LSAT * PrepTest June 2007 Explained © 2008 Kaplan, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by photostat, microfilm, xerography, or any other means, or incorporated into any information retrieval system, electronic or mechanical, without the written permission of Kaplan, Inc. LSAT is a registered trademark of the Law School Admission Council. Section 1: Logic Games the second is 2, or the first digit is 2 and the second is 4. That’s a Limited Options setup waiting to happen— we’ll write it all out in a moment. SECTION I LOGIC GAMES Game 1: Product Codes Questions 1–5 Situation: A company of some kind, where an employee is generating product codes. Entities: The digits in the codes. We don’t actually find out what these are until we look at the first rule, but that’s fine; it’s enough that we know they’re 0, 1, 2, 3, and 4. Action: Again, it’s hard to tell until we get a little bit into the rules, but if you guessed, “Sequencing,” you were right on the money. Limitations: Rule 2 is really something like we’d expect to see in a Limitation: each digit is used exactly once. No duplicates, no missing digits. The Initial Setup: We’ll use our basic Sequencing sketch with slots and numbers. Just be careful not to confuse the numbers of the slots with the digits going into the code! 0 1 2 3 4 1 2 3 4 5 Rule 4 isn’t quite as easy to work through, but it sets up a similar relationship between another two of the digits: the third digit is smaller than the fifth digit. There are too many possibilities to draw them out like we did in Rule 3, so we’ll just create some shorthand for this rule. Something like “3 < 5” might not be clear enough to remind us exactly what we should do when we come back to it during the questions, so we’ll make the shorthand just a touch more elaborate: “3rd < 5th.” Deductions: The Blocs of Entities that Rule 3 sets up will allow us to put together our Limited Options setup now: Option 1: 1 2 1 2 3 4 5 Option 2: 2 4 1 2 3 4 5 Option I leaves the digits 0, 3, and 4 to be used, and Option II leaves the digits 0, 1, and 3 to be used. We’ll keep this in mind as we answer the questions—it will be useful in applying Rule 4. There really aren’t any Deductions dealing with Established Entities, Numbers, or Duplications, so we’ll move right along. The Rules: Rule 1 and Rule 2 are really much closer to Limitations than Rules. They give us the Entities, and tell us that each one will be used exactly once. We’ve already got that information in our Master Sketch, so we’re already finished with these rules. Rule 3, on the other hand, gives us something to work with: the second digit is exactly twice the value of the first. Don’t let the math frighten you! Even when there is a little bit of math on the LSAT, it’s never very difficult. All we have to do here is multiply (or divide) by two. As long as you don’t panic, you won’t have any trouble, and you’ll be well ahead of most people taking the test, who were thrown off by this rule. Think for a second about how this could work with the digits you have, and you’ll realize there are only two ways for this rule to work: either the first digit is 1 and The Final Visualization: Option 1: 1 2 1 2 3 0, 3, 4 3rd < 5th Option 2: 2 4 1 2 3 0, 1, 3 4 5 4 5 1 Test 4 Explained The Questions: 1. (A) Must be True / “If” clause Don’t be thrown off if the first question isn’t an Acceptability question; the Kaplan Methods will still answer it. If the last digit of the code is 1, then we must be in Option II: otherwise we’d be using that digit twice. So the first digit of the code will be 2, and the second digit will be 4. That leaves 0 and 3; and to comply with Rule 4, we’ll have to make 0 the third digit, and 3 the fourth digit. (C) works with our sketch from Question 1; in fact, it works with both of our Limited Options, so we can be sure that (C) must be true. The digit 2 is always either first or second, so it must come before the digit 3. Let’s quickly eliminate the last choices: (D) Once again, our sketch from Question 1 shows us that (D) could be false. Toss it out. And (E) is true in Option II, but could be false in Option I. Get rid of it as well. 3. (C) Must be True / “If” clause “Must be true” means true in both Options. 2 1 4 2 0 3 3 4 1 5 As it turns out, we could have answered this question just based on our first deduction: the first digit must be 2, so (A) must be true and is the correct answer. The rest of the answer choices all could be or must be false: (B) Our sketch tells us that 0 must the third, not second, and that 4 must be second. (C) If the third digit were 3, the fifth digit would have to be 4 to avoid violating Rule 4. But the “if” rule in this question tells us that the fifth digit is one, so (C) must be false. (D) and (E) both deal with the fourth digit, and both of them get it wrong; we already saw that the fourth digit must be 3, not 0 or 4. 2. (C) Must be True Always make every possible Deduction when sketching out a question’s “if” clause—they will often help you with later questions. We didn’t really need to fill in all five digits in our sketch to answer the last question; the first Deduction we made actually gave us the answer. But having that sketch filled in might help us eliminate choices in a later question—like this one. Let’s work through the choices and see if it helps. Remember, since the right answer is something that must be true, the four wrong answers could be false: (A) 1 might come before 2 in some possibilities—like Option I—but we saw in Question one that 1 could also come after 2. Eliminate (A). (B) Again, our sketch from Question 1 eliminates this choice—1 was last in that sketch, so it was definitely after 3. Eliminate (B), too. Usually, a new “if” rule will point us to one or the other of our Limited Options, meaning that we only have to draw one sketch. But this question must be the exception to that general rule, because this “if” doesn’t narrow things down for us. If the third digit is not 0, that doesn’t tell us anything about the first and second digits. Again, don’t panic—just draw a new sketch for each option: Option 1: 0, 3, 4 1 1 3 4 Not O 5 Option 2: 0, 1, 3 2 4 1 2 3 4 Not O 5 That takes care of Step 2 of the Kaplan Method (the sketch), so we’ll move on to Step 3: the rules. The only rule we haven’t used yet is Rule 4: the 3rd digit is smaller than the fifth digit. Thankfully, if the third digit can’t be 0, there’s only one way this rule could work in each Option. In Option I, the third digit must be 3 and the fifth digit must be 4; in Option II, the third digit must be 1 and the fifth digit must be 3. Option 1: 1 2 3 1 2 3 0 4 4 5 Option 2: 2 4 1 0 3 4 5 1 2 2 2 2 3 Section 1: Logic Games In both Options, the fourth digit is 0. That means (C) must be true, and is correct. The remaining choices all could be false: (A) is true in Option I, but false in Option II. Toss it. (B) is also true in Option I but not Option II. Throw it out. (D) is the reverse: it’s true in Option II, but not Option I. Eliminate it anyway. (E) can only be true if the third digit of the code is 0, and that’s the possibility eliminated by the rule. 4. (E) Could be True / EXCEPT Don’t ever test choices in your head—draw out a quick sketch instead. We’ll start this question by characterizing the choices carefully. Four of the answer choices could be the third and fourth digits of an acceptable product code, but the correct answer could not. So the correct answer must violate a rule somehow. That rule will probably be Rule 4, since we’re dealing with the third and fourth digits of the code, and Rule 4 is the only one that affects them directly. We’ve seen three acceptable product codes in our previous work. In Question 1, the third and fourth digits were 0 and 3, respectively. That means that (B) is an acceptable code, so we can eliminate it. In Question 3, we saw two codes. In the Option I, the third and fourth digits were 3 and 0, respectively, and in Option II, they were 1 and 0. Option I eliminates (D), and Option II eliminates (C). That leaves (A) and (E). We’re out of previous sketches to use at this point, but that doesn’t mean we have to guess, or waste time staring at the choices wondering what to do. When in doubt, use your pencil to test the choices. And it doesn’t matter which one we choose to test, since we’re down to two choices. No matter which choice we test, we’ll know which one is correct when we’re done with it. So try (A): if the third and fourth digits are 0 and 1, respectively, we must be in Option II (otherwise 1 would be used twice). So 2 and 4 are used as the first and second digits, leaving 3 for the fifth digit. That sketch would look like this: 2 1 4 2 0 3 1 4 3 5 That sketch follows every rule, so (A) is acceptable and may be eliminated. That leaves (E) as the correct answer. If 3 is the third digit and 4 is the fourth digit (as (E) would have it, then Rule 4 is violated. The fifth digit can’t possibly be larger than the third with this choice, so it is unacceptable (and correct!). 5. (E) Must be True Use your previous work to eliminate choices whenever possible. The greatest strength of the Kaplan Method for Logic Games is that it helps you to work as efficiently as possible. That’s true not only when you’re setting up the Master Sketch, but also as you go through the questions. Think about it—is it more efficient to treat every question as though it has nothing to do with the rest of the game, and do the same work over and over again? Or would you rather use the sketch that you did for one question to help you answer two or three others? Obviously, you want to use previous work where you can, and this question is a great opportunity. The correct answer is a statement that must be true, so the wrong answers must be false. In other words, if we’ve seen a sketch in a previous question where they were false, we can eliminate them. (A) is out, since neither of our sketches from Question 3 have exactly one digit between 0 and 1. And Option I knocks (B) out of the water quickly—there are no digits between 1 and 2 there. (C) looks okay so far, so we’ll save it for the moment, and the same is true of (E), but the second sketch from Question 3 takes (D) out of the running. That sketch has three digits between 2 and 3. We’ll finish this game off by trying a sketch to eliminate either (C) or (E). (C) could be false if there are more than two digits between the digits 1 and 3. The only way that can happen is if 1 and 3 are at opposite ends of the code, and the only place that can happen is in Option I. There, 1 is the first digit, 2 is the second digit, and to test the choice, we’ll try putting 3 in as the fifth digit. That leaves 0 and 4 for the remaining slots. We can abide by Rule 4 (the third digit is smaller than the fifth digit) only if the third digit is 0, and that leaves 4 for the fourth digit, like so: 1 1 2 2 0 3 4 4 3 5 (C) could be false, so we can eliminate it. (E) remains, and must be true. As it turns out, our Options show us why it must be true—in Option II, 2 and 4 are next to each other, and in Option I, 2 is the second digit, so there can be no more than two digits between it and anything else. 3 Test 4 Explained Rule 2 is even more complex: either Greed or Limelight, but not both, is shown on Friday. Moreover, that film is the last film shown on Friday. We’ll have to put “ . . . G/L” in the space for Friday. Game 2: Film Club Festival Questions 6–10 Situation: A film club is having a festival. Entities: Three films—G, H, and L—are show on three days: Thursday, Friday, and Saturday. Action: The days make this sound like Sequencing, and there is a Sequencing element here, but there could be more than one film on a day, and the films could be shown more than once. So this is really closer to Matching. As we go through the Rules, you should realize that there could be some Sequencing thrown in—that makes this a Hybrid game. G H L Thurs Fri …H … G/L Rule 3 says basically the same thing as Rule 2, except that it deals with Saturday, and the movies involved are Greed and Harvest, not Greed and Limelight. So our shorthand will be substantially the same as it was for Rule 2: G H L Limitations: Lots of them. Each film is shown at least once. But no film is shown more than once on any given day. On each of the three days, at least one film is shown (notice that there could be more than one!). The films are shown one at a time. The Initial Setup: We’ll use a standard Matching setup since each of the films could be used more than once. That’ll look like this: Fri Thurs Fri Sat …H … G/L … G/H Now it may not look like we’ve got many Deductions here, but turn negatives into positives and you’ll find a couple. Deductions: G H L Thurs Sat The blank slot in each day’s column will remind us that at least one film must be shown there. Just don’t forget that it could be more than one. The Rules: Rule 1 is really two rules in one: Harvest is show on Thursday, and nothing is shown after Harvest. If you’re really analyzing this rule, you’re probably thinking, ‘but what about before Harvest is shown?’ Well, the rule doesn’t tell us anything about that. We should note that there could be some other movie shown before Harvest in our shorthand: There don’t appear to be any Blocs of Entities, or any Limited Options, but there are several Established Entities for us to play with. Harvest must be shown on Thursday; Greed or Limelight, but not both, must be show on Friday; Greed or Harvest, but not both, must be shown on Saturday. Those last two Establishments—and the “but not both” within them— will be particularly important when we’re trying to figure out how to make sure all three movies are shown. They’ll also tell us a couple of things about the Numbers—Thursday is the only day on which all three movies could be shown. Unfortunately, though, we can’t figure out anything concrete besides what was already in the rules. We’ll just have to move on to the questions and hope we get some concrete answers there. The Final Visualization: G H L G H L Thurs …H 4 Fri Sat Sat Thurs Fri Sat …H … G/L … G/H Section 1: Logic Games The Questions: 6. (C) Acceptability When working through an Acceptability question, don’t forget to check on the Limitations. We’ll begin this Acceptability question like every other, working through the rules to eliminate choices that violate them. Rule 1 eliminates (D), which has Limelight last on Thursday. Rule 2 eliminates (B), which has both Greed and Limelight on Friday; it also eliminates (E), which has Harvest after Limelight on that day. Lastly, Rule 3…doesn’t eliminate a single choice, leaving (A) and (C). But the most common Limitation on the LSAT gets rid of the last choice for us. Nearly every game has a Limitation that effectively says, ‘use all the Entities.’ (A) fails to do so—it would have the festival forget to show Greed. That’s unacceptable, so (C) must be the right answer. 7. (A) CANNOT be True Be prepared to skip early questions and come back to them after you’ve done more work. On Test Day, this would be a perfect question to skip. It’s a “Cannot be True” question, so the four wrong answers are all things that could be true. Any possibility in the game—for example, any sketch that we make to answer a later question—can be used to eliminate choices in a question like this. The last three questions in this game all have “if” clauses, so we should expect to sketch out new possibilities for each one. Those possibilities could be used to eliminate choices in this question, which would help us save time. For the purposes of these explanations, we’ll plow on ahead and start testing choices, but you should look for places where skipping a question and coming back to it will save you time on Test Day. (A) As it turns out, the correct answer shows up pretty quickly here: Harvest can’t be shown last on Friday without violating Rule 2. Let’s quickly eliminate the rest: (B) Limelight can be shown on every day of the festival as long as Greed isn’t shown on Friday. (C) is a little tougher to eliminate, but it’s still possible. Greed can be second on Thursday if Limelight is first, second on Friday if Harvest is first, and second on Saturday if Limelight is first again. (D) and (E) likewise take a little bit of time to work through, but it shouldn’t be too hard to find a possibility where they’re true. A different film can be shown first on all three days if Greed is first on Thursday, Harvest first on Friday, and Limelight first on Saturday; a different film can be shown last on all three days if Greed is last on Saturday and Limelight is last on Friday. 