat] so many bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in ambush just as many bourgeois interests.” 52 Karl Marx provides a perspective about what the law means, which in order to appreciate, is important to place it within Marx’s overall socio-economic and political context.2 In the Marxist view of law, the bourgeoisie and the proletariat are the two classes fighting for power. Societies that allow and give freedom to the bourgeoisie to formulate laws and make moral decisions are unjust societies. In the Communist Manifesto, Marx explains that the law is simply a reflection of the desires of the Bourgeoisie class. He says to the Bourgeoisie that “[Y]our jurisprudence is but the will of your class made into a law for all, a will, whose essential character and direction are determined by the economic conditions of existence of your class”3. Marx criticizes the entire tradition of government under the rule of law as no more than a mere expression of the “bourgeois” aspirations. What is Marxism? The concept of Marxism first emerged in the mid-nineteenth century as a result of the hostile conditions created by the capitalistic society. Marxism is what is known as conflict theory because it states the conflict between people in the society. It is a combination of critiques, political goals and theories scattered around the theories of criticism of Karl Marx. It consists of myriad ideas: that capitalism embodies a system of class exploitation, socialism is a social order in which private property and exploitation and which can be achieved through revolution. Basic Assumptions of Marxist Legal Theory In the Marxist theory of law, there are three basic assumptions. The first one is that law is the product of economic forces. Marx said that the way you work will shape your law and other institutions. He believed in the ‘two level model’ in which ‘economy’ was the ‘base’ and law as well as other institutions were in the ‘superstructure’. Marx was of the opinion that the most important sphere of relations to consider was the relations of economic production. However, Engels admitted that the various components of the superstructure, including the institution of the law and other norms, exercise a reciprocal effect upon the economic basis and may, within certain limits, modify it4. Thus, if we understand the way in which societies produced and reproduced the basic goods and services which formed their wealth, then we could understand much of the other things going on in those societies. It would be easier to explain their characteristic religious, political, moral, artistic, and legal principles. His main argument was that in a capitalist economy, the working classes (or proletarian) were exploited by the capitalist class (or the bourgeois). 53 The second important doctrine is the doctrine of the class character of law. According to Marx and Engels, law is considered to be the tool of the ruling class to maintain its powers over the ruling classes. Law is characterized as an expression of class will and it is the law and the state, and the means of production which determine the character of the various classes in a society. The third doctrine is what is known as the ‘withering away’ of law in the future communist society. There is some controversy about this doctrine. Engels anticipated that the society of the future would substitute (for the government) the administration of things and that state in such a society would wither away5. The ‘withering away’ phenomenon was explained by Eugene Pashukanis6. He argued that law is a social regulator in a market economy in which independent private producers and owners of commodities exchange their produce by means of contracts and transactions. He believed that law was out of place in a socialist society which is characterized by unity of social purpose. He maintained that legal rules for settling disputes between individuals and groups will not be needed in a socialist society. Consequently, according to this view, when classes disappear after the revolution, there is no need for a legal apparatus to continue and encourage class rule. So, poverty and exploitation, which are see as the root causes of a crime, will vanish within the new classless society and people will develop into ‘group creatures’ having no need for codes and rules so that the need for institutionalized law vanishes. 54 MARXIST LEGAL THEORY Marx’s ideas about law were expressed mainly in the Communist Manifesto and On the Jewish Question which he published in collaboration with his friend Friedrich Engels in 1848. In Marxist thought, material relations of production (economy) constitute the base, which determines the superstructure such as politics, religion, education, culture and law. Capitalism is inconsistent with our species-being, because it alienates us from labor, our production and from each other. The class conflict to which this leads will eventually lead to the demise of capitalism. To avoid this, capitalist relations of production need to be regulated, and this is the main task of the superstructure. One way of viewing the relationship between the economic base and law (as an element of superstructure) is instrumentalist. In simple words, according to this view, the law means the oppression and domination of the proletariat by the ruling class (the bourgeoisie). The latter has stronghold on the State and its law and uses it to promote its interests. It is on the basis of this that, according to Marx, law is present in all phases of class domination prior to the proletariat revolution but not to carry equal emphasis in all stages of development. Thus law is perceived as having a relatively minor role in the phase of feudal domination but started to make its role more prominent during the bourgeoisie phase, because of its least close relationship with institutions of private property. As Fredrich Engels said: “…law is sacred to the bourgeoisies, for it… enacted …for his benefit… because the English bourgeoisies finds himself reproduced in his law… the policeman’s truncheon… has for him a… soothing power. But… the working man knows… that the law is a rod which the bourgeoisie has prepared for him; and when he is not compelled to do so he never appeals to the law.” Marx and Engels themselves devoted relatively little attention to law. Marx concentrated on discrediting the illusion that law is a human intervention, or, as he put it, matter of “mere will”. Jurists tell us, he says, that individuals can choose to enter into relations with others through making contracts and that the content of these relations rest purely on the individual free will of the contracting parties”. But in fact, neither the general nor the private will can determine the existence of property, and legal titles as such are meaningless since the legal owner who cannot command the capital to cultivate his land really “owns nothing as a landed 55 proprietor”. The true nature of law can be grasped only by recognizing its link with the state. Because the ruling class declares itself by setting up institutions that constitute the state, it is supposed that law rests on will, “indeed on the will divorced from its real basis – on free will”. But in reality the law, like all political institutions, is an instrument through which the ruling class exercises its power to satisfy its selfish interests. What the bourgeoisie describe as the freedom to make legal arrangements is not only the reflections of the forms of relations in production at any particular time, nor does the belief that law presupposes equality, a belief promoted by the ruling class to correlate with any reality because law arises from the dominance of one class over the others. Although law makes it possible for the “personal rule” of the dominant class, it is nothing but the expression of the will, that is to say, the common interests of the ruling class. Example: When entering into an employment contract, the workers and the industrialist are considered equal and their agreement is validated by precisely those normative aspects imputed to them. But this blatantly disregards the real discrepancies in wealth and bargaining power between the parties, the crippling inequalities, which deprive workers of choice and those real forces, which in fact, though not in law, make them enter into these contracts in order to secure a livelihood. One Marxist named Louis Althusser had said that there are two courses by which the decision class can push its power over different classes: 1. By the utilization of power or force, (for example, police and armed force) .He called these" Repressive State Apparatuses". 2. By the utilization of belief system, ideology and socialization, (for example, broad communications, open promulgation, social specialists, and so forth.) He called these "Ideological State Apparatuses". Law forms a part of the Repressive State Apparatuses. The More dominant class, i.e., the bourgeoisie class makes use of the system of law to exert their dominance over the proletariat. 