Three Basic Assumptions About Consciousness BRUNO FORTI1* 1 Department of Mental Health, AZIENDA ULSS 1 DOLOMITI, Italy Submitted to Journal: Frontiers in Psychology Specialty Section: Consciousness Research w e i v re Article type: Conceptual Analysis Article Manuscript ID: 813918 In Received on: 12 Nov 2021 Journal website link: www.frontiersin.org Conflict of interest statement The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest Author contribution statement The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication. Keywords consciousness research, Phenomenal consciousness, Physical substrate, function, qualia, early visual perception Abstract Word count: 335 w e i v re In this paper I jointly analyse the implications for a theory of consciousness of three basic assumptions, with which most authors seem to agree. These are the assumptions that consciousness exists, is physical and has a function. The material existence of consciousness implies the need to have a structure. For research purposes it is useful to identify the simplest forms of consciousness in terms of existence, structure and function respectively. It is also necessary to consider the existence of consciousness in a specific form, in order to avoid formulating theories which refer to states which are not conscious, even if they have some characteristics of consciousness – as is the case in many theories of consciousness. At the same time, consciousness must have a structure and a function as such, in the sense that structure and function must not belong, at least in an exclusive way, to a neural correlate of consciousness, to a physical substrate or to anything else that does not entirely correspond to consciousness in its specific existence. The specificity of conscious existence leads us to set aside states that coincide with consciousness in the broad sense of access or with properties such as unity, integration, intentionality, and changeability, and to prioritize the different forms of phenomenal consciousness. Assuming that consciousness has a structure as such implies the need to search for a third-person phenomenal structure. This leads to identifying the simplest structural aspects of consciousness not in qualitative sensations, but in the phenomenal aspects of the perception of “a figure on a background”. Assuming a functional role for consciousness as such leads us to identifying a function which, although related to information processing, cannot be caused by a Neurocomputational brain and consequently cannot be computational in nature. The joint constraints of the three assumptions significantly restrict the field in which to identify the most suitable forms of consciousness to be investigated first. A possible research field to start from is the one of the simplest and earliest forms of visual perception. In Contribution to the field Consciousness is so hard to explain that it is still under discussion whether to assign to it three typical attributes of every biological phenomenon, namely existence, physical nature and function. What are the implications for a theory of consciousness if we assume that consciousness exists in a specific form, is material as such and has a function as such? If we refer to non-specific forms of consciousness, e.g., access consciousness or integration, we risk formulating theories that describe non-conscious states or processes. If we do not refer to consciousness as such, we are likely to attribute the structure that characterizes every physical phenomenon to the physical substrate and not to the experience itself. If we do not identify a function of consciousness as such, we risk attributing it entirely to the computational processes of the brain. This would result in the impossibility of assigning a function to consciousness. On the other hand, only phenomenal consciousness can fulfill these three requirements. In this context, the simplest structural and functional aspects of consciousness should be identified not in qualia, i.e., the qualitative aspects of the subjective sensations that characterize experience, but in the basic phenomenal aspects of visual perception. Ethics statements Studies involving animal subjects Generated Statement: No animal studies are presented in this manuscript. Studies involving human subjects Generated Statement: No human studies are presented in this manuscript. Inclusion of identifiable human data Generated Statement: No potentially identifiable human images or data is presented in this study. Three Basic Assumptions About Consciousness 1 Bruno Forti1* 2 1 3 4 5 * Correspondence: Bruno Forti brunoforti4@gmail.com 6 7 Keywords: consciousness research, phenomenal consciousness, physical substrate, function, qualia, early visual perception. 8 Abstract Department of Mental Health, Azienda ULSS 1 Dolomiti, Belluno, Italia w e i v re 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 In this paper I jointly analyse the implications for a theory of consciousness of three basic assumptions, with which most authors seem to agree. These are the assumptions that consciousness exists, is physical and has a function. The material existence of consciousness implies the need to have a structure. For research purposes it is useful to identify the simplest forms of consciousness in terms of existence, structure and function respectively. It is also necessary to consider the existence of consciousness in a specific form, in order to avoid formulating theories which refer to states which are not conscious, even if they have some characteristics of consciousness – as is the case in many theories of consciousness. At the same time, consciousness must have a structure and a function as such, in the sense that structure and function must not belong, at least in an exclusive way, to a neural correlate of consciousness, to a physical substrate or to anything else that does not entirely correspond to consciousness in its specific existence. The specificity of conscious existence leads us to set aside states that coincide with consciousness in the broad sense of access or with properties such as unity, integration, intentionality, and changeability, and to prioritize the different forms of phenomenal consciousness. Assuming that consciousness has a structure as such implies the need to search for a third-person phenomenal structure. Qualia and qualitative feel seem to be suitable for highlighting the simpler aspects of experience, even if the concept of qualia is scarcely compatible with the concept of structure, and even if sensations can only be experienced as belonging to some object. This leads to identifying the simplest structural aspects of consciousness not in qualitative sensations, but in the phenomenal aspects of the perception of “a figure on a background”. Assuming a functional role for consciousness as such leads us to the paradox of identifying a function which, although related to information processing, cannot be caused by a Neurocomputational brain and consequently cannot be computational in nature. The joint constraints of the three assumptions significantly restrict the field in which to identify the most suitable forms of consciousness to be investigated first. A possible research field to start from is the one of the simplest and earliest forms of visual perception. 34 Introduction 35 36 37 Different conceptual frameworks aimed at characterizing consciousness take sometimes radically different assumptions as their starting point. A possible method to formulate a theory of consciousness is to examine three basic assumptions: In Running Title 38 - consciousness exists; 39 - consciousness is material; 40 - consciousness has a function. 41 42 43 44 45 46 These assumptions are fundamental to any hypothesis that can be formulated about consciousness. They are apparently quite intuitive, and most authors agree with them (James, 1904; Searle, 1997, 2004; Earl, 2014; Kendler, 2005; Tononi and Koch, 2015; Jylkkä and Railo, 2019). However, in this paper I will try to argue that accepting these three basic assumptions about consciousness, especially when taken together, has implications that are not insignificant. They place considerable constraints on any possible theory of consciousness. At the same time, they can open up new lines of research. 47 Article type 48 Conceptual Analysis 49 Consciousness exists 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 A number of thinkers denied the existence of something we know with certainty to exist. They denied the existence of consciousness, conscious experience, the subjective qualitative character of experience, the ‘phenomenal’ what-it-is-like of experience (Strawson, 2018). Paul and Patricia Churchland (Churchland, 1989, 1995; Churchland and Sejnowski, 1992) argued that concepts relating to the mind belong to the ‘folk psychology’ of common sense and, like the concepts of phlogiston and vital spirit, they will no longer make sense when more effective explanations emerge. The mechanisms we call conscious can be explained in the context of a mind model inspired by connectionism and neural networks. Qualitative states can thus be identified with neural activity vectors within special neural network structures. 