8. (D) Maximum / “If” clause Read carefully when necessary to be sure you know exactly what the question is asking. This question doesn’t ask us for what must, could, or cannot be true. Instead, it asks us to figure out the maximum number of film showings that could occur during the festival. Don’t confuse this with the maximum number of different orders the films could be shown in, or the maximum number of possibilities for how the films could be shown. All the question asks us for is the greatest possibly number of showings during the three days. Hopefully, when you noticed that this wasn’t a common question stem, you slowed down and read it carefully to be sure you knew exactly what was going on. The question is further complicated by an “if” clause. The new rule tells us that Limelight can’t be shown after Greed. That rule doesn’t just apply on any given day; it applies for the whole festival. Once Greed is shown, Limelight can’t be shown at all, whether that happens on Thursday, Friday, or Saturday. At this point, you should re-copy the Master Sketch, and shorthand the new rule: “L . . . G.” The rule actually makes our task much simpler. If we want as many films to be shown as possible, and Limelight can’t be shown after Greed is shown, we’ll just put Greed at the very end of the festival and throw as many showings of Limelight and Harvest into the earlier parts of the festival as we can. Just make sure you comply with the rules: if Greed is last on Saturday, Harvest can’t be shown that day (Rule 3), but Limelight can be shown before Greed. That’s two showings on Saturday. If Greed isn’t shown on Thursday or Friday, the maximum number of showings on each of those days is two, for a maximum total of six—that’s (D). The final sketch looks like this: G H L (L…G) Thurs Fri Sat L…H H…L L…G (A) is the minimum number of showings. 5 Test 4 Explained (B) and (C) don’t quite pick up enough showings, although you might have picked (C) if you didn’t put in the last showing of Limelight on Saturday. (E) is the maximum number of showings that could occur in the festival before the “if” clause takes effect. 9. (E) Must be True / “If” clause Think through all the implications of the “if” clause before moving on to the choices. The “if” in this question is particularly complex. It gives us the number of times each of the three films is shown, but not when they are shown. We’ll have to figure that last piece out before we’re able to answer the question. If Greed is shown three times, it must be shown on every day of the festival. After all, there are only three days to begin with. Go ahead and plug Greed in on each day, and think through what that means— Limelight can’t be shown on Friday (Rule 2), and Harvest can’t be shown on Saturday (Rule 3). So far, our sketch looks like this: G H L Thurs G…H Fri Sat …G …G (no L) (no H) Harvest is shown twice. Since it can’t be shown on Saturday, it must be shown on Thursday and Friday. Limelight is only shown once, on either Thursday or Saturday. Our final sketch should look like this: G H L Thurs Fri Sat G…H H…G L? … G L? (no L) (no H) This will allow us to make short work of the choices. The correct answer is definitely true, and the four wrong answers all could be false: (A) could be false. All three films could be shown on Thursday, or the single showing of Limelight could take place on Saturday. (B) could be false. Greed could be the only film shown on Saturday. 6 (C) could be false for the same reason as (A)— Limelight could be shown on Saturday instead of Thursday. (D) could be false if Limelight is shown on Saturday. (E) Harvest and Greed must both be shown on Friday— Harvest must be shown on two of the three days, and cannot be shown on Saturday. (E) must be true, and is correct. 10. (D) Complete and Accurate List / “If” clause Be alert for places where your previous work can help you. It’s dangerous to use sketches from earlier questions to answer later questions that have an “if” clause. But sometimes the “if” clauses will be similar enough that you can get a head start on the later question, even if you don’t use a previous sketch. The “if” in this question is so similar to the “if” in the last question that you should be well prepared to work through it. If Limelight is shown three times, it must be shown on all three days. This means that Limelight is last on Friday, and that Greed cannot be shown on that day. Limelight must be shown earlier than Harvest on Thursday and earlier than either Harvest or Greed on Saturday. That gives us this sketch to start: G H L Thurs Fri Sat L…H …L L… G/H no G Harvest is shown twice, and Greed is shown once. Greed could be shown on Thursday or Saturday, and the second showing of Harvest could take place on Friday or Saturday. The rules don’t help us narrow down the possibilities any further than we already have, so it’s time to go to the choices and figure out the complete and accurate list of films that could be shown first on Thursday. You should eliminate (A), (C), and (E) immediately— Harvest is shown on Thursday, but it must be shown last, not first. The only difference between (B) and (D) is whether Greed can be shown first on Thursday. If it can, then (D) is correct; if it cannot, (B) is correct. A quick glance at the rules gives us no reason why the single showing of Greed cannot take place on Thursday, so (D) is the correct complete and accurate list. Section 1: Logic Games Game 3: Freedom Voyages GJMMT Questions 11–17 1 Situation: On a cruise line. Limitations: Each voyage is to only one of the destinations; each voyage is in one of seven weeks; each destination will be scheduled at least once. A quick head count shows that we’ve got seven weeks and only four destinations, so at least one of the destinations will be used more than once. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 4 5 Not J 6 Rule 4 sets up a Bloc of Entities: Guadeloupe is the destination in the week preceding a cruise to Jamaica. The easy mistake to make here is to just write “GJ” and be done with it. Unfortunately, that’s not accurate, because it would make us think that any time Guadeloupe is the destination, Jamaica must be the destination in the following week. To really get this rule correct, we should state it as an ‘if/then:’ If Jamaica is the destination in any given week, then Guadeloupe precedes it: If J → G J The Initial Setup: Our basic Sequencing sketch will work just fine here: GJMT 3 M…G…M Entities: The places the voyage will go: Guadeloupe, Jamaica, Martinique, and Trinidad. Action: Determining the order in which the cruise will go to each destination—that’s Sequencing. 2 T 7 And the contrapositive, if Guadeloupe doesn’t precede Jamaica, Jamaica can’t be the destination in that week. Of course, this means that Jamaica can’t be the first destination. If no G J → No J The Rules: Rule 1 eliminates a possibility: Jamaica isn’t the destination in Week 4. Write in a “not J” under week 4. Rule 2 gives us an Established Entity: Trinidad is the destination at week 7. After two rules, our sketch looks like this: Rule 5 is one that you might have expected from the beginning: “No consecutives” is a very common rule on the LSAT, and can be shorthanded as such. GJMT There are a lot of Blocs of Entities in this game, and G is Duplicated in both of them. Don’t fall into the trap of adding them together, though—we can’t be certain that will happen, since J is the trigger for Rule 4. J is also Duplicated in Rule 1, but again, that doesn’t help us much. There are no Limited Options to speak of, and the Numbers rule—that there are two voyages to Mar tinique—also doesn’t give us any fur ther deductions. The only concrete deduction we can make deals with an Established Entity: If T is seventh, it cannot also be sixth (Rule 5). Joy that down near your sketch, and move on to the questions. 1 2 3 4 5 Not J 6 T 7 Rule 3 is a bit more complicated: the ship makes exactly two voyages to Martinique, and at least one voyage to Guadeloupe is made in between those voyages. This is really two rules in one. We’ll shorthand the first rule by adding a second “M” to our list of entities (always note how many times an entity is used by writing it that many times in the roster) and shorthand the second rule by writing “M…G…M:” Deductions: 7 Test 4 Explained The Final Visualization: GJMMT 1 2 Not J 3 T 4 5 6 7 Not J Not T M…G…M If J → G J If no G J → No J The Questions: 11. (A) Acceptability Be sure to pick up a quick point with the Acceptability question. Rule 1 eliminates (D), which has Jamaica as the fourth destination, and Rule 2 eliminates (E), which has Martinique as the last destination. The “M…G…M” Bloc is violated in (B), and G does not immediately precede J in (C). That leaves (A) as the correct answer. 12. (A) CANNOT be True If you find the right answer early on, move on. Don’t waste time checking the other choices to make sure. If the correct answer cannot be true, then all four of the wrong answers could be true. In other words, if we can put together a sketch that follows all the rules and it matches up with one of the choices, we can eliminate that choice. Unfortunately, without an “if” to start from, it looks like we’ll have to draw out at least one sketch, maybe several, to find the correct answer. But as it turns out, we don’t have to do much work at all. A quick glance at our Master Sketch shows us that (A) cannot be true: If T were sixth, it would violate Rule 5. On Test Day, you should move on once you’ve found an answer like this, but for now we’ll work through the remaining choices. Jot down a quick sketch to test (B): Guadeloupe, Jamaica, Mar tinique, Guadeloupe, Mar tinique, Guadeloupe, Trinidad. That works, so (B) could be true. (C) Again, try sketching: Martinique, Guadeloupe, Jamaica, Martinique, Guadeloupe, Jamaica, Trinidad. Looks fine, so (C) could be true. And as a matter of fact, this sketch works for (D), so we can eliminate that choice as well. (E) A little tweak to our sketch for (C) and (D) will eliminate this one: Martinique, Trinidad, Guadeloupe, 8 Mar tinique, Guadeloupe, Jamaica, Trinidad works just fine. 13. (D) Could be True / “If” clause Even seemingly insignificant deductions can help get you to the correct answer. The “if” clause in this question is pretty simple: plug T in to week 5 and you’re done with it. But it leads to some pretty significant deductions. First off, J can’t be in week 6, since there isn’t room for G in the preceding week. That’s enough to eliminate (E). But that’s also where things get a little tougher to nail down. We have to fit in “M…G…M” and “G J” somewhere; as it turns out, there are only two possibilities for the former. The second M must be either fourth or sixth. That’s enough to get us to the correct answer, (D): M could be the destination in the fourth week. (A) If T is in week 1, then there’s no way to fit both blocs without putting J in week 4 and violating Rule 1. (B) is wrong for the exact same reason as (A); M can’t fit into week 2 without forcing J into week 4. (C), again, would force us to put J in week 4, or else make us unable to place the M…G…M bloc. (E) J can’t be the destination in week 6 if G isn’t the destination in week 5. 14. (E) Must be True / “if” clause Treat two-part “if” clauses as two separate rules, each requiring its own deductions. The “if” clause in this question gives us two new rules, so we’ll deal with each one separately and then see what the combination tells us. First, putting G into week 1 doesn’t immediately give us another Established Entity, but it does tell us that we could put J into week 2. It also tells us that Guadeloupe will be the destination in at least one other week, since the G in week 1 can’t be part of the M…G…M Bloc. The second part of the “if” is where we really get going. If Jamaica is the destination in week 5, then Guadeloupe must be the destination in week 4 (Rule 4): GJMMT G 1 2 3 G 4 J 5 M…G…M 6 Not T T 7 Section 1: Logic Games That leaves only weeks 2, 3, and 6 undefined, and we still haven’t placed the M…G…M Bloc. The only way it can fit is if the G in week 4 is the G in the middle of the Bloc. This means that Mar tinique must be the destination in week 6, as well as either week 2 or week 3: GJMMT G 1 2 G 4 3 J 5 M 6 T 7 M M…G…M The M in week 6 is (E). That deduction must be true, and is the correct answer. (A) and (C) both could be true, but need not be. If you wrote down “GJ” back when you were writing the rules, you might have been fooled into thinking that J must be in week 2, which would force M into week 3. Having two answers that both look right is a good indication that you need to go back and check your work. Really, either M or T could be the destination in week 2. (B) could be true as well, but need not be. (D) If G is the destination in week 6, there’s no room for the M…G…M Bloc. 15. (A) Must be True / “if” clause Make as many deductions as you can before trying to answer the question. It may not seem like it at first glance, but this “if” clause gives us enough information to nail down every single slot. Our initial setup with the new rule added (G in week 1 and T in week 2) looks like this: GJMMT G 1 T 2 3 4 5 6 Not J Not T T 7 M…G…M We still need to plug our M…G…M Bloc in somewhere, and we also need to find a place for J. As it turns out, there’s only one way we can do both of those things and follow all the rules. Remember, G must be in the week preceding J, and J can’t be fourth; so M must be the destination in weeks 3 and 6, and “G J” fills the gap between the M’s: G 1 T 2 M 3 G 4 J 5 M 6 T 7 This setup makes it a snap to answer the question. (A) is the only choice that must be true. (B) and (C) If you didn’t think through the “G J” rule, these choices might have been tempting, but it cannot be true. (D) Sure, we could put G in week 3 and plug “M G M” in for weeks 4, 5, and 6, but then Jamaica would never be the destination. That violates a Limitation, which knocks out a choice as surely as violating a rule. (E) If you forgot that J couldn’t be the destination in week 4, you might have chosen this one. Toss it instead. 16. (A) Could be True / “if” clause Read carefully to avoid being tripped up by the question stems. The words “accurate list” in this question stem might have fooled you into thinking that you had to list possibilities. But as it turns out, the LSAT really just wants to know a possibility for weeks 4 and 5, and that’s exactly the same as a “could be true” question. We can approach this like any other “if” question: copy the Master Sketch, plug in our new “if,” make any deductions, then work through the choices. If M is in week 3, we can’t be sure whether the big Bloc, M…G…M, begins or ends in the third week— either is possible. We could make a miniature Limited Options setup, and that’ s not a bad idea when you’re faced with this situation. But once we’ve made that deduction, it’s actually pretty quick to eliminate the choices that violate rules. (C) and (E) don’t work with the M…G…M Bloc, (B) has J in week 4, and (D) has J preceded by T instead of G. That leaves (A) as the only possible answer. 