2065G Evil, Suffering, and Pessimism Readings 1: - - - Metaphysical evil; evil that has to do with the way things exist or fail to exist o Absence theory: lack of an ability is evil; for example, a dog cannot stand on 2 legs. Evil is not a thing (a god). o Matter theory; Plotinus rejects – so matter is super evil? o Privation theory; Augustine says god created matter so its not evil. Combination of absence theory and idea that goodness is relevant to a things kind. As long as the dog achieves its ends set out by nature; it is fully good – even if its lower on the chain. Evil is not a being, but rather an absence, so god did not create it. o Real property theory; evil is some sort of reality – a determinate feature of certain finite beings. Evil is ultimately dependent on good. Empirical evil covers bodily pain, damage, disease, suffering, terror, depression, mental illness. Also oppression, poverty, and structural injustices. o Absence theory: as the absence of physical-psychological states of pleasure, health, stability, justice and even life. o Matter theory: pain, disease, mental malaise, and social ills as effects of our standing as material beings, vulnerable to the “matter” in our organism breaking down or coming into conflict with other parts of material creation o Privation theory:E evil is the absence of some such good which ought to exist o Real property theory: insists that pain and suffering are positive realities and not mere absences Moral evil is metaphysical or empirical evil that arises out of the acts or intentions of agents: sin, wickedness, trespass, iniquity Natural evil is metaphysical or empirical evil where the origins are nature – grounded in the natures of things and/or are the natural laws. Cancer, pandemics, earthquakes, meteor strikes, aging, (death?) o Aesthetic responses say that we don’t presently have the right perspective to see the overall beauty of the natural system, and thus that there really is no natural evil; Soul-making responses say that this present vale of natural evil is - - - justified because it gives us the chance to become virtuous; Skeptical theistic responses say that given our limited faculties we cannot reasonably expect to understand why God would allow natural evils Systemic evil exists at the level of groups, rather than the individual – governments, corporations, teams, religious institutions Symbolic evil: an object or act can have far more “symbolic” value to a certain individual than its exchange or monetary value on some market or other, typically because of its causal history To rank the will to happiness, which dominates among men’s motives, above the unconditioned law that shows itself in reason—that is the root of evil, the “propensity” which Kant calls “radical evil” Radical evil: Kant: humans are capable of committing evil acts without any external influence or motivation Lecture 1 - Modern period: 1600 to the 20th century o Early modern (1600-1800) o Late modern (1800-1900) - Metaphysis (the theory of what ultimately exists) and epistemology (the theory of what knowledge is and whether it is possible). Big topics of the modern period - Ethical systems, political philosophy, and views relating to gender or race were all huge topics in the modern period. - Susan Neiman outlined a thought in her book, being to question evil as a lens for reexamining modern philosophy - Unit 1: the case against God: theodicy and the problem of evil - Evil: any sort of harm, badness, or misfortune that happens to occur to human beings. Natural evils (natural disasters, diseases, etc) and moral evils (sin, vices, etc) - Dilemma that god doesn’t exist, or god is not the god defined as all-powerful and perfectly god. (Lactantius) o Historical responses of Christian philosophers: accept that god was limited by an opposing principle, or question the existence of evil o Evil could exist, but it is not something god created directly. Non-being or nothing, that god could have created. Evil is an absence. Our misuse of freedom in sin has brought upon a corruption in ourself and so we fall short of the perfection we once enjoyed. o These approaches only minimize evil. o Denying the existence of evil just seems naïve (or worse: sinister). The existence of evil is as undeniable as the reality of its effects—the suffering, the physical and psychological impacts that result from its occurrence o Problem of evil can never be solved… Online Lecture Week 2: - Rene Descartes: meditations on first philosophy published 1641. 1599-1650. “I think, therefore, I am” most important physicist before newton; newton argued his points. o Father of modern philosophy - o Focus on epistemological issues; questions relating to the nature and possibility of knowledge. Works on metaphysical issues too. o Mind body problem o Not very influential in the problem of evil. Method of doubt. Deceiver god hypothesis: god made me in a way that im mistaken about everything (even 2+2=4). Rejects it because its too powerful of a hypothesis. Evil genius hypothesis: a being lesser than god, but powerful enough to systematically deceive us about the truth of what our senses discose, or what we remember as being the case He does not consider whether the being’s existence might be compatable with god’s goodness th o By 4 meditation; our existence is something that we cannot doubt, and we can know that god does exist. We are responsible for our own errors. the intellect is limited (there’s only so much we can know, as finite beings), the will is unlimited in its extent—we can affirm or deny anything (or wish to do anything, or resolve to avoid anything). It’s this asymmetry that leads us into error. Were we to limit our affirmations to those propositions that are “clearly and distinctly perceived” by the intellect, then we would never make a mistake. However, our will is not bounded by our intellect, and so we frequently affirm or deny something that we don’t know to be the case o Descartes suggests that the failure to restrict the will to the boundaries of the intellect is not just responsible for my cognitive errors, but also is the source of my moral failings (sin) o Restricts the application of his account of error only to matters of “the true and false” and not to ‘matters which belong to faith and the conduct of life” o Doesn’t seem to have taken it seriously, left questions unanswered, and denies that his account of error has any relevance to moral or practical issues o .. not anymore the father when it comes to evil as central issue in modern philosophy Pierre Bayle, who is responsible for making evil a central problem of modern philosophy. 1647-1706. Wrote a variety of work. Views can be difficult to discern. o Dictionary; 1696 first ed. 1702 2nd. 4 quarto volumes. Resembles an ordinary reference work. Lecture 2 - Bayle supports manichean until he just dismisses it - Bayle wrote a dictionary by himself, 5 volumes in English. Organized alphabetically. o All entries devoted to manichaeans and their attempted explanation of the existence of evil - Bayle spent so much time arguing for this perspective until he calls it a false system. No one else at the time believed in it, so its odd he spent so much time studying it. He thinks manichaeans are absurd. - Preliminaries - - - o What does bayle understand by an explanation of the existence of evil? Looking for an account that renders the existence of evil consistent with the existence of a supremely good being o What does bayle mean by the orthodox view? A single god, whos supremely good, that’s all knowing and all powerful. But also omnipotent and omniscient o What kind of evil is bayle interested in an explanation of? Moral evil – sin or viscous behaviour. Physical evil – punishment for moral evil like suffering… god is cause of physical evil. Natural evil is different than physical evil. Natural evil is not problematic. Overview of bayles argument: elaborates complex argument over 2 articles we consider. First he argues that the orthodox explanation of the existence of evil fails. He then argues that Manichaeism succeeds where orthodox fails. He responds to various historical objections to it. Next he asserts that in spite of offering an explanation of evil, Manichaeism is manifestly false and even absurd. Finally he offers a sceptical resolution of this dilemma. Human reason is humiliated. 1. The orthodox view: some theologians deny that evil exists (anselm, Augustine). He focuses on those that accept it. Bayle says humans are morally viscous. Evil can be reconciled with gods goodness and power. Bayle tries to explain evil by: o Evil is necessary for god to manifest his wisdom Without evil god cant show his qualities. He wants us to worship him. Oppourtunity to know who god is. o Evil is necessary for god to manifest his justice and mercy o God permits evil because he cannot prevent it without infringing on human free will If people act badly with this free will, they get punishment (physical evil) – orthodox view Denies god knows what we will do with free will, because then its not freewill (socinians) It is entirely possible for god to turn humans away from evil without infringing upon freedom of will: he can influence us towards the good – tempting. Scare us from the bad. Incentives to choose right course. Given the magnitude of all the consequences of original sin, it would have been better for god to have not given human beings free will or to have infringed upon it before they acted wrongly o Rejecting orthodoxy: Bayle believes any explanation can be refuted.Orthofox theologians make two assumotions that turn to make it impossible to explain evil 1. God created humans and free will (allows humans to be evil) 2. God is supremely good, and all-powerful and all-knowing (god could have prevented evil) Bayle now allows a view that accepts a supremely good being, but rejects 1 and 2 above 2. The Manichaean hypothesis o Allows god is supremely good but denies all powerful and all knowing – two opposed supreme beings which limit eachother o Human being isn’t soley a creation of god, but also the other supreme being o Rejects old testament – denies gods creation of world/humanity - - - o Historical Manichaeism: extinct by Bayles time. Founded by Manes (Mani), flourished between 3rd and 5th centuries CE. Recognized other big religious figures. Heavily persecuted. o Bayle is only interested in the theory of evil within manichaen; not other aspects. Bayle extracts the isolated hypothesis that the origin of evil can only be explained by the assumption of two principles. Mix of good and evil requires postulation of two different original principles to explain them. o Doesn’t argue much for Manichaeism, mostly just shows how orthodox alternative falls short. o Reduction ad absurdum 5 reasons to justify having two supreme beings; one good one evil o Lactantius claims that’s its only through evil that we know good. Without evil we couldn’t know the limits to our own power. Like how true happiness is not real without sorrow. Through that knowledge we are granted immortality. With no evil, we would be deprived of proper real good Bayle views this as monstrous… points out inconsistency with other Christian doctrines. Angels cant be good without bad pasts? o Fits the experience. Better explanation than orthodox. Fills gaps where orthodox fails. 3. The manifest falsehood of Manichaeism o Believes Manichaeism is utterly false and absurd. Doesn’t believe its true, just that its better. o Should look at ancient greeks; good and bad gods. o Says manichaeans are refuted by reasons “a priori” (by considerations independent of experience) o A dilemma: A) a priori rasons to accept supreme being of perfection… but goodness not reconciled with existence of evil B) a posteriori grounds to accept Manichean; explanation of existence of evil (if evil exists, this is true and God is not) For Bayle, we know that both God exists and evil exists. Matters of facts that cannot be denied. Impasse. Cannot avoid or resolve issue in a conventional way. Only reveals the limits of human reason. 4. Bayle’s sceptical resolution (term from Hume who was likely inspired by bayle) o Rejects notion that we could ever understand the existence of god and evil. We can understand that there is a god, and there is evil, but we cannot understand how they can coexist. We know it is possible for them to exist together. o Bayle compares it to an item of faith, or religious belief, rather than knowledge… obedience of faith; never dispute about some things. Whats the problem with Bayle’s resolution? Were required to believe things irrationally. Resolution fairly optimistic: we don’t have to reject the goodness of god ven if we believe in evil. Manichaean articles highly controversial. He was taken to be so provocative… irrationality of this key belief amounted to a defense of the rationality of atheism. Is it even psychologically possible fpr us to be in this position; to hold two contradictory ideas to be true at the same time? - o Leibniz thought the canons of rationality were too high a price to pay for a resolution of the problem of ebil. So he responded to Bayle on behalf of the party of reason in the Theodicy Online lecture for next week & readings Online lecture week 3: English optimism - The optimist view: a popular line of response to Bayle’s challenge o The world as a whole is the best despite the evil. The world is morally speaking the worst; evil and bad outweighs the good – pessimist o Epistemic (knowledge) grounds: concern what we can know, and what we cant about the world and its order [english] Pope (1671-1744); Shaftesbury (1671-1713) Pope’s poetic ‘essay on man’ 1734. An attempt at theodicy; an effort to vindicate the ways of God to man Draws attention to our limited cognitive perspectives as function of our perception. What might appear disordered from the perspective of the part might be a function of an order obtaining at the level of the whole Pope thinks that even the possibility of such a grander order suffices to inspire hope in us—that in spite of disorder and evils occurring in our lives, there might nonetheless be a larger order in which these are all accounted for and gain significance in contributing to some greater end. A higher order inspires hope. o But what justification or vindication can there be for us having these limitations? More reason = more intelligent = more real : the great chain. What it is to be human is just to lack the sort of larger perspective available to greater sorts of beings. Accounting for natural evils ; disasters: mot a fault in the order of the world, but ultimately a product of it; a result of general laws willed by God Accounting for moral evils: result of an order set in place by God. Imperfect nature, being somewhere between beasts and angels. More hate on this one. We have no claim to an earthly existence of uninterrupted peace and happiness (whatever is, is right). All a part of gods plan. The very desire for things to be different (to have a world without moral evil, or to be able to have insight into the ultimate order of things) is sinfully presumptuous and unnaturall o Objections to English optimism (3) 1) what is the connection between order and right? Maybe everything in the world is as God wills it, but why does that imply its right? Objection 1: Shaftesbury’s influence: Pope can claim that “Whatever is, is right” because the world, in virtue of being ordered, is also beautiful and so, according to the Platonic equation, good, or right - 2) the invocation of epistemic limits cut both ways On what grounds are we justified thinking that in the world, an order obtains? 3) pope’s conception of a rationally ordered universe stands in tension with a traditional conception of God as providentially concerned with human affairs for Leibniz, the “metaphysical optimist,” preserving God’s personal concern for his creation is a priority and a key feature of his argument that this is the “best of all possible worlds” o Metaphysical (what is ultimately the case concerning reality) concerns: drawn from a view about the nature of reality as such (attributes of god, for instance, and what is involved in the idea of a world) [german] Leibniz’s theodicy of 1710 o Rival bayle o 1) preferace Week 3 lecture: - The occasion for the theodicy o The Theodicy represents the only book-length work Leibniz published in his lifetime, For the most part, Leibniz wrote brief, pithy essays published in learned journals (or kept to himself) and engaged in wide-ranging correspondence with leading European intellectuals o That Leibniz should be provoked to penning the Theodicy in the first place is thus already notable. As he explains, what moved him to do so was the threat he perceived in Bayle’s defense of Manichaeism. - The main aims of the theodicy o By way of forestalling these ‘dangerous conclusions,’ Leibniz seeks to respond to the problem of evil o Leibniz’s argument can be divided into two main parts (cf. sect. 1, p. 126) Explaining the existence of moral evil: that God, as supremely good, could create a world in which moral evil (human sinfulness) exists (this concerns the “conduct of God”) Providing a justification for physical evil: that the human being is appropriately held responsible (punished) for their actions o Leibniz’s discussion of the first issue constitutes his response to Bayle, proper (the first essay outlines Leibniz’s position and the second draws on it to respond to Bayle’s specific concerns). Leibniz’s answer is that this world is in fact the best of all possible, and that evil is an unavoidable part of it o That Leibniz needs to address the second issue is, to some extent, necessitated by his response to the first. In any case it allows him to engage a question he thinks is of vital importance: the “labyrinth” concerning the free and the necessary (Preface p. 55) Leibniz’s answer here is that we are justly punished for moral evils which we perpetrate since we do so freely - - - Leibniz on what he demonstrates concerning o Defends the “orthodox” conception of God (supremely good, as well as allpowerful and all-knowing) o Shows that God is not the “author” of sin, despite creating the world o Defends the “privative” nature of evil (that evil is not, strictly speaking, a thing but a kind of defect/lack) o God permits moral (and physical) evil, rather than willing it, and that this does not detract from his goodness or worthiness of worship o Free actions are not absolutely/logically/metaphysically/geometrically necessary (that is, they are genuinely contingent) o God’s choice to create the best world is not absolutely necessary, but neither is it arbitrary o Freedom of the will does not involve perfect indifference, i.e., being in a state of balance with respect to possible choices Leibniz’s vindication of the conduct of God in the existence of moral evil o Concerning the first issue (vindicating the conduct of God in the existence of moral evil), it is important to see that Leibniz’s starting point is just Bayle’s “a priori” argument o “The most certain and most clear ideas of order we have, teach us that a being, which exists by itself, which is necessary and eternal, must be one, infinite, almighty, and endowed with all kind of perfection [including goodness].” (Manichees D, 94) o That is, Leibniz begins by assuming that God is to be understood as a single, infinite principle, containing all perfections and realities (including goodness) and that he exists and created the world o While setting out from this a priori consideration of God, Leibniz offers some clarifications of key features of Bayle’s position, in line with his own metaphysical views, all of which he contends help to make the existence of evil explicable o In particular, Leibniz has a very specific understanding of what it means that “God created the world” What it means that God creates the world o The first thing to note is what Leibniz means by ‘world’: “I call ‘world’ the whole succession and the whole agglomeration of all existent things, lest it be said that several worlds could have existed in different times and different places. For they must needs be reckoned all together as one world or, if you will, as one universe” (I, sect. 8; p. 131) o So, a world: Includes all existent things; Includes everything that transpires to these things; and Leaves out nothing that exists, such that only a single world can ever exist (i.e., there cannot be two actual worlds) o Second, Leibniz has a rather distinctive conception of what God’s creation of the world amounts to o Simplified somewhat, Leibniz’s view is that what is involved in creation is that God takes one possible world and makes it actual - - o Just like any world, a possible world is one possible complete collection of existent things and that which occurs to them. One possible world is distinguished from another by what things are contained in it and/or what transpires to them (even a trivial difference serves to distinguish one world from another) o This means that an infinite number of possible worlds are conceivable. As a result, it would take a supreme intellect to survey all possible worlds and to select one to make actual Leibniz sometimes refers to the collection of all possible things/worlds as the “region of eternal verities” (see for instance sect. 20-21; pp. 138-9). His point (for our purposes) is just that God has insight, through his understanding, into all of the things that can possibly exist and what worlds they might exist in (not everything is compatible with everything else). After surveying all of the possibilities, God selects one world to make actual through his will o The question is, on what basis will God choose one among the infinitely possible worlds to make actual? The actual world is the best of all possible o The answer is that God will (necessarily) choose the best of all possible worlds to make actual “there is an infinitude of possible worlds among which God must needs have chosen the best” (I sect. 8; p. 131) o So, why does God choose the best? Because, God is supremely good. He is morally perfect and so infallibly wills what is, morally speaking, the best—moreover, because he is allknowing, he can discern what is best, and given his infinite power he can bring it about o But how do we know that there is only one among all possible worlds that is the best—couldn’t there be two or more that are equally good? Here Leibniz invokes the “principle of sufficient reason” (cf. I sect. 44; pp. 150-1), that for every thing that happens there’s a reason or cause why it was so and not otherwise. If there were to be two equally good possible worlds, there would be no reason for God to choose one rather than the other; therefore, for there to be an actual world requires one to be better: “since he does nothing without acting in accordance with supreme reason” (I sect. 8, p. 131) The explanation of moral evil o So, given all this, how does Leibniz account for the existence of moral evil in a world that is made actual by a supremely good being? o Notably, Leibniz does not deny that evil exists in the actual world (even though he thinks that metaphysically speaking it isn’t a “thing”). o Yet, Leibniz’s explanation of evil is fairly straight-forward (he sometimes characterizes this as reasoning ab effectu—from the result): God chose this world to make actual Therefore, this world is the best of all possible worlds But this world contains moral evil - - Therefore, a world that contains moral evil is better than one that does not (since God chose to make it actual) o There is, then, no mystery about the existence of evil. Given that evil exists, it must be part of the best possible world. And because it is part of the best possible world, it is hardly inconsistent with God’s supreme goodness Moreover, God does not will evil—he wills to make the best possible world actual, and it is only as a consequence of this that evil comes about, which is to say that he permits it to exist (I sect. 32; p. 129) Question: wouldn’t a world that lacked all moral evil be better than ours? o We might think, however, that a world is possible in which there is no evil whatsoever—wouldn’t that world be better than the actual one? o Leibniz’s reply is twofold. First, it’s not clear that a world without evil is possible. o In the Preface we saw that Leibniz claims that he understands evil as ‘privative,’ so as not really existing (like Augustine). At the fundamental, “metaphysical” level, Leibniz thinks that evil isn’t really a ‘thing’ but is rather just an imperfection: “Evil may be taken metaphysically, physically, and morally. Metaphysical evil consists in mere imperfection, physical evil in suffering, and moral evil in sin.” (I sect. 21; p. 139) o What Leibniz means by ‘metaphysical evil’ are the imperfections that riddle all finite beings (like us). Insofar as we are not perfect like God, we necessarily lack certain perfections, or do not have them to the degree that God does. These imperfections are the metaphysical root of moral evil o Given this, it’s not clear that any world can lack moral evil. Every world is a collection of finite beings, which is to say, beings that are imperfect in some way. Since moral evil is rooted in imperfection, every possible world will contain some amount of evil o But, secondly, even if such a world without evil is possible, Leibniz claims that it is not necessarily better: “We know, moreover, that often an evil brings forth a good whereto one would not have attained without that evil. Often indeed two evils have made one great good.” (I sect. 10; p. 132) Question: OK, but how about a world in which there is less evil than this one? o Allowing that every world will have some evil, we might nonetheless wonder whether our world wouldn’t be better without some sinful act (say a heinous crime). Couldn’t, or even shouldn’t God make our world better by removing just a single bad action? o Leibniz’s response to this is that even the slightest change to a thing or event in this world would make it into a different world: “For it must be known that all things are connected in each one of the possible worlds: […] the least movement extends its effect there to any distance whatsoever. […] Thus, if the smallest evil that comes to pass in the world were missing in it, it would no longer be this world” (I sect. 9; pp. 131-2) o So, were God to change anything in this actual world, it would be a different possible world. But if it’s different than the actual world, then it would no longer be the best - - - Question: How can this world be the best when there are more evils than good? o Here, Leibniz denies that there are more evils than good in the actual world. Instead, we just fail to attend to the good things that happen, whereas the evil draws our attention all the more, given that it is rare Question: But does this really ‘explain’ evil? o Even granting all this, it might be objected that Leibniz doesn’t really answer Bayle’s challenge in explaining the existence of moral evil. We know that it is part of the best possible world, but we don’t really understand how it contributes to the goodness of the world o Leibniz replies to this (and other aspects of Bayle’s Manichaean entries) in Essay II. Generally, Leibniz concedes that there is much we don’t understand here, but it’s not because what’s at issue is a mystery o In sect. 145, Leibniz rejects Bayle’s demand for a full “explanation of evil”—that is, Leibniz thinks that Bayle asks too much when he demands that we should be able to understand how the existence of evil is consistent with God’s goodness “I have explained it sufficiently by showing that there are cases where some disorder in the part is necessary for producing the greatest order in the whole. But it appears that Bayle asks a little too much: he wishes for a detailed exposition of how evil is connected with the best possible scheme for the universe. That would be a complete explanation of the phenomena: but I do not undertake to give it nor am I bound to do so (p. 217) o Where Bayle goes too far, according to Leibniz, is in demanding that we understand precisely how individual evils fit into the plan for this world (so that, for instance, we could see how removing them would make this world worse). Such an understanding clearly goes beyond what we are capable of—to be able to grasp the connection between all of the phenomena in this world exceeds our finite, limited capacity But that there is such a connection is not contrary to reason; rather, it is simply beyond the capacity of our reason 2. The justification of Physical evil o At this point (the end of Essay II), Leibniz thinks that he has fulfilled the principal task of his Theodicy. That is, he has vindicated the conduct of God in creating a world where moral evil exists. The actual world is the best of all possible, and whatever evil it contains must be understood only to contribute to its goodness o This would normally be sufficient to justify physical evil—that is, we suffer because we are responsible for our sin or vicious actions o However, Leibniz’s solution to Bayle’s challenge seems to come at a considerable cost. It accounts for the existence of moral evil but undermines any justification for physical evil—that is, we can explain why there is sin in the world, but we cannot explain why we should be punished for it o This is because responsibility for actions requires freedom of the will, which Leibniz also accepts. Yet, on Leibniz’s view, there seems to be no room for such freedom. Leibniz’s system seems to be fully deterministic The problem arguably starts at the top, as it would seem that God himself is determined in his choice to make this world actual - - - But even at the level of individual agents (you and I), what we do is already decided in advance (as part of the best possible world), so it looks like we lack freedom, and as a result are not responsible for our actions Is gods choice absolutely necessary? o Leibniz responds to both of these concerns (the first back in Essay I and the second in Essay III) o Concerning the first, there is a sense in which God’s is determined to choose the best of all possible worlds, that is, he doesn’t have a choice about making this world actual God wouldn’t be God if he didn’t choose the best world to make actual. The morally good are those from whom we expect the right actions; that God is morally perfect just means that he would always do the right thing, without fail o But the necessity involved here is different than other sorts. That some truths are logically or metaphysically necessary (2+2=4; that something and its opposite cannot be true at the same time) is something God perceives by means of his intellect. That the actual world comes to exist is something God effects by his will because he is good. So, Leibniz will say, that God is morally necessitated, rather than logically or metaphysically necessitated to do the best Are all events in the world necessary? o Leibniz thinks that this has important implications for the modal status of what takes place in the actual world, namely, that they are necessary in some sense but not determined o Here, Leibniz draws a distinction between two types of necessity: absolute and hypothetical “Yet supposing that God foresees [some event], it is necessary that it come to pass; this is, the consequence is necessary […]. This is what is termed hypothetical necessity. But our concern is not this necessity: it is an absolute necessity that is required to be able to say that an action is necessary, that it is not contingent” (I sect. 37; p. 147) o Leibniz understands hypothetical, or conditional necessity as the necessity of some event given that something else has happened. All the events in the actual world are hypothetically or conditionally necessary—they come to pass because God has chosen to make this world actual Yet, this falls short of making events in this world absolutely necessary— such necessity would require that other worlds were not even possible (or, that something that occurs occurs in all possible worlds). But that is not the case—other worlds were possible, it was God’s goodness that led him to choose this one o That events in this world should be determined would mean, for Leibniz, that they are absolutely necessary, but we’ve seen that this is not the case But how is human freedom possible? o Even allowing that events in this world are hypothetically necessary, this only seems to concede that human beings are not really free. And if that’s the case, we are not responsible for moral evil and should not suffer physical evil as a result - - o But Leibniz thinks that human freedom is not at all inconsistent with hypothetical necessity o To see why, we can consider Leibniz’s account of freedom, which he summarizes at III sect. 288; p. 306: “I have shown that freedom, according to the definition required in the schools of theology, consists in [1] intelligence, which involves a clear knowledge of the object of deliberation, in [2] spontaneity, whereby we determine, and in [3] contingency, that is, in the exclusion of logical or metaphysical necessity Leibniz on freedom o For Leibniz, a free action requires: 1. Intelligence, or (distinct) knowledge of what we are doing—that is, we are not ignorant of what we do or of its likely consequences (III sect. 289) 2. Spontaneity, or (minimally) that the action is voluntary—that is, “our actions and our wills depend entirely on us,” or, we do the action without being coerced (III sect. 290, 301) Note that this already distinguishes Leibniz’s view on freedom from a view that takes free action to involve indifference. For some (Descartes, for instance), freedom consists in a kind of balance of the will—a state of equipoise between two (or more) alternative courses of action. Leibniz, for a variety of reasons (cf. I sect. 35; p. 146, III sect. 303; p. 314), thinks that this is impossible—we are always inclined towards one course of action over another, and our spontaneity consists in our ability to choose in accordance with that preference (and not in our capacity to choose contrary to it) 3. Contingency, or that an action is not absolutely necessary Leibniz on contingency o Leibniz has already shown that our actions are contingent in the sense of not being absolutely necessary o God’s choice to make this world actual was not absolutely necessary but only hypothetically or conditionally necessary since it was the result of his moral goodness o That an action could be contingent but still necessary (albeit hypothetically) is admittedly a bit counter-intuitive. But there’s another way to consider it that might make it easier to grasp o Another way of understanding a free (and so contingent) action is that it is an action for which we could have done otherwise. Our choice to do X is free provided that it was also possible for us to do not-X o Leibniz thinks that his view allows for actions to be free in this sense. That is, for all free actions Leibniz thinks that the opposite is possible For every action that we perform in the actual world, there is a conceivable possible world in which that act does not take place—in which we do not perform that act. So, Leibniz can say that for any act, X, the opposite of that action was also possible in virtue of being part of another possible world, even if that act was (hypothetically) necessary in the actual world - o Putting this all together, for Leibniz a free action involves a knowing, voluntary choice in favour of our preference, but where the opposite remains possible Astra inclinant, non necessitant—the stars incline without necessitating (I sect. 43; p. 150) The justification of moral and physical evil o With this, Leibniz concludes that physical evil (suffering) is justified as a punishment for moral evil, since we freely will moral evil: “Now since it is henceforth permitted to have recourse to the misuse of free will, and to evil will, in order to account for other evils […] [n]ow we can seek with confidence the origin of evil in the freedom of creatures (III 273, p. 298) o So, summing everything up: The existence of moral evil is explained because it is part of the best of all possible worlds and God, because he is good, wills that the best world of all becomes actual Physical evil is justified because moral evil, in spite of being hypothetically necessary, is freely willed by the human being, and so we rightfully suffer as a result Week 4 lecture: - Cugoano’s thoughts and sentiments - Biography o Not much is known about the life of Cugoano. Many of the available details of his early life are provided in his own account of his abduction o He was born around 1757—this is suggested by his attestation that he was around 13 years old when he was abducted in 1770 o His full given name at birth was Quobna Ottobah (sometimes spelled ‘Ottobouh’) Cugoano. (After his baptism in England he took the name ‘John Stuart’) o He was born in Agimaque (Ajumako) in present-day Ghana - Early life o According to Cugoano’s account, after the death of the tribal chief, and succession by his father’s nephew, Cugoano (around 10 years old) became part of the household of the new chief o After a couple of years, he was called for by his uncle who lived “a considerable distance from Agimaque” o Cugoano resided with his uncle, and came to know his “hundreds of relations”— other children who were members of the extended family o It was while Cugoano was playing in the woods “gathering fruit and catching birds” that he was abducted—apparently on the pretence of having ventured too far into the woods, “several ruffians came upon us suddenly and said we had committed a fault against their lord, and we must go and answer for it ourselves before him” - Abduction and slavery o The “ruffians” were Africans, apparently of the same wider tribe (the Fante, or Akan people) as Cugoano (since he understood their language) - - - o “I must own, to the shame of my own countrymen, that I was first kidnapped and betrayed by some of my own complexion […] but if there were no buyers, there would be no sellers” o After threatening the children with violence, they began a week-long journey to the coast, at first with the original captors, and then those they turned the children over to (whose language Cugoano did not understand). A variety of pretences were made for the delay in reaching the ‘lord’ o Eventually, the children reached one of the European forts on the coasts, where Cugoano saw white people for the first time: “Next day we travelled on and in the evening came to a town, where I saw several white people which made me afraid they would eat me, according to our notions as children in the inland part of the country” o Soon, all pretence was dropped as Cugoano was abandoned by his captors and imprisoned for three days until he was put on a ship. He, along with many other abductees, were taken first to the Cape Coast, and then made the long sailing to Grenada, a British colony that was an increasingly important destination for African slaves From Grenada to London England o In a note added to a later edition of the Thoughts and Sentiments, Cugoano reports that he spent “nine or ten months in the slave-gang at Grenada, and about one year at different places in the West-Indies” o In 1772 (at around 15 years old), Cugoano was purchased by Alexander Campbell, a Scottish planation owner, who took him in his household and brought him back to England. There, Cugoano secured his freedom (while chattel slavery was not formally abolished in the British Empire until 1807, it was never recognized as a legal institution in Britain itself—cf. the Somersett case of 1772) o In 1773, in London, Cugoano was baptized—he was advised that baptized Africans could not be re-taken as slaves, and he harboured a desire to return to Ghana and reunite with his family o Cugoano could not arrange secure passage, however, and remained in England. In 1784, he was hired as a servant by the painter Richard Cosway Abolitionist activity and death? o Cugoano became active as an abolitionist around this time. Along with other Black former slaves (especially Olaudah Equiano) living in London, he founded the group the Sons of Africa. In connection with this group, he was involved in a variety of activities advocating the immediate end of chattel slavery, and was connected with other prominent abolitionist groups o Along with his activism, he published his Thoughts and Sentiments on the Evil and Wicked Traffic of the Slavery and Commerce of the Human Species in London in 1787. A slightly abridged version, with a new preface, was published in 1791 o While Cugoano evidently had a variety of plans relating to assisting the community of impoverished Black people living in London, no more is heard of him after 1791 Cugoano’s thoughts and sentiments - o Cugoano’s Thoughts and Sentiments is fairly lengthy, running to almost 150 pages in the original (I’ve been fairly selective in the version supplied) o In many ways, it resembles a couple of other sorts of treatises on the topic of slavery. It is, in part, a slave narrative—a genre of text where a former slave recounts the ordeals of their captivity. But it is also an abolitionist text, that is, a treatise that argues against the legality/morality/permissibility of the institution of chattel slavery The latter texts took various forms (form pamphlets to full treatises) and often, as in Cugoano’s case, were written in response to a treatise that had made a case for the institution of slavery as part of an ongoing public discussion Cursory Remarks upon the Rev’d Mr. Ramsay’s Essay on the Treatment and Conversion of African Slaves in the Sugar Colonies (1785, by James Tobin, an English born planter, and pro-slavery activist) o Cugoano’s text is thus fairly distinct in its genre. But also in the case it makes for abolition, I think Cugoano’s treatise is quite original So, we find the expected sort of arguments against the justifications (cultural, moral, biological) offered for slavery (and we’ll look at instances of these). But Cugoano presses further than this, diagnosing a prevailing and deadly ‘insensibility’ to the evils of slavery, and suggesting that one of the causes that has contributed to it is philosophical optimism Rebutting the specious pretence o Aside from these points, Cugoano also disputes the ‘facts’ as asserted by the advocate for slavery—he denies that Africans as a people are ignorant, unsociable and dispersed, or that they don’t think it a crime to sell another o Concerning their alleged ignorance, Cuguano points out that while it may be the case that some slaves (as he did) benefit from access to European science and technology, this is hardly the intention of those who force them into slavery; moreover, they also gain exposure to the corruption on the part of professed Christians, which leaves them more prone to lie and deceive “But amongst those who get their liberty, like all other ignorant men, [they] are generally more corrupt in their morals than they possibly could have been amongst their own people in Africa” (22) o As to being ‘dispersed and unsociable,’ Cugoano claims that this rests on a kind of cultural chauvinism—much of Africa is divided into “kingdoms and principalities” just like Europe, and that there is conflict between them is hardly different (25); moreover, the conflict among the tribes is in many cases fomented by Europeans (27) o Finally, Cugoano denies that Africans are somehow disposed to sell others, even their immediate family, into slavery Cugoano was, of course, abducted by his own tribesmen; however, Cugoano claims that the Europeans have “beguiled” them and that they did not know what they were selling them into (26) He notes that while there is a practice of enslaving prisoners of war among African nations, this is only temporary and a condition that bears no comparison to the treatment of slaves in the West Indies (25) - - - He also points out that obviously Africans have the same natural attachment to their kin as Europeans do (27-8) A scriptural defense? o Having rebutted the pretence, Cugoano turns to an alleged Scriptural ground for the enslavement of African people: “the supporters and favourers of slavery make other things a pretence and an excuse in their own defense: such as that they find it was admitted under the Divine institution by Moses” (29) o This is an apparent reference to the story of the Curse of Ham in Genesis 9:20-7, where Noah’s younger son Ham views his father’s nakedness and upon awaking and finding out what Ham had done, he curses his descendents with the condition of slavery o This story was taken by some as a Scriptural justification of the enslavement of Africans since it was popularly thought that the curse rendered Ham’s skin black. o Cugoano disputes this “inconsistent and diabolical use of the sacred writings.” As he stresses, whatever the result of the curse, the sons of Ham were still human beings, descended from the original couple, and a disputed interpretation of a Biblical passage cannot obscure what the light of reason reveals: “that no man ought to enslave another” (30) A side-note on polygenism o In response to the alleged Scriptural basis for slavery, Cugoano asserts: “That all mankind did spring from one original and that there are no different species among men” (30) o The claim that there were difference species of human beings was a fairly novel one. Some philosophers, drawing on recent ‘scientific’ discoveries had claimed that the morphological differences (largely in skin colour, but sometimes in skull size and shape) between different populations were evidence that there were different species (or races) of human beings “The Albinos and the Darians—the first originally of Africa, and the second of the middle of America—are as different from us as from the negroes. There are yellow, red, and gray races. We have already seen that all the Americans are without beards or hair on their bodies, except the head and eyebrows. All are equally men, but only as a fir, an oak, and a pear tree are equally trees; the pear tree comes not from the fir, nor the fir from the oak.” (Voltaire, Philosophical Dictionary “Different Races of Men”) o That the different races of human beings amounted to different species is known as the hypothesis of polygenesis (as opposed to ‘monogenesis’—that the human races are included within a single species) o Combined with certain claims about the distribution of various psychological and behavioural traits (intellectual, moral, etc.) among the different races, polygenism became a powerful (pseudo-)scientific basis for modern racism Cugoano on ‘Insensibility’ o In addition to rebutting the arguments of slavery advocates, Cugoano diagnoses a prevalent and profoundly disturbing ‘insensibility’ among modern Europeans o o o o “But such is the insensibility of men, when their own craft of gain is advanced by the slavery and oppression of others, that after all the laudable exertions of the truly virtuous and humane […] we find the principles of justice and equity not only opposed […] but that unlawful traffic […] still carried on with as great assiduity as ever” (20-1) “They that can stand and look on and behold no evil in the infamous traffic of slavery must be sunk to a wonderful degree of insensibility” (589) “it is moreover evident that the whole or any part of that iniquitous traffic of slavery can no where or in any degree be admitted but among those who must eventually resign their own claim to any degree of sensibility and humanity for that of barbarians and ruffians” (3) For Cugoano, insensibility amounts to a literal lack of sense or the ability to perceive what is present to us. In this case, it refers to a blindness to the evils of, and associated with, slavery Most obviously, those directly involved in the traffic of human beings are evidently blind to the wrongfulness of what they do “for the ensnaring of others and taking away their liberty by slavery and oppression, is the worst kind of robbery, as most opposite to every precept and injunction of Divine Law” (4) Further, those involved in “the whole business of slavery” (23)—from the operators of the forts, those (merchants) who profit from it indirectly (via the “triangular trade”), to the aristocracy and nobility who are best positioned to perceive (and rectify) the evil but instead ignore it “their forts and factories are the avowed dens of thieves for robbers, plunderers and depredators” (27) “if they can only prosper themselves, they care nothing about the miserable situation of others; and hence it is that even those who are elevated to high rank of power and affluence and as becoming their stations, have opportunity of extending their views afar, yet they can shut their eyes at this enormous evil of the slavery and commerce of the human species” (59; cf. also 86) Cugoano exposes this insensibility for what it is: a convenient and hypocritical blindness to the evils of slavery. It is only through this insensibility that those who have a stake in the slave trade can avoid the otherwise glaring contradiction of their actions with their professed moral values “No man will ever rob another unless he be a villain; nor will any nation or people ever enslave and oppress others unless themselves be base and wicked men, and who act and do contrary and against every duty in Christianity” (86; cf. also 59) “Every man of any sensibility, whether he be a Christian or an heathen, if he has any discernment of at all must think that for any man or any class of men to deal with their fellow creatures as beasts of the field […] are the greatest villains in the world” (24) - - - o But Cugoano is also interested in how this insensibility comes about—how is it that those involved in the slave trade can ignore the evils when one, literally, need only open one’s eyes to see them? o There’s no question that excessive greed, or avarice, is the culprit in some cases, as Cugoano often points out. But for most, even giving full scope to their greed would not lead them to oppress and abuse their fellow human beings. For them, this is possible only because this insensibility dulls their instinctive resistance to a practice so abhorrent o So the question remains—what brings about or promotes this insensibility? Philosophical optimism and slavery o Cugoano doesn’t provide an answer to this important question in so many words. And indeed, the explanation of such an unusual phenomenon is likely quite complex o However, one of the culprits that is suggested by Cugoano’s discussion, odd as it may sound, is philosophical optimism o This is not to say that optimistic thinkers necessarily held pro-slavery positions (Leibniz did not, as far as we can tell; Pope was invested in the South Sea Company, which was involved in the slave trade, but had also mildly denounced slavery in his poem “Windsor Forest”) o But some advocates of slavery drew on optimistic positions to argue that the practice of slavery is justified. The cursory remarker o Just such a justification is offered by Tobin, the author of the Cursory Remarks to which Cugoano’s text is intended as a response. Here’s Tobin: “I shall therefore content myself with observing that after all which has been produced on so fruitful and interesting a theme, slavery may perhaps be considered as one of those evils which, like pain, sickness, poverty, etc. were originally interwoven into the constitution of the present world, for purposes wholly unknown to its short-sighted inhabitants” (Cursory Remarks, p. 7) o Tobin’s audacious point is that slavery, like any other evil in the world, is part of the order willed by God. Thus, while it might appear to us “short-sighted” human beings that the institution of slavery is a terrible evil, it is actually part of a grander plan that tends to the goodness of all o As Tobin continues, to abolish the institution of slavery would be akin to upsetting the order of things willed by God: “that an African […] will enjoy the heartfelt triumph of seeing half a score white slaves crouching abjectly at his feet […] will undoubtedly furnish a new and pleasant compartment to that well known […] print called ‘The world turned upside-down’ (p. 22) The problem(s) with optimism o That the resources of optimism might be put to use in the justification of an institution as evil as slavery is hardly surprising o Indeed, it is not even clear that it amounts to an obvious misuse of those resources—after all, the optimist holds that “whatever is, is right”; and that this o o o o o o o o world which contains the institution of slavery is the best of all possible as it was chosen by God Cugoano offers a response to this attempted optimistic justification of slavery. So, he contends that the enormous and atrocious ills of slavery, properly accounted, can only outweigh any alleged goods that may accidentally come of it: “some [slaves] indeed may fall into better hands, and meet with some commiseration and better treatment than others, and a few may become free, and get themselves liberated from that cruel and galling yoke of bondage; but what are these to the whole, even hundreds of thousands, held and perpetrated in all the prevalent and intolerable calamities of that state of bondage and exile. The emancipation of a few […] cannot make that horrible traffic one bit the less criminal. For according to the methods of procuring slaves in Africa, there must be great robberies and murders committed before any emancipation can take place” “This must evidence that the whole of that base traffic is an enormous and wicked thing” (96-7) So Cugoano clearly thinks the optimistic position is untenable in the face of the profound moral evils of slavery But I think his worries about optimism go even deeper, as it also contributes to that insensibility that enables so many to engage in and perpetuate the institution The problem with philosophical optimism, as implied by Cugoano, is that it invites us to deny the fact of evil. When confronted with some circumstance which we might immediately recognize as wrong/bad/evil, the optimist will interject to say that what we perceive as an evil, in accordance with our own limited intellects, is actually a good from the perspective of the whole Cugoano denies that any amount goodness from the perspective of the whole could suffice to balance out the evils of slavery, as we have seen. But he also thinks that the optimistic view encourages a kind of insensibility to evil—a weakening, even deadening of our natural moral instincts or reactive attitudes towards evil acts “The prohibitions against [slavery and associated actions] are so strong, that in order to break through and to commit the most notorious and flagrant crimes with impunity, [the defenders of slavery] are obliged to oil their poisonous pretences with various perversions […] that the acrimonious points of the arsenic may be swallowed down the better and the evil effects of their crimes appear the less” (55) The point, then, is that for Cugoano, optimism is one of these “perversions” that “oils” the pretences—i.e., it weakens our immediate sense of the wrongs of slavery and makes one more receptive to the sham justifications (in Scripture, alleged cultural differences, race-based explanations) that are offered in defense of the institution In this way, the defender of slavery makes use of the optimistic denial of the truth of our immediate apprehension of the fact of some evil to bring about a general state of insensibility about the manifold harms of slavery The result is that the greed and corruption on the part of many is given full scope to act, in spite of their practices standing in glaring opposition to their (professed) moral values o It makes sense, then, that one of Cugoano’s aim in the Thoughts and Sentiments is to make vividly clear for all the evils of slavery, against the optimisticallyinspired rationalizations of its defenders. The point is to puncture the insensibility that stands in the way of recognizing it for what it is, and consequently abolishing it “this enormous iniquity is not conjecture but an obvious fact […] The very nature of that wickedness of enslaving men is such that, were the traffic […] a thousand times less than it is, it would be what no righteous nation would admit of for the sake of any gain whatsoever” (98-9) Online Lecture 4: - Introduction to English optimism - Responses to Bayle’s challenge o Even if few philosophers accepted Bayle’s own (apparent) response to the problem, Bayle succeeded in putting the problem of evil front-and-centre for modern philosophy o Indeed, the challenge was taken up beyond the relatively narrow confines of (selfidentifying) philosophers. The issue was not only taken up in dusty academic treatises, but also in (relatively) lively literary and dramatic works (including, as we’ll see by figures like Alexander Pope and Voltaire) o One popular line of response to Bayle’s challenge is the optimist view - Philosophical optimism o In ordinary usage, ‘optimism’ denotes an attitude of hopefulness, or cheerfulness in the face of some adversity (we tend, I think, not to call someone optimistic when they are cheeful in situations where things are generally going well) o The philosophical sense of optimism draws on this, albeit optimism in this sense is not (necessarily) a personal attitude but a kind of overarching belief or commitment—the (philosophical) optimist claims, broadly, that the world as a whole is morally speaking the best in spite of the evil that takes place within it (from Latin optimus—’the best’) o The counterpart to the philosophical optimist is the philosophical pessimist who claims that this world is in fact, morally speaking, the worst (or at least that evil/badness outweighs whatever good is in it) o (An old joke) What's the difference between a pessimist and an optimist? The pessimist says, "It can't possibly get any worse than this." The optimist says, "Of course it can!" - Varieties of (arguments for) optimism o In this course, we’re going to consider two kinds of optimism (or rather, two arguments for a philosophically optimistic position). o The first presents a case for optimism based primarily on epistemic grounds (‘epistemic,’ from the Greek episteme—knowledge). These grounds concern what we can know, and what we can’t, about the world and its order - - - We could call this ‘epistemic’ optimism, but I’ll refer to it as ‘English optimism’ since the proponents of this view that we’ll consider are both Englishmen. (Alternatively, we could note that this constitutes an a posteriori argument for optimism—one that draws on what is known from experience) o The second draws the optimistic conclusion from a set of metaphysical claims (that is, claims about what is ultimately the case concerning reality). While epistemic considerations play a limited role in such an argument (the boundaries of what humans can know about the world is acknowledged), the prevailing considerations are drawn from a view about the nature of “reality as such” (the attributes of God, for instance, and what is involved in the idea of a world) We could likewise call this ‘metaphysical’ optimism or, sticking with the geographical theme, ‘German optimism’ since the principal proponent of the view is G. W. Leibniz, a German philosopher. (Notably, the argument Leibniz offers is a priori--it does not draw on what is only knowable through experience—and this is likely because it is explicitly crafted to respond to Bayle’s challenge) English optimism o The two English optimists we’ll consider are Alexander Pope and Anthony Ashley Cooper (Earl of Shaftesbury) o Pope (1699-1744); Shaftesbury (1671-1713) o Pope might be familiar as a famous (and highly quotable) poet; Shaftesbury was a well-known English philosopher (John Locke was his childhood tutor) o Pope’s poetic “Essay on Man” was published in 1734; however, it is thought that Pope borrows heavily from Shaftesbury’s views, as expressed in a philosophical dialogue, “The Moralists,” originally published in 1709 Pope’s essay on man as theodicy o We won’t be considering Pope’s famous essay as a literary text, but rather considering the case for optimism that it advances o First, we should note that Pope is quite explicit about the intent of the essay. It is an attempt at theodicy, which means, in Pope’s phrasing, an effort to “vindicate the ways of God to man” (line 16) This is not the first poetical attempt at theodicy—the opening stanza of John Milton’s epic “Paradise Lost” announces much the same aim: “That to the highth of this great Argument/I may assert Eternal Providence,/And justifie the wayes of God to men.” o What stands in need of justification for Pope is the apparent disorder of the world. This is evident for instance outside of us in scenes of conflict and chaos and seemingly superfluous events around us (the fact that it rains, for instance, on the ocean), but also within us in the raging of our passions and our temptations to engage in vice: [Man is] “A mighty maze! […] A Wild, where weeds and flow’rs promiscuous shoot,/Or Garden, tempting with forbidden fruit” (lines 6-8) o The challenge, then, is: why would God create a world in which such disorder seems to run rampant? Denying disorder - - o Pope’s answer, in brief, is that what appears to us as disorder is actually the product of order of the highest degree. We fail to recognize this fact as a result of our own (cognitive) limitations. “Say first of God above, or Man below,/What can we reason but from what we know?/Of Man what see we but his station here,/From which to reason, or to which refer?/Thro’ worlds unnumber’d tho’ the God be known,/’Tis ours to trace him only in our own” (lines 17-22) o Pope’s point is that our perception of disorder is a function of our limited perspective. Our world is but one “part” of the cosmos (the distinction between parts and wholes runs through the Essay). So, what might appear disordered from the perspective of the part might be a function of an order obtaining at the level of the whole Might compare the apparent disorder of a military attack from the perspective of the soldiers involved with that same attack considered in the context of a broader strategic objective (you might engage in a costly battle at one spot to draw the enemy away from another that you’re aiming to take) Optimism and hope o The conclusion of this argument is rather limited—Pope is not contending that such an order must, or even that it does, obtain, but only that it might “So Man[…]/Perhaps acts second to some sphere unknown,/Touches some wheel or verges to some goal;/’Tis a part we see, and not a whole” (l. 56-9) o As limited as this result is, Pope has at least worked to undermine some of the apparent evidence for the opposing position. The disorder that we experience may actually be the product of a larger order, rather than a reflection of the imperfection in our world. So simply relying on experience, as Bayle does for instance, does not decide the matter between the optimistic and non-optimistic position o Moreover, Pope thinks that even the possibility of such a grander order suffices to inspire hope in us—that in spite of disorder and evils occurring in our lives, there might nonetheless be a larger order in which these are all accounted for and gain significance in contributing to some greater end: “What future bliss, [God] gives thee not to know,/But gives that Hope to be thy blessing now./ Hope springs eternal in the human breast;/Man never is but always To be blest” (l. 93-6) An objection and responses o So, for Pope, experience does not rule out that the world is thoroughly ordered by God, and even the bare possibility that a larger order obtains is sufficient to inspire hope of better things in store for human beings. o However, this position raises (at least) one further problem that needs to be addressed. o The argument, such as it is, turns on the assumption that we, human beings, have a very limited scope to what we can know. We cannot ourselves take the “cosmic” perspective of God on the world which would reveal its deeper order and give us certainty instead of mere hope - - o But what justification or vindication can there be for us having these limitations? Couldn’t God have made us so that we weren’t limited in this way? Isn’t it worse in the end that we aren’t able to have insight into the ordered character of creation? Doesn’t this make us susceptible to all sorts of undesirable things (including despair) as a result? o A key aim of the “Essay” is to address this additional concern, and Pope outlines a complex response. His argument begins with the claim that for humans to want to have been made (much) more intelligent amounts, paradoxically, to the desire to not be human The great chain o The idea here is that God, in creating the world, brings forth the greatest diversity of things, ranging from bare inanimate matter through unintelligent animals to intelligent beings (humans, angels, etc.). o These things can further be arranged in a kind of scale of reality or being. How this abstract quality is measured is not made clear, but for Pope, things like being alive, or possessing reason makes a being more real than one that lacks these traits, and the degree to which one possesses, say, reason, can also make a difference (more reason = more real). That which has a higher degree of reality or greater dignity in existence will be higher on the scale, and that which has less, lower. “Is the great chain that draws all to agree, /And drawn supports upheld by God or thee?” (l. 32-3) “Vast chain of Being, which from God began,/Natures aethereal, human, angel, man,/Beast, bird, fish, insect! What no eye can see,/No glass can reach! From Infinite to thee” (l. 237-40) o The point, then, is that humans occupy a precise point on this scale or a specific link in this chain. Were we endowed with greater intelligence (or microscopic eyes, or wings, etc.), that would remove us from our position in the hierarchy, and leave a gap in God’s creation “Where all must full or not coherent be,/And all that rises, rise in due degree;/Then in the scale of reas’ning life, tis plain/There must be, somewhere such a rank as Man” (l. 43-6) o So, for us to wish to have insight into God’s mind in framing the world amounts to the wish to not be human. What it is to be human is just to lack the sort of larger perspective available to greater sorts of beings Accounting for natural evils o With all this in mind, Pope turns in the fifth stanza to addressing the problem of evil directly. o There he engages in a conversation with personified Pride, who takes the human being as the centre of God’s creation. In Pope’s