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 According to Dennett, there seems to be such a thing as qualia, but it is an error of assessment that we make about what is actually happening. According to the Multiple Draft Model (Dennett, 1991), subjectivity is an illusory construction, a virtual entity implemented by a brain acting in a distributed and parallel way through a multiple set of cognitive activities. None of these cognitive agencies coincides with the self, which is merely an imaginary point, a sort of narrative centre of gravity. The information that reaches the nervous system is subject to a continuous “editorial revision”. Only the end product of these various interpretative processes becomes part of our experience, but these processes are not assessed by a chief reviewer. A content becomes conscious if and when it becomes part of a temporarily dominant activity in the cerebral cortex, the so-called ‘dominant focus’ (Dennet & Kinsbourne, 1992). 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 In later work Dennett replaced the metaphor of multiple drafts with the metaphor of fame in the brain. Consciousness is like fame; it is not a special ‘medium of representation’ in the brain into which content-bearing events must be ‘transduced’ in order to become conscious. Content-bearing events in the brain achieve something a bit like fame in competition with other fame-seeking events. What a theory of consciousness needs to explain is how some relatively few contents become elevated to this power, while most others evaporate into oblivion after doing their modest deeds in the ongoing projects of the brain (Dennet, 2001, 2005). 76 77 However, “experience is the most central and manifest aspect of our mental lives, and indeed is perhaps the key explanandum in the science of mind. Because of this status as an explanandum, In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 2 Running Title 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 experience cannot be discharged like the vital spirit when a new theory comes along. Rather, it is the central fact that any theory of consciousness must explain. A theory that denies the phenomenon ‘solves’ the problem by ducking the question” (Chalmers, 1995). According to Searle (1997), you cannot disprove the existence of conscious experiences by proving that they are only an appearance disguising the underlying reality, because where consciousness is concerned the existence of the appearance is the reality. If it seems to me exactly as if I am having conscious experiences, then I am having conscious experiences. Tononi and Koch (2015) state that “consciousness exists: my experience just is. Indeed, that my experience here and now exists – it is real or actual – is the only fact I am immediately and absolutely sure of, as Descartes realized four centuries ago.” 87 88 89 90 91 However, to formulate a theory of consciousness it is not sufficient to assume that consciousness exists. What forms of consciousness that we recognize as such do we need to explain? What is the explanandum? One way of asking this question is to ask whether consciousness exists in a specific form, in order to avoid referring to “false positives”, i.e., states that are not conscious even though they exhibit some features typical of consciousness. Which aspects of consciousness are specific? 92 93 The properties most often associated with consciousness (James, 1890; Tononi and Edelman, 1998; Zeman, 2001; Edelman, 2003; Searle, 2004; Tyler, 2020) are the following: 94 - Qualitative character; 95 - Personal; subjective; in first person; 96 - Unitary: its contents are unified at any one time; 97 - Intentional; 98 - Selective, with a foreground and background; 99 - Changeable: consciousness states are always changing. In w e i v re 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 A fundamental distinction is the one between ‘Phenomenal’ Consciousness and ‘Access’ Consciousness (Block, 1995, 2005). As proposed by Block in his seminal 1995 article, phenomenal consciousness is experience; the phenomenally conscious aspect of a state is what it is like to be in that state. The mark of access consciousness, by contrast, is availability for use in reasoning, reporting and enabling rational control of action (Naccache, 2018). Some theories of consciousness claim to be about the phenomenal aspect and thus carry a distinct explanatory pretence (Signorelli, et al. 2021). It is worth noting that many conceptions of consciousness do not address this fundamental aspect. 108 109 110 111 112 113 Access consciousness can be considered a non-specific form of consciousness, as it can belong to consciousness, but also to many other non-conscious states. In this sense, access consciousness would constitute a form of unconscious information processing that is not distinguishable from what could occur in a (biological or computational) neural network (Tyler, 2020). Several conceptions of consciousness have these characteristics and many of them fall broadly within the notion of access consciousness. 114 115 116 Many fall into the trap of equating consciousness with self-consciousness – to be conscious it is only necessary to be aware of the external world (Sutherland, 1989). For centuries, consciousness coincided with our spiritual and immortal soul, so we tend to identify it with something exclusively 3 Running Title 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 human, like verbal reasoning and self-awareness in its highest forms. Aristotle distinguished between the vegetative, sensitive and intellectual soul. For a long time, only the latter was investigated by philosophers and scientists. However, scholars gradually realized that our conception of consciousness cannot ignore much simpler experiences, such as our feelings of red or pain. At the same time, the subjective nature of consciousness has become increasingly evident, so much so that Searle (2004), in order to distinguish what is conscious from what is not, used the dichotomy between subjective, or first-person, ontology and objective, or third-person, ontology. The questions relating to these aspects of consciousness have turned out to be so challenging as to deserve the definition of hard problem of consciousness (Chalmers, 1995). 126 127 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 Many theories of consciousness, as was historically the case with binding (Feldman, 2013), fail from square one precisely because they refer to something that is not specific to consciousness. Binding is the process whereby separately represented pieces of information about a single entity are brought together to be used by later processing. Clearly, a theory might explain the binding of information contents, and perhaps it might yield a more general account of the integration of information in the brain. Such a theory would be valuable, but it would tell us nothing about why the relevant contents are experienced (Chalmers, 1995). Specificity is not fulfilled in the case of the unity of consciousness either, even though this is a characteristic that almost all authors attribute to consciousness. Although there are in fact a variety of ways in which experiences can be unified (Bayne, 2009), the unity of consciousness at a single time is related to the ability to integrate information from all senses into one coherent whole. In this sense, unity can apply to different non-conscious systems. 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 The Higher Order Theory (HOT) of consciousness claims that a mere first-order representation is not sufficient for conscious experiences to arise (Brown et al., 2019). However, also a first-order state being in some ways monitored or meta-represented by a relevant higher-order representation is in no way sufficient for a state of consciousness to occur. The Global Neuronal Workspace (GNW) model (Dehaene et al., 1998) is a part of Bernard Baars’s Global Workspace model (Baars, 1997). It is a model according to which conscious access occurs when incoming information is made globally available to multiple brain systems through a network of neurons with long-range axons densely distributed in prefrontal, parieto-temporal, and cingulate cortices. The best the theory can do is to say that the information is experienced because it is globally accessible. But why should global accessibility give rise to conscious experience? The changeability of conscious experience is attributed by many authors both to the high variability of environmental stimulation and to the dynamic and complex nature of the brain processes involved in it (Edelman, 2003). Intentionality, as a quality of being directed toward an object, has often been associated with consciousness. But even a non-conscious system like an automaton can relate to something external to it. 