17. (D) Must be True Sometimes it’s easier to eliminate wrong answer choices than to try to go straight to the correct answer. If the correct answer must be true, then all of the wrong answer choices could be false. In other words, if we’ve ever seen a possibility where a choice is false—or if we 9 Test 4 Explained can quickly jot one down without violating any rules—we can eliminate that choice. Let’s work through the choices and see what we can quickly get rid of: (A) to prove this false, try putting G someplace else, like week 3, and filling weeks 1 and 2 with other destinations. This could work if we put the M’s in weeks 1 and 4; a T in week 2; and “G J” in weeks 5 and 6. That has all of the entities, and doesn’t break any rules, so (A) could be false. (B) Actually, the sketch we just made doesn’t have Martinique in week 2 or week 3, so (B) could be false as well. It’s never a bad idea to test more than one choice at a time if you can. (C) To prove this false, we’ll have to write a sketch with at least three G’s. That will be difficult with both the “G J” and “M…G…M” Blocs, but we ought to be able to manage. How about this one: GJMMT G 1 M 2 G 3 M 4 G 5 J 6 T 7 Success! That sketch has three voyages to G, and doesn’t violate a single rule. (C) is out. (D) The Numbers will tell you that (D) must be true. If the ship makes more than two trips to Jamaica, it must make at least the same number of trips to Guadeloupe. So for three trips to Jamaica (the minimum number to prove (D) false), we’d also need three trips to Guadeloupe. That’s six of the seven weeks, and we haven’t even added in the two trips to Martinique yet. We can’t falsify (D) without breaking a rule (or adding a few more weeks), so (D) must be true. (E) Let’s make this last one quick. Combine the “G J” and the “M…G…M” Blocs, and throw a T in the middle with them for good measure: GJMMT T 1 M 2 T 3 G 4 J 5 M 6 T 7 No rules broken there, so (E) can be false. Toss it and move on. 10 Section 1: Logic Games Game 4: Rivertown Recycling Centers If w → n No n → no w Questions 18–23 Situation: Recycling centers in Rivertown. Entities: The Centers (1, 2, and 3) and the materials being recycled: glass, newsprint, plastic, tin, and wood. Action: Two sets of entities: a classic Matching game. Limitations: All five of the materials are recycled somewhere (“exactly five kinds of materials are recycled); and each of the centers recycles at least two, but not more than three, of the kinds of material. This last Limitation is a clue that the Numbers will be important in this game, so we should quickly do some arithmetic to work out the possibilities. With three centers and at least two kinds of materials recycled at each center, we’d have a minimum of six slots—so with five kinds of materials, at least one of them has to be recycled at two of the centers. There are several more possibilities, depending on how many of the centers have three slots, so we won’t waste time working out any more possible number combinations until the questions force us to. The second statement is the contrapositive: If newsprint isn’t recycled at a center, that center can’t recycle wood. Remember, this rule doesn’t work both ways—a center could recycle newsprint without recycling wood. Rule 2 is similar, but it deals with centers, not materials. Anything recycled at Center 2 must also be recycled at Center 1. Form the contrapositive: if something isn’t recycled at Center 1, it can’t be recycled at Center 2. If at 2 → at 1 If not at 1 → not at 2 And again, we’ll remind ourselves that this is a one-way rule: something recycled at Center 1 doesn’t have to be recycled at Center 2. Finally, Rule 3 gives us some numbers to think about: plastic is only recycled at one of the centers. Rule 3 also rules out a combination of entities: glass and plastic can’t be recycled at the same center. We should write these two rules separately: The Initial Setup: Our standard Matching table will work well here. The centers are the concrete entities, so we’ll put them across the top, and leave the materials to be filled in: gnptw Only 1 p No g p (2–3 slots each) Now we’re ready to see if we can combine these rules. Center 1 Center 2 Center 3 Deductions: The Rules: Thankfully, the Rules for this game are pretty simple. Rule 1 ties two of the materials together: any center that recycles wood must also recycle newsprint. “Any” should clue you in that this is an if/then, so we’ll write it as such: There really aren’t any Blocs of Entities: Even though wood and newsprint seem like they move together, we could have newsprint at a center without having wood. Similarly, glass and plastic are mutually exclusive, but that doesn’t allow us to make much of a deduction. There aren’t any Limited Options, either, nor are we able to create any Established Entities. We can, however, make a little bit of headway with the Numbers. If plastic is only recycled at one of the centers, and anything recycled at Center 2 is also recycled at Center 1, then plastic can’t be recycled at Center 2. We can jot down “no p” in column 2. The rule connecting Centers 1 and 2 also allows us to revise the arithmetic we did with the Limitations: Since 11 Test 4 Explained at least 2 materials are recycled in Center 2, at least two of the materials are Duplicated. That takes up four slots, and recycling the remaining three materials even once will use at least seven slots. So at least one of the centers recycles three different kinds of materials; if only one center does so, that center has to be Center 1 or Center 3. We can jot down an extra slot below the table to remind us that we’ll need it down the line. Those two Duplicated slots also mean something interesting for Rule 2: Center 1 can only recycle one kind of material that isn’t recycled at Center 2, and only if it recycles three materials and Center 2 recycles only two. The Final Visualization: (2–3 slots each) gnptw Center 1 Center 2 Center 3 19. (D) Complete and Accurate List Make a Deduction, earn a point. It’s a good rule of thumb that every Deduction you’re able to make in the initial setup will earn you a point when you get to the questions. That’s the case here. We noticed that Center 2 can never recycle plastic, since plastic is only recycled at one center and anything recycled at Center 2 is also recycled at Center 1; that’s enough to eliminate answers (C) and (E) in this question. You should have seen upon making that Deduction that either Center 1 or Center 3 could recycle plastic, so (D) is the correct choice. (A) and (B) each have only one of the remaining two centers; if the Formal Logic in Rule 2 tripped you up, and you thought that Centers 1 and 2 would always recycle the same materials, then (B) might have been tempting, but there’s no reason that Center 1 couldn’t recycle plastic. 20. (C) Must be True / “if” clause No p (+ If w → n No n → no w Only 1 p Be sure to check through every single rule when making deductions based on a new “if.” ) If at 2 → at 1 If not at 1 → not at 2 No g p The Questions: 18. (B) Acceptability The LSAT often phrases familiar question types in unfamiliar ways. Don’t be fooled by the “accurate account” language in this question stem. This is a classic Acceptability question, so we’ll attack it using the rules to eliminate violators. Rule 1 knocks out (A), where Center 3 recycles wood but not newsprint. Rule 2 gets rid of (C), where Center 2 recycles tin and Center 1 doesn’t. Rule 3 eliminates (D), where glass and plastic are recycled at Center 1, and (E), where plastic is recycled twice. That leaves (B) as the correct answer. 12 The “if” clause in this question is relatively simple: Center 2 recycles three kinds of material. A glance at the rules tells us that Center 1 must also recycle three kinds of material, and that those centers will be identical. At first glance, though, it doesn’t look like we’ll be able to figure out anything else. Unless, of course, you made the Deduction based on Rule 3, or at least looked back at that rule for this question. Plastic can only be recycled once, so it can’t be recycled at Center 2. With this new “if,” Center 2 has the maximum number of recyclables, which means that Center 1 does as well—and each of those recyclables is recycled at two centers, so none of them can be plastic. There is thus only one Center that can recycle plastic: Center 3. So Center 3 must recycle plastic, and (B) is correct. Before you move on, you should also note the next deduction: if Center 3 is recycling plastic, then Centers 1 and 2 must recycle glass. That gives us this sketch: Center 1 g Center 2 g Center 3 p Section 1: Logic Games (A) cannot be true—glass must be recycled at Centers 1 and 2. (B) and (E) there’s enough room for newsprint alone, or even wood and newsprint, in Center 3, but neither must be recycled there. (D) Tin could be recycled at any of the three centers, but need not be recycled at Center 3. 21. (D) Could be True / “if” clause Your previous work can help you answer later questions. The “if” clause in this question is very similar to the “if” clause in the question before it—the only difference is the number of centers recycling three kinds of material. In Question 20, Center 2 (and by extension, Center 1) recycled three types of material. Now, all three centers are recycling three types of material, but the deductions we made in the last question will hold true: Center 3 must recycle plastic, and Centers 1 and 2 must recycle glass: Center 1 g Center 2 g Center 3 p We also know that everything recycled at Center 2 must be recycled at Center 1, and vice versa. So (A), (C), and (E) are all out—each of those choices has Center 1 or Center 2 as the only center recycling one of the materials. We’re left to choose between (B) and (D), determining whether Center 3 can be the only center to recycle either newsprint or tin. It doesn’t matter which one we try at this point, since eliminating one choice means that the other one must be correct. Let’s try (B): if Center 3 is the only center recycling newsprint, then the other centers can only recycle glass, tin, wood, and plastic. But we’ve already seen that Centers 1 and 2 can’t recycle plastic in this scenario, and Rule 1 tells us that they can’t recycle wood without newsprint. So that would leave only glass and tin in those centers—two kinds of materials, not three. (B) doesn’t work, which means that (D) must be correct. Sure enough, if Center 3 recycles tin and newsprint and Centers 1 and 2 recycle wood and newsprint, all five materials are used and we’re done. 22. (B) Must be True / “if” clause You can always have the result of a Formal Logic statement without having the trigger. Sadly, our previous work won’t help us here; we’ve seen glass recycled at every center but Center 3. So we’ll just have to start with a new sketch. Once we’ve put g into the column for Center 3, a glance at Rule 3 tells us that we’ve also got to jot down “No p” in that column—glass and plastic can’t be recycled at the same center. So the only center where plastic can be recycled is Center 1; that’s as much as saying, plastic must be recycled in Center 1. gnptw (2–3 slots each) Center 1 Center 2 p No p Center 3 g No p Now why does our sketch have plastic in the third slot, and not the first? How do we even know that there are three slots in Center 1 at the moment? Simple: Rule 2 tells us that if something is recycled at Center 2, it must also be recycled at Center 1. There are at least two things recycled at Center 2, both of which will also be recycled at Center 1, and neither of which can be plastic. So the other two slots at Center 1 are taken up by whatever is recycled at Center 2. If you misinterpreted Rule 2 to say that Center 1 and Center 2 recycled the same materials, you were in big trouble on this question. To finish up, we have to look at what those last two slots in Centers 1 and 2 could hold. They can’t have glass, since that would force glass and plastic together; and since we’re talking about Center 2, they can’t have plastic. That leaves newsprint, tin, and wood. But we can’t just pick any two of those three— Rule 1 tells us that if Center 2 recycles wood, it must recycle newsprint. That narrows the possibilities down to two options: Center 2 must recycle wood and newsprint, or tin and newsprint. Either way, it must recycle newsprint, making (B) the correct answer. (A) If Centers 2 and 3 recycled glass, all three centers would recycle glass (Rule 2); that would leave no center able to recycle plastic (Rule 3). (C) Center 2 can never recycle plastic. 13 Test 4 Explained (D) and (E) Center 2 could recycle either wood or tin along with newsprint, but need not recycle one or the other. 23. (A) Complete and Accurate List / “if” clause Make every possible deduction before moving on to the choices. This is that rare question where it’s both possible to fill in every slot in the game and necessary to do so to get to the correct answer. That means we’ve got to make quite a few deductions before we finish. Start with the new rule, that Center 1 is the only center that recycles wood. That’s really two separate rules: Center 1 recycles wood; and no other centers recycle wood. Jot down “w” in column 1, and “no w” in the other columns. If wood is recycled in Center 1, but not Center 2, then Center 1 has to have three slots—two of those are filled by whatever is in Center 2 and the third is wood. And if the first two slots in Center 1 are filled by materials that are also recycled in Center 2, plastic cannot be among them. So we’ll jot down “no p” in the column for Center 1. That means the only place left for plastic is Center 3. Rule 3 then places glass in either Center 1 or Center 2; it doesn’t matter which one, because at this point anything that’s recycled in one center is recycled in the other. So fill in glass in Centers 1 and 2: Center 1 g Center 2 g Center 3 p w No p No p, no w No w Wait a minute! We haven’t even looked at Rule 1 yet! If wood is recycled in a center, so is newsprint, so newsprint must be recycled at Center 1. And since we’ve gotten to a point where anything recycled at Center 1 is recycled at Center 2, newsprint also must be recycled at Center 2. That leaves just one material unplaced: tin, which must fill in the last slot of Center 3. Our final sketch for this question is like so: 14 Center 1 g Center 2 g Center 3 p n n t No p, no w No w w No p The list at Center 3—plastic and tin—is (A), which must be the correct answer. And to think, we got there making the easiest deduction last. If we hadn’t started by thinking through the implications of “no w” in Centers 2 and 3, this question would have been even harder. (B) is an accurate list for Center 1, but it isn’t complete—Center 1 must also have glass. If you were pressed for time, or got stuck after making the “wood → newsprint” deduction, you probably chose this one. (C) and (E) Tin is never recycled at the same center as newsprint or glass in this sketch. (D) Again, this choice is close to what is recycled at Center 1, but is missing one of the materials. Section 2: Logical Reasoning SECTION II LOGICAL REASONING 1. (B) Main Point Look for different ways of phrasing the correct answer. The LSAT will often test your ability to find a different way of making certain statements. This is because an easy way to ratchet up the difficulty level of a question is to change the phrasing of the correct answer. Even the easiest questions in the section can ask you to perform this type of manipulation, and this one is no exception. A relatively simple statement about business productivity is the conclusion of this stimulus: Efforts to increase productivity don’t always help a business. We phrased that a bit differently than the stimulus did, and the correct answer choice phrases it yet another way: Some measures taken by a business to increase productivity fail to benefit the business as a whole. That’s (B). (A) is too broad. The stimulus does tell us why not all efforts to enhance productivity are beneficial—they often mean job cuts, which undermine employee security—but it doesn’t imply that an action must “enhancing the welfare of the business’s employees” to be beneficial. The situation described in (C), where the employees and the owners are the same people, might alleviate the problem raised in the stimulus, but it’s not the only way to do so. Besides, it’s outside the scope of the argument. (D) restates the first sentence of the argument, but that sentence is background information, not the conclusion. (E) fixates on a detail from the last sentence of the stimulus. 