presentation, Pride, assisted by reason, seems to takes the position that God might get off the hook for natural evils, but not for the existence of moral evil o So, Pride allows that the existence of natural evils (“When earthquakes swallow, or when tempests sweep”) can be explained through the fact that God works “not through partial but by gen’ral laws.” - - That Pride concedes that natural evils can be thus explained is perhaps a reflection of scientific advances in the period. Modern physicists, Newton foremost among them, had shown that diverse, even apparently heterogenous phenomena, like the rising of the tide and the phases of the moon, can be accounted for through universal laws and principles. That natural disasters take place, then, is not somehow a fault in the order of the world, but ultimately a product of that order, a result of general laws willed by God Accounting for moral evils o In any case, Pride finds cause to complain when it comes to the existence moral evils, that is, the fact that humans can act in sinful ways, committing terrible crimes against one another like “a Borgia or a Cataline” o Pope’s response is to deny any particular difficulty here in the case of moral evil. Instead he rejects any distinction between the two. That is, just like natural evil, moral evil is the result of an order set in place by God Whereas natural evil is a product of general laws that God wills, moral evil (sinfulness and its punishment) is the expected result of our imperfection, which imperfection is just a function of our rank or place in the order of things (the “great chain”) That we sometimes act wrongly, or sometimes desire the bad more than the good, is just a reflection of our imperfect natures, as a being somewhere between beasts and angels o In the case of both sorts of evil, then, God does will that they occur inasmuch as he wills the order that gives rise to them. But he could not will an order in creation without also willing a set of general laws and the complete diversity of beings (the entire “chain”). So assuming that an ordered creation is preferable to an un-ordered one, natural and moral evil cannot be eliminated from the world without making it worse Whatever is, is right o In the end, then, there is no “problem of evil.” The appearance of a problem is only generated when we adopt a self- or human-centred view of creation (which magnifies the importance of what occurs to us, at the expense of the universal order). To avoid feeling the sting of the problem, we simply have to accept our appropriate (subordinate) role in God’s order: “In both [cases of evil], to reason right is to submit” o Once we recognize this, we will see that we have no claim to an earthly existence of uninterrupted peace and happiness o The disorder of the world, the oscillation between moments of pleasure and pain, or bliss and misery, in our lives is just the result of a greater order in which we are only one among the many parts (and not the most distinguished one at that). To expect a life of uninterrupted happiness, of eternal cloudless skies and bountiful harvests would be to elevate ourselves to a position in the order that we simply have no right to “But ALL subsists by elemental strife;/And Passions are the elements of Life./The gen’ral ORDER, since the whole began,/Is kept in Nature, and is kept in Man” (l. 169-72) - - o Having shown that all evils, moral no less than natural, are all a part of God’s plan, Pope draws his famous conclusion at the end of the first Epistle: “And spite of Pride, in erring Reason’s spite,/One truth is clear, ‘Whatever is, is RIGHT.’” Human presumption in wanting to chage the order of things o There is (for our purposes) one final point of interest in Pope’s “Essay”: Pope goes as far as to contend that the very desire for things to be different (to have a world without moral evil, or to be able to have insight into the ultimate order of things) is sinfully presumptuous and unnatural o Pope attributes this desire to reason and a kind of selfish pride that directs it: “In Pride, in reas’ning Pride our error lies; All quit their sphere and rush into the skies” (l. 123-4). That is, we take ourselves to be the centre of Creation—that for which everything is intended—and proceed to regard the world as badly laid our to suit our ends. This is to presume to judge God’s order from the perspective of but one of his many creations o Pope thinks further that this prideful selfishness is unnatural as it is the product of European culture, education, and corruption. Strikingly, he cites as evidence of this unnaturalness the example of the (idealized) indigenous person in the pure state of nature, and the freed slave who has returned to their homeland far from European corruption: “Lo! The poor Indian, whose untutored mind/Sees God in clouds, or hears him in the wind;/His soul proud science never taught to stray/Far as the solar walk, or milky way” (l. 99-102) “Where slaves once more their native land behold/No fiends torment, no Christians thirst for gold!/To be, contents his natural desire,/He asks no angel’s wing, no seraph’s fire” (l. 106-8) Some objectives to English optimism o 1. What is the connection between Order and Right? While Pope might claim he has given us reason to think that the world is more ordered than we perceive (or at least questioned one reason to doubt this), he hasn’t given us a reason to also think that that order is also right or (morally) good. He’s shown that evils can be understood as products of order, but that doesn’t mean the system that yields them is necessarily good (for us) Another way of putting this is that we might concede that Pope has shown that everything in the world is as God wills it, but why does that imply that it’s right? o Response: shaftesbury’s influence Pope’s identification of what is (and its ordered character) with rightness, is rather elliptical. But here is where Pope, I think, is leaning particularly hard on Shaftesbury. For Shaftesbury, there is a direct connection between order, beauty, and goodness, which seems to be presupposed by Pope Keeping it brief, for Shaftesbury order is always the result of the activity of some mind, and what we take to be beautiful is the perception of the activity of some mind in some work. But like Plato, Shaftesbury identifies the beautiful with the good. He does so for slightly different reasons, - mostly because he claims that the pleasures we take in each are the same sort—they “afford contentment and satisfaction always alike and without variation or diminution” (The Moralists, 238) So, Pope can claim that “Whatever is, is right” because the world, in virtue of being ordered, is also beautiful and so, according to the Platonic equation, good, or right. o 2. The invocation of epistemic limits cut both ways Pope’s case for optimism assumes that apparent local disorder is offset or a product of an order that attains universally. It’s just our inalienable epistemic limitations that prevent us from seeing this However, this assumption is hardly uncontroversial. Pope concedes that our immediate experience is of local disorder, at least in part, so on what grounds are we justified in thinking that, in the world as a whole, outside of or beyond what we experience (and can experience), an order obtains? Of course, Pope might (and likely would) claim that it is because of our certainty in the existence of God that we can know that such an order obtains in all that he creates. Yet, this could raise the possibility of circular reasoning. Shaftesbury for his part endorses the argument from design for God’s existence—that the existence of order in the world licenses the inference to the existence of an intelligent architect. It’s not clear whether Pope endorses this, but if he did, then he would be guilty of a vicious circle. As he would claim on the one hand that we can know God exists because there’s order in the world; and on the other hand, that we can know there is order in the world because God exists o 3. Pope’s conception of a rationally ordered universe stands in tension with a traditional conception of God as providentially concerned with human affairs. Pope’s view of God might be compared to that of a (perfect) clockmaker, who designs and brings about his creation (a perfect machine) and then sets it to running and then simply leaves it be. Indeed, there seems to be little place in Pope’s divinely ordered universe for things like miracles and other interventions that are typically associated with God’s providence The denial of God’s providential concern for human beings and the rejection of miracles was associated in Pope’s time with a theological position known as deism. It’s not clear whether Pope does in fact endorse the deistic conception of God and his relation to creation. But we will see that for Leibniz, the “metaphysical optimist,” preserving God’s personal concern for his creation is a priority and a key feature of his argument that this is the “best of all possible worlds” Looking ahead to Leibniz o For our in-class meeting, we’ll be reading a fairly substantial selection from Leibniz’s Theodicy of 1710. - o Leibniz’s text is challenging to read, despite being written more-or-less in the form of a standard philosophical treatise. Like Bayle, Leibniz takes every opportunity of displaying his own erudition, with lots of names dropped, digressions on obscure points of doctrine, and plenty of Latin. Leibniz is clearly trying to rival Bayle in this regard (and he is one of the few thinkers in the early 18th century who might claim to be Bayle’s intellectual equal) o Moreover, Leibniz’s argument is made over the course of the entire book, which can make it hard to keep track of. To simplify things, I’ve tried to be very selective with the reading, cutting irrelevant passages and stitching it back together. As a result, the pdf you’ll have looks like this in many places Overview of Leibniz theodicy o By way of making the text (a little) easier to navigate, here’s an overview of the sections and their main topics: Preface (fairly standard—sets out the problem [that of evil] and outlines the main theses) “Preliminary Dissertation on the Conformity of Faith and Reason” (an introductory essay where Leibniz takes issue with Bayle’s apparent view that the claims of faith are contrary to reason—this isn’t terribly important for our purposes so it’s not included in the selections) “Essays on the Justice of God and the Freedom of Man in the Origin of Evil” (this is the main title for the remaining essays in the Theodicy, which are divided into three Parts) Part One (sect. 1-106—outlines the problem, particularly concerning God’s will as the cause of moral evil [sin/guilt]; presents the elements of Leibniz’s solution) Part Two (sect. 107-240—shows how the system presented in Part One answers Bayle’s specific objections) Part Three (sect. 241-417—turns to the origins of physical evil [suffering, especially through punishment], and traces its cause to our misuse of freedom) Appendices (among these is one I have included in the reading, but just in case it might be helpful—a “Summary of the Controversy Reduced to Formal Arguments”) Online lecture 5: - Humes dialogues concerning natural religion - The problem with optimism o Between Voltaire and Cugoano, the case against optimism seems fairly damning It is not, of course, impossible to remain an optimist while acknowledging the actuality of devastating natural evil and atrocious moral evil. Indeed, one wonders whether Leibniz might still remain unshaken in his optimism in spite of all this o Even so, acknowledging these terrible evils has the effect of removing one of the principal motives to adopt the optimistic position - - - We’ve seen that some, like Voltaire (initially) and Rousseau sought comfort in the optimistic view because it had the effect of promoting hope amid adversity But now the optimist is forced to admit that not only is horrific suffering not ruled out on the optimist view, but it is apparently quite consistent with it. Indeed, the optimistic mantra that this is the best of all possible worlds can even be (mis)used by some by way of justifying the existence and continuation of evil institutions like the transatlantic slave trade The failure of theodicy o The failure of philosophical optimism in light of these events gave rise to broader philosophical concerns about any attempts at theodicy, that is, of justifying the conduct of God in bringing about a world where evil exists o This represents a swing of the historical pendulum back to the position of Bayle. And we’ll find in the readings for this week two philosophers who provide an updated argument in favour of Bayle’s general conclusion that the existence of evil cannot be explained by setting out from the assumption of a supremely good being o Even so, while supporting Bayle’s broad conclusion in rejecting theodicy, both end up in rather different places On the one hand, Hume (who was a great admirer of Bayle) contends that the reasons for (natural) evil are rooted in facts about us and the world, the necessity of which we could never have insight into (and which should lead us to question the existence of God as such) On the other hand, Kant will make the case that the failure of all attempts at theodicy up until now only goes to show that our faith in God (and his goodness) must have its ground in morality and not in empirical observation David Hume o 1711-1776 o Published A Treatise of Human Nature, his principal work in philosophy, in 1738 (at the age of 28) o His contributions range widely over theoretical, moral, and political philosophy. Additionally, he wrote books of popular essays and a six-volume History of England o Best known for his discovery of the “problem of induction” (a challenge to the rational basis for our confidence that the future will resemble the past) o Dialogues concerning Natural Religion is one of a number of works to touch on philosophy of religion. Dialogues concerning natural religion o Hume began writing the Dialogues in 1750, only completing them in 1776 o However, because Hume (that is, the character thought to represent Hume’s views) takes a rather sceptical position regarding established religion in the Dialogues, he thought it better to suppress the text during his lifetime. In accordance with his wishes, it was published only after his death, in 1779 Hume had long been suspected of being an atheist (in the full-fledged sense of denying God’s existence and being a thoroughgoing naturalist). - - - This suspicion even cost him the chance at an academic position early in his career o As the title indicates, the Dialogues is written in the form of a dialogue. In the portions of the text we’ll be looking at, there are three characters involved: Philo—an empiricist and a sceptic, and usually taken to present Hume’s own view Cleanthes—a “natural theologian,” that is, a theistic thinker who holds that key theological truths (God’s existence, etc.) can (also) be known through reason (Bayle) Demea—a theist but who does not think that fundamental religious truths can be known by reason (sometimes identified as a mystical thinker) Dialogues part X-XI o Up until this point in the Dialogues, the discussion has focused largely on the socalled “argument from design.” This is the argument for God’s existence on the basis of the observed order in the world Just as you would infer, upon coming across a well-ordered machine (a watch), that it had some intelligent designer (a watchmaker), so on the basis of the observed order in the world we can infer some designer of sufficient power, intelligence, and goodness to bring it about o The argument is vigorously defended by Cleanthes, but Philo, Hume’s mouthpiece, raises a number of challenges to it. Philo particularly challenges the strength of the analogy: while we have experience of, say, watches and their causal origin (as human-made artifacts), we do not have experience of any other worlds nor of how they tend to come about o This leads into a discussion of the problem of evil, as the existence of evil is thought to be a further challenge to any argument for God’s existence o This discussion is broached in Part X, which we’ll return to later in the course (since it also raises broader questions about the nature and significance of suffering). For now, we’ll focus on Part XI, where Philo proceeds to challenge the basis of the theist’s attempt to establish our knowledge of God’s infinite power, wisdom, and goodness (independently of whether God might exist) Dialogues part XI o At the beginning of Part XI, then, the disputants take up the issue of what we can know about God’s attributes. o Cleanthes presents a “new theory” to Philo that resembles Bayle’s Manichaean hypothesis (and this is itself critically discussed at the conclusion of Part XI) o In any case, the presentation of this theory is just the occasion for Philo to begin a monologue where he (i.e., Hume) offers his view of what we can know about the divine attributes on the basis of our experience As opposed to the previous discussion of the design argument, which sought to prove the existence of some supreme being on the basis of observed order, the topic now discussed is what can be known about God, that is, about his nature or attributes Philo on how we (don’t) know the divine attributes o In presenting his own views on our knowledge of the divine attributes, Philo contrasts two different perspectives: one where we somehow know these - - beforehand (i.e., antecedent to any experience of the world) and that where we come to infer God’s attributes only on the basis of experience o The former corresponds to a (hypothetical) case in which we are informed about God before we have any experience of the world: “if a very limited intelligence, whom we shall suppose utterly unacquainted with the universe, were assured that it were the production of a very good, wise, and powerful Being […], he would, from his conjectures, form beforehand a different notion of it from what we find it to be from experience” (199) o Hume’s point is that were it the case that in framing our conception of God we relied on anything but experience, we might be convinced that the world was the product of a supremely good, etc. being o Moreover, assuming that we were so assured in advance, on encountering the world, replete with apparent imperfections, it is possible that we might nonetheless be convinced that all the imperfections in the world are consistent with our conception of the divine being as absolutely perfect: “Supposing now, that this person were brought into the world, still assured that it was the workmanship of such a sublime and benevolent Being; he might, perhaps, be surprised at the disappointment, but would never retract his former belief […] since such a limited intelligence must be sensible of his own blindness and ignorance” (200) Philo on how we (do) know the divine attributes o However, this is obviously not the order in which we come to frame our conceptions of God and his attributes o Instead, we first encounter the world and form impressions of its (im)perfections through our experience. It is only after that that we frame our conception of God and accommodate our conception of his attributes to our experience “But supposing, which is the real case with regard to man, that this creature is not antecedently convinced of a supreme intelligence, benevolent, and powerful, but is left to gather such a belief from the appearances of things” (200) o That this represents the “real case” concerning human knowledge of God is due, in part to Hume’s empiricism—all meaningful ideas that we have are drawn from experience—but is also just a characterization of our ordinary epistemological situation. Whatever “a priori” grounds might be offered to us regarding God’s existence and his nature, these arguments do not precede our encounters with the world and the conclusions we draw from them. It is not experience that must be squared with what reason has already discerned about God and his nature, but vice versa o In any case, Philo contends that this order and priority of experience “entirely alters the case” as far as what we can reasonably hold about the divine attributes Condemning the architect o In a parody of the design argument, Hume compares what we can know about God on the basis of the order and events in the world to what we can know about an architect on the basis of a building: - - o “[Were I to] I show you a house or palace where there was not one apartment convenient or agreeable; where the windows, doors, fires, passages stairs and the whole economy of the building were the source of noise, confusion, fatigue, darkness and the extremes of heat and could, you would certainly blame the contrivance […]. o Hume’s point is that our experience of the world is that it is in fact poorly designed to support and promote human life and well-being. There is no corner of the world where human beings can live free of cares, where securing even the necessities of life can be done without effort o Moreover, to defend God’s design by noting that a given inconvenience is required by the overall design does not satisfy us. Even if it was true, from our perspective it remains impossible to understand what necessitates some fault or why God could not have done otherwise, given the resources at his disposal o “The architect would in vain display his subtility, and prove to you that if this door or that window were altered, greater ills would ensue. What he says may be strictly true […]. But still you would assert in general that, if the architect had skill and good intentions, he might have adjusted the parts” (202) o Setting out from what our experience discloses, if we assume that God has “designed” the world for human well-being, then he has done a terrible job, and we cannot but blame him for it: o “If you find many inconveniences and deformities in the building, you will always […] condemn the architect” Hume’s Baylian conclusion o From these considerations, Hume does not reject the possibility that God exists and has the attributes (infinite goodness, power and knowledge) theologians claim of him. But he does deny that we are ever in a position to rationally infer that is the case on the basis of the evidence we have “I conclude that, however consistent the world may be, allowing certain suppositions and conjectures, with the idea of such a Deity, it can never afford us an inference concerning his existence” (203) o This is to say that, on whatever basis we might believe in God and that he has infinite attributes (a priori arguments; faith based in Scriptures), our experience will not support this and will even lead us in a direction contrary to it o This doesn’t mean that it isn’t the case that such a God exists and can be rendered consistent with what we know by experience; but it does mean that arguments from what we experience can never support it: “The consistence [i.e., consistency of God’s existence, infinite nature, and the faults in the world] is not absolutely denied, only the inference [from experience]” Humes arguments from natural evil o Hume goes on to offer another argument for a similar conclusion. Now, however, we will focus on the existence of natural evils in the world—the previous argument certainly included natural evils among the “inconveniences” in the architect’s building, but was not limited to it. Additionally, the conclusion will be that it is never rational for us to believe that God has the attributes theologians predicate of him - - o The new argument Hume offers proceeds as follows: There are four main sources of the natural evils of the world Human reason has no insight into the necessity or unavoidability of these four sources (that is, we can’t see why they must be part of creation) It thus strikes us as entirely possible that a perfectly wise, good, etc. creator could, and would, have arranged things differently Therefore, while it is possible that such a God exists, and that his nature can be rendered consistent with the necessity of these sources, human reason cannot have insight into this consistency o This argument obviously hinges on what the 4 circumstances are that give rise to natural evils in the world. We will consider each in turn, but bear in mind that the theist is committed to claiming that each of them is “necessary and unavoidable,” whereas Hume’s point is that it seems clear to us that each could be omitted from the world with little cost and great benefit The first circumstance o “There seem to be four circumstances on which depend all, or the greatest part of the ills [i.e., natural evils] that molest sensible creatures” (203) o “The first circumstance which introduces evil is that contrivance or economy of the animal creation by which pains as well as pleasures are employed to excite all creatures to action” (205) o This circumstance is that sentient beings are so constituted that they are driven to act by pleasure and by pain. That is, it is a burning sensation that moves us to put down a hot pan, or a sharp prick that moves us to remove a splinter o Hume’s point is that the use of pain seems an utterly contingent and needless way of moving us to act—why couldn’t a slight diminution in pleasure serve the same purpose? Why couldn’t the possibility of harm or a threat be communicated to us through some other means than the sensation of pain? “It seems therefore plainly possible to carry on the business of life without any pain. Why then is any animal ever rendered susceptible of such a sensation?” (205) The second circumstance o Even so, we might imagine a world filled with beings susceptible to pain and pleasure, but where circumstances never arise such that there is a painful sentiment. It might be the case, for instance, that whenever we were about to engage in some activity, or undergo something, that would yield a painful sentiment, God would intervene and ensure that the painful consequence was never experienced o Obviously, God does not do this, and Hume thinks that the fact that God opts instead to govern the world at a distance, as it were, through universal laws constitutes a further source of natural evil “But a capacity of pain would not alone produce pain, were it not for the second circumstance, viz. the conducting of the world by general laws; and this seems nowise necessary to a very perfect Being” (206) o We’ve already seen that Pope (among others) celebrates the ordering of the world through universal laws and takes this as a mark of divine wisdom. But as Pope - also admits, natural evils (sometimes disastrous) also inevitable come about as the result of God willing these laws. o While it might be simpler and more elegant that God regulates the world through a few universal laws, it nonetheless seems to us that it would be consistent with his wisdom and goodness to occasionally supplement them with particular volitions, at least in cases where it would avoid the worst miseries “A fleet whose purposes were salutary to society might always meet with a fair wind; good princes enjoy sound health and long life; persons born to power and authority be framed with good tempers and virtuous dispositions. A few such events as these, regularly and wisely conducted, would change the face of the world, and yet would no more disturb the course of nature […] than the present economy of things, where the causes are secret” (208) There might be “good reasons why Providence interposes not in this manner, but they are unknown to us” (209) The third circumstance o Here again, Hume allows that a world with beings susceptible to pain and pleasure, and regulated by universal laws could still be one in which natural evils are limited—perhaps just the odd earthquake, or the rare war upon the death of a good prince. What makes suffering more likely is the fact that these sentient beings are so poorly provided for, a circumstance that makes suffering inevitable o “If everything in the universe be conducted by general laws, and if animals be rendered susceptible of pain, it scarcely seems possible but some ill must arise in the various shocks of matter […]; but this ill would be very rare, were it not for the third circumstance, […] viz. the great frugality with which all powers and faculties are distributed to every particular being” (209) The circumstance Hume has in mind is that living beings are only minimally provided for in terms of their abilities, when it comes to survival—they have what they need to endure the elements, secure food and shelter, and defend themselves, but only just: o “Nature seems to have formed an exact calculation of the necessities of her creatures and like a rigid master has afforded them little more powers or endowments that are strictly sufficient” (210-11) Hume’s point is that this exceeding thrifty provision leaves us with little margin for error. The slightest mistake, injury, or accident can be devastating because we continually need every resource at our disposal to survive—not just to get what we need but also to secure it from those competing for the same resources o Hume thinks that this stepmotherly provision of natural capacities is hard to understand. Were we given just a slight increase—in humanity’s case, to our industriousness, or willingness to work—there would be a considerable improvement in our circumstances without making things too easy for us “it is hard that, being placed in a world so full of wants and necessities, where almost every being and element is either our foe or refuses its assistance, [that] we should also have our own temper to struggle with and - - - should be deprived of that faculty which can alone fence against these multiplied evils” (214-5) The fourth circumstance o “The fourth circumstance […] is the inaccurate workmanship of all the springs and principles of the great machine of nature.” (215) o This final circumstance is a bit peculiar but the idea is that the world seems to be ordered in a way that certain phenomena serve a precise and vital function (rain to water plants; the circulation of fluids in the body to preserve health; passions enhance our actions). However, these phenomena often fail to serve these functions or admit of excesses that are counter-purposive (rain leads to floods, or the fluids of the body fail to circulate, passions undo us) “There is nothing so advantageous in the universe but what frequently becomes pernicious” (217) o That these phenomena should permit of this excessiveness strikes us as unreasonable—why couldn’t they have been more capably regulated so that they would not exceed the boundaries beyond which they are no longer useful but harmful? Skeptical conclusion from the above o It would seem, then, that as far as we can see, the bulk of natural evils in the world could have been avoided: “Were all living creatures incapable of pain, or were the world administered by particular volitions, evil never could have found access into the universe” (217) o So what should we infer from this? Philo thinks it would be too hasty to conclude that the existence of these circumstances is inconsistent with God’s supreme goodness, wisdom, etc. Rather we have to “be more modest in our conclusions” o What does follow is that we can never claim to know the divine attributes on the basis of our experience “I am sceptic enough to allow that the bad appearances notwithstanding all my reasonings [concerning the four circumstances] may be compatible with such attributes as you suppose: but surely they can never prove these attributes” (219) o Indeed, Hume’s conclusion here is more sceptical than he lets on. It’s not just that we can’t claim to know the divine attributes on the basis of experience. More than this, Hume thinks that (repeated) experience is the only reasonable basis on which we can form beliefs, and since our experience is always of imperfections and inconveniences, it would actually also be irrational for us to hold that God is supremely good—it would be contrary to what our experience discloses even if we can’t rule it out completely Hume vs bayle o Hume’s sceptical conclusion might remind us of Bayle’s in his Manichaean articles. Well aware of this, Hume proceeds to distinguish his position from that of Bayle. Focusing on the “Manichaean hypothesis,” Hume situates it within four different, and exhaustive, hypotheses regarding the “first causes of the universe”: o that it/they are perfectly good; o that it/they are perfectly evil; o that they are both good and evil (= Manichaeism); - o that they are neither (i.e., are indifferent) o Hume agrees with Bayle that the “mixt” character of observed phenomena rules out the first two. But, against Bayle, he claims that the Manichaean hypothesis is also unsupported by experience: o “if we consider […] the perfect uniformity and agreement of the parts of the universe, we shall not discover in it any marks of the combat of a malevolent with a benevolent being” (220) o Hume points out that the Manichaean hypothesis would suggest a rather chaotic set of phenomena—a conflict between two principles would yield all sorts of inconsistent events. Instead, we experience a certain regularity in events in the world that suggests against the Manichaean position o Instead, the phenomena can be adequately explained by assuming that the first causes, whatever they are, are amoral—if it is a kind of agency, then it is simply unconcerned with the well-being of human beings (or it does not share human conceptions of good and evil) o “The true conclusion is that the original Source of all things is entirely indifferent to all these principles; and has no more regard to good above ill, than to heat above cold, or to drought above moisture, or to light above heavy” (221) o This would appear to undermine Bayle’s position—he had contended that the Manichaean hypothesis is the best supported by experience and that it was absurd, which necessitated a flight to faith. Hume’s reply is that Bayle is simply wrong about the empirical support of the hypothesis, and accordingly no irrational leap is needed Transition to kants essay on theodicy o Part XI of Hume’s Dialogues thus constitutes a considerable challenge to any attempt to “vindicate the ways of God to man” A consideration of the causes of natural evils will never be made to rhyme with God’s supreme goodness; and the hypothesis that is best supported by experience is not one that makes recourse to faith necessary but is, in fact, that the world, evils and all, has its origin in principles that lack moral qualities (and likely agency altogether) o Immanuel Kant is going to offer his own argument for the inevitable failure of attempts at theodicy, albeit with a rather different conclusion than Hume’s, in his essay “On the Miscarriage of all Philosophical Trials in Theodicy” o Kant’s essay is from late in his career, at the height of his fame. It is also quite technical and challenging to read (as all of his mature works are) o When reading, keep the following study questions in mind: 1. What are the three types of “counter-purposiveness” Kant lists at the outset (and what does each mean)? 