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 Therefore, there are aspects that do belong to consciousness, but not in a specific way. If we exclude those that refer to the highest forms of consciousness, many of these non-specific conceptions can be considered necessary but not sufficient for some form of experience to exist. In the absence of specific features of consciousness, there is a risk of formulating a theory that refers to something that is compatible with the absence of consciousness. The problem becomes even more complicated when we consider that some of the non-specific aspects of consciousness are precisely the ones that eliminative materialism or consciousness denial attribute to consciousness. Dehaene (2014) equates the global availability of information which characterizes the global neural workspace hypothesis with Dennet's fame in the brain. This raises the question of how many of the existing theories are actually theories of consciousness. 161 Phenomenal consciousness exist in a specific form In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 4 Running Title 162 163 164 165 166 Conversely, the specific characteristics of consciousness can be attributed to its phenomenal aspect. Phenomenal consciousness seems to represent what is unique to consciousness, which exists exclusively in the presence of consciousness and not in other situations. Consequently, if a property such as unity undoubtedly applies to consciousness, then we should understand how the unity that manifests itself on the phenomenal level differs from other forms of unity (Wiese, 2017). 167 168 169 170 171 172 How can we characterize phenomenal consciousness? Specificity can be expressed through Nagel's formula: “an organism has conscious mental states if and only if ...”. Specificity is certainly fulfilled if one experiences something in being an organism. Thomas Nagel’s “what it is like” criterion aims to capture the subjective notion of being a conscious organism (Nagel, 1974). According to Nagel, a being is conscious just if there is “something that it is like” to be that creature, i.e., some subjective way the world seems or appears from the creature’s mental or experiential point of view. 173 174 175 176 177 A similar way of characterizing phenomenal consciousness is the notion of qualia. The qualitative aspect of the subjective sensations that characterize experience is often associated with so-called qualia. Philosophers use the term qualia to refer to the introspectively accessible, phenomenal aspects of our mental lives (Tye, 2021). The qualia of our experiences are what give each of them its characteristic “feel” and also what distinguish them from one another (Kind, 2008). 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 Qualia seem to fully meet the specificity criterion. The sheer qualitative feel of pain is a very different feature of the brain from the pattern of neuron firing that cause the pain (Searle, 1997). Certain theories can explain the problem of control, connection, integration, but not what it is like to see something as red, square, or moving from left to right (Block, 1995). One thing is to provide neurological distinctions between qualia – to say that one group of neurons is activated by blue, another by salt, another by pain – but quite another to explain how blueness as you or I experience it comes out of what our brains are doing (Jackendoff, 1990). 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 In what-it-is-likeness and in qualia the subjective aspect is fundamental. Of course, the subject is not an entity in itself, but something that acquires meaning in relation to what it experiences, to the perceived object. This also applies to qualia, which are only such if they can be experienced by a subject. The feelings of pain, pleasure, heat, sweetness are inevitably subjective. It is as if consciousness implies an inseparable link between the subject and the content of the experience. In this respect, subjectivity as a link between these two poles appears to be a fundamental aspect of consciousness. 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 However, subjectivity can also be objectified to some extent. If we break it down into its constituent elements, we can identify, for instance, knowing aspects of the self, being an agent, representing the world from a point of view, acting as a bearer of interests and values. But a camera can have a point of view. A computer that processes information is an agent, as is an automaton that performs certain behaviors in response to environmental or internal stimuli. The automaton can have values if we include goals, objectives or priorities when we program it. Self-driving cars have something comparable to values, to the extent that they can generate conflicts between different priorities. From a phenomenal perspective, the fact remains that the subject appears to be closely associated with sensations and qualia, whether simple or complex. 201 202 203 204 This is how Chalmers (1995) summarizes the issue of the definition of consciousness: “the really hard problem of consciousness is the problem of experience …. If any problem qualifies as the problem of consciousness, it is this one. In this central sense of ‘consciousness’, an organism is conscious if there is something it is like to be that organism, and a mental state is conscious if there is In w e i v re 5 Running Title 205 206 207 something it is like to be in that state. Sometimes terms such as ‘phenomenal consciousness’ and ‘qualia’ are also used here, but I find it more natural to speak of ‘conscious experience’ or simply ‘experience’.” 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 216 217 218 219 220 221 In addition to identifying the aspects of consciousness that exist in a specific sense, in order to formulate a theory of consciousness it is necessary to address the simplest possible forms of consciousness. A theory of consciousness should identify the simplest forms of phenomenal consciousness. There are several reasons for this. First of all, in any theory it is important to identify the fundamental and basic aspects of the phenomenon under study. The identification of elementary units has been a key in many fields of science and could also be a key in the field of consciousness research (Kanai and Tsuchiya, 2012). Secondly, it is necessary to identify the simplest level at which consciousness manifests itself. Edelman (2003) distinguishes between primary consciousness, which concerns sensations, images and perceptual experiences in general, and higher-order consciousness, which includes self-consciousness and language. However, the main problem is the description of primary consciousness, because higher-order consciousness emerges from processes that are already conscious. Finally, the most difficult aspects to explain seem to be the apparently less complex ones. Simple aspects such as raw sensations seem to help identify the problem of consciousness very effectively. 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 In this sense, the mystery of consciousness seems to boil down to the impossibility of explaining the fact that we experience sensations. The hard problem of consciousness is the problem of explaining how and why it is that some internal states are felt states, such as heat or pain, rather than unfelt states, as in a thermostat or a toaster (Chalmers, 1995). Perhaps the most difficult biological question of all might be how and why electrochemical neuronal activity in the brain generates subjective conscious experience such as the redness of red or the painfulness of pain (Kanai and Tsuchiya, 2012). 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 However, it is doubtful whether qualia and sensations can be regarded as the simplest phenomenal experiences. Qualia, introduced in the philosophical field, seem to be more of a conceptual abstraction than an actual phenomenal reality, especially when it is assumed that “the entire phenomenal experience at a given point in time is considered as one quale” (Kanai and Tsuchiya, 2012). As an elementary form of phenomenal consciousness, the quale is inadequate, because a certain sensation is never perceived as something that coincides with conscious experience in its entirety or that can be separated from the experience to which it belongs. Searle equates qualia with the qualitative aspect (Searle, 2004). “Conscious experiences have a qualitative aspect. There is a qualitative feel to drinking beer, which is quite different from the qualitative feel of listening to Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony. Several philosophers have found it useful to introduce a technical term to describe this qualitative aspect of consciousness. Each conscious state is a quale, because there is a certain qualitative feel to each state.” In my opinion, they are different things. The notion of qualia is coextensive with the notion of consciousness (Searle, 2004) and, in this sense, it is a conceptual artifice. In contrast, the qualitative feel can best be defined as something that characterizes a conscious experience but is not identified with it, whether we refer to simple qualitative feels or more complex ones. 245 246 247 248 249 If we use the notion of qualitative feel because it better corresponds to phenomenal reality, then it becomes clear that none of us has the experience of the quale of green, of sweetness, of pain. We perceive something green, something sweet; we perceive pain in a part of the body, and therefore in relation to it. We cannot help but perceive these sensations in relation to something. There is no evidence that by eliminating what green belongs to, it would retain those phenomenal properties or In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 6 Running Title 250 251 that it would retain phenomenal properties in general. So, is that something, i.e., the object, the simplest phenomenal experience? 