56 MARXIST VIEW OF LAW, STATE, AND POLITICS The doctrine of state and law is part of a broader whole, namely, the complex of sciences which studies human society which in turn is itself determined by the history of class struggle. Marxist theories of the State go together with the theory of historical materialism propounded by Marx and Engels. One view of the state and law, which is predominant in Marx's writings, is that they are a notion of the economic interests of the bourgeoisie class. The state is thus viewed as an 'executive committee to manage the affairs of the bourgeoisie. The state acts as its oppressive agent in the civil society, suppressing the interests of proletarian and favoring capitalism. The personnel of the state owe their allegiance to only one particular class - the bourgeoisie. Lawyers would be viewed as waged servants of this class. Law is thus, part of this oppressive state mechanism and concentrate the ideological bewilderment of bourgeois intellectualism. The bourgeois class dominates political power through its domination of economic ability. The bourgeois state and legal system are based on class phenomena. According to Marx, class refers to large social groups which are linked together in certain social relations within a mode of production. Each class receives differential rewards, power, and status. Relations between classes tend to be conflictual. Within the instrumental perspective, the state and legal system are seen to focus on the interests of the dominant class. The state is not a representation of any collective good or impartiality. It is, rather, important to certain specific economic interests in society. Class interests are seen to head the state structure in the interests of that class - the bourgeoisie in capitalist society. The history of states is therefore incorporated under class interest. The above view reflects woefully on a number of issues. First, there does not appear to be any difference between a democratic rule-of-law constitutional state (Rechtsstaat) and an unconstitutional, undemocratic despotism. Both are simply exploitative class-based entities. The former state simply shields its basic exploitative character more successfully, particularly under guises like the 'rule of law'. Secondly, the 'general' rule-of-law principle and 'particular' property, contract or criminal laws, are simply there to buttress the property owners of capitalism. The rule of law is a typical example of legal fetishism, namely, giving law a false autonomy from the economic and class base of society. 57 Thirdly, Marx suggests that the so-called equal rights of liberal states have grossly unequal effects. The rights of human beings are in reality the rights of bourgeois men in civil society. They protect individual capitalists in their exploitative practices and they protect the unequal economic results of such practices. Rights are associated with individuals who 'own' them in order to protect private interests. Rights thus shield the basic inequalities and exploitative practices of bourgeois culture. Bourgeois culture ignores material inequalities and slavishly adheres to formal legal, moral or political equality of rights (which favor the Bourgeoisie) Marx found this whole scenario profoundly objectionable. From the same perspective, equally, the justice that we observe in liberal societies is just another aspect of the ideology of capitalism. It focuses minimally on how goods might be distributed (if it gets as far as distributive justice) and ignores the massive inequalities implicit in the production process itself. In other words, it shuts the stable door after the capitalist horse has bolted. Justice is not a virtue for communists. Marx thus quite explicitly takes an anti-justice and anti-rights stance. With genuine communism, there would be no classes, no coercion, no conflict, and no private ownership; in consequence, there would be no need for justice or right claims. If there is abundance and communal ownership, then there is no reason for principles of allocation or any allocating or adjudication mechanisms. In sum, Marx objects to the whole notion of the “juridical legal state” as a complex sham. As law is integral to the idea of the state in Marx, so the anti-statist stance of communism implies the abolition of law.13 The stricter class view of the state and law also suggests that if there were no class there would, in turn, be no law and no state. Class conflict is the prerequisite of the state. This view was later crystallized in Lenin's work, The State and Revolution. This idea, in turn, gives rise to the idea (initiated by Engels and carried on by Lenin, although many would contend it was also present in Marx) that the state and legal order will 'wither away'. In this sense a communist society would be lawless and stateless (in a strictly descriptive sense). Thus, from the standpoint of a strict materialism, the state is not a major player. The end result of this looks very much like communist anarchism, although Marx himself argued fiercely against such a conclusion and showed only vitriolic contempt for anarchists like Proudhon and Bakunin. However, Marx never resolved this issue of the relation between communism and mainstream anarchism. MARX’S BELIEFS • All of history was a “history of class struggles” • Oppressors vs. oppressed is a constant throughout history 58 • • • • • • • • • Oppressors own means to production (land, raw materials and money) Controlled government and society Oppressed- dependent on the owners of the means of production “Society as a whole is more and more splitting up into two great hostile camps, into tow great classes directly facing each other: Bourgeoisie and Proletariat”. Bourgeoisie- the middle/upper class- also known as the oppressors Proletariat-working class –also known as the oppressed. Struggle between proletariat and Bourgeoisie will eventually lead to a revolution. Proletariat would overthrow bourgeoisie Abolish economic differences that create separate social classes End up with a classless society MARXISM AND HUMAN RIGHTS Marx’s writings from the “Jewish Question” onward are wholly dismissive of all claims made to the lasting validity of unremovable human rights “bourgeoisie freedom”. The idea of the individual’s rights, Marx explains, implies a society in which the interests of each person is naturally and inevitably opposed to the interests of others, a society incurably torn asunder by the clash of private aspirations. The dominant motivations in this society are bound to be egoistic – not as a result of the corruption of human nature – but because of the character of the economic system, which is inevitably laden by conflict. All rights and liberties in bourgeois society simply assert and codify the simple fact the each individual’s aspirations and interests inevitably conflict with, and are limited by the interests and aspirations of others. Since the civil society is a place of all-pervasive and incessant war, where no real community is possible, the state steps in to provide an illusory unity, to set limits to the conflicts by imposing restrictions on hostilities. These restrictions appear in the form of civil liberties, which necessarily take on a purely negative character. Ideological legitimacy is given to the system by various social contract theories. ‘Equal rights’ says Marx, we indeed have here; but it is still a ‘bourgeois’s right’ which, like every right, presupposes inequality. Every right is an application of a uniform standard to different people who in fact are not identical, are not equal to one another; and therefore ‘equal right’ is really a violation of equality and injustice. Indeed every person, having performed as much social labor as another, receives an 59 equal share of the social product […]People, however, are not equal; one is strong, another is weak; one is married, another is not; one has more children, another has fewer, and so on. SUMMARY 1. Marxism is what is known as conflict theory because it states the conflict between people in the society. It is a combination of critiques, political goals and theories scattered around the theories of criticism of Karl Marx. 2. Karl Marx provides a perspective about what the law means, which in order to appreciate, is important to place it within Marx’s overall socio-economic and political context. 3. In the Marxist view, the bourgeoisie and the proletariat are the two classes fighting for power. Societies that allow and give freedom to the bourgeoisie to formulate laws and make moral decisions are unjust societies. 4. Marx explains that law, along with the whole state apparatus exists only for the sake of private property. 5. Law will wither away in the future communist society which is characterized by unity of social purpose. Legal rules for settling disputes between individuals and groups will not be needed in a socialist society. 6. Within the instrumental perspective, the state and legal system are seen to focus on the interests of the dominant class. The state is not a representation of any collective good or impartiality. 7. For Marx, equally, the justice that we observe in liberal societies is just another aspect of the ideology of capitalism. It focuses minimally on how goods might be distributed and ignores the massive inequalities implicit in the production process itself. 