2. (B) Parallel Reasoning (Flaw) You should probably skip a difficult early question. The difference in difficulty between this question and the question before it is astonishing. A relatively simple Main Point question followed by a Parallel Flaw? A Parallel Flaw question as the second question in a section? It’s enough to make an unprepared test taker wish they were trying to go to business school. The prepared test taker—in other words, the Kaplan test taker—knows that this is an early trap, and the best thing to do is skip the question and come back to it. Nonetheless, we’ll explain it for you before we move on. The stimulus deals with how much certain dogs bark. According to the information we’re given, Labradors bark a lot and Saint Bernards don’t bark very much. Does it then follow that a cross between the two would bark moderately? Probably not, and that’s the flaw in this argument. It looks at two groups that are the opposite of one another in regards to a certain characteristic (barks a lot/doesn’t bark much), and assumes that a combination of the two will produce a group with an average of that characteristic (barks moderately). That’s possible, but as any dog breeder will tell you, it’s not a sure thing. We’ll look for an answer choice that makes the same flawed assumption about combining two different groups. (A) starts well, defining a group with a certain characteristic—diligent students, who get good grades. But unlike the stimulus, the second group in (A) doesn’t always have the characteristic in question— only “some” non-diligent students get good grades. That difference is enough to eliminate (A). (B) Ah-ha! Here we have two groups with opposing characteristics: Group A is toxic, and Group B is nontoxic. The conclusion attempts to moderate the two characteristics: a combination of A and B is “moderately toxic.” This argument follows the same flawed path as the stimulus, so it is correct. For the record: (C) isn’t flawed at all. It combines two groups with different characteristics into the Perry family, but it doesn’t attempt to say that every member of the group will have a combination of the characteristics—it says that some members will have the characteristic from Group A, and some members will have the characteristic from Group B. (D) also isn’t flawed. Bob is a member of two groups, so he has the characteristics of each group. There’s nothing mutually exclusive about knowing shorthand and calculus, so there’s no reason Bob couldn’t know both. (E) The dresses in the closet (the group in the conclusion) could be Kenisha’s and Connie’s, or they could belong to other people entirely. Without knowing that Kenisha and Connie own all the dresses in the closet, the conclusion in (E) doesn’t follow. But it doesn’t follow for a different reason than the conclusion in the stimulus—this is a different flaw, so (E) is incorrect. 15 Test 4 Explained 3. (D) Inference Unlike other Inference questions, you can often prephrase an answer to Inference questions that ask you to complete an argument. This type of Inference question is very similar to a Main Point question, except that it asks us to find a conclusion that isn’t stated. We can do that by focusing on the scope of the argument and asking what it’s all leading up to. This argument starts by equating a century and a life, and noting that people behave the same way towards the end of each. So (the last sentence states), just as people at the end of their lives reflect on their life, people at the end of a century…reflect on the century. That prediction fits with the argument’s comparison between a life and a century, and can be found in (D). (A) distorts the stimulus; people reflect on what is ending, which is not always their life. (B) Fear is outside the scope of the stimulus. (C) is the opposite of what the stimulus suggests will happen. (E) is also a distor tion—there’s nothing in the argument about second-guessing the events of the past century. 4. (A) Flaw Scope shifts are one of the most common flaws on the LSAT. It seems like we just can’t trust one company to say nice things about another company’s products. At least, this stimulus tells us that we can’t trust Danto Foods to say nice things about Ocksenfrey’s prepackaged meals, even when Danto says them through something called the Connorly Report. All of the evidence suggests that Danto’s bias against its competitor influenced the report, so the report’s conclusions about Ocksenfrey can’t be trusted. It would be fine if the author just said that we shouldn’t trust the Connorly Repor t’s conclusions about Ocksenfrey, but the conclusion of this argument goes a step further than that—it claims that the opposite of the Report’s conclusions must be true. That shift in scope is just as wrong as trusting a consumer report written by a player in the industry, and is found in (A). (B) the argument itself doesn’t rely on any sample of Ocksenfrey’s products. Its evidence and conclusion both refer to the same products—Ocksenfrey’s prepackaged meals. 16 (C) may be true, but it has nothing to do with the argument, which is about Danto’s bias and its effect. (D) any comparison between Danto’s and Ocksenfrey’s prepackaged meals is irrelevant to the argument. (E) The problem with the report was not its hostility to Danto’s products, but its hostility towards Ocksenfrey’s products. Thus, (E) distorts the stimulus and is incorrect. 5. (B) Weaken the Argument Don’t let outside knowledge influence your answer to a question. It’s fairly rare to see a question that deals with a contentious current issue on the LSAT—the testmaker understandably likes to avoid claims of bias in its questions, and avoiding certain topics helps with that goal. But questions dealing with global warming occasionally show up, perhaps because the issue is so prominent. That doesn’t give us license to insert our own opinions into the question, or even to bring in whatever facts we may know about the issue. We should treat this like any other Weaken question— identify the conclusion and the evidence, find the assumption, and try to provide evidence against it. We can go a step further with this particular stimulus, since it gives us a causal argument—the increase in average annual temperatures over the last century is due to the buildup of minor gases in the atmosphere. Look for any of the classic alternatives to causation: the causation is reversed (an increase in temperature caused a buildup of minor gases); some third factor caused either the buildup of gases or the temperature increase or both; or the association is merely a coincidence. (B) suggests that there must have been some other factor at work, since the warming and the buildup of minor gases didn’t occur at the same time, so it weakens the causal relationship and is the correct answer. (A) “Industrial pollution” is outside the scope of the argument, but very much a part of the global warming debate—don’t let that lead you to select this wrong answer. (C) “more solar radiation” is likewise sometimes cited as a cause of warming in the real world, but if you read (C) carefully, you’ll notice that it talks about more radiation in some years than in others, not more radiation over the last centur y. That yo-yoing of radiation wouldn’t say anything about the cause of a steady increase in average temperature. Section 2: Logical Reasoning (D) doesn’t link the volcanic dust or the solar radiation to the buildup of minor gases or the Earth’s warming— this choice is outside the scope of the argument. (E) is a 180: if the accumulation of minor gases was greater over the last century, that makes it more likely that they were responsible for other anomalous conditions in the last centur y—like a rise in temperature. (E) would strengthen the argument. 6. (B) Assumption (Formal Logic) Translating Formal Logic statements can help you pinpoint the gap between evidence and conclusion. None of the evidence in this stimulus follows the traditional “if/then” format, but it’s all Formal Logic nonetheless. The first statement gives us something “necessary” for appointment to the executive board: an undergraduate degree. Anything “necessary” is the “then” part of an if/then statement: if someone is going to be appointed to the board, then they must have an undergrad degree. We could shorthand this statement by jotting down something like this: If App. → U. Deg. (No U. Deg. → No App.) The second statement is likewise amenable to translation: no one with a felony conviction can be appointed, so if someone has such a conviction, they won’t be appointed: If Fel. → No App. (If App. → No Fel.) A quick look at the two of these yields a deduction: if someone is appointed to the executive board, then they must have an undergraduate degree and no felony convictions. If App. → U.Deg and No Fel. That cer tainly sounds like a reasonable set of qualifications. Then, in the conclusion, along comes Murray, who is a candidate for Executive Administrator. He’s got both an undergraduate and a master’s degree, but he also has a felony conviction. Our Formal Logic tells us that Murray can’t be appointed to the executive board. That is not, however, the same as the conclusion of this argument—that Murray can’t be accepted for the position. The conclusion requires a fur ther assumption: that if someone can’t be appointed to the board, they can’t be accepted for a position on the board; in short, that there’s no way to get a position on the board besides being appointed. (B) points out this assumption: candidates can only be accepted to the board if they could have been appointed to the board. (A) and (C) might be true, but neither of them describes Murray, so they can’t link the evidence to the conclusion, which means they can’t be the argument’s assumption. (D) also might be true, but again doesn’t help us determine why Murray can’t be accepted as Executive Administrator with his felony conviction. (E) Regardless of its relevance to the duties of the position, a felony conviction disqualifies a candidate for appointment to the board—that’s part of the evidence. The question is whether disqualification for appointment is the same as disqualification for the position itself. 7. (D) Principle (Application) (Formal Logic) Questions that ask you to apply a Principle will often involve Formal Logic. This question asks us to determine which of five individuals (the five mentioned in the answer choices) exhibits the most advanced kind of moral reasoning. We don’t get to debate exactly what kind of moral reasoning is the most advanced, though; we just have to apply the ethicist’s description of it. That description is just two statements, both of which are Formal Logic. The first tells us that the most advanced moral reasoning is based solely on abstract principles. That’s not very clear at all, but it sounds like the ethicist is fully aware he’s being vague, since he defines this advanced moral reasoning even further: it is not selfinterest, and it is not a desire to adhere to social norms and conventions. A summary of the Formal Logic in these statements would look like this: If Adv. → Abs. If Adv. → Not SI and not SN/SC In short: if someone is applying the most advanced kind of moral reasoning, they are working from abstract principles, and from neither self-interest nor social norms and conventions. Only (D) showcases someone who acts from abstract principles, so (D) must be the correct answer. 17 Test 4 Explained (A) Bobby responded to a social norm, the idea that failing to contribute to charity would make him look stingy. (B) Wes was acting out of self-interest when he contributed to charity, since he hoped his contribution would influence his employer’s opinion of him. (C) Donna, like Bobby, was responding to fear of being seen as violating a social convention. (E) Leigh also acted according to social pressure, and not due to an abstract principle. 8. (A) Inference “Complete the argument” Inference questions are very closely related to Main Point questions. A glance at the end of this argument shows that we’re trying to complete a sentence that begins with the Conclusion Keyword, “thus.” It should be clear that we need to determine the conclusion of the argument to answer this question correctly, and that means we should probably think through a variation on Kaplan’s One Sentence Test: if we were to sum all this up in one sentence, what would that sentence say? We’ve already got the beginning of the sentence, so it shouldn’t be too hard to figure out the end. Let’s look at the earlier parts of the argument to see where they lead. First we learn that the electric car isn’t widely used because of technical problems—but once those problems are solved and electric cars are popular, auto emissions will drop and the associated environmental degradation will drop along with them. But, the author warns, the power for all those electric cars doesn’t just come out of thin air. It comes from coal plants, nuclear plants, and dams, all of which come with their own environmental problems. So, the author leads us to the point that the electric car isn’t a panacea; even if it reduces auto emissions, it could lead to environmental damage from other sources. The end of that last sentence should be something like (A), pointing out the negative environmental consequences of the electric car. (B) The argument never links environmental damage to lack of popularity, so this choice doesn’t fit what we already know. (C) is true, but it’s a detail from the very beginning of the argument. The author would have to take us in a circle to make this the conclusion of his argument, and he doesn’t do so. 18 (D) and (E) have the same problem: we know that the electric car has some environmental problems that not everyone has considered, but we don’t know anything about the net effect of that problem. The argument never forecloses the possibility that total emissions will drop or that net environmental degradation will decrease. 9. (E) Weaken the Argument You can always weaken a prediction by stating that the present circumstances will change. Time machines haven’t been invented yet, so there’s no way to know for certain what will happen in the future. All we can do is make educated guesses based on present and past circumstances. Those guesses necessarily assume that the present and past circumstances won’t change enough to affect the prediction, and we can weaken any prediction by showing that the circumstances are changing. The circumstances in this argument deal with video game sales. It’s no surprise to lean that most video games were purchased by people in their early teens—think about who plays most video games. And once we learn that this age group is shrinking, it’s easy to predict, as the author does, that video game sales would drop. But that assumes that the past circumstances will stay the same—that people in their early teens will continue to account for the overwhelming majority of video game sales. We could weaken this argument by showing that another age group will pick up the slack, and (E) does just that. (A) strengthens the prediction, by suggesting that other age groups will not make up for declining sales to people in their early teens. (B) could also strengthen the argument, but to be sure of that we’d have to assume that video game rentals move in tandem with video game sales. In fact, the reverse could be true—if fewer people rent video games, more people might buy them. But without knowing for sure how rentals affect sales, we can’t say that (B) affects the argument at all. (C) could strengthen the argument as well—new entertainment options might make people less likely to play video games. (D) the number of different types of games available isn’t necessarily relevant to how many of those games are actually bought. Section 2: Logical Reasoning 10. (B) Main Point The One-Sentence Test can help you find the conclusion of an argument. Ask yourself: what one sentence of the argument would the author refuse to get rid of? Once you’ve found that sentence, you’ve found the conclusion of the argument. Here, the first sentence is the crucial one: scientists should use double-blind techniques wherever possible. The rest of the argument tells us why: they help prevent bias from creeping into the experimental results. That evidence provides even more…er…evidence that the first sentence was the author’s conclusion. (B) restates that conclusion, and is correct. (A) restates the beginning of the last sentence, and (D) restates the end of it. These are both evidence in favor of the author’s conclusion, not the conclusion itself. (C) The argument hints at this idea—if it weren’t true, we wouldn’t need double-blind techniques in the first place—but doesn’t make it into a conclusion. (E) is true, according to the argument, but the author goes a step further in his conclusion than this choice does. 11. (C) Role of a Statement Be sure you know how the statement in question relates