252 Consciousness is physical 253 254 255 Consciousness is physical, it is material. This is apparently another assumption which we can agree with, and which should not be too problematic for those who address the problem of consciousness from a scientific point of view. 256 257 258 259 260 261 262 263 A not insignificant part of the scientific evidence on consciousness is based on the study of Neural Correlates of Consciousness (NCC) (Koch, 2004). Tracking the correlations between brain processes and states of phenomenal consciousness, such as feelings of pain, seeings of blue, hearings of trumpet sounds, is the basic method of scientific consciousness research (Polák and Marvan, 2018). This is a very promising approach which, at the very least, allows us to delimit the field of research. For example, it has enabled us to identify the cortex as the preferable field of research and to observe that the cerebellum, despite the complexity of its structure and the very large number of neurons it houses, is hardly involved in the occurrence of a subjective experience (Koch et al., 2016). 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 However, since consciousness is such a difficult issue, the nature of the relationships between neural structures and conscious experiences raises many questions. Chalmers (2000) has provided the most informative and influential definition of NCC (Owen and Guta, 2019). The Neural Correlates of Consciousness (NCC) can be defined as the minimal set of neural events jointly sufficient for a specific conscious experience – given the appropriate enabling conditions (Koch, 2004). However, when correlations are found between neural events and conscious experiences, we must consider all the following possibilities (Blackmore, 2003): 271 - neural events cause conscious experiences; 272 - conscious experiences cause neural events; 273 - something else causes both of them; 274 - neural events are conscious experiences; 275 - we have so misconstrued one or the other that none of these is true. 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 With respect to these possibilities, positions may differ (Crick and Koch, 1990; Gallotto et al., 2017); Polák and Marvan, 2018). The notion of NCC is in itself acceptable, because from a theoretical point of view it is neutral. Problems arise when the notion of correlate is associated with the notion of physical or material substrate of consciousness. What does physical substrate mean? Usually, in nature we do not seek something in the form of a substrate to justify the physical ontology of something else. None of us would wonder about the substrate of the solar system, a tectonic plate or a cell – something that exists alongside these entities and justifies their existence. I am of course referring to a “macro” level of the substrate. The fact remains that consciousness – like everything else – can be reduced to its “micro” components. We can search for the “micro” components of consciousness and expect them to provide elements of explanation for what we know at the “macro” level, but not to explain a “macro” level that coexists with consciousness and justifies its existence. The supposed substrate of consciousness, as it is currently conceived, does not concern solely a level below the observable one. It is such at both the “micro” and “macro” levels and may be to some extent independent of consciousness itself. In w e i v re 7 Running Title 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 So why do we speak of a material substrate? Because consciousness is an immaterial entity? Because it is an abstract entity, like information? No, if consciousness is an entity we have assumed to exist materially. If consciousness performs a function related to information, it is not an abstract function, but a particular way of performing it. Life is a way of ensuring the reproduction of an organism. In this sense, there may be other “material substrates” that allow this to happen. But life as we know it is a particular way of achieving this purpose. Therefore, we are not going to seek the material substrate of life, which biological phenomena as we know them have in themselves, in other entities than the phenomenon itself. 298 299 300 301 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 The neural substrate of behavior (Robie et al., 2017) is a different thing. It can be located in the brain unit that coordinates the individual actions underlying a behavior, and it can coincide with the activation of a program implemented in the neuronal network. In this case, there is a correspondence between the activated neuronal sequence and the observable behavior that has a functional role. In the case of consciousness, there could be a correspondence only if the latter is a sort of side effect of the neuronal activity, as we shall see later. Apart from the feedback it can generate, behavior has a function as output, but consciousness cannot have such a function. It would only have such a function if we accepted the idea of naive psychology that a sensory experience serves the perceiver. As Russel (1912) says, “in the presence of my table I am acquainted with the sense-data that make up the appearance of my table – its colour, shape, hardness, smoothness, etc.; all these are things of which I am immediately conscious when I am seeing and touching my table.” 309 Consciousness has a structure as such 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 How should we approach consciousness? The concept of structure can be helpful in this. If consciousness is a material entity, it must have a structure. To assume that consciousness is material is to assume that it has a structure. What is not usually taken into account is that it should have a structure as such. Many authors wonder about the structure and organization of the brain areas involved in phenomenal experience, i.e., the physical substrate. However, experience, being material, must have a structure as such. Before wondering about the structure of the brain areas involved in phenomenal experience, one should first look for the materiality of consciousness in the experience itself, i.e., what we might call the phenomenal structure. 318 319 320 321 322 323 What is the problem with attributing a physical structure to consciousness as such? The problem may be due to the fact that consciousness has a first-person ontology (Searle, 2004). The description of its structure should be in the third person and refer to something that leads to a first-person experience, whereas our knowledge about consciousness is exclusively first-person. Supposing we know some aspects of the phenomenal structure, we know them from a first-person perspective. Therefore, it is first necessary to adopt a third-person perspective. 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 Nagel argued that the purely objective study of an entity, such as the one science provides, does not allow any inference about the subjective character of being such an entity (Van Gulick, 2018). However, an objective approach may not be impossible if the third-person phenomenal structure is modelled precisely around the features of subjective experience, starting with the simplest ones. We do not expect the third-person phenomenal structure to be identical to the one we know first-person. Moreover, although consciousness is appearance, its third-person structure is not necessarily obvious and self-evident. Its nature may be counterintuitive. However, it must not only be compatible with experience, but also adhere to it in all its aspects. In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 8 Running Title 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 At a later stage we could ask ourselves how such a structure can be physically realized. We could even call the way in which this structure is physically realized a substrate. In any case, this physical realization can only be related to a phenomenal structure. The structure cannot exist in the physical substrate alone. A substrate construed in this way makes possible the third-person structure that produces the first-person phenomenal experience. This means that one step – the third-person phenomenal structure – would be missing in the perspectives usually adopted between phenomenal reality and the physical substrate. In a different sense from the one proposed here, the idea of a substrate of consciousness entails the risk of having to postulate a theory of the “double ontology” of consciousness, whereby consciousness would have a double existence: in the form we all know, devoid of structure and function – hence presumably immaterial – and in its substrate, with a structure and a function. 