8. Marx defined the state and all its laws as mere instruments of class oppression, which have to disappear when the final stage of human evolution were finally accomplished. CONCLUSION To sum up, we can safely argue that the Marxian view of law is influenced by his over-all theory of state and social change. Marx regards law as a part of the superstructure. Since state is an instrument of class rule, law is made to serve the interest of ruling classes and thus an arena of class struggle. The claim made in excessive optimism that laws are made in the general interest of the public, according to Marx, is only an ideological smokescreen to ensure its obedience by all. 60 VI. FEMINISM Reported by: NAGUIT, Jocelyn Mutya VALES, April Angel FEMINISM – A Shift from Inequality to Equality “Feminism is not about having power over men, but power over ourselves.” “I raise up my voice not so that I can shout, but so that those without a voice can be heard” EARLY FEMINISM In his classic Republic, Plato advocated that women possess “natural capacities” equal to men for governing and defending ancient Greece. Not everyone agreed with Plato; when the women of ancient Rome staged a massive protest over the Oppian Law, which restricted women’s access to gold and other goods, Roman consul Marcus Porcius Cato argued, “As soon as they begin to be your equals, they will have become your superiors!” Plato radically promoted the idea that in an ideal society, all worthy individuals would receive training and an education, regardless of sex. While Plato believed women to be physically weaker than men, he establishes in Laws that women would inevitably become more equal to men if they received appropriate training. So even in ancient time, women rights are not recognized and are set aside. As for the second wave of feminism, it began as a liberation movement. The idea was that women are entitled to be free and equal citizens—as free as men to participate in their societies, to pursue their ambitions and determine their own lives. A starting place for achieving equal citizenship was political equality. Right to Vote These are the other rights we, women gained because of Feminism. Increased educational opportunities, Protections against workplace discrimination, The right to make personal decisions about pregnancy, Access to contraception and legal abortions, Protection from sexual assault, sexual harassment, and domestic violence, The right to earn an equal wage, Right to enter legal contracts, women cannot own property. 62 Feminist Philosophy of Law Feminist philosophy of law which identifies the pervasive influence of patriarchy and masculinist norms on legal structures and demonstrates their effects on the material conditions of women and girls and those who may not conform to cisgender norms. In philosophy of law, as in feminist theory more generally, methods, presumptions, and approaches vary considerably. Radical, socialist and Marxist, postcolonial, transnational, relational, cultural, postmodern, dominance, difference, pragmatist, liberal, and neoliberal approaches to feminism are all represented in and provide differing contributions to feminist legal philosophy. Feminist Legal Theory Feminist legal theory is the manifestation of efforts to understand and propose remedies for the subordination of women, particularly in relation to the ways it is rationalized and naturalized in the legal system. It approaches law as a site of struggle for political transformation and exposes how legal doctrines, institutions, and culture perpetuate gender hierarchy. Feminism jurisprudence or feminist legal theory claims that law should be equal for all, without any social prejudice or male domination. It is understood as “a body of legal scholarship dedicated to understanding issues of relevance to the law’s treatment of gender and sexuality”. Feminist legal theory aims to: • Understand how the legal system rationalizes and naturalizes the subordination of women; • Expose how legal institutions, culture, and doctrines perpetuate gender hierarchy; • Identify the effects of patriarchy and masculinist norms on the material conditions of women and girls; • Develop reforms to correct gender injustice, exploitation, or restriction; • Analyze and redress more traditional legal theory and practice; and • Identify gendered components and implications of seemingly “neutral” laws and practices 63 Feminist legal theory is a critical theory that seeks to understand and address the subordination of women in the legal system. It does this by: a. Identifying bias - Feminist legal theory uses methodologies like genealogical analysis, conceptual analysis, and normative critique to identify bias in the legal system. b. Challenging assumptions - Feminist legal theory questions assumptions about the law, such as the idea that law is objective and impartial. c. Creating new doctrines - Feminist legal scholars use women’s experiences and perspectives to create new doctrines, methods, and proposals for reform. d. Exposing gender hierarchy - Feminist legal theory exposes how legal doctrines, institutions, and culture perpetuate gender hierarchy. Feminist legal theory has grown alongside the increase of women in lawyering, law-making, and judging professions. The work of feminist legal scholars and activists has influenced each other, but laws male bias remains pervasive. MODERN FEMINISM What is modern feminism defined by? Feminism is a set of values aimed at dismantling gender inequality and the structures that uphold it. Today, Gender-based violence, harassment, and discrimination are more widely recognized, thanks to feminism. Modern feminism emphasizes the need for recognizing the many experiences that women have, pushing for legislative reforms, and helping survivors. We can create a society that is more just and equitable for people of all genders by waging ongoing battles for equality on all fronts and adopting an inclusive mindset. Feminism is still vital to establishing a more promising future. Distinctions are often made among various strands of contemporary feminist legal theories. We have liberal feminists, radical feminists, postmodern feminists, and cultural feminists. Liberal feminists searching for ‘equality before the law,’ such as employment and politics. Such was met with criticism as it seeks to work within the system built by men without necessarily challenging such a system. The second wave comprised Radical feminists and Marxist/ socialist feminists who focused on the ‘societal structure which forms the foundation of the 64 law.’ This wave unmasked the masculinity of the law, legal systems, and society, in general, which resulted in female subordination. The third wave consists of postmodern feminists who raised that laws are as complicated as societies. To these theorists, while the law is gendered, the law responds to differing problems in different and even inconsistent ways. PHILIPPINES IN VIEW OF GENDER EQUALITY The Philippines continues to lead as the most gender-equal country in Asia with a 79.1 percent gender parity based on the 2023 Global Gender Gap Index Report by the World Economic Forum. The national average male to female ratio for Philippines law firms is 67 to 33 percent is slightly better than the overall Asia average of 71 to 29 percent. Male attorneys still greatly out number female attorneys, but that is gradually changing as more women are actively participating in our today’s society just like in legal field. FEMINISM IN OTHER COUNTRIES Unfortunately, in other parts of the world, for example in Afghanistan, instances of inequality still exists. According to CNN News, Taliban officials have suspended education for female students in Afghanistan. Preceding this suspension, women have also been completely restricted from working in certain sectors and traveling long distances without a male guardian. The motivation behind this ban was the failure of women to adhere to specific rules enforced earlier that year, such as a strict dress code. These rules themselves are already forms of suppressing women’s freedom, and it’s also evident that these stern rules leave men to have more control over society. There are also instances in western countries like the United States. One key example is the overturning of Roe v. Wade in June 2022, which resulted in abortion being banned to varying degrees in 13 different states. This ban is a clear dismissal of women’s agency over themselves and their bodies. Furthermore, there are subtler but still widespread instances in both the workplace and schools, in which women are not treated equally. Some examples include 65 unequal pay, a preference towards men when it comes to promotions, and unsafe environments which could potentially lead to sexual harassment. The wage gap is still a serious problem in the U.S. today, as a woman gets paid 77 cents for every dollar that a man makes. This disparity in income dates back to times when women were starting to acquire the right to work. Perhaps, the claim that gender equality has already been established is completely incorrect, not just globally but also domestically. Feminism is often misunderstood as the concept that women are somewhat superior, or that all of the blame for gender inequality falls on men, who must now be punished for the patriarchy. This perception of feminism does not demonstrate its true definition, which is simply fighting for equality between men and women CONCLUSION Legal efforts have focused, inter alia, on expanding reproductive freedom, deterring sexual violence, and eliminating sex-based discrimination in employment, education, family, welfare, and related contexts. Law furthers social stability but may entrench norms of oppression. Law can also be a necessary means for reform. Law can be an anchor to the past or an engine for the future. Each function has its place. Feminist legal philosophy is an effort to examine and reformulate legal doctrine to overcome entrenched bias and enforced inequality of the past as it structures human concepts and institutions for the future. 