2. What does Kant mean when he says “Job’s friends declare themselves for that system which explains all ills in the world from God’s justice”? 3. What does Kant understand by ‘truthfulness’? Week 5 lecture: - Kant on the failure of theodicy - Kant 1724-1804 – koenigsberg, Prussia o “had no life, therefore no biography” o Critique of pure reason – 1781 – revolution in metaphysics. Most popular work. o 1785 The groundwork of the metaphysics of morals, a revolutionary text in moral philosophy o 1791 on the miscarriage of all philosophical trials (more interested in religion) - Kants philosophy o Kant’s idealism: Kant argues that space and time are mere “forms of sensibility,” that is, things that are rooted in the ways in which we perceive the world (rather than things found in the world as such). This leads Kant to distinguish between the sensible world (or: the world as it appears to us) and the supersensible world (or: the world as it is in itself, i.e., independently of the ways we sense it) o Kant’s deontological ethics: Kant’s moral theory is often called deontological (from the Greek word deon [δέον] for ‘duty’). Kant thinks that the moral worth of an action does not rest in the goods/ills that are intended but in the fact that it is done solely because one wants to do what is right (or: “for the sake of duty”). Fulfilling our duty requires that we struggle against inclinations and adversity, but succeeding in this is what Kant understands by ‘virtue’ This view reflected in the moral uprightness of Job in the essay o Kant on proofs for God’s existence: Kant formulated a now-famous objection to Anselm’s ontological proof of God’s existence (summed up as: existence is not a perfection, so it is not part of our conception of God). Kant was generally sceptical of speculative proofs of God’s existence—proofs that rooted our conviction in God’s existence on some knowledge claim (like the design argument). As an alternative, Kant offered a moral ‘proof’ of God’s existence— that somehow God’s existence is implicated in a set of beliefs related to morality - Kant’s essay divides into roughly two halves. o The first (pp. 24-31) argues that all efforts at theodicy thus far have been a failure, but also tries to show that all that we can attain from such efforts is a sort of ‘negative wisdom,’ i.e., a knowledge that a theodicy is impossible The central feature of this part is a systematic classification of all previous attempts “No theodicy has, or can, ever succeed…” o The second (pp. 31-37) argues that the result of these failures need not shake our conviction in a moral order of the world—indeed, that it is even expressive of divine wisdom and moral perfection that such theodicies fail This, in any case, is the lesson Kant takes an ‘authentic’ interpretation of the Biblical Book of Job to reveal “…which is what God intends, and that’s fine.” - 1. The Tribunal of Reason - - o Kant frames his essay as a kind of tribunal, or court proceeding. God is, as it were, brought before the court and asked to justify his conduct in creating and ordering the world Kant is clear, however, that what presides over the court is human reason “The author of a theodicy agrees, therefore, that this juridical process be instituted before the tribunal of reason” o This means that the claims on the part of the “plaintiff” (the critic of God) and the “advocate” (the author of theodicy) are subject to the scrutiny of human reason— the complaints, but more importantly, the defense of God must be something comprehensible to us o This rules out some sorts of defenses of God: “[the advocate of God] cannot dismiss the complaints with a concession of the supreme wisdom of the author of the world, imposed upon the plaintiff” “he must rather attend to the objections and make comprehensible how they in no way derogate from the concept of the highest wisdom by clarifying and removing them” (24-5) o (Note, however, that Kant will himself defend a position that ‘dismisses’ objections to divine wisdom [cf. p. 31], but this is different since in doing so he doesn’t reject the authority of [practical] reason, and in any case Kant takes it to be God himself who dismisses such attempts, not human beings) 2. Kant on Theodicy o Beginning with the first half, the first thing we need to consider is what, precisely, Kant means by ‘theodicy.’ Kant understands this term in a variety of senses through the essay, and failing to distinguish them will only yield (more) confusion o Kant offers one definition at the outset: By ‘theodicy’ we understand the defense of the highest wisdom of the creator against the charge which reason brings against it for whatever is counter-purposive in the world” (p. 24) o This might appear to be just the traditional definition but a couple things are notable. First, Kant claims that what is at stake here is God’s wisdom, though what he means is God’s moral wisdom—”a will’s property of being in agreement with the highest good as the final end of all things” (p. 25n) In plainer English, by God’s ‘moral wisdom,’ Kant means his wise arrangement of events in the world to promote the morally best outcome 2. Kant on Counter-Purposiveness o Second, Kant characterizes the challenge to God’s moral wisdom in terms of the notion of counter-purposiveness. What Kant means here are events in the (sensible) world that seem contrary to any morally-wise arrangement. Moreover, these are events which we know through our experience o This is summed up in a later definition of theodicy (p. 30): by ‘theodicy’ is meant “the vindication of the moral wisdom of the world-government against the doubts raised against it on the basis of what experience of this world teaches” o A different definition is given soon after: “we cannot deny the name of ‘theodicy’ also to the mere dismissal of all objections against divine wisdom, if this - - dismissal is a divine decree” (p. 31). We’ll return to this sense later (but note for now, this is a sense of ‘theodicy’ which Kant defends in his essay) 2. 3 kinds of counter-purposiveness o As indicated, Kant argues that all efforts at theodicy thus far have failed. To make the case for this he offers a (systematic) classification of the sorts of challenges that any theodicy has to address o We’ve seen the general challenge is one of observed counter-purposiveness in the world, understood as that which cannot be consistent with (moral) wisdom o But Kant further distinguishes between three different kinds of counterpurposiveness that need to be addressed (and what aspect of our ‘moral concept’ of God they threaten): 1. Absolutely counter-purposive: something the willing of which (whether for its own sake or for the sake of something else) can never be reconciled with a wise purpose Moral evil/sin is ACP: It cannot be willed for its own sake, or even as a means to some other good (and were God to will moral evil at all, we would deny his holiness, or moral worthiness) 2. Conditionally counter-purposive: something, the willing of which is counter-purposive if willed for its own sake, but is not necessarily so if willed for the sake of something else Physical evil/suffering is CCP: it is not inconsistent for God to will it (to an extent), provided that it served a greater end (were God to will suffering for its own sake, we would deny his goodness/benevolence) 3. Disproportionately counter-purposive: a state of affairs in which there is no proportion between moral desert and reward/punishment A state of affairs in which the good suffer or the bad prosper is counter-purposive in its proportion (and if God wills such a state of affairs, we would deny his justice) 2. Three theodical strategies o A successful theodicy, then, must address all three of these sorts of apparent counter-purposiveness. (It might be possible to avoid the third sort, however, if one denies the existence of moral evil altogether, but Kant has little sympathy for this gambit) o Conveniently, Kant distinguishes between three different strategies of argument that might be used to address a putative case of counter-purposiveness “the would-be advocate of God [must] prove that either that whatever in the world we judge counter-purposive is not so; or, if there is any such thing, that it must be judged not at all as an intended effect but as the unavoidable consequence of the nature of things; or, finally, that it must at least be considered not as an intended effect of the creator [but] merely of […] human beings A) That which appears to us as counter-purposive is not really B) The counter-purposive unavoidably piggybacks on God’s creation - C) The counter-purposive is either the fault of human beings or willed by God for their sake (i.e., to improve them) For a theodicy to be complete, it must have to offer a response to moral evil, physical evil, and why theres a disproportion between the two. o o 2. Positions on Moral evil (1A, 1B, 1C) and Kant’s responses Kant also considers responses to the (conditionally counter-purposive) existence of physical evil on the basis of the same three strategies 1. Physical evil is not as bad as one might think since, in spite of it, everyone would “rather live than be dead” 2. It is part of the nature of an animal (sentient) beings to be more susceptible to pains rather than pleasures (the former, for instance, promote survival more effectively) 3. The pains of the world are intended for the sake of the human being, as a kind of “time of trial” where their commitment to virtue is tested To these, Kant responds as follows: 1. The claim is empirically false. Everyone who “has lived and pondered over the value of life” will have the same response “when asked […] whether he had the inclination to play the game of life once more” 2. This only begs the question: “why the creator of our existence called us into life when the latter [i.e., life] is not desirable to us” 3. This is possible, but we cannot have insight into whether it’s the case: “in this way one can indeed cut the knot loose […] but one cannot untie the knot” o 3. Positions on Disproportion between Evil and Suffering (3A, 3B, 3C) and Responses Finally, Kant considers responses to the fact that a (counter-purposive) disproportion between moral evil and physical evil seems to obtain in the world 1. It is not the case that there is such a disproportion. The conscience of the evildoer punishes them sufficiently for the commission of sin - 2. That the virtuous should suffer is part and parcel of what it means to be virtuous—that is, adversity is essential to prove the character and value of virtue 3. In this life, our state of happiness/sadness is determined by things like our technical prowess or ability to choose the right means to achieve our worldly ends (prudence) and does not depend on moral goodness/badness; it is only in the next life that we will see the rewards of virtue or the wages of vice As in the previous cases, Kant responds to each of these attempts to save God’s justice: 1. This is not the case—only those already virtuous suffer the pangs of conscience to the degree that it serves as a natural punishment 2. This puts the virtuous person in the perverse case of suffering not so that his virtue might be pure but because his virtue is pure, which does not seem just. 3. It is a reasonable postulate that the next life will see the rewards and punishments for actions in this one meted out; but this is not a vindication of God since there is no basis for this expectation given what happens in this life (it is rather in spite of what happens in this life that we hope this is the case) o Otherwise put, given what happens in this life, we have no reason to think that this will be the case (why couldn’t the next life see a similar disproportion?), but we can and should hope for a distribution of happiness in accordance with desert o 3. A negative wisdom o Kant takes the previous considerations to show that every previous philosophical attempt at theodicy has not succeeded. On its own, this does not rule out that some philosopher might later prove successful in this endeavour o Even so, Kant thinks that there is good reason to suspect that any philosophical attempt at theodicy must fail. The reason for this, broadly speaking, is that a - successful attempt would require us to be able to have a kind of insight that we are fundamentally incapable of “our reason is absolutely incapable of insight into the relationship in which any world as we may ever become acquainted with through experience stands with respect to the highest wisdom” (p. 30) o We’ll consider what this means shortly, but for Kant this amounts to a kind of negative wisdom—an “insight into the necessary limitation of what we may presume with respect to that which is too high for us” Otherwise put: this negative wisdom is the firm knowledge that any such insight is impossible for us 3. The inevitable failure of theodicy o Kant’s own explanation for why we cannot possible have the insight required to vindicate God’s moral wisdom is not exactly straightforward “For in the arrangement of this world we have the concept of an artistic wisdom—a concept which, in order to attain to a physico-theology, is not wanting in objective reality for our speculative faculty of reason. And we also have in the moral idea of our own practical reason a concept of a moral wisdom which could have been implanted in a world in general by a most perfect creator. – But of the unity in the agreement in a sensible world between the artistic and moral wisdom, we have no concept; nor can we ever hope to attain one.” (pp. 30-1) o We can, however, get a sense of why Kant thinks any theodicy would be impossible through the following considerations o Kant thinks that what a theodicy requires is an account of the harmony between God’s artistic wisdom and his moral wisdom o God’s artistic wisdom is evidenced in his wise arrangement of the events of the natural world—his direction of all natural events in accordance with an economy of natural laws God is artistically wise because he is able to direct an infinite diversity of effects through a few universal laws of nature o God’s moral wisdom, however, would be evidenced in his arrangement of the actions of moral beings such that the greatest good comes about through them That this should result is not included in the idea of God being artistically wise—that God is the best craftsmen does not mean that that which he crafts also serves the best moral end o But, generally put, the two sorts of “arrangements” involve reference to two different sorts of laws as governing things Artistic wisdom involves the “laws of nature”—the causal relationships among the things that constitute the world Moral wisdom involves the “moral law”—the law that specifies what actions free creatures are supposed to perform or omit o Kant’s point, however, is that both sorts of laws are, as far as we’re able to determine, incommensurable One way to put this is that laws of nature are descriptive (explain what does happen) whereas the moral law is prescriptive (explains what ought to happen) - - “from it [artistic wisdom] no inference is allowed to the moral wisdom of the author of the world, for the natural law and the moral law require principles of entirely different kinds” (p. 25n) o So, we can know the laws that govern nature, and we can know what the moral law demands of us, but we cannot know how a world designed to abide by the former might also serve to satisfy the demands of the latter o To get a better sense of what Kant is getting at, we might consider this issue from the perspective of human beings o Human beings are natural beings insofar as we’re governed by the sorts of laws that also govern nature; but we’re moral beings insofar as we are also subject to obligations we must fulfill As natural beings, we use our knowledge of natural causal connections (laws) to pursue our own happiness (something that is possible because of God’s artistic wisdom) As moral beings, we use our awareness of the moral law to determine what action we should perform to achieve virtue (something that is possible because of God’s moral wisdom) o It is inconceivable to us, however, how two such different orders can both obtain in the same world—how, for instance, acting for the sake of virtue, which frequently requires that we act contrary to what we desire, might also serve to bring about our happiness. It is something only God could understand and bring about. 4. Kant’s theodicy o In the second half of the essay, Kant changes his tune somewhat. Having shown that all theodicies have and must fail, he now contends that a theodicy of a different sort is possible, and indeed, an example of this is given to us in the Book of Job o Kant signals this transition by introducing an odd distinction between “doctrinal” and “authentic” interpretations of Scripture, but we don’t need to worry too much about what Kant means by this o What is essential is a distinction between two types of theodicy—one that Kant has argued is impossible (and which is now called ‘doctrinal’), and another that Kant thinks can be salvaged “Philosophical trials in this kind of interpretation are doctrinal; they constitute theodicy proper […]. Yet we cannot deny the name of ‘theodicy’ also to the mere dismissal of all objections against divine wisdom if this dismissal is a divine decree” (31) 4. A different approach to moral wisdom o As Kant sees it, his argument thus far has proceeded as follows: I cannot understand how the existence of evil fits into the order brought about by God I cannot see how, on the basis of the natural order, a moral order of things is possible Indeed, understanding this is beyond the capacity of human beings Therefore, I have no basis to hold that God is morally wise (i.e., that he has ordered things in this world to promote the morally best outcome) - o However, Kant thinks that this only goes to show that we should abandon this path to gaining assurance of God’s moral wisdom We should “dismiss” these challenges to God’s moral wisdom on the basis of our lack of insight—we’ll just never understand how evil fits into a moral order—but that does not mean dismissing the need to justify God’s moral wisdom altogether (so this is not a rejection of the “tribunal of reason”) (Also, reason is still involved, only now the emphasis changes from ‘speculative’ to ‘practical’ reason) o We should abandon trying to discern the moral order of things on the basis of the natural order. Instead, we should see whether we can have insight into the moral order itself and from there infer that God is morally wise (or something near enough) Moreover, Kant claims that God himself can be understood to assert the futility of the former path for theodicy, and to suggest Kant’s preferred alternative in the Book of Job (That God himself is taken to suggest this in the Book is why this is taken as an authentic theodicy) The book of job o Very briefly summarized, the Book of Job sees the following events: Job was a pious, morally upright, and prosperous man One day, Satan challenged God, claiming that Job was only pious because of his prosperity and without this he would turn on and curse God God takes up the challenge, and kills Job’s sons and daughters (not his wife), servants, and animals. He lets Satan afflict Job with sores all over his body Job is visited by three friends (the “comforters”) who try to console him by attempting to convince him that he has somehow sinned and this explains why his suffering is a punishment by God Job insists on his righteousness, even as he regrets ever being born, and claims that he would gladly plead his own case in front of God (thus seeming to find fault with God’s order) This draws God’s wrath. God reveals parts of the natural order that Job had not imagined—things beautiful and terrible—to show Job the limitations of human understanding of creation and its order But after humbling Job, God reproaches the comforters and restores to Job what he had lost (apparently finding in Job’s favour after all) o 4. Kant’s reading of Job Kant thinks that the Book of Job confirms his own views on theodicy First, negatively, the Book shows the futility of any attempt to know the moral order on the basis of the natural one God’s “ways [are] inscrutable to us, [and] must at the same time remain hidden—indeed already in the physical order of things” (33) As a result, both Job and his comforters are in error. Both speak of things “which are too high” for them and are therefore guilty of ignorance Job purports to know that his suffering is inconsistent with the natural and moral orders of things (i.e., that his suffering is not justified in the order of things) The comforters, in claiming that Job must be guilty because he suffers, are presuming some insight into these orders as well (i.e., that Job’s suffering is justified in the order of things) (Note again, it is God himself, in the story, who reveals this to Job—which is why this is an authentic theodicy) This still raises the question: if both sides are at fault, why does God favour Job at the end? This leads to Kant’s second, positive lesson from Job. It is not the respective claim to have insight into the order of God’s creation that sets Job apart from the comforters (Kant actually thinks Job would lose if the case was brought before an inquisition) Rather, it is Job’s conviction that he was morally blameless for his suffering: “on top of all this (what is most important) [Job was] at peace with himself in a good conscience” (32) Job does not dissimulate the conviction of his conscience—instead he maintains a sincerity of heart, or a truthfulness, in expressing what he feels is the case about his own moral uprightness, and it is this that leads him to question God “only sincerity of heart and not distinction of insight; honesty in openly admitting one’s doubts; repugnance to pretending conviction where one feels none, especially before God—these are the attributes which […] have decided the preeminence of the honest man” “[Job’s] friends […] speak as if they were being secretly listened to by the mighty one” (32) o OK, but how is this a theodicy? So, Job’s sincerity or truthfulness—that he stands by the convictions of his conscience—is why God favours him in the end. But how does any of this serve as a kind of theodicy for Kant? How does it show we can be assured of the moral order of things? Of God’s moral wisdom? Kant’s answer, in brief, is that Job’s conviction in his own righteousness, amidst everything that transpires, is an illustration of the fact that a moral order obtains in spite of what happens in the natural world. That no matter what happens, standards of ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ are immutable and apply irrespective of the circumstances This is precisely what the flexible morality of the comforters denies—Job must have done something wrong because he’s suffering for it. But according to Kant, this is what happens when you ground “morality on faith” and not “faith on morality” (33) The demands of morality, of the moral law, are unconditional and unchanging. They speak, as Kant puts it, as the “voice of God” (32). That these standards obtain is evidence of a moral order that supersedes the - natural one (which is why we’d be silly to look to the natural order for evidence of it) Moreover, that such a moral order obtains is not something we know, but something we feel through our own conscience. Conscience, then, immediately discloses a moral order of things to us, one that cannot be affected by the natural events around us. God’s moral wisdom is perhaps best evidenced in the fact that he gives us an insight into this other, higher order (up to which, we can hold the natural order) 4. A much more simplified version o What does it mean to “vindicate God’s moral wisdom”? Explaining how every evil fits into a divine plan for the morally best world? Kant: “No! Who could even do that?” Showing that in spite of what happens in the world, there is a moral order—an unchanging and unconditional standard for what’s right and wrong—that morality, as it were, speaks with “the voice of God”? Kant: “Yes!” Also Kant: “And isn’t losing that—an overarching moral order— what we were really worried about in the first place?” Online lecture 6: suffering without sin: problems of physical evil - The problem of evil o Our readings and discussions thus far have concerned the “problem of evil.” This is, as you well know, the reconciliation of the existence of evil in the world with God’s goodness o For the most part, the thinkers we have considered have maintained an unwavering commitment to God’s existence and to his supreme goodness (Voltaire and Hume are the least contentious exceptions here) o The principal difference among those who have attempted to “untie” (rather than “cut”) the knot is the question as to whether we can know, with a certainty based in reason, that the existence of evil is commensurable with God’s goodness Pope and Leibniz (and perhaps Cugoano) all contend that we can know that the world God brings about is the best in spite of the evil it contains Bayle and Kant both contend that we can never conclude that a moral order obtains on the basis of our experience of the natural order Bayle maintains that we nonetheless have an irrational belief, i.e., faith, that God is good in spite of the evils disclosed in our experience Kant denies that recourse to such a leap of faith is necessary, and argues that our own conscience (which he connects with practical reason) discloses a moral order - Suffering & sin - - o There are a number of things that might seem peculiar or antiquated about this debate (for starters, it presumes a commitment to a Christian conception of God which was not even universally shared at the time) o But one thing that might strike us as particularly odd is that physical evil (human suffering) gets so little attention in the discussion. The evil that provokes the theodicies of Leibniz and Pope, and that Bayle thinks requires a leap of faith in order to reconcile with God’s goodness, is moral evil Leibniz does consider physical evil in Bk. III of the Theodicy, but his interest in this topic is only by way of reassuring us that his solution to the existence of moral evil does not come at the cost of our freedom and responsibility for our own suffering o So, in the end, the problem of evil is primarily the problem of moral evil—but why then do these philosophers spend such little time considering physical evil on its own? Doesn’t it pose a distinct challenge that requires a resolution of its own? The presumption: we suffer because we sin o What accounts for this apparent neglect of physical evil is a shared presumption among these philosophers. This presumption is that suffering is (just) the result of sinful or vicious action. That is, physical evil is just the consequence of moral evil o We have already seen this presumption at work in the efforts of Job’s “friends” to convince him that his suffering was the result of some sin that he had committed (efforts which Kant ironically exposes as fruitless attempts to hypocritically flatter God) o But it is also at work in Leibniz’s discussion of physical evil in the last part of his Theodicy. His demonstration that this world is the best of all possible risked undermining the possibility of our freedom, and hence of our responsibility for the wrongs we commit. And if this were not answered, then the suffering that follows on our commission of evil actions would not be justified. Thus, Leibniz needed to show how freedom could be reconciled with the (hypothetical) necessity of all events, in order to preserve the justification for suffering “Now at last I have disposed of the cause of moral evil; physical evil, that is, sorrows, sufferings, miseries, will be less troublesome to explain, since these are the results of moral evil” (Theodicy, sect. 241) Unjustified suffering o And yet, largely undiscussed by the authors we’ve considered are cases of apparently unjustified suffering o Of course, much natural evil is unjustified in the way we’ve considered (as a punishment). Natural disasters, disease, etc. are not the sorts of things that afflict people who have engaged in morally wrong actions You may recall Voltaire pointing out that the victims of the Lisbon earthquake were probably less morally debauched than their counterparts in major metropolitan centres like London or Paris, and so their state of viciousness couldn’t possibly justify their suffering o The suffering caused by natural disasters is not necessarily the result of the commission of sin; yet, some optimistically-minded philosophers would claim that such suffering is nonetheless justified by other circumstances, whether a - - deeper sinfulness, the finitude of human nature, or human activity that is harmful if not sinful in itself Some with a theological interest might claim that none of us are, in the end, guiltless, given that we are all contaminated by original sin (and so the formula that “sin justifies suffering” can be taken to hold) Others, like Leibniz, will claim that suffering might not be the result of (original) sin, but it is the inevitable result of the finite or limited nature of the beings that constitute the world (so, we are subject to disease because of our imperfections—a kind of metaphysical original sin) And still others, like Rousseau, will allow that natural disasters are not the result of sin as such but that their harms are magnified by human activity nonetheless—the fact that we congregate in cities or establish artificial borders that obstruct the delivery of aid (so, “sin” is not the justification of suffering but human activity is nonetheless responsible for making it worse) o But there are other sorts of suffering, beyond those just mentioned, that don’t admit of easy, or any, justification o Most of us will be able to cite examples of this from our own personal experience that fits the bill. But one sort of physical evil that was discussed in the period was the seemingly needless suffering that takes place when some (human beings) are born with excessively debilitating physical conditions or severely restricted capacities o For some, the existence of such individuals (referred to with typical 17th century insensitivity as ‘monsters’—from the Latin monstrum indicating something inspiring fear or wonder) posed a challenge to God’s wisdom. Their appearance in the world was hard to account for in terms of God’s broader purposes, and there was no evidence that their suffering was justified by any deeper moral corruption o One philosopher who considered such cases of unjustified suffering seriously was Nicolas Malebranche Nicolas Malebranche o 1638-1715 o A philosopher and an ordained priest with an affinity for Augustine. His principal work, the Search after Truth was published in 1674-5 o Known primarily for his “occasionalist” solution of the mind-body problem o In a later text, the Treatise on Nature and Grace (1680), he takes up the issue of unjustified suffering o Malebranche himself was born with a severe malformation of the spine and suffered from frail health throughout his life Malebranche on suffering without sin o What is interesting about Malebranche’s discussion is that unlike the later optimists, he does not attempt to trace instances of suffering back to some deeper moral or metaphysical ground. He’s not trying to show that such suffering can be justified through moral evil, original sin, or the like That is, Malebranche does not deny the fact