343 344 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 The Integrated Information Theory (IIT) is a model in which the physical substrate can be regarded as the way in which a phenomenal structure is realized (Tononi, 2004). IIT starts from the essential phenomenal properties of experience, or axioms, and infers postulates about the characteristics that are required of its physical substrate. The theory then identifies five essential properties, namely intrinsicality, composition, information, integration, and exclusion (Tononi and Koch, 2015). The physical substrate is intended as a system of connected units in a state, such as a set of active and inactive neurons in our brain. If every experience has the essential properties of being intrinsic, structured, specific, unified, and definite, its physical substrate must satisfy these properties in terms of cause-effect power. On this basis, the integrated information theory proposes an identity between a particular experience and the particular cause-effect structure specified by a physical substrate in its current state. The goal is to account in physical terms for experience as such – the causal distinctions and relations that compose it – rather than merely for how the brain represents and performs functions (Tononi et al., 2016). 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 The question for IIT is whether the properties listed by Tononi et al. (2016) are actually specific to consciousness, whether they describe its phenomenal structure. Can we say that intrinsicality, composition, information, integration, and exclusion provide a comprehensive description of phenomenal experience as an explanandum? Axioms should be essential, complete, consistent and independent (Tononi and Koch, 2015). Although Haun and Tononi (2019) state that these five essential properties are immediate, indubitable, and true of every conceivable experience, whether the current set of five axioms are truly valid, complete and independent remains open (Tononi and Koch, 2015). These properties do not seem to concern the phenomenal aspect of consciousness and therefore do not satisfy the specificity criterion (Tyler, 2020). Intrinsicality does not imply subjectivity in the phenomenal sense of the term. The identity between the phenomenal quality and the form of the cause-effect structure is not very different from the identity between the qualitative states and the vectors of neural activity proposed by Paul Churchland (1989, 1995). 368 The phenomenal structure of consciousness 369 370 371 What is the phenomenal structure of consciousness? Since it is useful to address the simplest forms of consciousness in order to formulate a theory of consciousness, we have to ask ourselves what its basic structure is, and what the simplest aspects of its phenomenal structure are. 372 373 374 375 Usually, the idea of quale is scarcely compatible with the idea of structure (Loorits, 2014). To identify consciousness with qualia is to think that conscious structure is elsewhere. When we speak of qualia, we make no distinction between the quale of red, a feeling of pain, the perceptual experience of a vintage wine, listening to Beethoven's Seventh Symphony and the awareness of one's In w e i v re 9 Running Title 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 own human condition. Perhaps because, influenced by its supposed immateriality, we do not think that consciousness can have a structure and that this structure can be more or less complex. This position is untenable if we assume that consciousness is material, and therefore has structure as such, and if we consider the different level of complexity of conscious experiences. With regard to the problem of NCC, Koch attempts to find the sufficient conditions for consciousness to exist by making reference to the quale of red as a very simple conscious experience (Koch, 2004). Of course, the experience of red is very different from the one of a sunset view experienced in a certain emotional situation, or from many other common experiences in our everyday life, which are equally complex. However, we cannot justify the different complexity of these conscious experiences only on the basis of the different complexity of their neural correlates. 386 387 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 Thinking about the structure of consciousness means thinking about it in terms of the relations between its components. One reason why qualia are considered irreducible is their supposed intrinsic nature (Dennett, 1988; de Leon, 2001; Siddharth and Menon, 2017). But this misunderstanding stems from a phenomenal simplicity of the perception of a color which, in fact, is not so simple. Let us try to replace red with black in a black-and-white world, made up of black, white and a broader or narrower range of grays. It is a simpler world, but it is to all intents and purposes a phenomenal world. In a black and white world, it becomes much more difficult to speak of the blackness of black as an intrinsic element. Black or gray is black or gray in the context of its relation to the white background, from which it differs. Dark gray is dark gray because it differs from the white background more than light gray and less than black. Black is black because it differs from white more than any shade of gray. In this sense, a certain shade is in relation both to something that is present in the field of the stimulus and to something that is outside it. 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 Another relationship is the one with the object. As we have seen above, none of us perceives the quale of green, of sweetness, of pain. We perceive something green, something sweet, we perceive pain in a part of the body and therefore in relation to it. Moreover, if the quality is inevitably the quality of something, this something is in turn always in relation to a background. In other words, a phenomenal quality cannot but belong to something, and this something cannot but belong to a background. Green belongs to the leaf, pain to the knee. In turn, the green leaf is on the tree or against the background of the sky, the painful knee is in the leg. As Merleau-Ponty (1945) points out, “at the outset of the study of perception, we find in language the notion of sensation, which seems immediate and obvious: I have a sensation of redness, of blueness, of hot or cold. It will, however, be seen that nothing could in fact be more confused, and that because they accepted it readily, traditional analyses missed the phenomenon of perception … When Gestalt theory informs us that a figure on a background is the simplest sense-given available to us, we reply that this is not a contingent characteristic of factual perception, which leaves us free, in an ideal analysis, to bring in the notion of impressions. It is the very definition of the phenomenon of perception, that without which a phenomenon cannot be said to be perception at all. The perceptual ‘something’ is always in the middle of something else, it always forms part of a ‘field’ … The pure impression is, therefore, not only undiscoverable, but also imperceptible and so inconceivable as an instant of perception”. 415 416 A qualitative feel, insofar as it relates to a perceptual ‘something’ that belongs to a ‘field’, merely adds a sensory aspect to this dyad. 417 418 419 420 It is worth noting that for gestaltists perception is not preceded by sensation, but is a primary and immediate process (Kanizsa, 1979, 1980). With respect to the perceptual situations usually studied by gestaltists, at the basis of the laws of segmentation of the visual field, the simplest one should be identified, such as seeing a shape against a homogeneous background (Todorovic, 2008). Unlike In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 10 Running Title 421 422 423 424 425 426 qualia, this very simple perceptual situation has a structure. The quality of being an object is primary because it derives exclusively from characteristics present in the stimulus. There is no need to bring anything up from memory in order to see an object against the background of something. “According to Gestalt psychology all perceptual organization depends only on autochthonous factors, that is, on factors that are all in the stimulus, thereby they do not depend on previous knowledge, expectancies, voluntary sets, intentions of the observer” (Luccio, 2011). 