66 VII. LGBTQIA+ Reported by: GARCIA, Edward LUGUE, Jamey Lynn NABATA, Christin Jireh HISTORY AND BACKGROUND Terms: SOGIE Sexual Orientation: This is about who you're attracted to. It's about the gender(s) of the people you feel romantic or sexual attraction towards. Examples include heterosexual (attracted to the opposite gender), homosexual (attracted to the same gender), bisexual (attracted to more than one gender), and others. Gender Identity: This is who you are inside in terms of gender. It’s your personal, internal sense of being male, female, both, neither, or somewhere along the gender spectrum. It’s something you feel and understand about yourself, regardless of what you show outwardly. Gender Expression: This is how you show your gender to the world. It’s the outward way you express your gender identity through things like clothing, hairstyle, body language, and voice. Your gender expression might be more masculine, feminine, or somewhere in between, and it can vary over time. You can have a gender identity that doesn’t necessarily match your expression. For example, someone might identify as female (identity) but choose to dress in a more androgynous or masculine way (expression). Brief History of LGBTQIA+ Homosexuality is an attraction between persons of the same sex. It was removed from the American Psychological Association (APA) list of mental disorders in 1973. APA stated that "homosexuality per se implies no impairment in judgment, stability, reliability, or general social and vocational capabilities." The Psychological Association of the Philippines (PAP) released the LGBT Non-discrimination Policy Resolution in October 2011 as a response to complaints against a certified psychologist who recommended conversion therapy for children. This resolution also reinforced the American Psychological Association’s position in 1973 viewing same-gender sexual orientations as healthy, non-disordered variant of human sexuality, love, and relationships. 68 In understanding gender, one must consider other influences such as identity, expression, attraction, and biology. Terms to remember are the following: • Gender Identity – how one considers oneself, e.g., woman, genderqueer, or man • Gender Expression – how one shows one’s gender through actions, outfits, behavior, interactions. This includes being feminine, androgynous (a mixture), or masculine • Biological Sex – refers to the organs, hormones, and chromosomes that influence gender, e.g., female, intersex, or male • Sexual Orientation – refers to the physical, emotional, and spiritual attraction based on another’s gender in relation to one’s own gender, e.g., heterosexual, bisexual, or homosexual “Gay” was used as an umbrella term to describe the whole community for many years. When the acronym was created, all variations start with “L” as a gesture of gratitude for the support of the lesbian community who cared for gay men with illness. The acronym was set in stone as “LGB”. LGBTQIA+ represents inclusivity. This acronym means Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Transgender, Queer/Questioning, Intersex, Asexual, and a plus sign at the end of the LGBTQIA+ acronym. Explanation on the acronym: • Lesbian – a woman attracted to another woman • Gay – a man attracted to another man • Bisexual – an individual attracted to both females and males • Transgender – a person’s gender identity is different to the gender associated to the assigned sex at birth • Queer/Questioning – means operating outside the norms; someone who is still exploring • Intersex – an individual who is born with variations of sex characteristics that do not fit with binary definitions of male or female bodies • Asexual – also called “ace” refers to someone who has little or no sexual attraction; they may, however, experience romantic attraction • + or plus – meaning anyone who is not listed in the acronym but still identifies as part of the community, including but not limited to the list below: • Pansexual – an individual attracted emotionally, romantically, and/or sexually to another regardless of gender • Aromantic – an individual who has little to no romantic attraction 69 • Genderfluid – an individual without any fixed gender identity Modern day gay rights movement started when the police raided Stonewall Inn in Manhattan, New York City on June 28, 1969 which led to the 6-day Stonewall Riots starting on June 29. It was where the community frequently came together in the years where solicitation of same-sex relations was illegal in New York City. Around the 1960s, bars were constantly raided arguing that the mere gathering of homosexuals was disorderly. Although the commission on human rights ruled that gay individuals had the right to be served in bars, police harassment continued. The Stonewall Inn was purchased and managed by a crime syndicate family or mafia who saw profit in catering to shunned gay clientele, looking for places of refuge. It involved the blackmailing of club patrons who want to keep their sexuality a secret and also the bribing of New York’s 6th police precinct to ignore activities within the club. Raids continued but the Stonewall Inn was usually tipped off by corrupt police officers. However, the Stonewall raid on June 28, 1969 was not tipped off. This raid resulted in the 6-day riots against social discrimination. The celebration of the LGBT Pride in the month of June was in recognition of the activists’ efforts. It was a galvanizing force for LGBT political activism that led to numerous gay rights organizations. History of Pride March There was a one-year anniversary of the riots on June 28, 1970 where people marched the streets from Stonewall Inn to Central Park and would be known as the Christopher Street Liberation Day March. This was the first gay pride parade with an official chant of “Say it loud, gay is proud”. The Stonewall Riot was commemorated around the world including the Philippines. In the 20th anniversary of the riot, PROGAY Philippines or the Progressive Organization of Gays in the Philippines and the Metropolitan Community Church in Manila organized a pride march on June 26, 1994 held in 70 Quezon City. The march was small in number with 60 participants, but it was the first time for the LGBT community to speak out for equality in public. The pride flag with the colors of the rainbow was created in 1978 by artist Gilbert Baker. He stated that flags are torn from the soul of the people. In 2015, Gilbert was asked to contribute a Rainbow Flag to the permanent collection at New York City’s Museum of Modern Art. The unveiling ceremony took place on June 26, the same day that the Supreme Court of the United States legalized gay marriage nationwide. Currently, the community uses many different flags that represent different identities, each with different colors and meanings. Additionally, the community spreads awareness of respecting preferred pronouns. Existing National Laws and Policies a. Same-sex marriage is not legally recognized in the Philippines. As a reminder that laws reflect the people, our country's legal framework, societal norms, and religious beliefs, particularly the influence of the Roman Catholic Church, contribute to this stance. b. Department of Education (DepEd) Child Protection Policy in 2012 This policy includes provisions to protect Children in School from Abuse, Violence, Exploitation, Discrimination, Bullying and Other Forms of Abuse. It includes in its definition of terms and prohibited acts, the part which is “Discrimination against children” – this refers to an act of exclusion, distinction, restriction or preference which is based on any ground such as age, ethnicity, sex, sexual orientation and gender identity, language, religion, political or other opinion and even those being infected or affected by Human Immunodeficiency Virus and Acquired Immune Deficiency Syndrome (AIDS). The policy includes programs that are intended to promote Positive and Non-Violent Discipline. Schools must use training modules which include positive and nonviolent discipline in classroom management, anger and stress management and gender sensitivity. 71 Local Anti-Discrimination Ordinances Numerous local government units (LGUs) have enacted anti-discrimination ordinances to protect LGBTQ rights at the local level. Some prominent examples include: 1. Quezon City In 2003, Quezon City became the first Philippine city to pass an antidiscrimination ordinance protecting LGBTQ individuals. The ordinance has since been updated and strengthened to include comprehensive protection against discrimination in employment, education, healthcare, and other sectors. They have established the QC Pride Council which is supposed to integrate the city’s programs with the LGBT community. The city also passed other ordinances such as the Gender-Fair Ordinance in 2014 for prohibiting discrimination against the community in their workplace, educational institutions and in the delivery of goods and services. The ordinance also lists “affirmative acts” that should be adopted in these areas, like equal pay and sensitivity training in workplaces. 