of suffering—the existence of physical evil—but instead tries to explain how it comes about in a way consistent with divine wisdom - - - o When it comes to the explanation itself, it is more or less what we’d expect. Malebranche thinks that what explains the existence of human beings born with severely debilitating conditions is that God governs creation through general laws (or volitions). These are framed to regularly bring about a specific set of effects. o But, since these laws operate at a general level, and since God does not want to unwisely supplement these with particular laws or volitions, it happens that cases of unjustified suffering are generated o “God, no doubt, could have made a world more perfect than the one we inhabit. […] But in order to make this more perfect world, He would have had to change the simplicity of His ways and multiply the laws” (Treatise, XIV) o “God, foreseeing before the establishment of natural laws all that must follow from them, ought not to have established them if He had to annul them. The laws of nature are constant and immutable and are general for all times and places.” o “If the rain falls upon certain lands, and the sun scorches others; if a seasonable time for harvest is followed by a destructive hail, if an infant comes into the world with a monstrous and useless head growing from his breast that makes him wretched, it is not because God willed these things by particular volitions, but rather because He has established the laws […] of which these effects are necessary consequences” (XVIII) Malebranche’s contribution: taking physical evil seriously o There’s obviously much that we might find objectionable in Malebranche’s account (not the least the premise that the very existence of certain types of human beings were a challenge to divine wisdom). But what he succeeds in doing better than nearly all of his contemporaries is foregrounding the issue of physical evil or suffering over and against the issue of moral evil o In doing so, Malebranche inaugurates a rather different discussion of evil in the early modern context, one that is quite distinct from that concerning “problem of evil” o As we have already seen, the problem of evil was an explicitly and unavoidably theological problem. But the discussions surrounding physical evil raise a host of issues that don’t presuppose a narrow theological context and whose significance extends well beyond it The problems of physical evil o The nature of suffering What is the relation between pleasure and pain? What sorts of pain/suffering are there? Do pains always outweigh pleasures? Is anyone ever happy? o The origin of suffering Apart from natural sources, what are the principal causes of suffering? Are humans the primary cause of their own suffering? How do institutions, cultural practices, etc. cause or exacerbate suffering? o The significance of suffering If pains outweigh pleasures in this life, how should we react? The nature of suffering; back to bayle - - o As it happens, Bayle again provides an important starting point when it comes to the discussion of physical evil o In the article “Xenophanes,” particularly in footnote F, Bayle revisits a debate in antiquity concerning whether the pains in life outweigh pleasures, that is, whether human life contains more sorrow than happiness o Bayle raises this issue in the context of an account of the life and thought of Xenophanes, a Greek poet-philosopher of the late 6th and early 5th centuries BCE (his precise dates are unknown, though apparently he was rather long lived, according to some even reaching the age of 104) o Xenophanes is thought of as the founder of the Eleatic school of philosophy—the Greek school of philosophy that included Parmenides (a defender of monism) and Zeno (author of the famous paradoxes). He was also a critic of popular religion (especially of anthropomorphic conceptions of the gods) o For Bayle, Xenophanes is primarily of interest because of his claims regarding physical evil, namely, “that the sweets of life are not equal to its bitters” (228). Otherwise put: that pains outweigh pleasures in life. Working off of Xenophanes, Bayle will argue for this, largely by reflecting on the nature of pleasure and pain The intensity of pleasure and pain o Bayle argues that Xenophanes’ claim that pains outweigh pleasures is not to be understood as claiming that in life we have more pains in terms of quantity. Bayle allows that over the course of one’s life, most people will count more pleasant (or neutral) days than bad: “[There are] [v]ery few persons, of what age soever we suppose them, but can compute infinitely more days of health than of indisposition; and there are many people who, during twenty years, have not had a fortnight’s sickness” (228) o Instead, Bayle takes Xenophanes’ claim as justified by the relative intensity of pains to pleasures. Another way of putting this is that while pleasant days might outnumber painful ones, the experience of pain has an intensity that far outweighs that of pleasures (such that the pleasures enjoyed over a long life are inconsiderable in comparison to the pains experienced at the end) o Bayle makes use of the metaphor of density (and its opposite, rarity—the quality of being diffuse) to make this point: “To employ a comparison […] porous bodies contain little matter under a large extent; […] dense bodies contain a great deal of matter in a little extent” “Such is the emblem of sickness and health. Sickness resembles dense bodies, and health porous bodies. Health is diffused over a great number of years, and yet it contains but little good. Sickness is spread only over a few days, and yet it includes a great deal of evil” “the good things of this life are less good than the evils are evil” (228) Anxiety, fear and regret o The foregoing shows, then, that the intensity of pains can overcome even an overwhelming quantity of pleasures over the course of a lifetime - - o But Bayle also argues that the experience of pleasure itself is not an uncomplicated phenomenon. Rather, pleasure is attended by other feelings and conditions that are themselves unpleasant or sources of pain o First, the pursuit of pleasure can be a source of anxiety, generated through the effort we have to expend in order to attain them: “anxiety precedes the enjoyment of pleasure” (229); “nature makes us purchase her presents at the expense of so many sufferings” (230) o Second, once we have attained the good thing that is the source of pleasure, we also become subject to the fear of losing it, or feel displeasure when others obtain the same themselves “For those who are called happy are afraid lest [nature] should afterwards frown upon them, and where such a fear prevails, there is no solid felicity” (229) “we not only are afraid of losing what we enjoy, but we likewise have the uneasiness to see other persons equal or surpass us” (229) o Finally, depending on the sort of pleasure we attain, it might be attended by a consequent feeling of disgust, regret, or repentance: “if anxiety precedes the enjoyment of pleasure, disgust and repentance follow close after it” (229) o “Wherever pleasures are, pain is at hand” (229) Disproportion of causes to effects o A further consideration introduced by Bayle concerns the diverse effects (pleasures/pains) that result from good and bad things o So, attaining a good (some object, a position, or an objective) can be the cause of pleasure for us; and likewise attaining some bad (or being deprived of a good) can be the cause of pain/sorrow for us o Despite this parallel causal connection, Bayle claims that the greatest goods are the causes of the least pleasure, while even a small evil can be the cause of considerable pain and suffering o Regarding goods, Bayle considers “very great goods” as things like attaining a high position, or winning a military battle; yet, these are either attended only with moderate pleasure or the pleasure that accompanies them is outweighed by the attendant concern and worry: “the victories gained in some provinces do not correspond with the losses which are suffered in others; [thus] we have reason to believe that joy is not pure and unmixed” (231) the fate of the prominent “is an assemblage in which evil has a greater share in proportion to good” (232) “A very great good in itself, which should excite but a very moderate pleasure, ought to be considered only as a moderate or indifferent good; but a little evil in itself, which should excite an insupportable uneasiness, grief or pain, ought to be considered as a very great evil” (230) Manichaeism redux o Given the nature of pleasure and pain—that pain will always outweigh pleasure in its intensity, that pleasure is never without some pain, and that even the greatest goods are only sources of a moderate pleasure—Bayle thinks that it is highly probable that every human life will involve some pain - - o This leads Bayle (again) to offer another Manichaean hypothesis of sorts, albeit couched in a Homeric story: “Homer […] says that two vessels or urns are placed by Jupiter, the one containing blessings, the other evils.” (230-1) o The myth here is that for each individual human being, Jupiter scoops from each vessel and bestows a mixture of good things and bad things upon them. Like the original Manichaean hypothesis, Bayle doesn’t actually believe that this Homeric myth is true, but he does think that it reflects an important truth; namely, that every human life, even the happiest, will always involve a mix of pleasure and pain Bayles conclusions o The claim that everyone will, in the course of their lives, experience a mixture of pleasures and pains is not the same as the claim that for everyone pain and suffering will inevitably outweigh pleasures (which was what Xenophanes had claimed) o But Bayle thinks that Xenophanes’ much stronger claim can be supported, as he details when he lists his own “conclusions” from note F: “I. That if we consider mankind in general, methinks Xenophanes might have said that they have more uneasiness and pain than pleasure.” “II. That there are some patient persons whose lives we may suppose are chequered with a much greater proportion of good than of evil.” “III. That there are others who we may suppose meet with much more evil than good.” “IV. That my second proposition [II. above] is especially probable with regard to such as die before old age and that my [third] appears chiefly certain with regard to those who live to a decrepit age” (232) “We must determine that no man is happy” o So Bayle thinks (I) that, on the basis of the foregoing considerations, Xenophanes’ claim that pains outweigh pleasures holds in general, that is, on the whole the amount of suffering experienced by humanity outweighs the pleasures experienced o Bayle allows (II) that some few individuals might live a life where pleasures outweigh pains. However, this is hardly reason to celebrate since he qualifies this in (IV) by saying that these are cases where one dies in the prime of their life o But for anyone who lives beyond their youth, and especially for those who live to an advanced age (i.e., who experience more of life than others), pain and suffering will outweigh our pleasures (both remembered and currently experienced) Online lecture 7: Masham and the harms of women’s under-education - The origin of suffering o Bayle’s “Xenophanes” presents an argument for the conclusion that pain/suffering outweighs pleasure solely through the consideration of the nature of pain/suffering and its relation to pleasure o But Bayle has less to say about the sources of suffering. Clearly, he thinks that many of our sufferings (outside of those caused by moral evil) are due to our - - natural desires and wants, the pursuit and satisfaction of which is inter-twined with painful sensations o However, he gives little attention to more sophisticated, human-made causes of unjustified suffering*—the sort of suffering that has its roots in social or cultural practices, or in long-standing institutions o * One notable exception are the harms that result from religious intolerance. As a persecuted religious minority himself, Bayle was well aware of these, and many of his articles on religions/religious figures (including Manichaeism) can be understood as an effort to undermine any claim to superiority/privileged access to the truth on the part of any religion) Womens education o One social/cultural practice that was a source of unjustified harms and which received increasing attention in the 17th and 18th centuries was the lack of formal educational opportunities for girls and young women o The model of mass public education, of course, was not yet in place (and wouldn’t be until the 1800s, and in any case still excluded women). Rather, education was undertaken in small schools founded for the male children of the aristocracy, or via private tutors (usually university students or recent graduates). These students would then enter university in preparation for careers in the state bureaucracy, military, the clergy, academia, etc. o Indeed, women were by and large shut out from opportunities at such careers (and this was often used as an argument against the need for women’s education). Even those who managed to obtain a decent education in their youth were permitted only in exceptional cases to attend university. There were, moreover, were subject to social prohibitions on engaging in the wider intellectual culture (taboos facing women’s authorship, or ridicule of “overly-intellectual” women) o The question concerning the particular need for the education of girls and young women, and what that education should consist in was for the most part left to female intellectuals to discuss and (very rarely) to implement A brief history of the “woman question” o There is some historical background here that might be useful. Perhaps the most (in)famous philosophical discussion of the question of women’s education occurs in Bks. V-VI of Plato’s Republic. After having outlined the components of the best state (the “city in speech”), Socrates is challenged by Glaucon to explain what role women will play in it: Glaucon: “[…] What sort of community of women and children is this which is to prevail among our guardians? and how shall we manage the period between birth and education, which seems to require the greatest care? Tell us how these things will be.” Socrates: “Yes, my simple friend, but the answer is the reverse of easy; many more doubts arise about this than about our previous conclusions. […]” o As many of you will know, Socrates’ response is that women should be educated in the same manner as the male guardians (and that children should be raised communally) - - - o Little came of this ambitious project, though the debate concerning whether women should or even could be educated continued long after. This debate— which issued in a genre of writing all of its own—was known as the querelle des femmes. It was sparked by a misogynist medieval romance, the Roman de la Rose, and saw erudite women (and their allies) defending the intellectual capabilities of women against recurrent misogynist criticism (including some who denied that women were human beings at all) Womens education in early modernity o The situation for women’s education in early modern UK and Europe did not see much in the way of improvement o This period did see considerable innovation in educational theory—from John Locke’s Some Thoughts concerning Education (1693) to Rousseau’s Emile, or On Education (1762), and many others besides. And yet this was all for the most part devoted to the improvement of the education of boys and young men o More important for enhancing women’s access to modern science and philosophy was the recent innovation of publishing in the vernacular—English, French, or German—rather than Latin (which could only be learned in schools) o There were some isolated attempts to found schools for girls that would offer instruction in languages, writing, music, and other subjects (largely relating to the reading and interpretation of Scripture), but these were often poorly-subscribed and short-lived endeavours o One notable success in this area was the school for girls, the Maison royale de Saint-Louis, founded by Madame de Maintenon (a former mistress of Louis XIV) in 1686 Some exceptions o There were, however, a small number of women who, in spite of the profound cultural and institutional obstacles, managed to gain an advanced education o Elena Lucrezia Cornaro Piscopia (1646-84), received a degree in philosophy in 1678 in Padua o Laura Bassi (1711-78), received a degree in philosophy and held a chair in physics in Bologna o Dorothea Erxleben (1715-62), received a degree in medicine in 1754, and practiced as a physician in Germany Also wrote Rigorous Investigation of the Causes that Obstruct Women from Study (1741), which made the case for women’s education and diagnosed the prejudices that were often invoked to justify it The harms of under-education o Significantly, these (and other) women were in a position to experience but also to expose the needless harms caused by denying women access to formal education. Some, like Erxleben, published treatises advocating for women’s access to education o Typically, these treatises are framed rather conservatively—they argue for the necessity of women’s education on the basis of woman’s traditional gender role, namely, as wife, housewife, and mother o It bears noting, however, that upholding this traditionalist view of women was essential for these treatises to reach the public. Systems of censorship (by the state - - - and/or religious entities) were in place to ensure that nothing too radical could be published. And while many female authors of the period would not have disputed these traditional gender roles anyway, for some few others it was clearly just something they paid lip service too in order for their treatises to reach the public o We will consider the writings of Lady Damaris Masham on this topic, which very much couches the case for women’s education in terms of upholding traditional gender roles. But before we consider her text, we will briefly turn to another female author and early English feminist—Mary Astell Mary Astell o 1666-1731 o Born in Newcastle, moved to London where she established herself as one of a few working women writers o A proponent of the Cartesian philosophy (particularly its “occasionalist” variant, developed by Malebranche, among others) o Published A Serious Proposal to the Ladies (1694, 1697), which debunked myths about women’s intellectual inferiority and outlined a plan for self-study for women without access to education o Also published Some Reflections upon Marriage (1700) which critically reflects upon the institution of marriage (Astell remained unmarried her entire life), partly through the example of her neighbour’s “shipwrack’d” marriage Astell’s serious proposal (1697) o One particularly interesting feature of Astell’s Proposal is that it sets out from a rather cynical estimation of the modern woman’s intellectual talents o Astell thinks that her female contemporaries have minds that have been corrupted by social forces—women pursue vain trivialities and vacuous diversions, reading novels and watching plays, rather than cultivating any real intellectual interests or improving themselves morally “There is a sort of Learning indeed which is worse than the greatest Ignorance: A Woman may study Plays and Romances all her days, and be a great deal more knowing but never a jot the wiser. Such a knowledge as this serves only to instruct and put her forward in the practice of the greatest Follies” (SP p. 81) o The fault for this, of course, lies in the lack of access to (real) education, which would train women in the use of their intellect and the proper objects of their will: “as Exercise enlarges and exalts any Faculty, so thro' want of using, it becomes crampt and lessened; if therefore we make little or no use of our Understandings, we shall shortly have none to use […]. What is it but the want of an ingenious Education that renders the generality of Feminine Conversations so insipid and foolish and their solitude so insupportable?” (SP p. 80) Astell’s method o This diagnosis of women’s contemporary corrupted intellectual position serves as the starting point for Astell’s recommended method for improving women’s intellect - - o Astell’s method, broken down into a set of 6 rules, is loosely inspired by a similar set of rules designed to improve the intellect, developed by Descartes (and others in the broader Cartesian tradition) o In any case, part of what makes Astell’s rules distinctive is that they are designed specifically with what she regards as the faults of women’s intellect in mind, and ultimately with the aim of combatting a persistent scepticism on the part of women who infer from the current intellectual situation to woman’s natural unsuitedness to knowledge and scientific pursuits Rule 1: “Acquaint our selves thoroughly with the State of the Question, have a Distinct Notion of our Subject whatever it be, and of the Terms we make use of, knowing precisely what it is we drive at.” Rule 2: “Cut off all needless Ideas and whatever has not a necessary Connexion to the matter under consideration.” Rule 3: “To conduct our Thoughts by Order, beginning with the most Simple and easie Objects, and ascending by Degrees to the Knowledge of more Compos’d.” Rule 4: “Not to leave out part of our Subject unexamin’d.” Rule 5: “Always keep our Subject Directly in our Eye, and Closely pursue it thro all, our Progress.” Rule 6: “To judge no further than we Perceive, and not to take anything for Truth, which we do not evidently Know to be so.” Damaris Masham o Another important contributor to the debate concerning women’s education is (Lady) Damaris Masham (1659-1708) o She was well connected with some of the most prominent philosophers of her day Her father was Ralph Cudworth, a well-known Cambridge Platonist She had a lasting intellectual friendship with Locke, who actually lived in her family’s home after his return from exile She also corresponded with Leibniz (in which letters they discussed Leibniz’s metaphysics) o Wrote A Discourse Concerning the Love of God (1696), which was part of an ongoing discussion with Astell about occasionalist themes. Also: Occasional Thoughts in Reference to a Vertuous and Christian Life (1705) In addition to containing thoughts about moral improvement, Masham’s Occasional Thoughts also argues for the necessity of women’s education. Moreover, particularly important for our purposes, it surveys the manifold harms—not just to women but to society at large—that result from women’s lack of education Masham’s arguments o Masham offers a number of arguments in favour of women’s education. In the selection we have, we can distinguish the following three: Argument from Religion (pp. 160-9) Argument from Woman’s Role as Mother (pp. 185-97) Argument from Woman’s Role as Wife/Companion (pp. 203-19) - - o In each case, Masham is going to argue that a vital private or public good that is typically demanded of women requires that they be educated in order to deliver and enjoy it The argument from religion o Quite appropriately, the first argument contends that some knowledge about religious matters is required for the sake of women’s virtue and salvation—that they cannot live a good, Christian life without some education regarding religion o Of course, it is not as if Masham thinks that women are completely ignorant of such matters. However, she does think that even women of higher rank are not in a position to understand and defend their religious beliefs “How many of these […] may it be presume’d that there are […] that can give any such account of the Christian Religion, as would inform an inquisitive Stranger what it consisted in; and what are the grounds of believing it?” (160-1) “They are, perhaps, sometimes told in regard of what Religion exacts, that they must believe and do such and such things, because the Word of God requires it; but they are not put upon searching the Scriptures for themselves” (162-3) o This puts women at risk in terms of their personal salvation—”Women have Souls to be sav’d as well as Men; to know what this religion consists in and to understand the grounds on which it is to be receiv’d, can be no more than necessary knowledge to a Woman as well as to a man” (166). o Moreover, as long as they are not certain about what (and why) they believe, they may be prone to scepticism or faithlessness “Whence it is but needful that they should so well understand their Religion as to be Christians upon the Convictions of their Reason” (168) Argument from womans role as mother o The argument from religion focuses on the private good (of personal salvation) as a reason for educating women (with the aim, presumably, of primarily convincing religious and civil authorities of its necessity, though some theologians of the time who think knowledge unnecessary for true religious belief might also be targets) o Two further arguments, by contrast, turn on women’s traditional social roles in contending for the need for education. The first of these argues that in her role as mother, and primary care-giver and first educator, of her children, a woman requires education o Masham conceives of this education as both moral (i.e., helping them avoid passions that make them miserable—192) but also extending to various subjects, including Latin, arithmetic, geography, history (195) o Moreover, mothers are, for Masham, naturally best positioned to succeed in this since they will not grow “disgusted” with the business of educating their own child nor will they grow complacent in trying to win the child’s affection (194) “[…] this great concernment […] ought to be the Care and Business of Mothers. Nor do women seem less peculiarly adapted by nature hereunto, than it can be imagin’d they should be, if the Author of Nature […] design’d this to be their Province” (190) - - o Masham’s point, then, is that in order to succeed in educating her children, a mother must herself be educated, and without this, both she and her children suffer injustice “From Womans being naturally thus fitted to take this care of their little Ones, it follows that besides the injustice done to themselves thereby, it is neglecting the Direction of Nature for the well-breeding up of Children, when Ladies are rendered incapable hereof” (191) Argument from womans role as wife o The last argument (for our purposes) turns on woman’s role as wife and companion to a (male) partner o Masham contends, for instance, that a woman who is educated is less likely to be led astray (in matters of religion, but also by implication in terms of fidelity) by someone else: “For these believers […] will hardly escape meeting some time or other with those who will ask them why they Believe, and if they find then that they have no more Reason for going to Church than they should go to Mass, or even to the Synagogue […] they must needs […] doubt whether or no the Faith they have been brought up in is any righter than either of these” (208) o Secondly, as it was often women managing the financial affairs of the household, when she is not educated, she is unable to govern those in a way that preserves the domestic economy (with cascading consequences): “Whence Want, mutual Ill Will, Disobedience of Children, their Extravagance and all the ill effects of neglected Government and bad Example follow, till they make such a Family a very Purgatory to every one who lives in it” (241) o Lastly, and perhaps most interesting, Masham claims that a wife who is not educated in the use of her reason is poor company for her husband—they are unable to entertain or edify one another and thus forego an important pleasure in life (friendship) “yet scarce any virtuous and reasonable Man and Woman who are Husband and Wife can know that it is both their Duty and Interest reciprocally to make each other happy [….] since Friendship has been allow’d by the wisest, most virtuous, and most generous Men of all Ages to be the solidest and sweetest pleasure in this World” (216) The cause of all this: the ignorance of men o Masham proceeds to offer her own diagnosis of the cause of the current situation, which she traces to the ignorance of men o In particular, the ignorance of gentlemen (which is to say, their failure to pursue a proper education themselves, in favour of a life of leisure) combines with vanity to make men jealous of any woman who might excel them in learning: “As for other Science [i.e., beyond religion], it is believe’d so improper for, and is indeed so little allow’d [women], that it is not to be expected from them: but the cause of this is only the Ignorance of Men” (169) - - “what wonder can it be if [men] like not that Women should have Knowledge; for this is a quality that will give some sort of superiority” (174) o Interestingly, Masham contends that this ignorance fuels wider social forces that work to discourage women from even wanting to pursue education (or educate others): Women are subject to ridicule for pursuing education: a woman who seeks a minimum of knowledge for the sake of educating her children “can hardly escape being call’d Learned [i.e., in a derogatory way] by the Men of our days, and in consequence thereof becoming a subject of Ridicule to one part of them and of Aversion to the other” (175) Another social force involved here is romantic attraction, as men according to Masham do not find learned women appealing: “if Men did usually find Women the more amiable for being knowing, they would much more commonly than now they are be so” (204) o These pressures can even dissuade well-intentioned parents from seeking to educate their daughters: “For Parents sometimes do purposely omit it [education] from an apprehension that should their Daughters be perceive’d to understand any learned Language or be conversant in Books, they might be in danger of not finding Husbands” “Nor probably would even the example of a Mother herself who was thus qualify’d […] be any great incouragement to her Daughters to imitate her example, but the contrary” (197) Masham on the harms of under-education o Masham thus shows that women’s lack of access to education is a considerable harm—both to the women who lose that opportunity, but also to her partner and her children, all of which causes broader social problems o This exclusionary practice is, moreover, rooted in male ignorance and vice (primarily vanity and laziness) “Vice and ignorance, thus, we see, are the great Sources of those Miseries which Men suffer in every state. These, oftentimes, mingle Gall even in their sweetest Pleasures; and imbitter to them the wholesomest Delights” o But, even as it is rooted in vice and ignorance, what holds this practice in place are broader social forces—social norms that govern how women, wives, and mothers ought to comport themselves, what makes them attractive to potential mates, and how they can fulfill their obligation to their children o But given that it is ignorance that grounds and perpetuates this practice, Masham claims, ironically and perhaps a bit forlornly, that the only remedy for it is precisely that which is being denied to or refused by all those involved: education “But what remedy hereto can be hop’d for, if rational Instruction and a well order’d Education of Youth, in respect of Vertue and Religion, can only […] rectify these Evils?” (219) Looking ahead to Astell’s some reflections o We have already seen that the issue of marriage is closely connected to that of women’s education—whether it is important for a woman to be educated to fulfill her role as spouse, and to educate her children o But the topic of marriage as such—the reasons for which women should seek to be married, the constitution of a happy marriage, and what recourse a woman should have in the case of an unhappy marriage—was itself a popular topic of early feminist writing o We can already see that Masham was something of an optimist regarding marriage: “It seems therefore one of the worst Marks that can be of the Vice and Folly of any Age when Marriage is commonly contemn’d therein” (217) o We will get a rather different perspective from Astell, in her Some Reflections concerning Marriage. To guide you in your reading, do keep the following questions in mind: o Study Questions 1. Does Astell think that a happy marriage is possible? 2. What does Astell mean when she says “the Husband’s Vices may become an occasion of the Wife’s Vertues”? 