427 428 429 430 431 432 433 434 435 In the perception of an object against a background, we cannot ignore the role of contrast. In this respect, the relational nature of the dark shade of an object emerges even more clearly in its primary relationship with the background. Before being more or less dark, i.e., having a shade that distinguishes it from other shades, the role of a gray or black object is to contrast with a light background in order to be seen. In other words, it is to make perception possible. In this respect, it does not differ in any way from a light object, which must contrast with a dark background in order to be seen. This means that something dark, before being dark, and therefore in relation to something outside the field of the stimulus, must be perceptually “something” through its contrast with the background to which it belongs. 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 In the structure of the stimulus, what corresponds to the relationship between an object and what surrounds it is the contrast between two concentric regions. This contrast is a precondition for perceptibility, in the sense of being able to consciously perceive something (Forti, 2015). Thus, the conditions for the emergence of an elementary form of phenomenal experience do not depend on the – metaphorical – turning on of the light of consciousness, but on the development of a certain kind of relationship between darkness and light. Light certainly illuminates an object in darkness, but darkness also makes something light visible. Total darkness, as well as total light, caused by the absence of a contrast between the object and what surrounds it, are incompatible with any form of consciousness, as suggested by the Ganzfeld effect (Schmidt, et al., 2020). In this sense, even the redness of red, if it coincides with the entire phenomenal experience at a given point in time, would consist in the impossibility of seeing anything. 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 The role of the relationship between subject and object in the basic phenomenal structure remains to be clarified. The question is whether this apparently obvious role (Searle, 2004; Damasio, 2010) is a fundamental aspect of this structure. If the basic aspect of consciousness is perception in its simplest forms, it appears less intimately linked to subjectivity than sensations. It is certainly true that all our conscious experiences are subjective. However, when we turn our attention to the outside world, our conscious experiences are not characterized by introspective awareness (Seager, 2002). When we become absorbed in some intense perceptual task, we are vividly conscious but, often, we may lose the sense of self (Tononi and Koch, 2008). If we hypothetically eliminated the subjective component of consciousness, the phenomenal problem of vision – about why a red triangle appears as such and it is not just a configuration eliciting a response – would still remain unsolved. The fact that a red triangle appears to us cannot be the only element accounting for its appearance and for its phenomenal ontology (Forti, 2009). It is therefore possible to temporarily set aside the problem of subjectivity. As Merleau Ponty (1945) points out, “it is the very notion of the immediate which is transformed: henceforth the immediate is no longer the impression, the object which is one with the subject, but the meaning, the structure, the spontaneous arrangement of parts.” 462 463 464 465 Being in the middle of something else could therefore be the basis for the construction of a thirdperson phenomenal structure. It should be pointed out that the perception of a figure against a background cannot be equated with the mere result of an operation like the assignment of borders, to which cognitive science attributes the choice of the object (Williford and von der Heydt, 2013). Ever In w e i v re 11 Running Title 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 since Rubin's first descriptions, it has been clear that a figure seen against the background of something has purely phenomenal characteristics. The figure has an object-like character, and there is a tendency to see the figure as positioned in front, and the ground at a further depth plane and continuing to extend behind the figure. Furthermore, the border separating the two segments is perceived as delineating the figure's shape as its contour, whereas it is irrelevant to the shape of the ground (Todorovic, 2008). On this basis, rather than with qualia and simple sensations, basic consciousness might coincide with conscious perceptibility and the structural aspect associated with it. 474 Consciousness has a function 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 Also in this case, consciousness should not only have a function, but also have it as such. Again, the concept of quale proves problematic, as it refers to the raw sensations of an experience separate from any cognitive or behavioral effects which the experience might have (Farber and Churchland, 1995; Tye, 2021). The problematic nature of qualia can also be extended to other forms of phenomenal consciousness (Block, 1995; Morsella, 2003). Another problem is the one of panpsychism. IIT takes no position on the function of experience as such – similar to physics not having anything to say about the function of mass or charge (Tononi and Koch, 2015). However, consciousness is different from mass or charge. As a biological phenomenon, it must necessarily have a function. Theoretically, also the evolutionary perspective could be compatible with the epiphenomenalism of consciousness (Halligan and Oakley, 2021). However, it is difficult to argue this when we consider the pervasiveness of experience and its centrality in mental functioning (Lindahl, 1997; Pauen, et al., 2006; Earl, 2014; Baumeister, et al., 2018). 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 It is very likely that the function of consciousness – as such – is related to information processing. This would mean that, from an evolutionary point of view, consciousness would have been selected to provide something that a Neurocomputational (NC) brain (Churchland, 1989, 1995; Churchland and Sejnowski, 1992; Piccinini and Bahar, 2013) in the broad sense is unable to do or finds very difficult to do. NC brains do not involve consciousness in their functioning (Overgaard, 2006) and they are based on serial or parallel information processing programs designed to deal with a predictable universe. This view clashes with many theories of consciousness, whereby it is a particular aspect of the NC organization that causes consciousness. 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 Moreover, such a function is difficult to conceive, since we are starting from the assumption that a processor can perform any kind of function related to information. We would have to imagine that in a biological organism there is some kind of function related to information that a NC brain finds difficult to perform and for which consciousness is more suitable. We would have to imagine that this function is performed by non-computational processes, which is even less easy to do. If the function of consciousness as such is related to information processing, and if the function performed by a non-conscious brain is computational, the function performed by consciousness can only lie within certain limits of the computational function, so it cannot be of a computational nature. 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 If a function performed by non-computational processes is difficult to conceive, a conscious function performed by computational processes of a certain kind – which most authors support – is logically untenable. Supposing that computational processes do not have significant limitations in performing the functions necessary for biological organisms, we should hypothesize that some of them give rise to conscious experiences. Assuming this is the case, it is not possible for conscious experiences generated by computational processes to perform a functional role in the same computational processes, or in computational processes of another kind. Whatever solution we try to give to the In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 12 Running Title 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 517 problem – which we may define as the double translation problem – leads us back to NC processes, which do not require a conscious nature to have a causal effect on other NC processes (Jackendoff, 1990; Bechtel, 1988; Dennett, 1991, 2018). From this point of view, consciousness may be compared to a computer screen. If there was no human user, why would a processor project an internally codified image on a screen if, in order to elaborate it further, the processor would have to translate it back to the previous format? The image on the screen helps the human user to interact with the machine, but it has no functional meaning for the actual processor operations (Forti, 2009). This would result in epiphenomenalism and in the impossibility of assigning a function to consciousness. 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 The idea of a conscious function on a non-computational basis is compatible with the empirical evidence showing that NC organization does not seem capable of explaining phenomenal experience in any way. This does not seem to be the case even if we hypothesize a more complex NC organization than the existing ones. Ultimately, this is the explanatory gap – or, at least, an explanatory gap revolving around computational and traditional brain processes. In this sense, rather than representing a hard problem, consciousness would represent a computationally unsolvable problem. 