2. Cebu City Cebu City passed its Anti-Discrimination Ordinance in 2012, prohibiting discrimination based on sexual orientation and gender identity in employment, education, and other areas. 3. Davao City Davao City implemented an anti-discrimination ordinance in 2012, which covers SOGIE-based discrimination and includes penalties for violators. 4. Iloilo City, Baguio City, and Mandaluyong City These cities, along with several others, have passed similar ordinances to prevent SOGIE-based discrimination in their jurisdictions. 72 SUPREME COURT CASES INVOLVING LGBTQIA+ IN THE PHILIPPINES o Silverio v. Republic o Ang Ladlad LGBT Party v. Commission on Elections o Cagandahan v. Republic o Falcis v. Civil Service Registrar o Laude vs. Ginez-Jabalde Silverio vs Republic FACTS Rommel Jacinto Dantes Silverio, born male, alleged that he is a male transsexual, that is, "anatomically male but feels, thinks and acts as a female" and that he had always identified himself with girls since childhood. Silverio finally underwent sex reassignment surgery in Bangkok, Thailand on 2001. She (let’s use the she/her pronouns because Silverio identifies as a female) lived from then on as a female and got engaged. She petitioned to change her first name from "Rommel Jacinto" to "Mely" and her sex from "male" to "female" in her birth certificate. RTC: granted the petition with the principles of justice and equity. RTC believes no harm or prejudice will be caused and will bring happiness to Silverio and American fiance. (sobrang nakakatouch yung sinabi ng RTC huhu) However, the Republic of the Philippines, represented by the Office of the Solicitor General (OSG), appealed to the Court of Appeals, arguing that there was no legal basis for such changes in the birth certificate. CA: ruled in favor of the Republic, setting aside the trial court's decision. Petitioner’s arguments: Petitioner essentially claims that the change of his name and sex in his birth certificate is allowed under Articles 407 to 413 of the Civil Code, Rules 103 and 108 of the Rules of Court and RA 9048. 73 ISSUE (1) WON a person who has undergone sex reassignment surgery validly contract a marriage as a person of the sex to which they have transitioned? NO. (2) WON a person who has undergone sex reassignment surgery can legally change the name and sex in their birth certificate. NO. RULING (1) NO. The Supreme Court ruled that a person who has undergone sex reassignment surgery is still legally considered to be of the sex they were assigned at birth for the purposes of marriage under Philippine law. Silverio is still considered male. Article 2 of the Family Code stipulates that the essential requisites of a valid marriage include the legal capacity of the contracting parties, who must be a male and a female. Since the Philippine legal system does not recognize changes in a person's sex for purposes of marriage registration and family relations, the Court found that Silverio, despite undergoing sex reassignment surgery, could not be legally recognized as female. As such, Silverio’s marriage to a male would be deemed invalid under Article 2, which requires that one party be male and the other female (2) NO. There is no law in the Philippines allowing the change of name or sex in a birth certificate based on sex reassignment surgery. (and sad naman huhu) The Court emphasized that a change of name is a privilege, not a right, and is controlled by statutory provisions. Article 376 of the Civil Code states that no person can change their name or surname without judicial authority. However, even with judicial authority, the reasons for changing one’s name do not extend to sex reassignment, as there is no legal provision for such a change. The court clarified that judicial authority under Article 376 is limited to situations explicitly recognized by law, which does not include changes in civil registry entries based on sex reassignment. Republic Act No. 9048 (Clerical Error Law) allows the correction of clerical or typographical errors in civil registry entries without the need for a judicial order, except for changes involving the sex, nationality, status, or legitimacy of a person. The Court noted that Silverio's request 74 falls outside the scope of the Clerical Error Law because it involves a substantial change, not merely a clerical or typographical correction. Article 412 of the Civil Code provides that no entry in a civil registry shall be changed or corrected without a judicial order. The Court ruled that while a judicial order is necessary to change civil registry entries, it must be based on legal grounds. Since no law permits the change of sex based on reassignment surgery, the judicial order issued by the RTC was deemed beyond the court's authority. Ladlad vs COMELEC FACTS The case "Ang Ladlad LGBT Party v. Commission on Elections" was decided by the Supreme Court of the Philippines on April 8, 2010. Ang Ladlad, an organization representing the LGBT community, first applied for party-list registration with the Commission on Elections (COMELEC) in 2006 but was denied due to a lack of substantial membership. "Lack of substantial membership" refers to the insufficient number of members or supporters within an organization to demonstrate that it has a genuine and active base In 2009, Ang Ladlad filed another petition, emphasizing that the LGBT community is marginalized and under-represented, suffering from discrimination and violence. However, the COMELEC dismissed their petition on moral grounds, citing that Ang Ladlad’s advocacy allegedly promoted immorality and contravened religious teachings, referencing religious texts to justify their decision. The COMELEC further argued that accrediting the group would endanger society’s moral fabric and negatively influence the youth. After a divided vote among the COMELEC commissioners and a decision from the Chairman upholding the dismissal due to Ang Ladlad’s perceived lack of a national political agenda, Ang Ladlad petitioned the Supreme Court to annul the COMELEC's resolutions and compel the approval of their application. The Office of the Solicitor General supported Ang Ladlad, contending that the COMELEC’s claims of immorality were unsubstantiated. 75 ISSUE Whether the COMELEC’s denial of Ang Ladlad’s application for partylist accreditation on the grounds of immorality and societal harm violated Ang Ladlad’s constitutional rights. RULING The Supreme Court ruled in favor of Ang Ladlad, determining that the COMELEC's actions infringed upon Ang Ladlad’s rights to privacy, freedom of speech and assembly, and equal protection under the law. The Court highlighted the non-establishment clause of the Constitution, requiring governmental neutrality in religious matters, and dismissed moral disapproval as insufficient grounds for exclusion from the political process. The Court recognized the LGBT community as a marginalized and under-represented sector entitled to party-list participation. Cagandahan v. Republic FACTS Jennifer B. Cagandahan was born on January 13, 1981, and registered as female on her birth certificate. Due to Congenital Adrenal Hyperplasia (CAH), she developed secondary male characteristics, including ambiguous genitalia and male hormone production. On December 11, 2003, she filed a Petition for Correction of Entries in her Birth Certificate with the Regional Trial Court (RTC) of Siniloan, Laguna, seeking to change her name from Jennifer to Jeff and her gender from female to male. This was supported by medical testimony from Dr. Michael Sionzon, who confirmed her body's production of male hormones. The RTC granted her petition on January 12, 2005, ordering the changes in her birth certificate and other pertinent records. ISSUE Did the trial court err in granting the petition for correction of entries in the birth certificate to change the respondent's sex or gender from female to male and name from "Jennifer" to "Jeff" under Rules 103 and 108 of the Rules of Court? RULING 76 Falcis III vs. Civil Registrar General FACTS: Jesus Nicardo M. Falcis III, who filed a Petition for Certiorari and Prohibition under Rule 65 of the 1997 Rules of Civil Procedure on May 18, 2015. Falcis sought to declare Articles 1 and 2 of the Family Code unconstitutional, which define marriage as a union between a man and a woman, and to nullify Articles 46(4) and 55(6) of the Family Code. Falcis, an openly homosexual individual, claimed that these provisions violated his rights to due process, equal protection, and the right to marry. The Civil Registrar General was named as the respondent. The LGBTS Christian Church, Inc., Reverend Crescencio "Ceejay" Agbayani, Jr., Marlon Felipe, and Maria Arlyn "Sugar" Ibañez intervened, supporting Falcis' claims. ISSUE: W/N denying same-sex couples the right to marry tantamount to a denial of their right to life and/or liberty without due process of law? HELD: The Court found that there was no actual case or controversy, and that Falcis lacked legal standing. The Court emphasized the need for public discussion and legislative action on the recognition of same-sex marriage. The Court's decision was based on several key points. First, the