Uploaded by dogsled_dig_0w

Jeremy Bentham

advertisement
Principles of the Civil Code
Jeremy Bentham
Part 1
Objects of the Civil Law.
Chapter 1
Of Rights and Obligations.
Every thing which the legislator is called upon to distribute among the members of the 'Community, may
be reduced to two classes:
1st, Rights.
2d, Obligations.
Rights are in themselves advantages; benefits for him who enjoys them: obligations, on the other hand, are
duties; burthensome charges for him who has to fulfil them.
Rights and obligations, though distinct and opposite in their nature, are simultaneous in their origin, and
inseparable in their existence. According to the nature of things, the law cannot grant a benefit to any,
without, at the same time, imposing a burthen on some one else; or, in other words, a right cannot be
created in favour of any one, without imposing a corresponding obligation on another. In what manner is a
right of property in land conferred on me? By imposing upon every body, except myself the obligation not
to touch its produce. How is the right of commanding conferred on me? By imposing upon a district, or a
number of persons, the obligation to obey me.
The legislator ought to confer rights with pleasure, since they are in themselves a benefit; he ought to
impose obligations with repugnance, since they are in themselves an evil. In accordance with the principle
of utility, he ought never to impose a burthen but that.he may confer a benefit of a greater value.
In the same proportion as it creates obligations, the law curtails liberty: it converts into offences, acts
which would otherwise be permitted and unpunishable. The law creates an offence, either by a positive
commandment or by a prohibition.
These curtailments of liberty are inevitable. It is impossible to create rights, to impose obligations, to
protect the person, life, reputation, property, subsistence, or liberty itself, but at the expense of liberty.
But every restraint imposed upon liberty is liable to be followed by a natural feeling of pain, more or less
great, independent of an infinite variety of inconveniences and sufferings which may result from the
particular mode of this restraint. It follows, therefore, that no restraint should be imposed, no power
conferred, no coercive law sanctioned, with out a specific and satisfactory reason. There is always one
reason against every coercive law, and one reason which, were there no other, would be sufficient by
itself: it is, that such a law is restrictive of liberty. Whoever proposes a coercive law, ought to be ready to
prove, not only that there is a specific reason in favour of this law, but also that this reason is more
weighty than the general reason against every law.
The proposition, although almost self-evident, that every law is contrary to liberty, is not generally
recognised: on the contrary, the zealots of liberty, more ardent than enlightened, have made a conscience
of combating it. And how have they done it? They have perverted the language, and will not employ this
word in its common acceptation. They speak a language that belongs to no one: they say, Liberty consists
in the power of doing every thing which does not hurt another. But is this the ordinary meaning of this
word? The liberty of doing evil, is it not liberty? If it is not liberty, what is it then? and what word should
we make use of in speaking of it? Do we not say that liberty should be taken away from fools, and wicked
persons, because they abuse it?
According to this definition, then, I do not know if I have the liberty of doing or not doing any action,
until I have examined all its consequences? If it appear to me hurtful to a single individual, whether the
law permit, or even command it, I have not liberty to do it! An officer of justice would not have liberty to
punish a thief, unless he was sure such punishment would not hurt such thief! Such are the absurdities
implied in this definition.
What says unsophisticated reason? Let us seek from thence for true propositions.
The sole object of government ought to be the greatest happiness of the greatest possible number of the
community.
The happiness of an individual is greater, in proportion as his sufferings are lighter and fewer in number,
and as his enjoyments are greater and larger in number.
The care of providing for his enjoyments ought to be left almost entirely to each individual; the principal
function of government being to protect him from sufferings.
It fulfils this office by creating rights which it confers upon individuals: rights of personal security; rights
of protection for honour; rights of property; rights of receiving assistance in case of need. To these rights,
correspond offences of all classes. The law cannot create rights without creating the corresponding
obligations. It cannot create rights and obligations without creating offences. It can neither command nor
prohibit, without restraining the liberty of individuals.
The citizen, therefore, cannot acquire any right without the sacrifice of a part of his liberty. Even under a
bad government, there is no proportion between the sacrifice and the acquisition. Governments approach
to perfection, in proportion as the acquisition is greater, and the sacrifice less.
[Back to:]
Part 1, Introduction Introduction.
[Forward to:]
Part 1, Chapter 2 Distinct Objects of the Civil Law.
[Up to:]
Intro and TOC, Principles of the Civil Code
Download