to the rest of the argument. The LSAT tries to ratchet up the difficulty level on this question by using a lot of difficult vocabulary. Phrases like “extemporaneous eloquence” aren’t as easy to grasp as we might like, but that doesn’t mean we can’t understand them or the argument as a whole. The basic premise here is a complaint that all of us have heard: TV and the internet (the electronic media) are destroying the intellectual abilities of our population. But the statement in question points out an important fact: when literary culture arose, people complained that it destroyed certain intellectual skills that had been valued in oral culture. The author uses that statement to conclude that the fears of intellectual devastation aren’t necessarily valid, and that it’s more likely that our culture is simply developing different intellectual skills. The statement in question is an example that supports the conclusion; that’s closest to (C). (A) gives us the exact opposite of what we’re looking for. If this choice were correct, we’d expect the statement in question to begin with a Keyword that suggests support, like “for example,” instead of the Contrast Keyword, “but.” (B) the statement does help to illustrate a general hypothesis, but not the one cited in (B). (D) goes a touch too far—the author says that the cultural change is “probably” not a bad one, but (D) tries to claim that he’s proving the common complaint false. That scope is just too broad. (E) The statement in question is never dismissed, as (E) would have it. 12. (A) Parallel Reasoning To form a paraphrase of the answer in a Parallel Reasoning question, sum up the argument using the broadest terms possible. Suddenly, the LSAT has become philosophical, wrestling with the idea of keeping conflicting promises. The conflict arises between a promise to keep a confidence and an unspoken promise to tell the truth; if someone asks a question that can’t be answered truthfully without breaking the confidence, then it’s impossible to both tell the truth and keep the confidence. Ultimately, the author’s argument regarding these two promises boils down to a very simple assertion: if it’s impossible to do two things at once, there can be no obligation to do both of them all the time. Notice that we didn’t have to stick to the scope of keeping confidences and telling the truth, so we can use that assertion to test the answer choices. We quickly find the right answer in (A): it’s impossible to both say what you want at all times and be civil at all times, so there can’t be an unlimited duty to be civil and an unlimited right to say what we want. The two things can’t always happen at the same time, so we can’t be obligated to do both of them all the time—this argument makes the same assertion as the stimulus. (B) There are two problems with this answer choice. First, it doesn’t arrive at the conclusion that it’s impossible to keep two obligations at once; and second, there’s never any hint that there are two obligations in the first place, since there’s no proof that politicians must be popular. Either of these would be enough to say that the argument isn’t parallel. (C) is just too uncertain. The stimulus deals in absolute obligations, but (C) is concerned with what might happen in either of two different scenarios. That’s not parallel. (D) and (E) both take an argument through two Formal Logic statements and uses the contrapositives to draw a conclusion. But the conclusion in (D) tells us that 19 Test 4 Explained either of two things must be true, and the conclusion in (E) says that the initial trigger can’t happen—both are different than the stimulus’s assertion that two things cannot both be true. 13. (C) Assumption Beware of irrelevant comparisons in the answer choices. We learn quite a bit about aluminum soft-drink cans in this stimulus—for instance, all standard aluminum soft drink cans contain the same amount of aluminum, and the amount of material other than aluminum in the cans is negligible. We also learn a bit about two groups of standard aluminum soft drink cans—L and M. It turns out that group L was recycled to form 50% of the aluminum in group M. The author uses that fact, plus the facts about the amount of aluminum in the cans, to conclude that group M must be twice the size of group L. That makes a certain amount of sense, since all the cans hav the same amount of aluminum in them, and group M has twice the amount of aluminum as group L…or does it? Look closely at how group M is described: half of the aluminum in group M “was recycled from” group L. That doesn’t say that group M contains twice as much aluminum as group L; it only says that half of the aluminum in M was recycled from group L. How does the author then conclude that group M contains twice as much aluminum as group L? She must be assuming that the recylcing process reclaims and reuses all of the aluminum in standard soft drink cans. We find that assumption in (C). (A) The argument has nothing to do with recycling the aluminum from group M—only the amount of recycled aluminum from group L. (B) draws an irrelevant comparison between the quality of recycled aluminum and unrecycled aluminum. (D) So what? The cans in group L were recycled into group M, whether they’d been recycled before or not. Their history has nothing to do with the author’s argument. (E) is another irrelevant comparison between aluminum soft-drink cans and other types of soft-drink cans. apparently rougher on it than heating it on the stove. Heating milk to 50 degrees Celsius (about 120 Fahrenheit) in a microwave destroys half of the lysozyme in the milk, while heating milk to the same temperature on a stove retains nearly all of its lysozyme. So clearly, the author concludes, the heat isn’t the culprit, the microwaves are. And there we have a classic causal argument, and a hint as to how to weaken it. The author argues that the microwaves are the culprit, and that heat can’t be. To weaken that argument, all we have to do is find some evidence in favor of the alternative—something that suggests that heat might be behind the destruction of the lysozyme. And if heat is really to blame, then there has to be some difference between heat in the microwave and heat on the stove, to account for the fact that heating milk to the same temperature by different methods leads to different results. (E) gives us both a difference between conventional heat and microwave heat, and a reason why the heat from the microwave could behave differently: microwaving a liquid creates hot spots within the liquid, spots that are much hotter than the final temperature. That gives us a way in which heat could still be responsible for destroying the lysozyme in milk, as long as lysozyme doesn’t really start to break down until it gets hotter than 50 degrees Celsius. Then the hot spots in the microwave would lose their lysozyme, but the milk on the stove wouldn’t get hot enough to start losing any. (E) would weaken the argument, and is thus correct. If anything, (A) strengthens the argument, by showing that more microwaves destroy more lysozyme. In any case, it doesn’t show any difference between microwave heat and conventional heat. (B) The possibility of adding enzymes to replace those lost through heating doesn’t tell us what caused their loss in the first place. (C) starts off well, suggesting that a conventional heat source heats milk more slowly than…a hotter conventional heat source. No difference between conventional heat and microwave heat means that there’s nothing here that weakens the argument. (D) The taste of milk exposed to different kinds of heat is well outside the scope of the argument. 14. (E) Weaken the Argument 15. (D) Assumption Keep an eye out for causal arguments in Weaken questions. Beware of choices that restate the evidence. Warm milk is a classic cure for insomnia, and it’s certainly tasty. But heating the milk in the microwave is With all of the panicked stories about bird flu flying around in the past few years, it’s a surprise that more 20 Section 2: Logical Reasoning flu questions haven’t shown up on the LSAT. The testmakers finally managed to put one together here, but with Kaplan’s techniques innoculating your work, it shouldn’t even be harsh enough to give you the sniffles. The question outlines a new government program designed to avoid the most serious cases of the flu: everyone defined as a high-risk individual will get a flu shot every year. But the vaccination only works against a single flu strain, the strain deemed most likely to be prevalent that year. So, the author concludes, all of the high-risk individuals will have to get vaccinated for a different strain of the flu every year. But that’s only true if we make a key assumption: the strain of the flu that is deemed most likely to be prevalent will be different every year—if the most prevalent strain doesn’t change from year one to year two, then year one’s vaccination should still work a year later. (D) points out this assumption. (A) The number of high-risk individuals is irrelevant, since the evidence tells us that all of them get the vaccine annually. (B) The likelihood of an epidemic might have influenced the government’s policy decision, but it doesn’t connect the evidence about that program to the conclusion about multi-year vaccinations. (C) merely restates the evidence: the vaccine only protects against one strain of the virus. (E) Side effects are outside the scope of the argument. 16. (D) Point at Issue The correct answer to a Point at Issue question must fall within the scope of both speakers’ arguments. Taylor is understandably skeptical of the researcher’s claim that exactly 61 percent of information transferred in a conversation is communicated through nonverbal signals. Essentially, his argument is that the number is far too precise to be taken seriously, because such exact claims can never be scientifically established. Sandra, on the other hand, is much more credible of scientific claims—she notes that many scientific disciplines are extremely precise, so their precision isn’t a reason to doubt them. But notice what Sandra doesn’t mention: the claims of the researchers at the local university. Her argument implies that she’s not ready to dismiss their claim just because it’s precise, but she only speaks about scientific claims in general. The Kaplan Decision Tree will help us find the right answer, by focusing on the scope of each speaker’s opinion and asking whether they’d disagree on each choice. Let’s use it to run through the choices: Taylor has an opinion on (A)—he doesn’t think it’s possible for research to make such a precise claim. But Sandra doesn’t mention anything about this specific claim, so we can reject (A) as outside the scope of her argument. The same analysis gets rid of (B) and (C): Sandra has no opinion about the precision of research on verbal and nonverbal communication, only on the precision of certain scientific disciplines. (D) Taylor thinks that all mathematically precise claims are suspect, and Sandra argues that many scientific claims can be both precise and inherently valid. Both speakers have an opinion on (D), and those opinions differ: we’ve found the correct answer. We can quickly dispatch (E) to finish the question off: Sandra doesn’t mention “inherently suspect claims,” so she can’t have an opinion on them or what they mean for most scientific claims. 17. (B) Flaw Flaw questions are closely related to Assumption questions. With people like this author in charge of hospitals, it’s no wonder that health care costs so much. He’s willing to trust a bunch of computer experts at a conference to tell him what the highest priority of his hospital should be. The assumption underlying his trust of the experts is simple: that these experts know what they’re talking about! If he’s listening to computer experts with regard to setting up the hospital’s database, then his assumption would probably be valid. But who ever heard of asking computer experts how to run a hospital? That would be like asking a doctor how to write a chess program— there’s no reason to think that you’re more likely to get a right answer from them than from anybody else. (B) points out this flaw: the hospital executive is relying on experts whose expertise doesn’t apply to the decision he’s trying to make. (A) The causes of the problem are never discussed in the argument. Neither is any inference about property—that’s (E). Both of these choices are outside the scope of the argument. (C) and (D) both refer to flaws that commonly appear on the LSAT: drawing a conclusion from an unrepresentative sample, and drawing a conclusion about causation from evidence of a correlation. While there’s a good chance that these flaws will appear somewhere on this test, they don’t appear in this problem. 21 Test 4 Explained 18. (B) Inference Don’t strain to predict an answer in Inference questions; just test each choice to see whether it must be true. It’s refreshing to hear global warming discussed in terms of the scientific method, rather than in the political terms that usually accompany the issue. Perhaps that’s why the testmaker chose to include this question. Anyway, the author points out that the scientific method is designed to test hypotheses by attempting to prove that they are incorrect, and that succeeding in disproving a conventional theory is the most prestigious accomplishment for a scientist. Thus, it’s not surprising that a number of scientists are attempting to disprove the conventional wisdom regarding predictions of global warming—the surprising thing is that none of them have yet succeeded. We could make all sorts of predictions for where else the argument might go, or what else must be true according to the author. But our time will be better spent combing through the answer choices for something that must be true based on the statements we already have: (A) There’s no evidence that scientists involved in the global warming debate, on either side, haven’t been acting in accordance with the accepted standard. This choice is outside the scope, and is thus incorrect. (B) The stimulus does indeed point out a substantial motive for scientists to discredit the global warming hypothesis: the recognition that would come with success in doing so. (B) must be true, and is the correct answer. Let’s quickly eliminate the last choices: (C) is far too extreme—there’s no evidence that global warming is true, only a lack of evidence that would prove it false. (D) Alternative hypotheses are outside the scope of the stimulus, which deals only with the conventional hypothesis. (E) is also extreme: the stimulus says that a desire for recognition is a driving force behind global warming resarch, but not the primary force. 