Court found that the mere passage of the Family Code did not create an actual case or controversy, as Falcis had not applied for a marriage license and had not been directly injured by the provisions he challenged. Second, the Court held that Falcis lacked legal standing because he had not suffered a direct injury. Third, the Court determined that the petitionin-intervention did not cure the procedural defects of the original petition. Fourth, the Court ruled that the issues raised were not of transcendental importance and did not warrant bypassing the hierarchy of courts. Finally, the Court emphasized that the recognition of same-sex marriage should be addressed through public discussion and legislative action, rather than judicial fiat. 77 o G.R. No. 217456: Laude vs. Ginez-Jabalde Laude vs. Ginez-Jabalde FACTS: Marilou S. Laude and Mesehilda S. Laude filed a petition against Judge Roline M. Ginez-Jabalde and several other respondents. The case arose from the murder of Jeffrey "Jennifer" Laude on October 11, 2014, in Olongapo City, allegedly by Pemberton. A complaint for murder was filed on October 15, 2014, and Pemberton was detained at Camp Aguinaldo on October 22, 2014. The Public Prosecutor filed an Information for murder on December 15, 2014, and Pemberton was arraigned on December 19, 2014. On the same day, Marilou S. Laude filed an Urgent Motion to transfer Pemberton's custody to the Olongapo City Jail and to allow media coverage. The motion was denied by Judge Ginez-Jabalde as was Laude’s motion for reconsideration. ISSUE: W/N trial court commit grave abuse of discretion in denying the Urgent Motion to transfer custody of Pemberton to the Olongapo City Jail HELD The court denied the petition because the petitioners failed to comply with the three-day notice rule for filing motions, which is essential for ensuring that the adverse party has sufficient time to prepare and respond. This noncompliance was deemed unjustified and a violation of procedural due process. Additionally, the court found that the petitioners did not demonstrate any grave abuse of discretion by the trial court judge, and the issues raised regarding custody under the Visiting Forces Agreement were not sufficient to warrant the requested relief. o SOGIE BILL v. R.A. 11313 [comparison] SOGIE Bill V. R.A. 11313 The SOGIE Bill is more directly focused Although it does not focus on SOGIEon addressing issues of discrimination related discrimination explicitly, the against the LGBTQ+ community, Safe Spaces Act provides significant 78 aiming to provide comprehensive legal protection and rights. Its focus on employment, education, and other public services is crucial for promoting equality in a broader context. However, the bill has faced difficulty passing in Congress due to opposition, particularly from conservative groups. protection for LGBTQ+ individuals from harassment, especially in public spaces and workplaces. The law acknowledges that LGBTQ+ persons, especially transgender individuals, face unique challenges related to harassment. The Safe Spaces Act complements the SOGIE Bill by offering a legal framework for addressing harassment that may intersect with issues of SOGIE. Prominent LGBTQ movements and advocacy groups in the Philippines that have significantly contributed to pushing for legislation or policies related to LGBTQ rights: Ladlad Party Established in 2003, Ladlad is the first LGBT political party in the Philippines. It has advocated for anti-discrimination policies and the recognition of LGBTQ rights, bringing visibility to LGBTQ issues in the political sphere. Although unsuccessful in gaining congressional seats, Ladlad's efforts influenced awareness and support for LGBTQ rights among legislators. UP Babaylan Formed in 1992, UP Babaylan is the oldest LGBTQ student organization in the Philippines, based at the University of the Philippines. It has been active in advocating for LGBTQ rights on campus and in the broader community, supporting legislation such as the Anti-Discrimination Bill (ADB) through awareness campaigns and advocacy. Philippine LGBT Chamber of Commerce This organization has advocated for diversity and inclusion in the workplace and contributed to legislative discussions around the SOGIE Equality Bill. The chamber emphasizes economic empowerment and inclusion for LGBTQ individuals, working with corporations and policymakers to create inclusive policies. 79 Metro Manila Pride Originally organized in the 1990s, Metro Manila Pride is a community-led, non-profit organization that annually holds the Metro Manila Pride March. It has been instrumental in raising awareness and gaining public support for the SOGIE Equality Bill and other inclusive policies. Bahay Tuluyan This organization, while primarily focused on supporting marginalized children, has advocated for LGBTQ youth, particularly regarding anti-bullying policies in schools. Their advocacy has contributed to the development of LGBTQinclusive programs within the Department of Education. Galang Philippines This grassroots organization advocates for LGBTQ rights, especially among low-income LGBTQ communities. Galang Philippines has worked on local legislation for anti-discrimination ordinances and supported national campaigns for the SOGIE Equality Bill, emphasizing intersectionality in LGBTQ advocacy. LGBT Pilipinas A national federation of LGBTQ organizations, LGBT Pilipinas has been at the forefront of pushing for the SOGIE Equality Bill and other legislative reforms. They represent LGBTQ issues in various government consultations, amplifying the community’s voice on a national scale. Home for the Golden Gays The Home for the Golden Gays (HGG), is a Philippine non-profit organization that provides support and care facilities for elderly LGBTQ people. It was originally established in 1975 by Justo Justo (September 21, 1941 – May 18, 2012), a Filipino columnist, Pasay City councilor, and LGBTQ activist. Currently, there are around 40 active members of the organization, mostly aged 60 and above. They are colloquially known as "the lolas" (lola is Filipino for "grandmother"). These groups and movements have made considerable strides in pushing for inclusive policies, the passage of the SOGIE Equality Bill, anti-discrimination ordinances, and other legislative reforms aimed at advancing LGBTQ rights and protections in the Philippines. 80 VIII. EASTERN PHILOSOPHY Reported by: DAVID, Kevin Christofer HERRERA, Dominique Ricca INTRODUCTION The “self” is an illusion. Personal identity, consciousness, and core philosophies are all illusions. This is what Eastern Philosophy speaks about. Eastern philosophy, that originated from the Eastern and Southern part of Asia, believes that we are all interconnected and part of a greater universal whole. Hindus believe that the Atman, or human soul, is a part of Brahman, the soul of god. Atman is part of Brahman, and therefore cannot be a completely separate entity or "self." Buddhists believe that we are all so interconnected that there can be no distinctions of "self" made between us, and "the self" is ultimately an illusion. LEGAL SYSTEMS A legal system is the framework of rules, procedures, and institutions that a community uses to interpret and enforce their laws. A legal system is binding on all legal disputes within its jurisdiction. There is no uniform legal system across the globe. Each jurisdiction uses its own legal system. The type of legal system a jurisdiction uses will have a significant impact on the application of the law. A. COMMON LAW SYSTEM • Common law meant judge-made law that filled in gaps when there was no written law. Judges looked to prior decisions to determine the unwritten judge-made law and apply it to new cases. However, today, almost all law is in writing and enacted by a legislature as statutes. • A purely common law system is created by the judiciary, as the law comes from case law, rather than statute. Thus, a common law system has a strong focus on judicial precedent, stare decisis, and the rule of law. B. CIVIL LAW SYSTEM • However, most of the world uses a form of the civil law system. A pure civil law system is governed by statutes, rather than by case law. In a civil law system, the judge takes a more active role in the investigation. 82 • • A civil law system relies on comprehensive legal codes that contain all laws for the country In civil law systems, court cases are investigations by the court to see how the facts fit into the already established codes applicable to the situation. The court system is set up so that the jurisdiction of each court is a specific type of code: tax courts, administrative courts, maritime courts, constitutional courts, and so on. C. RELIGIOUS SYSTEM • In a religious law system, the law relies on religious texts as its primary basis, and the courts interpret the present facts and statutes in light of those religious texts. Many Middle Eastern countries use religious law systems for all or part of their laws. • The legislature enacts statutes, but all are tested against Islamic tenets. Certain religious leaders can overrule any government act, including court decisions, on religious grounds. The legal system includes general and summary sharia courts, with some administrative tribunals for specific topics. Religious law systems do not use juries, and criminal trials do not present defensive evidence to the same extent as in other legal systems. Each judge, a specialist in the religious sharia text, makes their interpretation of the law and is not bound by any precedent. D. OTHERS • Aside from Common, Civil, and Religious law systems, we also have Customary and Hybrid or Mixed Legal Systems. Is there a “god?” Eastern Philosophy stands strong on the existence of a god. According to some Eastern Philosophers, the question, of whether there is a god, is answered with a yes. Moreover, this god is not a man or a woman. This God (AKA Tao), is cosmic energy, which is the beginning, and the end. Every action has an opposite reaction. One needs to understand this and build up good Karma before they are able to transcend. Since the world is unpredictable, and everyone has to become, what they are meant to be, judgment is not necessary. If a person takes the wrong path, then the soul will be born again, so that it will have another chance, to do it right. 