3. On p. 83 of the selection, Astell refers to the ‘Conscience of Duty’— does she think that women have an obligation to marry? Week 7: Mary Astell on Injustice and marriage - Transition to unit 2 o Our readings and discussions thus far have concerned the “problem of evil.” This is, as you well know, the reconciliation of the existence of evil in the world with God’s goodness o For the most part, the thinkers we have considered have maintained an unwavering commitment to God’s existence and to his supreme goodness (Voltaire and Hume are the least contentious exceptions here) o The principal difference among those who have attempted to “untie” (rather than “cut”) the knot is the question as to whether we can know, with a certainty based in reason, that the existence of evil is commensurable with God’s goodness Pope and Leibniz (and perhaps Cugoano) all contend that we can know that the world God brings about is the best in spite of the evil it contains Bayle and Kant both contend that we can never conclude that a moral order obtains on the basis of our experience of the natural order Bayle maintains that we nonetheless have a non-rational belief, i.e., faith, that the evils in the world can be reconciled with God’s goodness Kant denies that recourse to such a leap of faith is necessary, and argues that our own conscience (which he connects with practical reason) discloses a moral order - Sin and suffering o There are a number of things that might seem peculiar or antiquated about this debate (for starters, it presumes a commitment to a Christian conception of God which was not even universally shared at the time) o But one thing that might strike us as particularly odd is that physical evil (human suffering) is treated more or less as an after-thought, or only in connection with moral evil - - Leibniz does consider physical evil in Bk. III of the Theodicy, but his interest in this topic is only by way of reassuring us that his solution to the existence of moral evil does not come at the cost of our freedom and responsibility for our own suffering o So, in the end, the problem of evil is primarily the problem of moral evil—but why then do these philosophers spend such little time considering physical evil on its own? Doesn’t it pose a distinct challenge that requires a resolution of its own? The presumption: we suffer because we sin o What accounts for this apparent neglect of physical evil is a shared presumption among these philosophers. This presumption is that suffering is (just) the result of sinful or vicious action. That is, physical evil is just the consequence of moral evil o We have already seen this presumption at work in the efforts of Job’s “friends” who tried to convince him that his suffering was the result of some sin that he had committed (efforts which Kant ironically exposes as fruitless attempts to hypocritically flatter God) o But it is also at work in Leibniz’s discussion of physical evil in the last part of his Theodicy. His demonstration that this world is the best of all possible risked undermining the possibility of our freedom, and hence of our responsibility for the wrongs we commit. And if this were not answered, then the suffering that follows on our commission of evil actions would not be justified. Thus, Leibniz needed to show how freedom could be reconciled with the (hypothetical) necessity of all events, in order to preserve the justification for suffering “Now at last I have disposed of the cause of moral evil; physical evil, that is, sorrows, sufferings, miseries, will be less troublesome to explain, since these are the results of moral evil” (Theodicy, sect. 241) Unjustified suffering? o And yet, largely undiscussed by the authors we’ve considered are cases of apparently unjustified suffering o Of course, much natural evil is unjustified in the way we’ve considered (as a punishment). Natural disasters, disease, etc. are not the sorts of things that only afflict people who have engaged in morally wrong actions You may recall Voltaire pointing out that the victims of the Lisbon earthquake were probably less morally debauched than their counterparts in major metropolitan centres like London or Paris, and so their state of viciousness couldn’t possibly justify their suffering o The suffering caused by natural disasters is not necessarily the result of the commission of sin; yet, some “optimistically”-minded philosophers would claim that such suffering is nonetheless justified by other circumstances, whether a deeper (i.e., original) sinfulness, the finitude of human nature, or human activity that is harmful if not sinful in itself o But there’s something deeply troubling about such broad optimistic justifications of suffering. They seem not unlike the words of “comfort” offered by Job’s friends in that they infer from the fact of suffering to some underlying condition of sinfulness. In so doing, they invite the victims of such suffering to contradict the verdicts of their own consciences that they are blameless for the suffering that they undergo - - - Kant, as we have seen, thinks that admitting that our consciences could err so thoroughly is a worse result than admitting the possibility of unjustified suffering o Perhaps, then, instead of seeking for a perspective that rules out the very possibility of unjustified suffering, we might admit the reality of unjustified suffering and think more carefully about physical evil, in abstraction from moral evil The problems of physical evil o The nature of suffering What is the relation between pleasure and pain? What sorts of pain/suffering are there? Do pains always outweigh pleasures? Is anyone ever happy? o The origin of suffering Apart from natural sources, what are the principal causes of suffering? Are humans the primary cause of their own suffering? How do institutions, cultural practices, etc. cause or exacerbate suffering? o The significance of suffering If pains outweigh pleasures in this life, how should we react? The nature of pain/suffering: back to bayle o As it happens, Bayle again provides an important starting point when it comes to the discussion of physical evil o In the article “Xenophanes,” particularly in footnote F, Bayle revisits a saying attributed to the pre-Socratic Greek philosopher, namely, that “that the sweets of life are not equal to its bitters” (228) o Bayle argues in favour of a version of Xenophanes’ claim, namely that, in general (if not in every case), human life contains more pain than pleasure. He thinks this is so on the basis of the following considerations relating to the nature of pain (and its relation to pleasure): I) We experience pains more intensely than pleasures, even if we more frequently experience pleasure/the absence of pain: “the good things of this life are less good than the evils are evil” (228) II) Pleasures are always attended with displeasure/pain, particularly anxiety in their acquisition, fear in their loss once obtained, and regret after their satisfaction: “Wherever pleasures are, pain is at hand” (229) III) The greatest of goods provides little pleasure (and is always adulterated with concern), whereas even the smallest of evils can be attended with significant pain o Note: We will return to this issue in week 8, as Hume offers further considerations in favour of Bayle’s case for pains outweighing pleasures The origin of suffering o While Bayle’s “Xenophanes” offers a fairly detailed treatment as to the nature of pleasure and pain, he has rather less to say about the sources of suffering o For the most part, he thinks that many of our sufferings (outside of those caused by moral evil) are due to our natural desires and wants, the pursuit and satisfaction of which is inter-twined with painful sensations - - One notable exception are the harms that result from religious intolerance. As a member of a persecuted religious minority himself, Bayle was well aware of the suffering that intolerance causes. Many of his articles on religions/religious figures (including Manichaeism) can be understood as an effort to undermine any claim to superiority/privileged access to the truth on the part of any religion) o However, he gives little attention to other sophisticated, human-made causes of unjustified suffering—the sort of suffering that has its roots in social or cultural practices, or in corrupted institutions Women’s lack of access to education o One social/cultural practice that was a source of unjustified harms and which received increasing attention in the 17th and 18th centuries was the denial of formal educational opportunities to girls and young women o The model of mass public education was not yet in place (and wouldn’t be until the 1800s, and in any case still excluded women). Rather, education was undertaken in small schools founded for the male children of the aristocracy, or via private tutors (usually university students or recent graduates). These students would then enter university in preparation for careers in the state bureaucracy, military, the clergy, academia, etc. o Indeed, women were by and large shut out from opportunities at such careers (and this was often used as an argument against the need for women’s education) o Some women, however, managed to obtain a decent education and even secured a living as intellectuals outside of the academy. One example is (Lady) Damaris Masham (1659-1708), a well-connected and influential philosopher. In her Occasional Thoughts in Reference to a Vertuous and Christian Life (1705), she makes the case for the education of girls and young women There, she also identifies the manifold harms—not just to women but to society at large—that result from women’s lack of education Masham on the harms of under-education o Masham offers a number of arguments in favour of women’s education. By way of an overview, we might distinguish the following three: Argument from Religion Argument from Woman’s Role as Mother Argument from Woman’s Role as Wife/Companion o As is clear, Masham’s arguments are premised on an acceptance of woman’s traditional gender role (wife, mother, housewife). (And this is by no means exceptional.) Her point though is that in order to perform these roles adequately, women require education. o Women’s lack of access to education thus turns out to be a source of considerable harm, as a function of women’s essential contributions to domestic life and society as a whole. It generates harms not only to the women who lose that opportunity, but also to her partner and her children, all of which causes broader social problems o She also claims that this exclusionary practice is rooted in (male) ignorance and vice (primarily vanity and laziness) - - - “Vice and ignorance, thus, we see, are the great Sources of those Miseries which Men suffer in every state. These, oftentimes, mingle Gall even in their sweetest Pleasures; and imbitter to them the wholesomest Delights” Marriage as a source of suffering o The issue of marriage is closely connected to that of women’s education—as we have seen, Masham considers whether it is important for a woman to be educated to fulfill her role as spouse, and to educate her children (within the context of traditional family) o But the issue of marriage as such—the reasons for which women should seek to be married, the constitution of a happy marriage, and what recourse a woman should have in the case of an unhappy marriage—was itself a popular topic of early feminist (and misogynistic) writing We can already see that Masham was something of an optimist regarding marriage: “It seems therefore one of the worst Marks that can be of the Vice and Folly of any Age when Marriage is commonly contemn’d therein” (217) o But the institution of marriage also came to be recognized as a source of unjustified suffering for women. In the case of Mary Astell, the institution of marriage in its present constitution was a significant source of unjustified suffering A woman in an unhappy marriage, according to Astell, “is as unhappy as any thing in this World can make her” (30) Mary Astell o 1666-1731 o Born in Newcastle, moved to London where she established herself as one of a few working women writers o A proponent of the Cartesian philosophy (particularly its “occasionalist” variant, developed by Malebranche, among others) o Published A Serious Proposal to the Ladies (1694, 1697), which debunked myths about women’s intellectual inferiority and outlined a plan for self-study for women without access to education o Also published Reflections upon Marriage (1700) which critically reflects upon the institution of marriage (Astell remained unmarried her entire life), partly through the example of her neighbour’s “shipwrack’d” marriage Astell on the purpose and benefits of marriage o Astell’s position on marriage is not that the institution as a whole is problematic, but that a number of underlying forces and circumstances contribute to making it profoundly harmful (to women in particular, but not only) “The wise institutor of matrimony [i.e., God] never did anything in vain; we are sots and fools if what he design’d for our good, be to us an occasion of falling. For marriage […] is too sacred to be treated with disrespect” (8) o Indeed, Astell is quite clear about the myriad social benefits (domestic and beyond) that are ideally provided by the institution of marriage. These benefits are such that they hold even outside of a religious context: - - “The Christian institution of marriage provides the best that may be for domestic quiet and content, and for the education of children, so that if we were not under the tie of religion, even the good of society and civil duty would oblige us to what that requires at our hands” (10) o Even so, Astell identifies a crucial condition that must be met for marriage to yield these benefits. This condition, also reflected in Masham’s discussion, is that the choice to marry is based on friendship: “He who does not make friendship the chief inducement to his choice [to marry], and prefer it before any other consideration, does not deserve a good wife, and therefore should not complain if he goes without one” (10) Astell on the corruption of marriage o Astell’s rosy view when it comes to the purpose and the benefits of marriage contrasts rather starkly with what she views as the reality of the institution in her day “But if marriage be such a blessed state, how comes it […] that there are so few happy marriages?” (11) o In fact, Astell claims that this is not surprising—given the reasons for which marriage is entered into, and how individuals (namely men) are given licence to conduct themselves within it, what is surprising is that some marriages are happy “it is not to be wonder’d that so few succeed, we should rather be surprised to find so many [that] do, considering how imprudently men engage, the motives they act by, and the very strange conduct they observe throughout” (11) Bitter consolation o As it stands, the only consolation that women can draw from an unhappy marriage is that it provides them with an opportunity to develop their own virtues in coping with adversity. Here Astell offers a litany of such alleged “blessings” (Loss of her estate) “She might have been exposed to all the temptations of a plentiful fortune, have given herself to sloth and luxury” (15) (Overbearing/jealous husband) “he makes it necessary to withdraw from those gaieties and pleasures of life which show more mischief” (Forced isolation) “Silence and solitude, being forced from ordinary entertainments of her station, may perhaps seem a desolate condition at first…” “[b]ut a little time wears off all the uneasiness and puts her in possession of pleasures which till now she has been kept a stranger to” “There is not a surer sign of a noble mind […] than being able to bear contempt and unjust treatment […] evenly and patiently” (48-9) o Rather ironically, Astell concludes that, for women, affliction is “the best instructor and indeed the only useful school that women are ever put to” (16) o Astell even thinks that an unhappy marriage can provide women with a kind of cynical wisdom concerning how the world really works—she can see passed the appearances of things to the deeper reality, learns not to trust the flattering words of others, and recognizes that what seems to be a supreme good is in fact only apparently so: “Affliction, the sincerest friend […] rouses her understanding, [and] opens her eyes […]. She now distinguishes between truth and appearances, - - - between solid and apparent good, has found out the instability of all earthly things and won’t any more be deceived by relying on them” (16) o All this might serve as a kind of consolation for a bad marriage—that namely “the husband’s vices may become an occasion of the wife’s virtues”—except that it is not the rule “all injur’d wives don’t behave themselves after this fashion” (17) Astell on why marriage fails o Given the importance of marriage, and its nearly universal and wholesale failure, Astell turns in the Reflections to diagnosing the reasons why marriage, in the form it is practiced in her day, falls so far short of its intended result. o To this end, Astell canvasses a wide variety of causes for the corruption of marriage. While she doesn’t present these in a terribly systematic way, it will be convenient to divide these into two sets: (i) those (psychological) causes that operate at the level of individual decisions or motives, and (ii) those causes that work in the background—what we might call ‘systemtic’ or ‘structural’ sources of the corruption of marriage (and its consequent harms) Why marriage fails: individual choice o At the level of individual choice, Astell faults both men and women for failing to choose their spouse on reasons founded in friendship. o In the case of men, Astell contends that for the most part their choice of a wife is grounded in ‘mercenary’ considerations “What will she bring is the first enquiry” (12) o Yet, that men choose their spouse on the basis of financial benefit amounts to a misuse of the institution of marriage and so little of its benefits should be expected: “He who marries himself to a fortune only must expect no other satisfaction than that can bring” (12) o Astell also reserves some condemnation for the choices women make in selecting a spouse. While some might be motivated by a financial incentive as well, others according to her let themselves fall prey to flattery through the courtship: “tho’ we complain of being deceived this instant, we do not fail of contributing to the cheat the very next. Though in reality it is not the world that abuses us, tis we [who] abuse ourselves, it is not the emptiness of that, but our own false judgments, our unreasonable desires and expectations that torment us” (53-4) “If a women were duly principled and taught to know the world [...] and the traps [men] lay for her under so many gilded compliments […] women would marry more discreetly” (80) Why marriage fails: structural/systemic causes o Astell does not, then, overlook the poor decisions and personal responsibility, on both sides, that contributes to the contemporary failure of marriage o However, and significantly, she also considers the deeper role played by broader social/cultural conditions and structures in corrupting the institution o Here, we might distinguish between three sorts of structural causes or conditions: - - 1. Broader social conventions (access to education) or socio-economic circumstances 2. Radical inequality (in law and conventionally) 3. Prevailing misogyny o While we can distinguish these structural causes in these ways, it should be kept in mind that these structural causes interact with one another Misogyny justifies, and is in turn reinforced by, social conventions (i.e.: denying women access to education leaves them comparatively ignorant, which in turn seems to justify holding them to be inferior) Moreover, each of these structural causes exercise a decisive influence on individual choice (making them arguably more important in Astell’s analysis) Structural causes: social conventions/socio-economic circumstances o Among the structural causes in this category, we might consider, first, that men are misled into choosing their spouse on financial grounds on the basis of wider socio-economic forces o That is, men come to see that a primary route for social mobility (particularly among the middle and upper classes) is the choice of a bride with means; and the best way to preserve what one has gained, is through children. These sorts of ‘mercenary’ considerations influence men’s decision to choose a spouse only as a means to an end: “For under many sounding compliments, words that have nothing in them, this is his true meaning: he wants one to manage his family, a housekeeper, a necessary evil, one whose interest it will be not to wrong him […]. One who may breed his children, taking all the care and trouble of their education, to preserve his name and family.” (34-5) o On the other side, women are likewise misled by wider social conventions into thinking that their happiness lies solely in finding a spouse and raising a family. This generates a kind of urgency in finding a husband which creates a situation in which women are left without time or incentive to question her suitor’s motives: “a woman […] has been taught to think marriage her only preferment, the sum-total of her endeavours, the completion of all her hopes, that which must settle and maker her happy in this world” (53) “she whose expectation has been raised by courtship, by all the fine things that her lover, her governess, and domestic flatters say, will find a terrible disappointment when the hurry is over” (54) Structural causes: radical inequality o Of course, a key structural issue, and one that Astell brings up frequently, is the radical inequality between men and women. This is not solely a social issue, since in Astell’s time (and for long after), men and women had unequal standing under law. o This inequality extended to their respective roles in a marriage. Men were accorded nearly absolute power over their spouse, who was legally and in fact a dependant “She who elects a monarch for life, who gives him an authority she cannot recall” (31) - - “how can a woman scruple entire subjection […] if she at all considers it” (55) “she is taken to be a man’s upper-servant” (89) o This serves to create a situation where a husband’s mistreatment of his spouse and abuse of his role is far more likely. That he has such authority feeds his “pride and self-conceit” (29), and gives him little incentive to listen to a subordinate “She has made him her head, and he thinks himself as well qualify’d” (39) “He who has sovereign power does not value the provocations of a rebellious subject, but knows how to subdue them […] and will make himself obey’d” (27) o There are, moreover, no avenues of legal recourse and the verdict of custom is often harsh: “she puts herself entirely into her husband’s power, and if the matrimonial yoke be grievous, neither law nor custom afford her redress” (27) “For covenants betwixt husband and wife, like laws in an arbitrary government, are of little force” (37) o Given the position in which she is placed, Astell concludes that even a ‘prudent’ decision to marry is attended with “Risque” (34) Structural causes: Misogyny o A final structural cause, and one which obviously works in tandem with the other two, is a prevailing attitude of misogyny, or contempt for women “But how can a man respect his wife when he has a contemptible opinion of her and her sex?” (47) o Concerning this, Astell first points to the ways, both subtle and explicit, in which misogyny pervades ordinary life. This attitude is reflected in what Astell regards as a misinterpretation of Scripture and the story that woman was created as a ‘helpmeet’ for man. A prevailing attitude of contempt for women takes what is intended as a relationship of (reciprocal) assistance and makes it an occasion for men to treat women as they please: “when we suppose a thing to be made purely for our sakes, because we have dominion over it, we draw a false conclusion”; “how are these lords and masters helped by the contempt they show of their poor humble vassals” (47-8) o This attitude also underlies the “satires” and “jests” relating to the female sex written by theologians, academics, and popular authors. Given that they already view women as inferior, Astell wonders why they would bother to satirize women other than because they also view them with contempt: “But that your grave dons, your learned men, and which is more, your men of sense […] should stoop so low as to make invectives against women, forget themselves so much as to jest with their slaves, who have neither liberty nor ingenuity to make reprisals! […] this indeed may justly be wondered at!” (50-1) Structural causes: misogyny and male fragility o For Astell, then, that men hold women in contempt is evident because men go beyond whatever natural inequality obtains between the sexes to assert a - complete dominion over them. And it is this contempt that lies behind the fact that they ridicule those they claim not to be “worth their pains” (51) o But Astell also speculates as to the cause of this misogynistic attitude. And while she doesn’t use the term, it seems clear that she locates the source in male fragility—that men are afraid that, outside of a situation in which women feel degraded and inferior, they cannot and will not command their esteem and obedience o As Astell argues, however, men’s mistreatment of women and arbitrary use of their authority only demonstrates that they are unwise and unjust, and so undeserving of esteem: “Is it possible for her to believe him wise and good who by a thousand demonstrations convinces her and all the world of the contrary? [If] the bare name of husband confer sense on a man, and the mere being in authority infallibly qualify him for government, much might be done. But […] a ‘wise man’ and a ‘husband’ are not terms convertible” (57) “a blind obedience is an obeying without reason, for aught we know against it. God himself does not require our obedience at this rate, he lays before us the goodness and reasonableness of his laws” (83-4) Saving marriage? o In the end, Astell’s Some Reflections is largely critical in intent—she is seeking to expose the various causes of the corruption of marriage as the institution is currently practiced. Given that some of these causes are cultural/structural, any effort to address these would require large-scale systemic and cultural changes o But, as with Masham, Astell suggests that a key part of any reform would be providing women access to education. This would put women in a position to understand, by means of reason, what her duties and responsibilities are (and presumably what they aren’t), allowing her to more effectively fulfill her role in marriage. Moreover, this is no more than what the husband owes his spouse: “It is therefore very much a man’s interest that women should be good Christians […]. [W]hat can be more the duty of the head than to instruct and improve those who are under government?” (84) o Obviously, educated women risk infringing on male fragility. Astell concedes this but claims that only those who exercise their authority in a way contrary to what’s right or what’s wise have reason to fear: Some worry that “a philosophical lady as she is call’d by way of ridicule […] would be too wise and too good for the men; I grant it, for vicious and foolish men” (85) o What is in any case clear for Astell, is that under the current circumstances, no woman has reason to be “fond of being a wife” (89) Online lecture 8: Hume on suffering and suicide - Hume’s dialogues o We have already seen that in Part XI of the Dialogues, Hume (through his spokesperson Philo) takes on the problem of evil. There he challenges the - theist’s claim that we can infer the divine attributes (supreme goodness in particular) from our experience of the world o This week, our first reading is the part of the Dialogues which leads up to that discussion (so obviously the same dialogue characters are still involved—Philo, Cleanthes the proponent of natural religion, and Demea the mystic) o However, the topic in Part X is notably different than that of Part XI—it concerns the topic of suffering, and considers whether there is more suffering or misery in life than happiness, and if so, what the significance of that is for our actions o Significantly, this issue leads into the discussion of the problem of evil in Part X (from p. 188) and Part XI. Philo thinks that we are certain by means of our experience that life contains more suffering or physical evil than happiness; but he thinks proving this strong claim is not actually necessary to undermine our credence in the Christian conception of God, as the existence of any evil anywhere already suffices to call this into question “But allowing you, what never will be believe’d [namely, that] human happiness in this life exceeds its misery, you have yet done nothing: For this is not, by any means, what we expect from infinite power, infinite wisdom, and infinite goodness. Why is there any misery at all in the world?” (194) Hume’s dialogues, part X o The discussion in Part X starts out with Demea’s contention that it is the human being’s awareness of and reflection upon their own miserable and helpless situation (rather than a chain of reasoning) that leads them to turn to God and religion for comfort “It is my opinion, I own, replied Demea, that each man feels, in a manner, the truth of religion within his own breast; and from a consciousness of his imbecility and misery, rather than from any reasoning, is led to seek protection from that Being, on whom he and all nature is dependant” (171) “Wretched creatures that we are! What [recourse] for us amidst the innumerable ills of life, [if] religion did not suggest some methods of atonement, and appease those terrors with which we are incessantly agitated and tormented” (172) o Philo is happy to concede that this is why many turn to religion (largely because, as we know, Philo thinks that this is ultimately irrational as we have no basis to claim to know God’s moral goodness and this would be required for religion to provide us with the comfort we seek) o But this gives rise to a wider discussion of the relation and proportion of suffering (pain) and happiness (pleasure) in life—a discussion in which Demea and Philo are in fundamental agreement that life offers more pain than pleasure “The people, indeed, replied Demea, are sufficiently convinced of this great and melancholy truth. The miseries of life; the unhappiness of man; the general corruptions of our nature; the unsatisfactory enjoyment of - - pleasures, riches, honours; these phrases have become almost proverbial in all languages” (172-3) Return to Bayle and Xenophanes I o In exploring this theme, Hume (via Philo and Demea) returns to a number of points with which we are already familiar from Bayle’s treatment in his “Xenophanes” who, we will recall, contended that what is bitter in life outweighs what is sweet o So Demea claims that humans, like all sentient beings, are born into a life filled with want, conflict, and fear. The portrait Demea paints is of life as a kind of Hobbesian state of nature, or a state of “perpetual war”: “The whole earth, believe me Philo, is cursed and polluted. A perpetual war is kindled amongst all living creatures. Necessity, hunger, want stimulate the strong and courageous: Fear, anxiety, terror, agitate the weak and infirm. The first entrance into life gives anguish to the newborn infant and to its wretched parent: Weakness, impotence, distress, attend each stage of that life: and it is at last finished in agony and horror.” (175-6) o Indeed, Demea claims that even the things that some would claim redeem human life and offer some recompense of pleasure are not obvious sources of pleasure. So, after saying that if he wanted to show an alien the ills of human life, he would take it to “a hospital full of diseases, a prison crowded with malefactors and debtors”; but were he to show this stranger “the gay side of life”: “whither should I conduct him? To a ball, to an opera, to [a royal] court? He might justly think that I was only showing him a diversity of distress and sorrow” (180-1) o All of this is readily understood through our own experience, but also through the testimony of others (Cicero, Emperor Charles V) who were in positions where apparent happiness did not offset their cares and suffering. As a result, this all suggests that human life contains more suffering than happiness Return to Bayle and Xenophanes II o In addition, and similarly to Bayle, Hume also argues for this conclusion on the basis of a consideration of the nature of pleasure and pain o So, like Bayle, Hume stresses that even if the quantity of pleasures in a life outnumbers that of pains, the intensity of pains easily eclipses the intensity of our pleasures “if pain be less frequent than pleasure, it is infinitely more violent and durable. One hour of it is often able to outweigh a day, a week, a month of our common insipid enjoyments” (191-2) o Moreover, our pains are capable of reaching a height of intensity, a maximum, that cannot long be matched by that of even a great pleasure: “Pleasure scarcely in one instance is ever able to reach ecstasy and rapture: And in no one instance can it continue for any time at its highest pitch and altitude. […] But pain often, good God how often!, rises to - - torture and agony, and the longer it continues it becomes still more genuine agony and torture” (192) Extending Bayle’s case: Psychic suffering I o But Hume also adds to Bayle’s case by considering a type of suffering that was largely left out of Bayle’s discussion: psychic suffering o This kind of suffering is important because it is something that human beings, insofar as they have minds, are uniquely capable of. The sorts of suffering Bayle had considered are types that pertain to any merely sentient being (i.e., a being with a capacity for feeling). We might, for