19. (A) Strengthen the Argument EXCEPT Characterize the choices whenever you see an EXCEPT. The historian concludes that the Land Party succeeded in the Banestrian elections of 1935 because it 22 specifically addressed the problems of agricultural and small business interests, which were facing particularly deep economic problems that year. The evidence in favor of his conclusion is that the Land Par ty specifically targeted those groups; those groups were particularly hard hit economically in 1935; the location of those groups in rural and semi rural areas; and the fact that 1935 was the only time the Land Party ever won a national election. Four of the answer choices will strengthen the connection between those disparate pieces of evidence and the conclusion about why the Land Party won the national election in 1935, while the correct answer will either weaken that connection or do nothing to it. Let’s test the choices: (A) Urban groups are outside the scope of argument, as are attempts to reach them. In fact, the argument states that the Land Party targeted other areas of the country in its victory. (A) doesn’t make the conclusion any more likely to be true, so it is the correct answer. All of the other choices will strengthen the argument. Let’s look at how. (B) strengthens the likelihood that the Land Party’s efforts to target agricultural and small business interests would bear electoral fruit, and (C) bolsters the connection between the economic problems in those areas and the Land Party’s success. (D) points out that the Land Party was the only party addressing the issues of certain voters that helped them win the election, (E) strengthens the correlation between those voters’ economic distress and the likelihood that they would vote. All of these choices strengthen the ties between a specific piece of evidence and the conclusion the historian draws from it. 20. (E) Method of Argument An author will often proceed by pointing out a flaw in a position she opposes. Whenever the LSAT begins with the formulation “soand-so claims that…” you should expect the author to contradict the claim somehow. After all, if they weren’t going to contradict a claim, they’d make it themselves, instead of pointing out who is responsible for such a ridiculous idea. This argument is no different. Gamba begins by outlining Muñoz’s claims: that the Hopewell Neighbors Association opposes the new water system, and that this means the city opposes it. She then goes on to shred Muñoz’s evidence for his claims. As Gamba tells us, it turns out that less than 10% of the 350-member Association even voted on the water system, and that even then the vote was pretty close— it came out 15 to 10 against the water system. The 15 Section 2: Logical Reasoning opposing votes are less than 1% of the membership of the association, and Gamba tells us that such a small sample doesn’t accurately represent the views of the association, much less the town as a whole. If the word “represent” in the conclusion turned on a light bulb in your brain that said, “representativeness,” you probably got this question correct very quickly. (E) recognizes that Gamba points out the flaw of representativeness in Muñoz’s argument. (A) Perhaps the reason that so few members of the Association voted on the water measure is that people with certain views were more likely to vote, as (A) suggests, but Gamba never brings this up in her argument. (B) Gamba also never mentions the possibility of statistical manipulation. (C) Gamba never gets down to arguing about whether the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion—she denies the truth of the premise Muñoz uses, that the Neighbors’ Association overwhelmingly opposes the water system. That also shows that the evidence in question is not “impossible to disconfirm,” as (D) would have it. 21. (A) Flaw Certain common flaws appear regularly on the LSAT. After a long section of difficult questions, a simple Flaw question that employs one of the most common logical fallacies on the LSAT has to be refreshing. As is often the case with arguments involving drivers, this author sounds like he’s not far out of high school. His friends are all worried that he’ll get into an accident because he’s such a reckless driver. Yet he’s convinced that all he has to do is trade in his sports car for a minivan, and he’ll be less likely to have an accident, since minivans and sedans have low accident rates compared to sports cars. What he doesn’t realize (and what should be obvious to us) is that accidents are caused by drivers, not by cars. Drivers of minivans tend to be more cautious than drivers of sports cars, so minivans have a lower accident rate than sports cars. The author won’t be able to take advantage of that accident rate unless he starts driving like the typical minivan driver instead of the typical reckless sports car nut. He’s fallen into a classic logical flaw: mistaking a correlation (minivans have low accident rates) for causation (driving a minivan causes fewer accidents). That’s (A). (B) was the flaw in Question 20! Even though there is a mention of a statistic, there’s no sample here—the rate of accidents for different types of vehicles comes from data about all accidents. (C) is a pretty good definition of the flaw of Possibilty vs. Certainty, but that flaw isn’t present here. (D) also mentions a common flaw that isn’t present in the argument: Necessity vs. Sufficiency. (E) No source, well-informed or otherwise, is cited in the argument. 22. (D) Inference An Inference on the LSAT is something that must be true based on the information in the stimulus. As is often the case, this Inference stimulus doesn’t contain a full argument. We simply get a series of facts and have to try to link them together to find a deduction, or look for an answer choice that restates part of the stimulus. The correct answer will be a statement that must be true based on the information we’re given, and the four wrong answers will all be statements that could be false. The stimulus itself is a series of disheartening facts about the news media and local politics. The news media doesn’t cover local politics, and local politics are conducted in secret; these two factors each work to isolate local politicians from the electorate. This isolation reduces the chances that residents can influence local politics, which discourages their participation, which (we can guess) leads to a vicious circle where there is less and less participation in democracy. As soon as we’re finished mourning the death of the republic, we’ll work our way through the choices: (A) goes too far. Perhaps, if politicians were less isolated, resident participation would be more likely to elicit a response than it is now, but we can’t be sure that the response would be likely. (B) adds an opinion to the stimulus that isn’t really present. The author might agree with this statement, but for all we know, he might also think that less resident participation is a good thing! Without any statements one way or another, we just can’t be sure. (C) is too extreme. A positive official response is clearly a factor in resident participation, but it need not be the most important factor. (D) The rarity of media coverage of local politics is cited as a factor that isolates local politicians from the electorate, and this isolation discourages resident par ticipation…so adding more coverage of local politics would reduce the isolation, which would reduce the discouragement. (D) ties together different pieces 23 Test 4 Explained of the argument in a way that logically follows, so it is correct. (E) We can quickly eliminate this last choice as extreme. Isolation from the electorate discourages participation; there’s no evidence that if we reduced the discouragement, the isolation would also drop. 23. (C) Assumption (Formal Logic) Watch out for different ways of phrasing Formal Logic statements. The “if” in the first sentence should immediately clue you in that you’re dealing with Formal Logic. So we’ll start translating statements and looking for ways to combine them right away. First, we learn that if an action is reasonably expected to increase the aggregate well-being of the people affected by it, then it’s morally right (notice how we were careful about the order of the “if” in that statement). This translates as: If WB up → Right And the contrapositive: If something isn’t morally right, then it doesn’t increase the well-being of those affected by it. If not Right → WB not up The next statement is a bit more complicated, since it’s an “if and only if.” That’s really two statements in one, and it’s the only time that a statement and its reverse are true. An action is morally wrong if it is reasonably expected to reduce the aggregate wellbeing of those it affects; and if it is reasonably expected to reduce the aggregate well being of those it affects, it is morally wrong. Those statements (and their contrapositives) look like this: If Wrong → WB down; If WB not down → not Wrong If WB down → Wrong; If not Wrong → WB not down The author uses these statements to conclude that if an action is reasonably expected to leave the aggregate well-being of the people it affects unchanged, then it’s morally right. There’s just one problem with that statement—actions that leave the well-being of those they affect unchanged are outside the scope of the original statements, which only deal with actions that change the well-being of those they 24 affect. The only way to link that evidence to this conclusion is by making an assumption about when an action is morally right—and the only way to connect neutral actions to the evidence about actions that affect the well-being of the population is by simply assuming that if an action isn’t morally wrong (in that it doesn’t negatively affect the well-being of people it affects), then it must be morally right. (C) does just that, giving us a reason why neutral actions would be morally right. (A) merely restates a piece of evidence, that an action is morally wrong only if it is reasonably expected to reduce the aggregate well being of the people it affects. Something that’s already stated in the argument cannot be the author’s assumption. (B) comes close, because it tells us that even actions that do not affect the aggregate well-being of their targets cannot be both right and wrong. But it doesn’t give us a reason why those actions would be right. (D) restates another part of the stimulus, but the mere fact that such actions exist doesn’t tell us whether they are right or wrong. (E) is yet another restatement of par t of the evidence—if an action has good consequences (in other words, if it increases the aggregate well-being of the people it affects), then it is right. 24. (A) Principle A Principle question asks you to rephrase the gist of the argument in general terms. Auto manufacturers have a problem. They get all kinds of consumer information about whether certain parts of their cars work well for consumers, but that information isn’t as helpful as actual interaction with consumers. The reason why not is simple—consumer information can tell them what the problem is, but not how to fix it. Interaction between designers and the consumers is, we’re told, “superior” to survey data. The natural conclusion is that the interaction helps the designers determine the best way to correct problems with their cars. (A) restates this conclusion in broad terms: consumer input on the proposed modifications can help designers do their jobs well. (B) It’s true that car companies solicity consumer informaion, but that’s not the point of the argument. Choices that focus on a detail instead of the argument as a whole will never be the right answer to a Principle question. (C) Market niches are outside the scope of the argument altogether. Section 2: Logical Reasoning (D) If consumers aren’t consulted during the design phase, it’s possible that a car will end up with unappealing features, but nothing in the argument suggests that it’s a given. (D) is thus too extreme. (E) Both of the design features mentioned in the argument—seats and controls—are internal components of a car, contradicting (E). 25. (C) Paradox Get as much information as you can from the question stem. The stem for this question doesn’t just tell us that it’s a Paradox question; it also tells us exactly what the paradox is. Before we even look at the stimulus, we know we’re trying to explain a difference in the amount of innovation into different art forms, painting and sculpture, in nineteenth century France. From the stimulus, we learn that there was far more innovation in painting than there was in sculpture. The reason appears to be the desires of the academy of art. We learn that the academy was the main sponsor of French art in the nineteenth century, and that it discouraged innovation. Our job is to figure out why the academy’s sponsorship discouraged innovationin sculpture, but wasn’t able to do so in painting. We find a reason in (C): due to the relative costs of their media, painters didn’t need nearly as much money as sculptors, so they could create unsponsored works. In other words, the academy of ar t could control sculptors, but there were a large number of independent painters who were doing most or all of the innovating. (A) and (B) would actually deepen the paradox, since it would suggest that the academy would have greater ability to discourage innovation in painting than in sculpture. (D) The overlap between sculptors and painters is irrelevant; we’re concerned with the amount of innovation in each art form as a whole, not the innovations of individual artists. (E) Decreasing financial support might explain why artists were more dependent on the academy of art, but it would, if anything, only deepen the paradox of innovation in one supported art form and not another. 25 Test 4 Explained SECTION III LOGICAL REASONING 1. (C) Principle (Application) Familiar question types will sometimes be phrased in unfamiliar ways. At first glance, this might look like a Parallel Reasoning question, but it’s really asking you to apply a Principle, the analysis in the second paragraph. Only one of the answer choices will be subject to the same analysis. This application does have elements of parallel reasoning (it’s asking you to find a similar situation), but there’s no reason to waste time struggling with the distinction just find the answer choice that conforms to the general idea that people may sacrifice comfort/pleasure for the sake of appearances. (C) fits both pieces: the couple sacrifices cost & taste (comfort & pleasure) in favor of impressing their friends (appearances). (A) is missing the “sacrifice” element. (B) is also missing the sacrifice; in fact, the decision is based in part on comfort. (D) here at last we find the missing element of sacrifice, but the second piece, “in favor of appearances”, is absent. (E) again, no sacrifice, though the element of “appearances” is present. 2. (A) Paradox EXCEPT Characterize the choices carefully in EXCEPT questions. Here, the four wrong answer choices will all help to resolve the Paradox. The oddball correct answer will either have no effect or aggravate the confusion. Job one in a Paradox question is always to identify what seems to be wrong. Here, Jimmy bought a new, allegedly more efficient gas water heater, but his bills went UP. What does that mean? Either the new water heater doesn’t compare as favorably with the old one as Jimmy had hoped, or there’s some other factor driving up his gas bills. All of the choices except (A) provide an alternative explanation as to why Jimmy’s gas bills have increased (and so are readily eliminated); (A) is in keeping with what we would have expected from the new, higher efficiency water heater and it does nothing to explain the higher bills. (B) More usage = higher cost; that’s one outside factor that could explain the increase. Eliminate. 26 (C) Again, increased usage explains the increased cost. Eliminate. (D) Higher rates could mean a higher gas bill even though Jimmy’s usage might have decreased—another outside factor that resolves our confusion. Eliminate. (E) Just like (B) and (C), (E) explains the increased cost by giving us a reason for increased usage. Eliminate. 3. (E) Point at Issue The key to every Point at Issue question is that BOTH speakers must have addressed the issue set forth in the correct answer. You might well be able to predict the answer to this question—Carolyn says this thing on display isn’t a portrait at all, while Arnold says it’s “a maximally realistic portrait”. That’s (E). If you didn’t see that, the Kaplan Decision Tree makes quick work of this one. (A) Carolyn doesn’t mention “art.” Eliminate. (In fact, Arnold doesn’t either, but there’s no reason to get that far.) (B) Carolyn doesn’t address whether or not it’s Quinn’s work, either; Eliminate. (C) Carolyn takes a position on this, so keep it on the first pass. Does Arnold talk about a “recognizable resemblance”? He does not, so eliminate the choice. (D) Carolyn doesn’t take a position on this directly— does she do so implicitly by pointing out that it’s replicated DNA? That question is a distraction we don’t need to deal with: if she does implicitly address the issue, her conclusion is yes—and so is Arnold’s. There’s no disagreement. 