83 To establish, eastern philosophies center on various religions found in the East and South of Asia. These philosophies are deeply rooted in religion - such as Buddhism, Confucianism, Hinduism, and so on. 1. CONFUCIANISM Confucianism is a Chinese philosophy that focuses on social and ethical conduct, and is often described as a "civil religion.” Confucianism is a philosophy and belief system from ancient China that laid the foundation for much of Chinese culture. Confucianism promotes ancestor worship and human-centered virtues for living a peaceful life. Some examples of ancestor worship include maintaining a shrine in one’s home for relatives that have passed on and making offerings of food and drink, flowers or incense at gravesites. The golden rule of Confucianism is “do not do unto others what you would not want others to do unto you.” It is worthy to note, however, that scholars argue whether Confucianism is a religion or not. It began as a revival of an earlier religious tradition and has some characteristics of the Western framework of religion. There are also Confucian temples where important community and civic rituals happen. There are no Confucian gods, and Confucianism focuses neither on the creation of the Earth or human life nor the afterlife. Although many people emphasize that Confucianism is both a religion and a philosophy, it is better understood as an ethical guide to life. The main idea of Confucianism is the importance of having a good moral character, which can affect the world around a person through the idea of cosmic harmony. This moral character is achieved through the virtue of ren, or “humanity,” which leads to more virtuous behaviors, such as respect, altruism and humility. He thought that people are essentially good yet may have strayed from the appropriate forms of conduct. Rituals in Confucianism were designed to bring about this respectful attitude and create a sense of community within a group. a. Beliefs - Confucianism is based on the belief that people are inherently good, and can be improved through self-cultivation and personal effort. b. Values - Confucianism emphasizes virtues such as kindness, righteousness, wisdom, sobriety, and trustworthiness. 84 c. Relationships - Confucianism is based on the idea that people should behave well towards others, and that relationships are important for balance in life. d. Influence - Confucianism has influenced cultures and countries in the Chinese cultural sphere, including China, Taiwan, Korea, Japan, and Vietnam. e. Characteristics - Confucianism is different from other religions because it has no deity, and it's not established in a way that competes with other religions. f. Punishment - Confucianism advocates for moderate punishments that aren't the primary way to manage society. g. Justice - Confucian corrective justice aims to restore harmony and peace in human relations, not to punish violators or uphold the legal order. h. Rule of law - Some say Confucianism is incompatible with modern rule of law because it values social roles and status over legal resolution and equality before the law. i. Compatibility - Others say Confucianism is compatible with the rule of law and has co-existed with Chinese legal systems throughout history. Other aspects of Confucianism and law: j. Moral law - Confucianism holds that human law should be subordinate to a higher moral law that's revealed by reason. k. National authority - Confucianism supports obeying national authority, but only within the context of moral obligations that rulers have toward their subjects. l. Revolution - Confucians recognize the right of revolution against tyranny. Effect of Confucianism It can be said that Confucianism does not play an important role in the regulation of punishment in general and the death penalty in particular in the law. The great success of Confucianism is that it protects Confucian moral values in legal regulations. The relations between a ruler and his minister, father and child, husband and wife, in which the submission of the minister to the ruler, the child to the father, and the wife to the husband with the values of loyalty, filial piety, and getting along with siblings were protected by the criminal laws through severe 85 penalties for violations including capital punishment. The making of laws and regulating penalties were based on the principles of Legalism more than Confucianism. Confucius’s pessimism about the law in the form of punishments is that it would not build a sense of shame, as the people would merely seek to avoid punishments. It is not enough for Confucius to avoid punishments, as his philosophical goals were not simply to create a society that avoided legal punishments, but to cultivate individuals to actively seek good. Instead, people ought to be led by virtue and li, in which they would have a healthy sense of shame that would lead to the self correction of their wrongness into a good moral character. Thus, the goal is not just to prevent misconduct, but to develop proper moral emotions, like a sense of shame to moral shortcomings which would motivate moral development. 2. COMMUNISM Communism was an economic-political philosophy founded by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels in the second half of the 19th century. Marx and Engels met in 1844, and discovered that they had similar principles. In 1848 they wrote and published "The Communist Manifesto." They desired to end capitalism feeling that it was the social class system that led to the exploitation of workers. The workers that were exploited would develop class consciousness. It became the dominant political philosophy of many countries across Asia, Eastern Europe, Africa and South America. In the late 19th century, communist philosophy began to develop in Russia. In 1917, the Bolsheviks seized power through the October Revolution. This was the first time any group with a decidedly Marxist viewpoint managed to seize power. They changed their name to the Communist Party, and sent their ideals to all European socialist parties. They then nationalized all public property as well as putting factories and railroads under government control. Stalin continued leading by the communist philosophies, and extended the growth of the the USSR. This example of Communism has been followed in many countries since then, including China. 86 Marxist views on law Marxists believe that law is a feature of pre-communist societies and that it will disappear in a communist society. They also believe that law is unnecessary for human civilization. a. Law in communist states – In communist states, law was subordinate to the Communist Party. For example, in the Soviet Union, the court system was designed to ensure party control over judicial decisions. b. Absence of a legal tradition – In the Soviet Union and China, there was a weak or nonexistent legal tradition. China's legal system was primarily oriented toward maintaining order under state dominance. c. Long-lasting effects Communism has had long-lasting effects on preferences, trust, views towards immigration, and gender norms. The effects are the largest for cohorts that lived the longest under communism. This provides evidence that more prolonged exposure to the features of socialism—including indoctrination and repression—collectively lowers the appreciation of freedom of speech values. Our results are robust to a battery of sensitivity checks and provide suggestive evidence pointing to indoctrination as a mechanism behind our findings. As such, our paper contributes to the scarce body of literature on the economics of free speech, suggesting that freedom of speech may be a part of informal institutions and slow-changing cultural values. Exploiting the natural experiment of German separation and later reunification, we show that living under communism has had lasting effects on free speech opinions, and the convergence process has been slow. East Germans are still less likely to consider freedom of speech a key government priority than West Germans. Communism has had different effects on gender norms in different countries, but in general, it aimed to promote gender equality and women's rights: 87 a. Soviet Union - The Bolsheviks emphasized gender equality as a central goal, and the USSR established legal equality for women in the 1920s. This included equal pay, full citizenship, and the right to divorce. b. China - The Communist Party in China committed to emancipating women and restructuring gender relationships. The party used persuasive communication, such as radio, to create "new men" with new values. c. Eastern Europe - Communist regimes opened up opportunities for women in activism, politics, and paid employment. However, they also perpetuated pre-existing gender relations by marginalizing certain sectors. In general, communist regimes treated people equally in the eyes of the government, regardless of education or financial standing. However, some say that communist societies still showed high levels of social stratification and inequality. 