convenience’s sake, call this physical suffering o Hume notes that, unlike animals, human beings have a capacity to surmount a number of sources of physical suffering (hunger, conflict)—we can band together and engage in collective action to secure food sources and guarantee our security. But, Hume will claim that having mitigated the threat of physical suffering is not the end of the story, as in such cases human beings quickly invent imaginary concerns and fears and proceed to torment themselves with them “Man it is true can, by combination, surmount all his real enemies, and become master of the whole animal creation: but does he not immediately raise up to himself imaginary enemies, the demons of his fan[tasy], who haunt him with superstitious terrors”? (177) o For Philo, these “superstitious terrors” are clearly the supernatural beings posited by religious traditions—ancestors, demons, spirits, and vengeful gods who make our very enjoyment of our newfound security a fresh cause for guilt and repentance, and a kind of self-inflicted punishment: “His pleasure, as he imagines, becomes in their eyes a crime: his food and repose give them umbrage and offence: his very sleep and dreams furnish new materials to anxious fear, and even death […] presents only the dread of endless and innumerable woes” (177-8) Extending Bayle’s case: Psychic suffering II o Moreover, it is not just the suffering that proceeds from superstition that afflicts human beings, but also suffering that proceeds from the “disorders of the mind.” By these, Hume refers to the kinds of emotions that arise from our capacity to reflect on our past behaviours or uncertainty about what might lie in our future. These emotions can also deeply unsettle even the most prosperous person “Remorse, shame, anguish, rage, disappointment, anxiety, fear, dejection, despair; who has ever passed through life without cruel inroads from these tormentors?” (179) o But even in cases where we have nothing in our past to regret, or no future state to be anxious about, Hume thinks we still undergo a kind of psychic suffering. We suffer, namely, when we achieve what we want, or even when we don’t do anything at all, we suffer from a kind of let-down or a vexatious boredom: “an anxious languor follows [one’s] repose; disappointment, vexation, trouble, their activity and ambition” (182) - - o So, when we act, we suffer insofar as we are disappointed, frustrated, or troubled with the result; but when we do not act, when we simply keep to ourselves and mind our own business, we grow anxious, uneasy, and bored, which are forms of (psychic) suffering, even if arguably milder than other types The objection: If life is so bad…? o Philo thinks that it is now evident, from this consideration of physical and psychic forms of suffering, that life contains more miseries than pleasures and that no one can ever be truly happy. o At this point in the dialogue, things take a rather darker turn o Philo now imagines a sceptical opponent who denies that happiness is impossible, and that those who “complain incessantly of the miseries of life” simply suffer from a particularly “discontented, repining, anxious disposition” (181) This would be to say something like: the folks who claim loudly that life is full of sorrow just suffer from depression or some other mental ailment that makes them focus on the bad over the good o Philo (replying to his own imagined opponent) thinks that having such a disposition, where one would be highly sensitive to the miseries of life, would count as a source of misery in its own right (so that the depressed person is not simply imagining their suffering). o Against this, Philo imagines the following reply on the part of his opponent: “But if they were really as unhappy as they pretend, says my antagonist, why do they remain in life?” (181) o That is, if the individual who complains about the miseries of life really thought this, then they would not want to live anymore and would take the necessary actions to exit this life Hume’s “On suicide” o This obviously raises the issue of suicide, which is touched on at a couple of points in the middle of Part X of the Dialogues (pp. 181-85) o However, this was a rather taboo topic to talk about in Hume’s day (as it arguably still is in our own). As a result, it is never explicitly mentioned and Hume does not here make evident what might be thought to be the natural conclusion of his discussion (instead he abruptly transitions on p. 185 to the critique of the theist on the problem of evil) o We’ll return to Hume’s brief treatment of suicide in the Dialogues at the end of this lecture. For now, we will look at Hume’s considered views on the topic of suicide, which he expressed in an essay entitled “On Suicide.” Unsurprisingly, given the taboos associated with the topic, this essay was among the works that Hume wrote but suppressed during his lifetime (much like the Dialogues itself), and was only published posthumously at the discretion of the executor of his will o “On Suicide” gives us a better sense of Hume’s own opinion on suicide (since there are no dialogue characters to make things ambiguous) o There are some who have argued that suicide is an appropriate response to the preponderance of pain over pleasure in this life - - Such a view was reported, if not endorsed, in Bayle’s “Xenophanes,” note D: “[Pliny] does not omit the reflection, which many have made, that it would be extremely happy for man not to be born, or to die very early. […] He affirms, in another book, that the greatest blessing, which God has given to many among the punishments of this life is that they can lay violent hands upon themselves” (226) o In his essay, Hume does not go quite this far and commend suicide. But he does argue that it is not “criminal,” which is to say, that the act of committing suicide is not deserving of sanction (“guilt or blame”) o As we will see, there are some cases in which Hume thinks that suicide can be ‘prudent’ (that is, a reasonable decision based on the circumstances) and even ‘courageous,’ even if he stops short of claiming that it is a universally appropriate response to a life that promises more suffering than happiness Hume on the permissibility of suicide o Hume’s focus in the essay is on showing that none of the traditional arguments for the criminality of suicide are successful o Hume considers three sorts of reasons for the criminality of suicide: 1. It is a transgression against our duty to God 2. It is a transgression against our duty to our neighbours (i.e., family/those closest to us) or society 3. It is a transgression against our duty to ourselves o But, beyond this critical discussion, Hume clearly thinks that any strict prohibition on suicide is unjustified—that the prohibition on suicide is ultimately an attempt by systems of “superstition” to exert control over their followers. They play up the miseries of this world and then offer their system as the only possible source of comfort o The ultimate goal of Hume’s discussion, then, is to loosen the hold of systems of superstition over us and to restore us to a kind of freedom to dispose over ourselves as we please “Let us here endeavour to restore men to their native liberty, by examining all the common arguments against Suicide, and showing that that action may be free from every imputation of guilt or blame” (3) 1) that suicide violates our duty to God o Many religious traditions contend that suicide is impermissible because it violates a duty towards the supreme being—that we are, as it were, the property of God and a vehicle for His purposes in creation; as a result, that we should destroy ourselves would be contrary to His purposes for us and so an act of defiance “you are placed by Providence like a sentinel, in a particular station, and when you desert it without being recalled, you are equally guilty of rebellion against your almighty sovereign” (10) o Hume offers a variety of considerations against this sort of argument: The act of suicide abides by the same general laws of matter and motion through which God governs the rest of creation (it is not a violation of - - these), and these sometimes result in the destruction of a being. Selfdestruction as such is not inconsistent with the order of things (6) The power to end our lives is a natural power God has bestowed on us. Making use of it, then, cannot be inconsistent with divine purposes (7) To think that the voluntary end of one human life could impact God’s ability to realise his purposes is to over-estimate the significance of a single human life in the cosmos (7) Ending one’s life need not be an act of defiance of God, but an act in which there is gratitude for the pleasures already enjoyed but an understanding that the future promises only suffering (8) If God forbids suicide, then he would also have to forbid our willingly putting ourselves in situations where our death is likely, but this would mean that there would be no acts of heroism (9) We cannot know whether an individual’s act of suicide isn’t in fact in accordance with the divine plan (9, 10-1) 2) That suicide violates our duty to our neighbours/society o The act of suicide is also sometimes taken to violate our duty to our neighbours or society. Namely, that community/society is essentially a co-operative undertaking, so when I voluntarily remove myself from this, I cause harm to my fellows (I no longer “shoulder my load”) o Against this, Hume argues that duties to neighbours or society are, as far as we can tell, reciprocal—the receipt of a benefit is conditional on the payment/contribution of what I owe “All our obligations to do good to society seem to imply something reciprocal. I receive the benefits of society, and therefore ought to promote its interests” (12) o Hume notes, however, that the person who commits suicide no longer enjoys the benefit society confers (i.e., security of goods, protection from others). Rather, they remove themselves from society entirely and as such remove themselves from any debt/obligation o Moreover, Hume contends that in some cases a suicide is a public good—when for instance I am a “burden” to society (“my life hinders some person from being much more useful to society”—12) or, less controversially, a public official who is taken hostage and knows that they will divulge state secrets under torture decides instead to commit the act (13) “In such cases, my resignation of my life must not only be innocent, but laudable” (12) 3) that suicide violates our duty to ourselves o With respect to a putative violation of a duty to ourselves, the worry here seems to be that suicide is (always) contrary to our own “interests,” but we have a natural duty to promote our own interest o Hume denies this, and claims that there are obvious cases in which ending our lives is within our interest, and so does not violate our duty to act in accordance with them: - - “That suicide may often be consistent with interest and with our duty to ourselves, no one can question, who allows that age, sickness, or misfortune may render life a burden and make it worse than even annihilation.” (13) Hume the Pessimist? o Hume’s conclusion in the essay, then, is that suicide is not an act deserving of moral condemnation; far from it, there are even circumstances where it is consistent with our duty and interest, and where we might even praise someone for the prudence or courage that undertaking such an act involves: Far from being criminal, “both prudence and courage should engage us to rid ourselves at once of existence, when it becomes a burden” (14) This is to say, that the act of suicide can be a reasonable (prudent) decision when life promises more sorrow than happiness, and it can be courageous in cases where we sacrifice our life for the good of others. But that the act can have this character is only possible if we accept that suicide is not itself a criminal, or morally reproachable act o On its own, this result of Hume’s considerations in the essay is perhaps only of limited significance. However, when it is combined with the claims Philo makes in Part X of the Dialogues, then the result is rather more controversial We have already seen that in Part X Philo argues that, due to physical and psychic suffering, human life does, in most cases, promise more pain than pleasure But if suicide is not only permissible, but even prudent, when this is the case, then is a consequence of Hume’s argument that, for the most part, suicide is a permissible and even prudent choice, given the preponderance of suffering in human life? o But if this is all the case, then, returning to the challenge raised by the imaginary opponent in Part X of the Dialogues, why is it that more people do not commit this act of self-destruction? o Hume’s answer is that our natural fear, even terror of death is the only thing that prevents us from taking this final step Back to Philo on suicide o Returning to the Dialogues, in response to the challenge of the imagined opponent, if someone’s life is full of suffering why do they remain in life?, Hume (Philo) begins by quoting the following line: “Not satisfied with life, afraid of death” and continues: “This is the secret chain, say I, that holds us. We are terrified, not bribed to the continuance of our existence” (181-2) o That we are not “bribed” to continue living, means that it is not in virtue of expected pleasures that we remain in life and endure its miseries. In fact, Philo goes on to claim that the belief that the future promises more pleasure to offset the suffering we have endured in the past is irrational: - “Ask yourself, ask any of your acquaintances whether they would live over again the last ten or twenty years of their life. No! but the next twenty, they say, will be better” (184-5) But to think that the rest of one’s life holds out the possibility of pleasures that one could not obtain in the first part is, according to Philo, irrational. The best chance for us to attain a taste of happiness is, as Bayle would agree, the first part of our life, and if we haven’t got it then, then it is foolish for us to hope for it later o Instead, Philo claims that our decision to remain in life is a result of our “terror” of death. The fact that someone who experiences profound suffering does not exit this life is not evidence that their sufferings are only feigned. Instead, it is evidence that their fear of death overpowers or outweighs the sufferings they endure. o Returning to Hume’s essay, it is because of the power that this fear naturally has over us that we can also be sure that most of those who decide not to “remain in this life” have not come to this decision as a result of trivial considerations: “I believe that no man ever threw away life, while it was worth keeping. For such is our natural horror of death, that small [i.e., insignificant] motives will never be able to reconcile us to it” (13) Grounds for optimism? Rousseau’s second discourse o Hume’s conclusions in Part X of the Dialogues and the essay “On Suicide” seem to leave us in a rather pessimistic place. Life is, on the whole, worse than it is better, and suicide is a permissible, even reasonable course of action in light of this. The only thing that preserves us in existence, however, is a terror of death that makes us afraid of taking matters into our own hands. And this terror of death is itself a further source of (psychic) suffering that only makes life worse o It’s hard to think about what might serve to alleviate the concerns that Hume (and Bayle) raise. But one attempt is that of Rousseau in his “Discourse on the Origin of Inequality,” also know as the “Second Discourse” (a previous discourse on the arts and sciences was published previously) o The way in which Rousseau arguably responds to Hume is by contending that the primary sources of suffering (including the psychic variety) are man-made—they are functions of the corruptions that ensue when human beings congregate into societies and thereby leave their preferable, solitary natural state You might recall Rousseau’s response to Voltaire on the Lisbon earthquake which was right along these lines—human action significantly amplifies the physical harms caused by the natural disaster o For Rousseau, human psychic suffering stems from a system of inequality that we ourselves introduce. But he thinks this has the optimistic consequence that we might rectify the situation through human action (i.e.: we broke it so we can fix it). Whether Rousseau comes across as an optimist is, in any case, a question you might keep in mind as you read the Second Discourse Lecture 8: J.J Rousseu - Who is Rousseau? o Philosopher o Born in Geneva (1712-1778) o Also known for his book Social Contract (1762), which is why you are likely to read him in a political theory/philosophy course. o His ideas influenced the French Revolution. o Freedom is fundamental guiding principle. o The people, not monarchs, have the legitimate power to legislate laws for themselves. o Perhaps his most famous quote: o “Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains” (Social Contract, Book 1, chapter 1). o He favoured direct democracy as this was the best way to ensure human freedom and authority. Only laws given to ourselves by ourselves can secure our freedom. o Social Contract theory. Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) John Locke (1632-1704) Rousseau (1712-1778) Rawls (1921-2002) - Why Rousseau for this course? o If Rousseau is read as a primarily political philosopher, why study him in a course on evil, suffering and pessimism? o Because he has much to say on the human condition. o An account of unhappiness and of our miseries, of what has gone wrong with our lives. o While he is not attempting to answer any fundamental questions about the nature of existence itself, make claims about the ultimate value of life or offer a metaphysical view of existence, he does provide insights into suffering - Reading the second discourse o Complete title: Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Mankind (1755). o The First Discourse is called A Discourse on the Moral Effects of the Arts and Sciences (1750). o The Second Discourse was written in response to a question posed by the Academy of Dijon: o What is the origin of inequality among mankind and does natural law decree inequality? o In other words, where does inequality come from? Are we naturally unequal? If so, why? How? If we are not naturally unequal, then (again) where does inequality come from? Is it justified? o Natural inequalities: health, strength, so on. o These are not philosophically very interesting. o Moral and political inequality. o This is the question. Why do some have authority over others? Why do some have more wealth, honour, influence, power and privileges than others? How can this be justified? o The points: Moral inequality is not natural Inequality is a human invention Human misery is the result of society Therefore: the root of all our predicaments are found in our relations with others, in society itself o How, where do we start to answer the question of moral inequality and start to arrive at the answer we have just seen? o Suppose there was a time before any established authority existed, a time before we were governed and coerced into acting in certain ways and refraining from acting in others. Call this the state of nature. o How was life in the state of nature? o How would we live with no authority above us? o What would we do? Not do? o What would be right? Wrong? o Would any of this impact our happiness? Why? o Would we suffer more or less? o Do we generally, agree with Rousseau? o “(...) it is no such easy task to distinguish between what is natural and what is artificial in the present constitution of man” (82). o This is a common problem. How do we get around it? o Many of our behaviours are often justified because they are natural in us. Competition, a degree of selfishness and so on are often described as natural tendencies in us. o How can we know this?? o “(...) it is no such easy task to distinguish between what is natural and what is artificial in the present constitution of man” (82). This is a common problem. How do we get around it? o Many of our behaviours are often justified because they are natural in us. Competition, a degree of selfishness and so on are often described as natural tendencies in us. How can we know this?? o “If we consider human society with a calm and disinterested eye, it seems at first sight to show us nothing but the violence of the powerful and the oppression of the weak” (85). o “ (...) nothing is less stable in human life than those exterior relations (...) weakness or power, poverty or riches” (85). What do we think? o “If I consider him (...) such as he must have issued from the hands of nature (...) I see him satisfying his hunger under an oak, and his thirst at the first brook; I see o o o o o o o o o o o o o him laying himself down to sleep at the foot of the same tree that afforded him his meal; and there are all his wants completely supplied” (90) (...) it appears that no other animal naturally makes war on man, except in the case of self-defense or extreme hunger” (92) Are humans our major threats? “(...) In proportion as he becomes sociable and a slave to others, he becomes weak, fearful, mean-spirited” (94) Do others bring out the worst in us? “(...) the man who first made himself clothes and built himself a cabin supplied himself with things which he did not need much, since he has lived without them till then” (94) How is this familiar to us today? Do we still do this today? Why? We humans are motivated by perfectibility –the faculty of improvement (96). This is what differentiates us from other animals. Perfectibility is progress. We are not content, satisfied with simply being, with only existing. If this is true, what does this say about us and existence? “It would be a melancholy necessity for us to be obliged to allow this distinctive faculty [to be] the source of all man’s misfortunes” (96). But it is, or not?? Sad. Perhaps. To admit this. “this faculty (...) produces his discoveries and mistakes, his virtues and his vices, and, in the long run, renders him both his own and nature’s tyrant” (96) “the knowledge of death, and of its terrors, is one of the first acquisitions made by man, in consequence of his deviating from the animal state” (97). This is a mistaken claim about animals, but setting this point aside for now, what is the main point here? What do we think about this? “In civil life we can scarcely meet a single person who does not complain of his existence” (104). “Was ever any free savage known to have been so much tempted to complain of life, and do away with himself? (104) Do we all complain at some point? Do we all have some sort of existential crisis? Do we get depressed and fall into ennui (weariness, discontent). In support of the claim that, overall, we have a disposition to reject cruelty and harm: “the pathetic picture of a man, who, with his hands tied up, is obliged to behold a beast of prey tear a child from the arms of his mother, and then with his teeth grind the tender limbs (...) what horrible emotions must not such a spectator experience at the sight of an event which does not personally concern him? What anguish must he not suffer at his not being able to assist the fainting mother or the expiring infant?” (107) A Clockwork Orange, directed by Stanley Kubrick, 1971. What about Love? Love is a social creation as well. - - - - “As his mind was never in a condition to form abstract ideas of regularity and proportion, neither is his heart susceptible of sentiments of admiration and love” (109). “the jealousy of lovers and the vengeance of husbands every day produce duels, murders, and even worse crimes; where duty to fidelity serves only to propagate adultery” (110) Takeaways thus far: o We strive (perfectibility) o We give ourselves objects and things we do not need. o We come to know death o We start to complain about existence o Even love (the noblest of emotions) is a creation that causes more harm than good How did we get here? Why did we leave our happy lives in nature behind and create a society where laws, customs, social expectations and morality encroach themselves upon us and create misery in our lives? o The answer? “The first man, who after enclosing a piece of ground, took it into his head to say, this is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him, was the real founder of civil society” (113). o What negative impacts did private property bring about? All the ones we have seen, plus: The establishment of the nuclear family which meant dependence (117). The reliance on objects. “To lose them was a misfortune, to possess them no happiness” (117). Comparisions. “Everyone began to notice the rest, and wished to be noticed himself; and public esteem acquired a value. He who sang or danced best; the handsomest, the strongest, the most eloquent, came to be the most respected” (118). Division of labour. We became dependent on others, power and authority arise. Inequality entrenches itself. “The rank and lot of every man established, not only as to the amount of property and the power of serving or hurting others, but likewise as to genius, beauty, strength or skill, merits or talents (...) it became the interest of men to appear what they were really not” (122). o This was not what life was like in the state of nature. How accurate is this description of life in society today? Now, “in consequence of a multitude of new needs, [we are] brought into subjugation, as it were, to all nature and especially to his fellows” (122). o Thus, society and its laws are in place to benefit the powerful and ensure that inequality is entrenched. There is nothing natural about this Online week 9 lecture: Giacomo Leopardi (1798-1837) - Born in Recanati, Italy. Lots of health issues. - His family belonged to the land-owning aristocracy. Born into wealth. - Educated at home - His father, Monaldo, owned an impressive library of over 10000 books. It was open to the public in 1812. - He taught himself Greek, then Hebrew. - Numerous health issues, among them were a hunchback formed in his teens, and deterioration of his spine. - His magnum opus: Zibaldone (1898, posthumously): all his work collected over his lifetime. A compilation of thoughts. Poetry, philosophy, literature, general thoughts. - Why Leopardi? o A poet and philosopher o Widely read. Schop, the foremost pessimist philosopher said of him in regards to the misery of existence that “no one has treated this subject so thoroughly and exhaustively as Leopardi in our own day. He is entirely imbued and penetrated with it; everywhere his theme is the mockery and wretchedness of his existence. He presents it on every page of hus works, yet in such a multiplicity of forms and application, with such a wealth of imagery, that he never wearies us”. (WWR2, 588). These are remarkable works of praise, given that shop had a reputation for being a harsh critic of philosophers he considered charlatans (Like Hegel) o Leopardi therefore offers the best gateway to pessimism o So was he a pessimist? Not really. Depends how you define it. But he did not think highly of life. Rather, he thought happiness was not possible at all. - We will look at two texts found in moral fables (1824). This is a series a fables an dialogues on existence and suffering o 1) the history of the human race; origin of humanity o 2) nature and an Icelander; dialogue between a traveller and nature - The history of the human race o An alternate account of human “fall from grace: o Reveals truths about the human condition o Reveals why existence is filled with pain and struggles o Life was one, it seemed, good… too good perhaps? “… and the idea of being content with what they enjoyed at present, without the promise of any increase of their well-being, did not attract them” (3)… like the garden of eve, being perfect? Did not interest humans as there no room to increase our well-being. Life was too easy, everything was known. “an overt distaste for their existence took universal possession of them” (4). Boredom. “this situation horrified the gods – that luving creatures preferred death to life and that life itself in some of its own subjects (…) should be the instrument of their destruction” (4). o Jove wondered: “how is it not enough for them, as it is for other creatures, to be alive and free from all bodily aches and pains (…) since they always desire in all circumstances the impossible, this desire troubles them the more” (6) o Our minds, our thoughts and desires are the source of our predicaments. We are our own tormentors. o Life was made difficult NOT as a punishment but as a solution. Difficult was introduced in order to love life. o Jove desired to preserve humanity through two means: fill their life with real ills, and involve our lives with a thousand toils to keep them occupied and distracted from their own minds (6) o “So he began by spreading among them a multitudinous of diseases and an endless array of other misfortunes. He wished, by varying the conditions and chances of mortal life, to obviate satiety and increase the value of benefits in contrast to ills; and he hoped that the lack of pleasure in those now accustomed to worse things should prove to be much more bearable than it had in the past” (7). Made difficult for us to find pleasure in life. o As a further compensation for these new-found difficulties, phantasms (illusions) were introduced into the world. Love-Justice-Virtue-Patriotism-Wisdom o Humans were now willing to fight and give there lives for these phantasms Q: Are there any ideals or principles we would be willing to die for? o Alas, once again we become unsatisfied with life. Once societies were firmly established, boredom and sloth reigned again among us. “There was a resurgence of that bitter desire for a happiness unknown and alien to the nature of the universe” (9). Q: Can we ever be satisfied and not have desires? What else do we want? o At this point, Jove gave up on us. “He was certain by now that no measures could provide, no condition be suitable, no place satisfactory (…) ultimately their stupidity and arrogant demands roused the wrath of the god (…) he resolved to lay all sympathy aside and punish the human race forever by condemning it for all future ages to wretchedness” (10,11) o In the end, truth was sent to live among us. Truth became our “perpetual director” (11). Truth revealed all our “unhappiness and keep it continually before (our) eye, representing it as not merely the result of chance, but something they could by no accident or remedy escape – nor ever, while they lived, interrupt” (11). Truth revealed all our unhappiness We can never change the fundamental feature of existence. This is a central pessimist claim. o The truth, therefore, is dangerous. We will realize that “human life will lack all value, all rectitude, in thought as in deed” (12). We may wage war of all against all or become extinct through some other measure. Q: Is it true that if happiness in life is impossible, then life lacks value? For whom? For the child born in a warzone or that perishes in an earthquake? Is it valuable for us, lucky enough to not live in a war torn country ravaged by natural disasters? - Nature and an Icelander o An Icelander flees society, trying to flee nature itself, searching for a peaceful tranquil life o The main points: Nature (the world) is not interested in us or our well-being The world was not made for our sake (71) Life is a cycle of production and destruction (72) o The Icelander: “I often marvel not a little that you (nature) have inspired in us so great and constant and insatiable a craving for pleasure” - again, desire and pursuit appear to be reasons for the misery of life. Keep this in mind. o Nature: do you think I built this villa for you? Or that I keep these children of mine, and these servants, to minister you? I certainly have other things to think about than amusing you and keeping you in luxury. o Icelander: Look, friend, just as you have not made this villa for my use, so it was in your power not to invite me here. But since of your own free will you have asked me to live here, do you not have an obligation to ensure, so far as you, that I at least live here without suffering and without danger? I now ask whether I ever begged you to place me in this universe. Or whether I forced myself into it with violence and against your will? (72) Week 9: Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1869) - What is philosophical pessimism? o It is not a mood, a temperament, a phycological predisposition. Not everyone that claims life is bad or miserable is a pessimist. Not all philosophers that argue this are pessimists. o It is a view about the essence of existence. Pessimists have a metaphysical view. This view holds that suffering, pain, and misery are inescapable features of existence itself. In virtue of this; nonexistence is preferable to existence. The retches character of existence is a philosophical truth that is to be debated and argued against on philosophical grounds. o There are many different approaches to pessimism - Schopenhauer o Born in Danzig, Prussia (now Poland) o The first systematic pessimist philosopher o His book The World as Will and Representation (1818) is where his complete pessimist system is laid out. All other pessimists that followed him are in a conversation with the WWR. They agree, expand, disagree and/or dispute the points he presented there. o His metaphysical system is essential in order to have a fair understanding of his pessimism. A transcendental idealist working within the Kantian tradition. We need to have a notion of the will. So what is it? - Very summarized: That which is reality beyond how we perceive it. Its defining feature is to want and endlessly desire. Makes it possible that we have images and representations of things. We can understand will as a source of life – what gives rise to all the objects we see. o After reading his views, everyone can agree that he makes very clear points and he is a good writer. “Nothing is easier than writing so that no one can understand it, just as conversely nothing is harder than to express meaningful thoughts so that everyone must understand them. Unintelligibility is related to unintelligent, and it is always infinitely more likely that it conceals a mystification rather than a great profundity.” (PP2, pg 465). This is a criticism of Hegel (and Fichte and Schelling). Keep this in mind while writing philosophy papers and exams Parerga and paralipomena o Parerga means subordinate work, and paralipomena means passed over. o Fame and recognition was achieved with this (1851), something he wanted and thought he deserved. Was a best seller o Written in an aphoristic style, more accessible to the general public. It is not a continuous ongoing argument as WWR is. o Largely a posteriori (after experience) arguments, whereas WWR is… o For some, evil is privation, absence of good, like darkness is absence of light. In this way, then, evil is not a thing created by God. o But for Schopenhauer, pleasure, not evil, is the privation (pleasure is a privation, an absence). We always experience and feel pain and only when we do not feel pain do we feel the absence of pain, which is to say pleasure. For example, we never directly feel health, only pain. When we say we feel health we are really saying we feel an absence of pain. Health is a negative, a momentary retreat of the will. o “All happiness and satisfaction, is the negative, that is the mere suspending of desire and ceasing of pain” (S. 149). This is related to his claim that everything is will, the will is always present. o We feel hunger, but when hunger is satisfied (it retreats), we no longer feel hungry. o “We painfully feel the loss of pleasure and enjoyments, as soon as they fail to appear (…) we do not become conscious of the three greatest blessings of life as such, namely health, youth, and freedom, as long as we possess them, but only after we have lost them (…) we notice that certain days of our life were happy only after they have made room for unhappy ones” (WWR 1, 575) What is it like to feel youth? Freedom? Health? Do we actually directly feel these things when we are young, healthy, and free? Do we feel free or do we feel unimpeded? DO we feel health or do we feel nothing? o His theory of the negativity of pleasure is, rightly so, disputed by other pessimists (Hartmann in particular), but his pessimism does not live or fall on this claim. o S. 152: If everything came to you so simply and you had everything you want, there would be no purpose. A fool’s paradise. o S. 148: life was designed around pain and not pleasure. Suffering is the base of life. You can be happy, but you will be unhappy. It’s a pretty bad design. Is it true that, in general terms, the dangers and pains are numerous (infinite), but pleasures are few, limited and unique to each one? o From WWR2, he says that if we look at this world, its full of needy creatures. o An essential point for pessimists is that the misery of existence is not an anthropocentric concern. o When pessimists denounce existence for its wretchedness they really do denouse all of existence, not just human existence. WWR, 199. He says its all about humans, but were not that different from other animals. Animals also suffer, and some humans suffer more than other humans. Not just in nature, but today in factory farming. Animals die and live miserable lives. How much pleasure is one animal getting from food as compared to all the suffering the prey animal went through? More suffering than pain. o Existence as a whole is filled with pain, work, sacrifice, and misery. Its how nature works. WWR1, 325. o Animals, much more so than we, are satisfied by mere existence (S.153) Is mere existence tolerable or desirable? Or just be? o “One should try to imagine that the act of procreation were neither a need, nor accompanied by sexual pleasure, but instead a matter of pure rational reflection; could the human race even continue to exist?” (S. 156) If having children was a decision left purely to reason and logic, would we procreate? o Schopenhauer was one of the first European philosophers to seriously consider eastern philosophy. Looked at buddhism and Hinduism. o Pessimism and compassion Compassion is an important attitude in pessimism. Due to the essential miserable character of existence and therefore that we are all bound to suffer, he argues that to inflict even more harm on others is misguided. This is also related to his monism (the oneness of the will). S. 156 Life is essentially a state of distress and often misery, where everyone has to struggle and fight for his existence and therefore cannot always put on a happy face S.156 Be nice to others, we’re all going through this together. Its terrible for everybody. Be understanding. We’re all one at bottom, theres no real difference between you and I. Online lecture week 10: James Sully 1842-1923 - Pessimism, a history and a criticism. James is English, a psychologist and a philosopher. - A history o Some important points to keep in mind: o Pessimism, a History and a Criticism was published in 1877 o James Sully was primarily a psychologist. This is an important fact to keep in mind because it may be relevant to his overall critique of pessimism. o This book represents the first comprehensive study of 19th Century German pessimism o This is the most important historical period for pessimism. o In Germany, for reasons not totally known, there occurred a unique event: pessimism was a popular topic. o As Frederick Beiser says in his book Weltschmerz (2016) “Beginning in the 1860s, and lasting until the end of the 19th century, the dark cloud of pessimism hung thick over Germany. This bleak and black mood spread far and wide. It was not confined to decadent aristocratic circles; it could also be found in the middle classes, among students at universities, workers in factories (…) pessimism soon became fashionable, the talk of the town, the theme of literary salons“. (1) o This period is known as the period of Weltschmerz. This is a German word that means worldpain (Beiser, 1). Largely forgotten today, it is currently experiencing a renewed interest. Important figures in that period (from left to right): Arthur Schopenhauer Olga Plümacher Philipp Mainländer Agnes Taubert Julius Bahnsen Eduard von Hartmann o Sully’s book is important for two reasons: It introduced German pessimism (in real-time) to the English speaking world. It made direct criticisms to pessimism that were later answered by Olga Plümacher. We shall look at some of her replies in the next in-person lecture. So what did Sully say about pessimism? - A criticism of pessimism o Rightfully so, he says that to most people pessimism “is nothing like a philosophical creed or a speculative system“.(1) o But, as he acknowledges, it is (a philosophical system). At least partially so. o Recall the distinction I made between philosophical pessimism and psychological pessimism and how I defined it (in class lecture on Schopenhauer). o For Sully, it is mistaken to draw such a clear difference between them. Why? o “At first sight it might seem that these two kinds of pessimism, the popular and instinctive, and the philosophical and reasoned, have nothing to do with one another (…) it is true that German pessimism as a philosophy of existence must be examined and estimated on its own grounds and be accepted or rejected [on its merits, but] at the same time the full significance of this speculative doctrine cannot be understood except by reference to a pre-philosophical pessimism. Systems of philosophy do not spring from pure isolated intellect, but are the products of concrete times made up in part of certain emotional and moral pecularities“ (2,3) o As a consequence, he says: “I propose, therefore, to interpret the terms optimism and pessimism in their widest meaning. Any theory which distinctly attributed to the world and to human life a decided worth, representing it as something good, beautiful (…) will be included under optimism (…) similarly, pessimism will cover all doctrines (…) which distinctly deny this value to life“ (5). o What we can say for now is that Sully’s background in psychology certainly seems to be play a role here insofar as he views pessimism (and optimism for that matter) as philosophical systems that can only result from minds that are predisposed to negativity (or positivity in the case of optimism). This line of criticism, however, is not very fruitful. To think about: is there any philosophy not made possible by one’s own predispositions, temperaments, interests? o Sully ultimately considers pessimism (and optimism) to be extremes. o The problem with pessimism: “an impartial view of the facts of life and the teachings of science properly so called has led us to believe that happiness, interpreted in a rational sense, is and has been attained by some indeterminable proportion of mankind” (398) o Recall what we learned about pessimism: it is not only about human suffering. Even if human existence has largely achieved happiness, animal life would need to be taken into consideration before any definitive evaluation about the worth of life and the amount of happiness that exists is possible. o Sully ultimately considers pessimism (and optimism) to be extremes. o A better position is what he calls meliorism. o He gets this term from English author, George Elliot (Mary Ann Evans, 18191880). She wrote Middlemarch (1871). o “Our line of reasoning provides us, then, with a practical conception which lies midway between the extremes of optimism and pessimism, and which, to use a term for which I am indebted to our first living woman-writer and thinker, George Elliot, may be appropriately styled Meliorism. By this I would understand the faith which affirms not merely our power of lessening evil—this nobody questions—but also our ability to increase the amount of positive good” (399) o To think about: arguments are never extreme. They are valid, invalid, sound, unsound, strong or weak. Keep this in mind when evaluating pessimism (and optimism for that matter). o A conclusion may be extreme. But if it is, then that is in virtue of some premise (reason) that is already extreme (by extremes we can mean something to be wholly unreasonable, unjustifiable, outlandish, abusive, discriminatory and so on). But if the premises are plausible then given a sound argument the conclusion is also plausible. Read Sully with that point in mind: “As we have seen, neither optimism nor pessimism can lay any claim to be a strictly logical belief—that is to say, the pure result of observation and induction” (403). o Setting aside whether or not any philosophical system can ever be strictly logical (that is devoid of any personal biases, predispositions or other subjective preferences that may taint ones approach to an issue) it is still the case that the strength of the arguments is an essential aspect that needs to be considered when evaluating a system. Pessimism and/or optimism should be able to stand on the strength of its arguments –even if they are not strictly logical. The personal temperament or psychological predispositions of the thinker should take second place. To think: Is there anything extreme or unplausible in the pessimist argument? o "Pessimism is the natural outcome of the carping, fault-finding disposition (…) to perceive the defects of our dwelling-place is to set ourselves above it, to prove the superiority of our conception to the actual object before us. By how much, one wonders, would the amount of human criticism be diminished if men no longer derived from the process any agreeable feeling of intellectual elevation" (423). So what is sully saying? Pessimism is not the result of an analysis of arguments, but it is the natural outcome of a fault finding disposition. Result of people with negative attitudes to life. There is some pleasure that some people obtain when they complain about life and struggle for existence. o "Again, although all men dislike pain itself, most men like the credit of bearing it" (423). o "According to this, we are hopelessly enchained by the very nature of things, and all our struggles to get free from misery are destined to be futile" (424) o Although this is not quite accurate, the point is well taken. o "In truth pessimism flatters him with a portrait of himself, in which he appears as another Prometheus, suffering tortures from the hand of the cruel Zeus (…) pessimism enables its adherent to pose as some wronged and suffering divinity, to the admiration of himself at least" (424). What to make of this line of criticism? o It seems to me that this criticism misses the mark and is largely due to a misunderstanding of pessimism. o Pessimism is not a self-centred philosophy. The questions are really different ones: Is life, overall, a happy fulfilling experience? How much suffering is there in all existence? Why is there so much suffering? What are we to do about it? If anything, this line of criticism could be addressed to Nietzsche insofar as he did indeed claim that suffering and pain provided us with the means necessary to achieve greatness and give our lives meaning and purpose. To bear pain is a sign of greatness. We shall see more on Nietzsche during the last week of March. Lecture week 10: Olga Plümacher and Eduard von Hartmann: scientific pessimism and extinction - Need a good understanding of Schopenhauer metaphysics for further concepts. He is first pessimist philosopher. Hartmann was last great pessimistic philosopher. - Plümacher 1839-1895 o Born in St. Petersburg, Russia o Important philosopher pessimist actively involved in the pessimism controversy. o Working from Hartmann’s pessimist philosophy. Defends, develops, and expands Hartmann’s pessimism. o Engaged with Sully’s criticism of pessimism. Sully has misread Hartmann. Recall what sully said about pessimism more generally: that as a philosophy it is largely possible only where there already is a psychological predisposition to see the negative in life As she says, “the result is, to give the reader not only an inadequate, but a decidedly distorted view of Hartmann’s great book.” She does clarify that Hartmann’s pessimism, as Schopenhauer’s, follows a priori from certain metaphysical claims. In both cases, the will. In doing so she defends the relevance of metaphysics. So, while Hartmann’s pessimism is largely meant to be supported by empirical a posteriori claims, metaphysics, Plümacher clarifies, still matters and factors in. The fact of happiness does not defeat pessimism. Quotes from slides*** o (73) - o Sully says: “we have the fact that happiness has been and is now being realized. By this fact alone the fundamental idea of modern pessimism is amply refuted.” o The reply (82) So is happiness preferable to nothingness? If it is, then how much more happiness than pain must we experience in order to make life preferable (justified)? To think about: Why does the psychological critique faul in its criticism of pessimism? o 1. My life is good, but is it about my life? No. Think of all of humanity. Wars, famine, disease, death… o 2. But what If now (or at some point in the future) humanity achieves a level of development whereby all (or most) of our ills are overcome? But is it about the life of humanity? No. o 3. Think of animal life. In nature. In our use of them. The numbers of death and suffering are staggering. Recall: 63 billion land animals are slaughtered each year plus 100 billion aquatic animals. This alone can support the claim that the vast majority of life is a decidedly miserable experience. Death is an evil, a source of suffering and not, as Sully suggests, something pessimists would welcome. o Quote Hartmann 1842-1906 o Born in Berlin Actively developed a pessimist theory that was different to Schop His pessimism was meant to be scientific – this is to say a pessimism susceptible to empirical verification. By looking at the actual lived conditions of our lives and the sorts of being we are, pessimism follows. His most important work was Philosophy of the Unconscious (1869) This book was a bestseller. Hartmann became a public celebrity. As Beiser said, “Hartmann’s philosophy became the hot topic in literary circles, and droves of articles, reviews, pamphlets and whole works appeared, either attacking or defending it” (122) o Hartmann and the Unconscious Largely a posteriori, there is still an important a priori argument The essence of the world is what he called the unconscious. Complicated philosopher to understand; not a great writer The unconscious plays the same role that the will does in Schops philosophy This means that the world, existence itself is at bottom constituted by a force that, in turn, has two components: will and reason. Will: an irrational, purposeless and insatiable force Reason: arises because the will needs it in order to give content to the will. In other words: the will needs an object of desire (it cant simply will in abstract) and so reason supplies the will with that object o Hartmann on pleasure and pain Our biology makes pleasure difficult. It also makes pain easily felt This has to do with, among other things how our nerves work. Think of any pleasure we may experience. We get easily accustomed to and require ever higher exposure to sustain the levels of pleasure: more likes, more praise, more drugs, more money, more, more, more. Most pleasures require work. They are acquired. In other words, there is struggle and sacrifice involved at first, think of riding a bike. Appreciating literature, music, art, food. Learning a new language. Pain has no such requirements. It always makes itself felt straightforwardly, We do not have to learn to feel pain. Would you like to taste the worst flavour, followed by your favourite? Worst smell, followed by your favourite? Worst smell, followed by your favourite? Hartmann thinks we would always say no, showing that nonexperience (non-being) is the better choice to experience (being). Life is decidedly a miserable experience Let us imagine death to draw nigh this man and say “thy life-period is run out, and at this hour thou art on the brink of annihilation; but it depends on thy present voluntary decision, once again, precisely in the same way, to go through thy now closed life with complete oblivion of all that has passed. Now choose!” Death says you can have a chance to relive your life, but you wont remember it. Would you? Leibniz: yes, we would, given different circumstances but same amounts of goods and bads. Neitzsche: We should aim to say yes, so live life so as to make that yes something we would fully embrace and welcome. Hartmann and possible worlds Hartmann says that this is the best of all possible worlds Wait! Is this not what optimists say? Why would a pessimist agree with this? Precisely because the unconscious has a rational side Reason tries to tame and guide the will to lessen suffering and makes the best of what it has to work with “for the reason the question therefore is to repair the mischief \ done by the irrational will” (126) And, so far, this is the best that reason can accomplish. So it is indeed the best possible world and look at how bad it is! o Hartmann on extinction – if life is so bad, then why do we continue to exist? To Hartmann’s credit he dealt directly with what is known as the question of redemption. That is, what (if anything) can we do to eliminate suffering? The answer: given how this world is (unconscious) and the sorts of being we are, there is no possibility of ever achieving a good life. Nonexistence will always be preferable (insofar as we want to avoid pain and suffering). Another question: so if this is the case and we are irremediably lost, why do we continue to exist? Why do we procreate? The answer: Once again, to his credit, he addressed this question head-on and offered an explanation. Three illusions keep us alive We continue to live and favour life because we have not yet come to realize the truth of pessimism. Reason will, however, one day reveal this to all of us 1. We think we are already happy, but this is an illusion insofar as a more reasoned look at our lives reveals that happiness is not possible (recall pain and pleasure). The past is always better or the future is filled with hope. Humans have a tendency to forget past bad moments and romanticize the good things… but its bad because we don’t have the ability to objectively evaluate our lives. 2. We think that happiness is possible in the other world… role that religion plays. We suffer and endure hardships here. Yes. But the after-life is the promise of that happiness that is denied to us in this world. 3. If happiness is not possible now and there is no after-life, then happiness is possible in the future. Collective matter – humanity as a whole an progress and obtain happiness in the future. o Personal happiness is no longer main concern. Serve society for all happiness. Sacrifice self for the greater good. Conservative politics comes from this. o But destined to failure. No matter how much progress we will never berid sickness, age, dependence on will and power of others, want, discontent (103) o Even education (a valued good) only increases discontent. The more we know, the more we see through illusions and understand the misery of existence. o (114) o Redemption? Are we hopelessly lost? What can we do about this? Can suffering be erased? YES> We should all cease to exist. Total disappearance of everything that exists in the universe. Extinction. Nonexistence is preferable to existence. However this does not entail killing or murdering violence is ruled out To be peaceful, informed and voluntary affair Peaceful: perhaps ceasing procreation? Informed: a thorough knowledge of our situation and understanding the natyre of the unconscious and how life unfolds through history Voluntary: after understanding……… Schop recommended each individual adopt the ascetic life-style. Don’t listen to will. Hartmann disagrees (131). The collective is very important for Hartmann. 1. Reason will eventually reveal that happiness is not possible o 127 2. … (133) (134) as a consequence, we must participate fully within this universal unconscious and devote ourselves to its deployment Do last couple slides from ppt (135) (137) (139) Week 11 lecture: Friedrich Nietzsche 1844-1900, Röken, Prussia - Philologist (study of language, interpretation of texts within a historical context) and a philosopher - Nietzsche and Schopenhauer; A tale of suffering, pessimism, and life o Nie was initially captivated by Schop o He greatly admired his courage, strength and honesty o In his eyes, schop challenged traditional morality, was an atheist and was relentless in the pursuit of truth He has an essay called “Schopenhauer as Educator” Praises schop’s pessimistic views o Later, distanced himself from Schop. He took a different view of human existence, the “problem of suffering” o Still he continued to engage his ideas with Schop? o Differences: Nie has no system, and no grand metaphysical architecture His philosophy ends up being life-affirming; about achieving individual greatness Rejecting ascetism, quietism, passivity and any ethics of renunciation o The birth of tragedt His first published work 1972 Became very critical of it in his later works – too endebeted to Schop Many readings possible Is it a work about the origins/development of Greek Tragedy? Is it an attempt to explain why Greek Tragedy disappeared? Is it an attempt to show how Western culture can recover the spirit that was lost when tragedy ended? Is it a work of aesthetics? All of the above Four our purposes in this course: Pessimism and suffering are universal concerns The Greeks dealt with these questions in a way that allowed them to live and achieve greatness How did they deal with this? (19) There is a duality; not revealed in philosophy but in art. Metaphysical principles are lived principles. Big on re-assessing his work; self-criticism. He used schops terms because he didn’t have the courage to use his own (21) what does apollo represent? Apollos principle of individuation; giving sense to objects which gives structure. Apollo more represents appearance, strength, beauty, courage, wisdom. The divine image of all of these – what we aspire to be. God of the Sun. Stands for representations: strong, powerful, calm As we learned from Schop, the world is WILL and REPRESENTATIONS and Nie buys into this Enter Dionysius (22). What are those forces?? o Energy, desire, the flourishing of life Music, dance, frenzy. Connection with the vital energies of life (23). Dance gestures communicate an entranced state. A thirst for life. The boundless force of life came, apparently, to Greek society from the outside The Greeks were, for a time “completely sheltered and shielded by the figure of Apollo who stood tall and proud among them and who with the Medusa’s head warded off this grotesque barbaric Dionysian force, the most dangerous power it had to encounter. (25)” The Dionysian spirit, however, only achieved a high artistic expression in Greek culture and was not bare and uncultured as it was in those that were at the door of Greece The outside Dionysian forces were largely incomprehensible o the Greek Apollonian culture What was unique about Greek culture? (25)(26) how these two forces are merged in Greek art Through this artistic expression, we become one in the Dionsyian “Music expresses … with the greatest distinctness and truth, the inner being, the in-itself, of the world” (WWWRI, 264) “Here I believe I have accomplished this task in his [Schop] spirit and in his honour” (37) Music is an expression of the will itself; of the vital forces and energies of life itself The Olympian gods were seen as a collection of happy, calm, and serene Gods, looking over humanity Recall Apollo is one of them He provided protection from the forces of unbounded life “knocking at the doors” But Nie says that the Dionysian forces were always, however, present in Greek culture, living side-by-side with the Apollonian even though Apollo cast a veil over the Dionysian so as to conceal it from the Greeks This was the result of a cultural vital need, because the Greeks knew the truth and they channeled it through their Gods “The Greeks knew and felt the terror and horrors of existence” (28) They needed help to face this. “… through the Apollian drive towards beauty, the Olympians’ drive divine reign of hoy developed in a slow series oftransitions from the original Titan’s divine reign of terror”(28) The Gods were always there to make life possible for the Greeks. HOW? o Greek gods are more relatable to humans (26) Regardless of whether it is good or evil*** It is life itself that must be deified (28) x2 Because of the ways the Greeks could balance Apollo and Dionysius they were able to revert the idea that death is the best option. These gods are not conceived of beings above human affairs and always good – since they don’t have these characteristics, the Greeks were able to better face existence. In the Gods they saw life itself reflected. As defined by the Dionysian forces, life is pain, suffering and struggle The will redeems itself (gives meaning and purpose to itself) by creating us, appearances … *QUOTE Schops pessimism and its denial of the will is challenged because redemption is not achieved through denial (31) “For only as an aesthetic phenomenon are existence and the world justified to eternity” If you want to redeem yourself, you don’t do it by denying the will but you reaffirm appearances (apollo). Affirm existence. (91) So what happened? Why did the tragedy die?... Because of the theoretical man We want knowledge obtained through reason. We elevate rationality, We seek to concquer the world and tame it. Quote Socrates, the theoretical man, “the archetype of the theoretical optimist” (83)… (82)… (100) We can know individual things (the world of objects, as it appears to us), correct them, manipulate them and this has lead to the current situation whereby we think we can master the world Make the contrast with pessimism in general but with Schop in particular. In essence, existence is one – suffering, pain. But for Schop the way to deal is will denial (renounce life desires and individualism), Nie suggests how Greeks dealt with same terrors we all deal with in a way that brings about greatness. Online lecture week 11: The world as will and representation - Representations o What is a representation? o “everything that exists for knowledge, and hence the whole of this world, is only object in relation to subject, perception of the perceiver, in a word, representation” (3). o “For with the exception of the Sceptics and Idealists, the others in the main speak fairly consistent of an object forming the basis of the representation”. (95). o “This object indeed is different in its whole being and nature from the representation, but yet is in all respects as like it as one egg is like another” (95). o Natural sciences and math cannot reveal to us what the basis, what the object of representations is o “But in this way we do not obtain the slightest information about the inner nature of any of these phenomena” (97) o “we want to know the significance of those representations; we ask whether this world is nothing more than representations. In that case, it would inevitably pass but us like an empty dream, or a ghostly vision not worth our consideration” (99) o “… the forms and laws of the representation must be wholly foreign to it (the object itself)” (99) o “here we can see that we can never get at the inner nature of things from without” (99) o What can we do?? Is the divide unbridgeable? - In a world of objects. Are there any objects that we can know from the inside, that is beyond how they merely appear to us? - The body o We are embodied beings. We, as bodies, occupy a place in space in time. o “… this body is a representation like any other, an object among objects [our movements] would be equally strange and incomprehensible to him, if their meaning were not unravelled for him in an entirely different way” (99) o “To the subject of knowing, who appears as an individual … this body is given in two entirely different ways, It is given in intelligent perception as representation, as an object among objects, liable to the laws of these objects. But it is also given in a quite different way, namely as what is known immediately to everyone, and is denoted by the word will” (100) o “We do not have such immediate information about the nature, action, and suffering of any other real objects” (103) - - - - - The principium o “I shall call time and space the principium individuations (principle of individuation), an expression borrowed from the old scholasticism, and I beg the reader to bear this in mind … for it is only by means of time and space that something which is one and the same according to its nature and the concept appears as different, as a plurality of coexistent and successive things” (113) Phantoms? o “Now if the objects appearing in these forms are not to be empty phantoms, but are to have meaning, they myst point to something, must be the expression of something, which is not … representation, something existing merely relatively, namely for a subject. On the contrary, they must point to something that exists without such dependence (…) in other words, must point to something that is not a representation, but a thing-in-itself” (119) Will o “But if now we analyse the reality of this body and its actions, then, beyond the fact that it is our representation, we find nothing in It but will (…) therefore we can nowhere find another kind of reality to attribute the material world” (105). Trying to picture it o Will (the thing-in-itself): not subjected to space and time. Principium individuationis does not apply. o Representations: In space and in time. Principium individuationis applies Suffering? o We already know Schop is a pessimist. So does any of this have any bearing on his pessimism? Will and suffering o “The will dispenses entirely with an ultimate aim and object. It always strives, because striving is its sole nature, to which no attained goal can put an end. Such striving is therefore incapable of final satisfaction; it can be checked only by hinderance, but in itself it goes on forever” (308) Remember, space and time do not apply to the will. o “For all striving springs from want or deficiency, from dissatisfaction with one’s own state or condition, and is therefore suffering so long as it is not satisfied” (309)