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 Accepting the assumptions that consciousness exists, is material, and has a function has an additional consequence. We can indeed assume that, if conscious functions have been selected in the course of evolution, they have been added to the NC functions, somehow integrating with them. We must therefore assume the existence of forms of interaction between conscious functions and NC functions. If we then assume that consciousness appeared before the human species, we must refer to brains far less evolved than ours, in which a consciousness-mediated function made a difference in terms of adaptive advantage. It is also reasonable to assume that the presence of consciousness stimulated additional NC functions that could only have occurred in the presence of consciousness. Consequently, the subsequent development of mental functions would have been based not on consciousness alone or on the NC brain alone, but on the integration of NC and conscious functions. It is thus on an integration between NC functions and conscious functions, rather than on a mere conscious function, that we should measure the adaptive advantage of consciousness. In more advanced organizations, this integration would occur at progressively more complex levels. 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 This poses a not insignificant methodological problem. If consciousness has a function, it is presumable that our mind and our phenomenal experience itself are an expression of this integration of conscious processes and NC processes (Morsella, 2003). It is now clear that many mental processes that we carry out, and which we considered fully conscious many years ago, have a large unconscious component. However, we do not know to what extent conscious processes and NC processes are present, nor what relationship exists between them. As mentioned above, the idea that consciousness receives the result of unconscious processes does not seem tenable, all the more so because it would deprive the idea of a conscious function of its meaning. Nor is it certain that conscious and unconscious functions can easily be separated, or that consciousness exists only at higher levels, since it is already present at the perceptual level. It is much more likely that the conscious and NC functions are closely intertwined, with the consequent difficulties that such a relationship entails. The identification of the conscious function thus entails the need to isolate it from the overall mental function, which also includes the non-conscious function. Consequently, the challenge is to disentangle the conscious processes from the non-conscious ones, again starting with the simplest ones where possible. 553 554 If the simplest aspects of perception are at the basis of the phenomenal structure, a related functional field is the one of early visual perceptual processes, which have been studied above all by gestaltists. In w e i v re 13 Running Title 555 556 557 558 559 560 561 562 In this regard, a promising distinction could be the one made by Kanizsa between primary and secondary processes (Kanizsa, 1979, 1991). As Luccio (2008) states, “usually in psychology when we speak about perception, we refer at least to two different concepts. The first meaning refers to an immediate segmentation of the field, which appears to the awareness as a plurality of distinct objects, before and independently from the attribution of any meaning. The second meaning, however, refers to the identification of such objects, with their categorization and recognition. One can note that it is the first concept, specifically visual, that Kanizsa called primary, while the second, primarily cognitive concept, he called secondary”. 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 According to Kanizsa (1985), “the formation of a visual object as an entity separate from other objects must occur before the object can be identified.” Whatever the nature of the primary process, the merit of Gestalt theory has been to identify in it something substantially different from cognitive processes. One hypothesis could be to equate what we call cognitive processes with NC – hence not conscious – processes, and to equate the primary process with a conscious process instead. In this case, such a distinction could help to identify simple functional aspects which could be a starting point to formulate future theories of consciousness. 570 Conclusion 571 I have analyzed the implications for a theory of consciousness of three basic assumptions: 572 - consciousness exists; 573 - consciousness is material; 574 - consciousness has a function. 575 As I argued, these assumptions can be reformulated as follows: 576 - consciousness exists in a specific form; 577 - consciousness has a structure as such; 578 - consciousness has a function as such. 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 Regarding existence, it is not sufficient to refute positions such as eliminative materialism or consciousness denial. By referring to non-specific forms of consciousness, many theories risk describing phenomena that exist in the absence of consciousness. If we do not refer to consciousness as such, we are likely to attribute the structure that characterizes every physical phenomenon to the physical substrate and not to the experience itself. In a similar way, the functional role must belong to consciousness as such. Otherwise, due to the double translation problem, function remains in Neurocomputational processes, with the consequence of falling back into epiphenomenalism. 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 The joint implications of these assumptions significantly restrict the field in which to identify the most suitable forms of consciousness to be investigated first. We have to set aside states that coincide with consciousness in the broad sense of access or with properties such as unity, integration, intentionality, and changeability, and to prioritize phenomenal consciousness. Of course, this does not mean, for example, that consciousness is not integrated and should not be characterized as such. Moreover, it is necessary to identify the simplest structural and functional aspects of consciousness not in qualia or in raw feelings, but in the basic phenomenal aspects of visual perception. As In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 14 Running Title 593 594 595 Merleau-Ponty (1945) points out, a figure on a background is the very definition of the phenomenon of perception, that without which a phenomenon cannot be said to be perception at all. The perceptual ‘something’ is always in the middle of something else, it is always part of a ‘field’. 596 Conflict of Interest 597 598 The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest. 599 Author Contributions 600 The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication. 601 References 602 603 Baars, B.J. (1997) In the theatre of consciousness: Global workspace theory, a rigorous scientific theory of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 4, 292–309. 604 605 Baumeister, R.F., Lau, S., Maranges, H.M., Clark, C.J. (2018) On the Necessity of Consciousness for Sophisticated Human Action. Frontiers in psychology 9:1925. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01925 606 Bayne T. (2009) Unity of consciousness. Scholarpedia 4:7414. doi: 10.4249/scholarpedia7414 607 608 Bechtel, W. (1988) Philosophy of mind. An overview for cognitive science. Hillsdale, NY: Lawrence Erlbaum. 609 Blackmore, S.J. (2003) Consciousness: An Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. 610 611 Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 18, 227-247. 612 Block, N. (2005) Two neural correlates of consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 9, 46-52. 613 614 Brown, R., Lau, H., LeDoux, J.E. (2019) Understanding the Higher-Order Approach to Consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 23, 754-768. 615 616 Chalmers, DJ. (1995) Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2, 200-219. 617 618 Chalmers, D.J. (2000) What is a neural correlate of consciousness?, in Neural Correlates of Consciousness, ed. T. Metzinger (MIT Press), 17-39. 619 620 Churchland, P.M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective. The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 621 Churchland, P.M. (1995). The engine of reason, the seat of the soul. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 622 Churchland, P.S., and Sejnowski, T.J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 623 624 Crick. F., Koch, C. (1990) Towards a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences 2, 263-275. In w e i v re 15 Running Title 625 Damasio, A. (2010) Self comes to mind: Constructing the conscious brain. Pantheon/Random House. 