3. RABBINIC LAW Rabbinic law is a set of legal discussions and rulings that are part of classical rabbinic literature. It covers a wide range of topics, including civil, criminal, ritual, and marital law. Rabbinic law is characterized by its detail, systematization, and preoccupation with legal matters. Characteristics of Rabbinic Law • Sources - Rabbinic law is based on rabbinic biblical exegesis, custom and tradition, rabbinic legislation, and logical reasoning. • Categories - Rabbinic law is divided into three general categories: Gezeirah, Takkanah, and Minhag. Gezeirah laws are created to prevent people from unintentionally breaking Torah law, Takkanah laws are created for the public good, and Minhag laws are long-standing customs. • Purpose - Rabbinic law was created to add restrictions on top of the Bible to keep people from breaking biblical law. 88 • Approach - Rabbinic law is case-based and often uses analogy in legal reasoning. • Family law - Rabbinic law introduced the ketubba, a marriage contract that outlines the obligations of the husband and wife. Rabbinic law also obligated sons to support their widowed and unmarried sisters. • Financial law - Rabbinic law developed laws around contracts, partnerships, and legal arrangements to work around the biblical prohibition on usury. Rabbinic law is different from state law and has rarely had the political power to enforce its rules. 4. LAW OFMESOPOTAMIA OR ANCIENT NEAR EAST Mesopotamian law influenced Rabbinic law and may have shaped ancient Greek and Roman law. The laws of Mesopotamia include the Code of Hammurabi, which is one of the oldest and most complete written legal codes in the world: a. Code of Hammurabi Written by the sixth king of Babylon, Hammurabi, around 1754 BCE, this code is made up of 282 laws that covered topics such as trade, slavery, theft, and divorce. The code is known for its "an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth" form of punishment, also known as lex talionis. Other punishments included: o If a son hit his father, his hands were hewn off. o If a son and mother were caught committing incest, they were burned to death. o If a pair of lovers conspired to murder their spouses, both were impaled. o For crimes that could not be proven, the accused was put through a "trial by ordeal". 89 Lex talionis: The law of retribution, or "an eye for an eye". For example, if a man broke another man's bone, his own bone would be broken. Harsh punishments: The code included severe punishments, such as removing the guilty party's tongue, hands, breasts, eye, or ear. Innocent until proven guilty: The code was one of the earliest examples of this principle. Different standards of justice: The code outlined different standards of justice for the three classes of Babylonian society: the propertied class, freedmen, and slaves. Divine origin: Hammurabi claimed that he received his laws from the gods, and had an image of the god of justice, Shamash, engraved at the top of the stele. Written on stone and clay tablets: The code was written on stone stele and clay tablets. Discovered in 1901: The code was discovered in 1901 at the ancient site of Susa in Khuzestan. b. Code of Ur-Nammu o If a man committed murder, he must be killed. o If a man committed robbery, he would be killed. o If a man deflowered a virgin wife of a young man, they shall kill that male. c. The Code of Lipit-Ishtar of Isin d. The Laws of Eshnunna 5. BUDDHISM 90 Buddhism is a spiritual tradition that focuses on personal spiritual development and the attainment of a deep insight into the true nature of life. There are 376 million followers worldwide. Buddhists seek to reach a state of nirvana, following the path of the Buddha, Siddhartha Gautama, who went on a quest for Enlightenment around the sixth century BC. The basic doctrines of early Buddhism include the "four noble truths": existence is suffering (dukhka); suffering has a cause, namely craving and attachment (trishna); there is a cessation of suffering, which is nirvana; and there is a path to the cessation of suffering. Theravāda Buddhism codifies ethical behavior in the form of moral precepts. o Refrain from killing or injuring living creatures. o Refrain from taking what is not given. o Refrain from committing sexual misconduct. o Refrain from ‘wrong speech’, such as lying and gossiping. o Refrain from using intoxicants that cloud the mind, such as alcohol or non-prescription mind-affecting drugs. Buddhism and Human Rights The doctrine of ‘ahimsa’ in Buddhism elucidates the view that every individual respects the inherent dignity of their own life, furthering love and protection to others in a selfless manner, and does not deserve the suffering which is extended to others. It is argued that there are non-Western ethical traditions that can espouse human rights, such as Theravāda Buddhism. Human rights can be deduced from Buddhist moral teachings by assessing the association between the Buddhist precepts and social justice as seen in the Theravāda tradition. Concerns regarding ‘self-fulfilment, respect for others and the quest to contribute to others’ have been found in Confucian, Hindu and Buddhist traditions, hence implying correlative duties for a just and peaceful society. Hesanmi expounded the reasonability of affirming the mutual entailment of rights and duties rather than erecting a false dichotomy between the two. 91 Ethical Principles of Buddhism a. Karmic Debt A common concept that underpins ethical decision-making is the idea of karmic debt (related to the concept of karma). This refers to the idea that beings cannot avoid the negative results of their unskillful or unwholesome actions. As such, all bad deeds or actions must be eventually paid for. b. Non-violence (Avihiṃsā) In Buddhism, avihiṃsā (usually translated as non-injury, non-killing or nonviolence) refers to the concept of not causing harm to other living things. Adherence to the principle of non-violence is thought to generate positive kamma, while defying the principle is believed to bring about negative kamma. The concept of avihiṃsā forms the basis of vegetarianism for many Buddhists as well as the tolerance towards all forms of life. Sexuality in Buddhism There are no strict sexual ethical guidelines presented in Buddhism for lay Buddhists. Buddhists are generally open to the use of birth control. However, other topics related to family planning such as abortion or reproductive technologies are usually influenced by factors other than religion (such as culture, family perceptions, financial security, etc.). Monogamy is the predominant model of relationships. In some cases, there is local variation in marriage and dating customs in the Buddhist world. Positions on homosexuality vary; some Buddhists are conservative on the matter, while others may be tolerant or supportive. Sexual Misconduct in Buddhism Avoidance of sexual misconduct is one of the main moral precepts expected to be observed by all Buddhists. ‘Sexual misconduct’ for lay Buddhists generally refers to sexual offences such as non-consensual sexual acts, sexual activity with minors or those protected by the law, and adultery. It can also broadly refer to any irresponsible use of sexuality (such as promiscuity, an overindulgence of sex or sexual addiction). In the context of monasticism in Theravāda Buddhism, monks and nuns are expected to practise celibacy. 92 Marriage in Buddhism Though Buddhism recognizes the importance of marriage as a social institution, marriage is usually not understood as a religious concern. Rather, marriage is seen as a matter of secular society in which the partners assume obligations to each other. Divorce in Buddhism Generally, Buddhism has no religious objection to divorce. Social and cultural influences play a major role in determining the level of acceptance when it comes to divorce and remarriage. CONCLUSION The very point of eastern philosophy in contemporary times, especially in the rule of law and legal systems is the incorporation of holistic perspectives and the interconnectedness of all things. While western philosophy focuses mainly on scientific findings, eastern philosophy puts our feet to the ground that in the greater scheme of things, everything’s connected. After all, we are, as ourselves, are collection of experiences. Eastern philosophy greatly affected the contemporary issues concerning the execution of justice and the law at present. Eastern philosophies often prioritize experiential knowledge and intuition over purely rational thought. This has led to different approaches in education, psychology, and even science, encouraging a more integrative understanding of knowledge. 93