4. (E) Flaw Boil down an argument to its true elements; don’t be distracted by extraneous information. As always in an argument-based question type, start by breaking the argument into its components. The crux of this one is concentrated in the last two sentences of the stimulus. The conclusion is that motivational posters at these corporations won’t boost employee motivation to work productively. Why not? The only evidence submitted is that most are already motivated to work productively. But the goal was to “boost” motivation, not to create it. The fact that it already exists doesn’t preclude an increase. That’s a perfect match for (E). This question lends itself very well to Section 3: Logical Reasoning prediction and you shouldn’t have to analyze answer choices, but for the record: (A) The argument addresses only those companies that are using the posters, so (A) is outside the scope. (B) Again, outside the scope—since we’re only concerned with whether THESE corporations will achieve their goal through the use of these posters, representativeness is irrelevant. (C) We’re concerned only with one beneficial effect: motivating employees to work productively. (D) Also outside the scope; we’re not concerned with actual employee productivity, but with motivation. 5. (C) Assumption Assumption questions are always vulnerable to prediction, and it’s the best protection against getting tangled up in wrong answer choices. Conclusion: The entomologist who thought the ants were carrying food to another colony was wrong. Evidence: Later research showed that they were emptying their own colony’s dump site. Notice that the evidence doesn’t say anything about food—the assumption has to bridge that gap. Does the fact that they were emptying their dump site mean they weren’t bringing food? Only if the dump site didn’t contain food. That’s a match for (C). (A) Irrelevant comparison; all we’re concerned about was whether or not the ants might have been bringing food. (B) Outside the scope—whether or not the ants were “making gifts” and whether or not they were carrying food to the other colony may be two very different questions; in addition, the answer choice asserts only lack of evidence, not an actual lack of capacity. (D) So? The ants in the receiving colony are outside the scope of this argument, which focuses on the behavior of the carrying ants. (E) Does retraction mean he was wrong? Nope, just that he either changed his mind or thought it politic to say that he had. (E) might be distracting because it’s just the kind of thing we’d view as evidence in the real world, but remember that we’re not just asked to find something that makes the conclusion more likely; we’re asked to find the answer choice that tightens the link between the evidence and the conclusion. This answer choice doesn’t provide any kind of bridge. 6. (B) Principle Boil the fact situation in a Principle question down to its elements and you’ll have your prediction in hand. Summarize the key points in the stimulus: Jablonski did a nice thing for the community, and it benefited her. Don’t make the mistake of getting caught up in the details of the driver’s ed program. Find the answer choice that matches the key elements: do a good turn and maybe you’ll get something good in return. (B) matches that perfectly: altruistic actions = nice thing; positive consequences = benefit to her. All of the pieces fit, and we have a match! For the record: (A) may be tempting because it’s on topic, but that’s often a trap. Where’s the nice thing here? Where’s the payoff? The absence of either is reason enough to eliminate. (C) Again, easy to fall into the relevant subject matter trap, but Principle questions are about generalizing. Again, there’s no beneficent action and no payback. Eliminate. (D) Close, but “usually” does this answer choice in; we only have one example here, and can’t draw any conclusions about how often this sor t of thing happens. Contrast with the correct answer choice, which says “sometimes”. (E) Outside the scope—there’s nothing about the success of the action here, only how the community responded. Eliminate. 7. (B) Point at Issue In Point at Issue questions, stay focused on the Kaplan Decision Tree—it’s very easy to get distracted by answer choices related to one argument or the other if you’re not methodical. Start with Antonio and run through all the answer choices, eliminating any that he doesn’t take a position on. Then, walk through any remaining choices and see if Marla’s taken a stand. In this case (as in many Point at Issue questions), the third step, asking whether their opinions on a point disagree, merely confirms that the only answer choice remaining after the first two passes is correct. (A) Antonio takes a position on this—he ties taking great chances with “joy of spontaneity”. Keep it on the first pass. Marla doesn’t state a position on desirability, though, so eliminate this one in round two. 27 Test 4 Explained (B) Correct. Antonio says it means “never deviating from the middle course”; Marla says “never” taking risks is immoderate in itself. For the record: (C) Antonio doesn’t mention embracing other virtues; Eliminate. (D) How often? Antonio didn’t mention that. Eliminate. (E) “Moderately spontaneous”? Antonio doesn’t acknowledge that there’s any such thing, so he certainly can’t take a position on its desirability. Eliminate. 8. (E) Flaw Use the bonus information in your question stem. This one tells you what kind of flaw you’re looking for: something the ad fails to consider. The conclusion set forth in the ad is that Fabric-Soft is the most effective fabric softener available. What’s the evidence to support that? 99% of consumers preferred the Fabric-Soft towel to one washed without it. There is, of course, a significant difference in the key terminology in the evidence and that in the conclusion: the evidence compares towels washed with Fabric-Soft to towels washed without it. The conclusion compares Fabric-Soft’s effectiveness to that of all other fabric softeners. What’s wrong with that? Well, we don’t have any information about the other fabric softeners. Our speaker overlooks (or, more likely, glosses over) the question as to whether Fabric-Soft was compared to the rest of the fabric softeners. That’s (E). (A) Outside the scope; we’re looking only at the link between the study conducted and the conclusion that Fabric-Soft is “most effective” (B) Also outside the scope; Fabric-Soft’s effects on the environment have nothing to do with its effectiveness. (C) Cost also falls outside the scope. (D) Again, whether or not it’s worth the cost has nothing to do with effectiveness. 9. (D) Assumption Don’t let slight changes in formatting distract you— an Assumption question is about finding the Evidence and Conclusion and bridging the gap, no matter what the stimulus looks like. The language of the question stem reveals that this Assumption question is vulnerable to the Denial Test. It’s asking for an assumption the argument depends upon, or one that MUST be true in order for the argument to hold water. Still, predicting should be your 28 first line of attack. The conclusion is that the Tasmanian tiger no longer exists. Evidence? No one in the area has found any evidence of its survival. The first thing that jumps out at you might be the assumption that lack of evidence means lack of tigers—that’s a classic logical fallacy. That’s not exactly the answer that the testmakers are looking for, but (D) gives us a specific reason that lack of evidence in the area might not mean the tigers no longer exist. If you recognized that relationship and picked it out quickly, great; if not, the Denial Test works here. What if the tiger DID move to another region? Then the lack of evidence of the tiger’s continued existence in THIS region is irrelevant, and the conclusion can no longer be true. (D) must be the author’s assumption. (A) What if this isn’t true? The Tasmanian tigers might have ceased to exist for some other reason, so it’s not a necessary assumption; Eliminate. (B) What if there are no scavengers who can destroy all traces of the tiger? Well, then, we should have seen some trace of them if they were still around, just like the author said. (B) actually weakens the argument by providing an alternative explanation for the lack of evidence; Eliminate. (C) What if there was one who hadn’t? Would that invalidate the argument? Would it be necessary that every naturalist had looked for the data to be valid? Of course not. More importantly, this distracts from the hole we already identified—the gap wasn’t in the data, but in drawing the conclusion that the tigers had ceased to exist simply because no one had seen traces of them in the area. (E) If this wasn’t true, and experienced naturalists had been reporting sightings, what would happen to the argument? Since the argument is based on the lack of evidence such as carcasses and tracks, it would have no effect at all; (E) is outside the scope. 10. (E) Inference Ordinarily, you should move straight to evaluating the choices in an Inference question; but if a prediction jumps out at you, feel free to scan for it. Advertisers have found that people will develop more positive attitudes about things when they’re pictorially linked to things those people already have positive feelings about. This question lends itself very well to prediction. Since it’s an advertiser’s job to engender positive feelings in his market, what’s he likely to do? That’s right—create pictorial links to things people have positive feelings about. That’s (E). Section 3: Logical Reasoning (A) The stimulus didn’t tell us anything negative about prose, only that it worked better when there were also pictorial links. Eliminate. (B) Distortion—it’s the associations we need to create pictorially; it’s the advertisers’ methods, not their products, which are at issue. (C) Both television and magazines can include visual images, so this is an irrelevant distinction. (D) Nothing in the stimulus leads us to believe there’s a benefit in negative associations or contrast. 11. (E) Assumption An Assumption is something that MUST be true in order for the argument to hold water. The author’s conclusion is that mercury levels in saltwater fish are higher now than they were 100 years ago. How does he know? His evidence is that the mercury in a seabird’s feathers comes from the fish he eats, and that live birds have more mercury in their feathers than seabirds stuffed in the 1880s. You can predict the assumption generally as “nothing has happened to diminish the mercury in the stuffed birds’ wings”. A slightly more specific version of that prediction is (E). (A) Might be tempting at a glance, and the hasty may be penalized here; it is a weakener, not an assumption. (B) Maybe it does and maybe it doesn’t, but either way, it doesn’t affect the link between the mercury content in the birds’ feathers and the conclusion that fish have a higher mercury content today. (C) Just like (B), this may or may not be true, but it has no bearing on the link between the evidence and the conclusion. (D) would be more appropriate as the answer to a weakening question; both it and (A) provide alternative explanations for the lower mercury levels in the stuffed birds’ feathers. 12. (D) Main Point Don’t make a question harder than it is; if there’s one thing you know how to do by now, it’s break an argument into its component parts. Find the conclusion, find the choice that matches, and move on to spend your time on questions that require a greater investment. “it is more likely that” provides a nice flag, and the conclusion follows: it is more likely that the similarities are coincidental. More likely than what? Than that one plagiarized the other. (D) is a perfect match—and if you kept your attention tightly focused on the conclusion, the wrong answer choices will be far less tempting. (A), (B), and (C) are mentioned in the stimulus, but not as the conclusion. If you’ve identified the conclusion up front and stay focused on it, you should be able to eliminate these choices quickly. (E) summarizes the whole argument, but just doesn’t answer the question you were asked. This question provides a great illustration of the power of reading the question stem, understanding what the question is asking of you, and then focusing in on that issue. 13. (B) Strengthen the Argument The correct answer to a Strengthen question need not prove the argument, only make the conclusion a little more likely to follow from the evidence. The therapist tells us that cognitive psychotherapy is likely to be more effective than forms that focus on the unconscious. Why? Because only conscious beliefs are under the patient’s direct conscious control. Identifying the assumption will provide us a loose prediction for our strengthener: the therapist assumes that it’s more effective to work with those beliefs that are under a patient’s direct conscious control. The argument would be strengthened if we could confirm that assumption— and that’s exactly what (B) supplies. The stimulus may be intimidating in terminology and in that most of it is one long sentence; that’s all the more reason to stay focused on the components and resist the temptation to get sucked into the technical aspects. (A) is a weakener—if changing unconscious beliefs is the key to solving at least some psychological problems, then the assumption that working with conscious beliefs is more effective is undermined. (C) is outside the scope; the stimulus only compares cognitive psychotherapy to forms of psychotherapy that focus on changing unconscious beliefs and desires. (D) blurs the issues: the stimulus concerns itself with comparing a type of psychotherapy that focuses on conscious beliefs/desires (cognitive) with others that focus on unconscious beliefs/desires. We aren’t told about any hybrids (E) looks good going in, but takes a twist at the end in “cannot be controlled effectively without the aid of psychotherapy”. Since we’re comparing two types of psychotherapy, the second clause takes this choice outside the scope. 29 Test 4 Explained 14. (C) Principle Always know what you’re looking for before you attack the answer choices. There’s a lot of talk about open-source software and how it works in the first two thirds of the stimulus, but the “reasoning” referenced in the question stem all takes place in the last sentence—be careful not to get tripped up in the details. Open-source software better matches the values of scholarship; scholarship is essential to universities; therefore, universities should only use open-source software. Why? Attack this just like an assumption question...the conclusion is that universities should only use open-source software, and the evidence is that open-source software better reflects the values of scholarship, which is important to universities. Like an assumption, the correct answer will tie the “reflects the values of...” to “should only use”.(C) does that. (A) directly contradicts the author’s conclusion—he wants universities to use the software that reflects the values of scholarship, not necessarily the most advanced or efficacious. (B) also contradicts the author’s asser tion that universities should use only open-source software. This one is a bit sneakier, though, since the first half of the stimulus does indicate that open-source software doesn’t require a fee to customize (as proprietary software does). Open-source apparently is less expensive, but the author’s preference isn’t based on cost. (D) is a trap for the careless reader—the first four lines appear dead-on, but then a twist at the very end: who said anything about efficient? (E) is outside the scope; the author talks only about reflecting the values of scholarship; there’s no indication that proprietary software might somehow “block the achievement of the goals of academic scholarship”. 15. (C) Weaken the Argument Every LSAT question has one correct answer and four terrible ones. Pay no attention to the phrase “most seriously” in a Weaken stem; one answer choice will weaken the argument and the other four will not—it’s not a balancing test. Begin by breaking down the argument. We learn that psychological treatment lasting more than 6 months is more effective than shorter-term treatment. This conclusion is based on a survey 30 reporting that 20% of people who received treatment for 6 months or less said it “made things a lot better”, compared with 36% of those who received longer treatment. In essence, more of those who stayed in treatment longer said it worked. To weaken the idea that those numbers mean longer-term therapy works better, all we need is another reason that the 6-monthplus group reported better results. (C) gives us just that—it isn’t that longer-term therapy works better, but that people more often opt for longer-term therapy if they feel it is working. (A) “Made things worse” is outside the scope; we’re looking for an alternative reason for the greater number of positive responses among the 6-month-plus group. (B) A variation on the old numbers/percentages scope shift—since the data was reported as a percentage of each group, the raw numbers don’t matter. Eliminate. (D) An irrelevant comparison; presumably this would be true across both groups, and so wouldn’t explain why one group rated the treatment more successful than the other group. Eliminate. (E) We’re interested in the reason for the discrepancy in positive ratings, not a reason for people to remain in treatment longer. If anything, (E) strengthens the argument, since the recommendation might show, more effective to undergo longer-term treatment. 