626 627 Dehaene, S. (2014) Consciousness and the Brain: Deciphering How the Brain Codes our Thoughts. New York: Viking Penguin. 628 629 Dehaene, S., Kerszberg, M., Changeux J.P. (1998) A neuronal model of a global workspace in effortful cognitive tasks. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 23, 754-768. 630 631 Dennett, D.C. (1988). “Quining qualia”, in Consciousness in contemporary science, eds. A.J. Marcel, and E. Bisiach (Oxford: Clarendon Press), 42-77. 632 Dennett, D.C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company. 633 Dennett, D.C. (2001) Are we explaining consciousness yet?. Cognition 79, 221-37. 634 635 Dennet, D.C. (2005). Sweet dreams. Philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 636 637 Dennett, D.C. (2018) Facing up to the hard question of consciousness. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 373: 20170342. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2017.0342 638 639 Dennett, D.C., and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) Time and the observer: the where and when of consciousness in the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15, 183-247. 640 641 Earl, B. (2014). The biological function of consciousness. Frontiers in psychology 5:697. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00697 642 643 Edelman, G.M. (2003) Naturalizing consciousness: a theoretical framework. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 100, 5520–5524. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0931349100 644 645 646 Farber, I.B., Churchland, P.S. (1995). “Consciousness and the neurosciences: philosophical and theoretical issues”, in The cognitive neurosciences, ed. M.S. Gazzaniga (Cambridge: MIT Press), 1295-306. 647 648 Feldman, J. (2013). The neural binding problem(s). Cognitive Neurodynamics 7, 1–11. doi: 10.1007/s11571-012-9219-8 649 650 Forti, B. (2009) How could phenomenal consciousness be involved in mental function? New Ideas in Psychology 27, 312-325. 651 Forti, B. (2015) What are the limits of Gestalt theory? Gestalt Theory 37, 161-188. 652 653 Gallotto, S., Sack, A.T., Schuhmann, T., de Graaf, T.A. (2017) Oscillatory Correlates of Visual Consciousness. Front. Psychol. 8:1147. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01147 654 655 Halligan, P.W., and Oakley, D.A. (2021) Giving Up on Consciousness as the Ghost in the Machine. Frontiers in psychology, 12, 571460. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2021.571460 656 657 Haun, A., and Tononi, G. (2019) Why Does Space Feel the Way it Does? Towards a Principled Account of Spatial Experience. Entropy 21:1160. doi10.3390/e21121160 658 Jackendoff, R. (1990) Consciousness and the computational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 16 Running Title 659 James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. London: MacMillan. 660 661 Jylkkä, J., and Railo, H. (2019) Consciousness as a concrete physical phenomenon. Consciousness and cognition, 74:102779. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2019.102779 662 663 Kanai, R., and Tsuchiya, N. (2012) Qualia. Curr. Biol. 22, R392–R396. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2012.03.033 664 Kanizsa, G. (1979). Organization in vision. Essays in gestalt perception. New York: Praeger. 665 Kanizsa, G. (1980). Grammatica del vedere. Bologna: Il Mulino. 666 Kanizsa, G. (1985) Seeing and thinking. Acta Psychologica 59, 23-33. 667 Kanizsa, G. (1991) Vedere e pensare. Bologna: Il Mulino. 668 Kendler, K. (2005) Toward a philosophical structure for psychiatry. Am J Psychiatry 162, 433-440. 669 670 Kind, A. (2008). “How to believe in qualia”, in The Case for Qualia, ed. E. Wright (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 285-298. 671 Koch, C. (2004). The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. Roberts & Co. 672 673 Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., Tononi, G. (2016) Neural correlates of consciousness: progress and problems. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 17, 307–321. doi:10.1038/nrn.2016.22 674 de Leon, D. (2001) The qualities of qualia. Commun. Cogn. 34, 121–138. 675 676 Lindahl, B.I. (1997) Consciousness and biological evolution. Journal of Theoretical Biology 187, 613629. 677 678 Loorits, K. (2014) Structural qualia: a solution to the hard problem of consciousness. Front. Psychol. 5, 237. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00237 679 Luccio, R. (2008) Computational Gestalts and Prägnanz. Gestalt Theory 30, 135–143. 680 Luccio, R. (2011) Gestalt Psychology and Cognitive Psychology. Humana Mente 17, 95-128. 681 Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard. 682 683 Morsella, E. (2003) The function of phenomenal states: is there progress for the “softer problem” of consciousness? Psychological Report 93, 435-440. 684 685 Naccache, L. (2018) Why and how access consciousness can account for phenomenal consciousness. Philos. Trans. R Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 373:20170357. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2017.0357. 686 Nagel, T. (1974) What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review 83, 435–450. 687 688 Overgaard, M. (2006). Consciousness studies: the view from psychology. British Journal of Psychology, 97, 425-438. In w e i v re 17 Running Title 689 690 Owen, M., and Guta, M. P. (2019). Physically Sufficient Neural Mechanisms of Consciousness. Front. Syst. Neurosci. 13:24. doi:10.3389/fnsys.2019.00024 691 692 Pauen, M., Staudacher, A., Walter, S. (2006) Epiphenomenalism: dead end or way out? Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 7-19. 693 694 Piccinini, G., and Bahar, S. (2013) Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Cognitive science, 37, 453–488. doi:10.1111/cogs.12012 695 696 Polák, M., and Marvan, T. (2018) Neural Correlates of Consciousness Meet the Theory of Identity. Frontiers in psychology 9, 1269. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01269 697 698 Robie, A.A., Hirokawa, J., Edwards, A.W., Umayam, L.A., Lee, A., Phillips, M.L., et al. (2017) Mapping the Neural Substrates of Behavior. Cell 170, 393–406. doi: 10.1016/j.cell.2017.06.032 699 Russell, B. (1912). The Problems of Philosophy. London: Williams & Norgate. 700 701 702 Schmidt, T.T., Jagannathan, N., Ljubljanac, M. Havier, A. et al (2020) The multimodal Ganzfeldinduced altered state of consciousness induces decreased thalamo-cortical coupling. Sci Rep 10:18686. doi:10.1038/s41598-020-75019-3 703 Searle, J.R. (1997) The mistery of consciousness. New York: The New York Review of Books. 704 Searle, J.R. (2004). Mind. A brief introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. 705 706 707 Siddharth, S., and Menon, S. (2017). What Does It Mean for Qualia to be Intrinsic?, in Self, Culture and Consciousness, eds. E. Menon, N. Nagaraj, V. Binoy (Singapore: Springer), doi: 10.1007/978-981-10-5777 708 709 710 Signorelli, C.M., Szczotka, J., Prentner, R. (2021) Explanatory profiles of models of consciousness towards a systematic classification. Neuroscience of Consciousness 00, 1-13. doi: 10.1093/nc/niab021. 711 712 Strawson G. (2019) A hundred years of consciousness: “a long training in absurdity”. Estudios de Filosofía 59, 9-43. doi:17533/udea.ef.n59a02 713 Sutherland, S. (1989) The International Dictionary of Psychology. New York: Crossroads Classic. 714 Todorovic, D. (2008) Gestalt principles. Scholarpedia 3:5345. doi: 10.4249/scholarpedia. 5345 715 716 Tononi, G. (2004) An information integration theory of consciousness. BMC Neurosci. 5:42. doi: 10.1186/1471-2202-5-42 717 Tononi, G., and Edelman, G.M. (1998) Consciousness and complexity. Science 282, 1846–1851. 718 719 Tononi, G., and Koch, C. (2008). The neural correlates of consciousness: an update. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1124, 239–261. doi:10.1196/annals.1440.004 720 721 Tononi, G, ad Koch, C. (2015) Consciousness: here, there and everywhere? Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 370, 1-18. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2014.0167 In w e i v re This is a provisional file, not the final typeset article 18 Running Title 722 723 Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., Koch, C. (2016) Integrated information theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 17, 450–461. doi: 10.1038/nrn.2016.44 724 Tye, M. (2021) Qualia. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2021 Edition. 725 726 Tyler, C. W. (2020) Ten Testable Properties of Consciousness. Frontiers in psychology 11:1144. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01144 727 728 Van Gulick, R. (2018) Consciousness. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2018 Edition. 729 730 Wiese, W. (2017) How to solve the problem of phenomenal unity: finding alternatives to the single state conception. Phenom. Cogn. Sci. 16, 811–836. doi: 10.1007/s11097-016-9478-7 731 732 Williford, J.R., and von der Heydt, R. (2013). Border-ownership coding. Scholarpedia journal, 8:30040. doi:10.4249/scholarpedia.30040 733 Zeman, A. (2001) Consciousness. Brain, 124, 1263-1289. In w e i v re 19