16. (B) Inference Inference questions that ask for the logical conclusion to the argument are good targets for prediction. The language gets a little tough here; just take it piece by piece. Nations aren’t persons. Thus, they don’t have moral rights and responsibilities. BUT, for a nation to survive, its citizens have to think it does. All that means that if citizens recognize that a nation has no moral rights and responsibilities, it won’t survive; or, if it’s going to sur vive, citizens have to think (erroneously) that it does have some moral rights and responsibilities. That’s (B). (A) Introduces a new element; the answer choice that “logically completes” the argument will be based on the evidence provided in the argument. Eliminate. (C) Draws a conclusion from one statement within the argument; we’re specifically asked here for the logical conclusion to the argument itself. Eliminate. (D) Outside the scope; the argument isn’t about value judgments. Section 3: Logical Reasoning (E) The “always” in this answer choice is too Extreme— it also takes us beyond the scope of the argument, which is about one particular belief. 17. (B) Assumption The difference between the language of the evidence and the language of the conclusion reveals the gap the Assumption must fill. As always, begin by breaking the argument into evidence and conclusion. In this case, the conclusion is in the first sentence: to maintain a healthy back, it’s important to exercise the muscles on opposite sides of the spine equally. The evidence is that balanced muscle development is necessary to maintain a healthy back. The last four lines of the stimulus tell us why that’s true, but we already have the core of the argument here and don’t want to be distracted by those details. It might seem clear from a common sense perspective that exercising both sides equally is important to balanced development, but that’s one of the traps in some assumption questions: we’re prone to make the assumption right along with the author. What we are actually told about the connection between equal exercise and balanced development is, well, nothing. The author assumes a connection—and that assumed connection is set forth in (B). (A) is wrong all over. The author says balanced development is necessary, not sufficient, and the answer choice goes beyond the scope of the argument. Although (C) focuses on exercise rather than muscle development, it’s wrong for all the same reasons as (A). (D) is too extreme; the words “irreparably damaged” should have sent up a big red flag. (E) “Daily” comes out of nowhere; it’s outside the scope. 18. (B) Flaw Always be on the lookout for classic flaws. The author concludes that it’s likely to be widely accepted that it’s sometimes morally right to obstruct the police. That’s a surprising conclusion, and as we’d expect in a Flaw question, the evidence supporting it is tenuous: it’s widely accepted that we have a duty to protect our families from harm, and so most would agree that parents would be right to hide a child falsely accused of a crime. In three short sentences we’ve moved from “obligation to protect family” to “morally right to obstruct police”. But the stimulus makes no mention of other moral obligations that might come into play; for example, there might be a moral obligation to obey the law, or to work within the legal system to resolve false accusations. (B) points out this oversight. (A) The author hasn’t really drawn a “broad generalization” in his conclusion; he said “sometimes”, and that could mean only under ver y narrow circumstances. (C) Justice is outside the scope, unless we’re assuming it’s synonymous with “morally right,” and we have no basis in the stimulus for that assumption. In any case, this is the direct opposite of the idea the author is advancing. (D) is too Extreme. The author qualified his conclusion with “sometimes”, and limited it to cases of false accusation. He might recognize a moral obligation to obey the law, and simply be balancing moral obligations and finding the duty to protect family more powerful. (E) The evidence we’re presented says “if the person is known...to be falsely accused”. Don’t argue with that; our analysis is of the validity of the conclusion must be based on the evidence we’re presented. 19. (A) Strengthen the Argument Never lose sight of the tight connection between Strengthen questions and Assumptions—identify the Assumption and most of your work is done. The conclusion is neatly identified for us by “Thus” in the last sentence: governmental intrusion into our lives isn’t likely to decline substantially in a democracy. Why not? Because we elect people who promise to solve problems, and those solutions require intrusion (at least in the form of taxes). As always, there’s a gap to be bridged, but this time it takes place within the evidence itself. One piece of the evidence talks about promises to solve problems, the other about the solutions themselves. Our author sees continued intrusion as inevitable because that’s what it will take for the politicians we elect to keep their promises...but we have no evidence that they will keep their promises. That’s the author’s assumption, and (A) points it out. (B) Weakens the argument by breaking the link between the promises and the “inevitable” intrusion. (C) is outside the scope; our concern is about whether or not politicians will follow through on their promises, thus necessitating the intrusion of taxes. (D) is an irrelevant comparison; we’re interested only in democracies. (E) Whether politicians believe in their promises is outside the scope; we’re only concerned with action. 31 Test 4 Explained 20. (C) Parallel Flaw Parallel Flaw questions are both manageable and vulnerable to a methodical approach so long as you don’t get tangled up in the facts and lose sight of the structure. The argument in the stimulus concludes that “we” should take a certain action (accept the proposal to demolish the train station) because people with questionable motives say otherwise. The most efficient means of attacking this one is to recognize the flaw: a position isn’t necessarily wrong just because it’s endorsed by people whose motives you question. That’s a match for (C), If piece by piece analysis is required: (A) “Nevertheless” lets us know this author wants to act in spite of possible opposition, not because of it. Eliminate. (B) No “other side” is presented at all in this choice. Eliminate. (D) Proposes conceding to the people who object, not acting because of their opposition. Eliminate. (E) Just like in (B), there’s no outside voice in play here. Eliminate. 21. (B) Weaken the Argument Just like Strengthen questions, Weaken questions are tied tightly to Assumptions, so begin just as you would in an Assumption question. The author concludes that the consumption of meat will soon be morally unacceptable. She bases this conclusion on the facts that we use up 16 pounds of grain to produce one pound of meat, and that grain could feed a lot more people; moreover, the population is growing and grain production is leveling off. In essence, there’s going to be less grain to go around, and it can feed more people as grain than as meat. The author’s ruling against meat relies entirely on the investment of grain, and that’s where we’ll find the gap in her argument: she assumes that meat can’t be produced without that investment of grain. If we can show that it is possible to produce meat without using up grain people could be eating, it will weaken the argument—and that’s what (B) does. (A) is outside the scope; our author is concerned with morality, not preference. Eliminate. (C) is a 180: it strengthens the argument by eliminating a possible argument in favor of meat eating. Eliminate. (D) The author introduces a number of factors impacting the viability of investing grain in meat: yields leveling off, 32 farmland going out of production, and population growth. (D) addresses only one aspect of one of those factors, and not the investment of grain that meat requires. (E) Outside the scope, and the word “solely” is the tipoff: the author never suggested eating only grain; she’s concerned with eliminating meat consumption. There are many food sources that don’t fall into either category. 22. (C) Inference (Formal Logic) When confronted with a Formal Logic question, translate and combine the statements sentence by sentence. The first three sentences are pretty straightforward, if you break them down one at a time: If the cost of coffee beans continues to increase, the Coffee Shoppe will have to raise prices. (If CB up → P up) If the Coffee Shoppe has to raise prices, either it will add non-coffee products or coffee sales will decline. (If P up → NC or CS down) If it adds non-coffee products, profitability will decrease. (If NC → Pr down) The last sentence takes a bit more work, but the investment is worth the payoff: The Coffee Shoppe can avoid a decrease in profitability only if coffee sales do not decrease. That means: profitability will not decrease only if coffee sales do not decrease. Translate “only if” into “then,” and we get, “if profitability does not decrease, then no coffee sales will not decrease.” (If Pr not down → CS not down) The contrapositive of this last statement (If CS down → Pr down): if coffee sales decrease, then profitability will decrease too. Combine all these statements, and it looks like the Coffee Shoppe is in trouble; if the price of coffee beans keeps going up, it will have to either add non-coffee products or increase the price of coffee, and either way, its overall profitability will drop. That’s (C). Let’s test this against the choices: (A) is a classic reversal. We know that if coffee bean prices continue to increase, profitability will decline, but the reverse is not necessarily true. Eliminate. (B) Likewise, we know that certain events will trigger a decline in profitability, but nothing here precludes other causes. (D) is all right except that it says “decrease” where it should say “increase.” This is a trap for the careless reader. Section 3: Logical Reasoning (E) Coffee sales increasing isn’t referenced at all in the stimulus, nor is it the necessary result of anything we’re given. 23. (D) Flaw The same flaw can be accurately described in a number of different ways; be prepared to be flexible in the phrasing of your prediction. The argument is brief and to-the-point. The author concludes that promises made in candidate speeches are selfishly motivated and unreliable. His evidence is that they’re motivated by the desire to get elected. That explains “selfishly motivated,” but “unreliable” is an entirely new element introduced in the conclusion. The author apparently assumes that any promise made for personal gain is unreliable. There are a number of different ways that could be presented as a flaw. For instance, “the author assumes without justification that promises made for personal gain are inherently unreliable.” In this case, (D) is phrased in “overlooks the fact” terms, but the core meaning is the same as our prediction. (A) Another trap for the skimmer—this answer is a perfect match for our prediction, except that it says “reliable” where it should say “unreliable”. (B) Is too extreme: “unreliable” doesn’t necessarily mean “never kept”. (C) Cause and effect plays no role in this argument; don’t be fooled by the fact that an answer choice restates a familiar flaw. Stay focused on your prediction. (E) Whether a candidate is “worthy of office” is outside the scope; this argument is concerned only with the reliability of promises made in campaign speeches. 24. (E) Principle (Strengthen) A Principle that “helps to justify the argument” is a Strengthener phrased in general terms. The phrasing is a little tricky here, but a moment’s investment to untangle the double negatives and sentence structure will set it right. The sociologist concludes that those who think people aren’t born evil but can be made evil by institutions are wrong. His evidence is that institutions are just collections of people. Thus he seems to assume that the collective cannot form the individual person—that is, that the institutions must be shaped by the people in them, and not vice versa. In this case, as in many Principle questions, the principle and the assumption are one and the same, and as in Strengthen questions, providing evidence for that assumption is enough to strengthen the argument. (E) provides evidence for the “rule” the sociologist relies on without stating directly: the collective doesn’t determine the characteristics of the members. (A) is an irrelevant comparison; the question at hand is the ability of institutions to make people evil. (B) is undoubtedly true, but what does it have to do with the question as to whether institutions can make people evil? Or the more general issue about the collective impacting the individual? (B) is far too general. (C)’s optimism and (D)’s societal values are both outside the scope of the argument. 25. (A) Flaw Necessity vs. sufficiency is one of the most common flaws on the LSAT. Just like in Reading Comprehension, when an author starts out by saying, ‘some other people think X,’ you can be sure he’s going to disagree with X. This author doesn’t break the pattern. The anthropologists claim that humans couldn’t have survived without evolving the ability to cope with different environments, and the author attacks them for it. His reasoning is that another species that also had that ability to adapt died out. There’s a classic flaw (necessity v. sufficiency) screaming to be recognized here. The anthropologists never claimed that any species that could adapt to diverse environments was guaranteed survival, only that adaptation was one essential factor in prehistoric humans’ survival. (A) points out that mistake. (B) Starts out looking good, but takes a twist. The argument doesn’t take for granted that a related extinct species shared the characteristic; it presents that fact as evidence. (C) “Exactly the same conditions” is far too exteme, especially since we’re talking about “diverse natural environments.” (D) is probably tempting, since it explains the discrepancy the author is hung up on. But the argument isn’t really about Australopithecus afarensis at all, but about whether its extinction proves that adaptability to diverse natural environments was unnecessary to the survival of early humans. (D) misses that point. (E) We don’t have the same result occurring in two cases; one species survived while the other became extinct. 33 Test 4 Explained SECTION IV READING COMPREHENSION Passage One: “Poetry and Fiction” Paragraph 1 jumps right into the Topic—the division between poetry and fiction in the U.S. The Scope and Purpose won’t become clear until later in this Humanities passage, but the first paragraph does narrow the topic for us a bit by focusing in on writers and how they’ve perpetuated the division between fiction and poetry. Paragraph 2 suggests a possible reason for the division: U.S. culture doesn’t think much of generalists. We also get a good taste for the author’s perspective in the last sentence, “...as if ability in one field is diluted or compromised by accomplishment in another.” That should clue you in that the author thinks ability is not diminished by involvement in multiple fields, and starts to suggest the Scope of the passage. Paragraph 3 starts with another strong indication of the author’s view, the Keyword “Fortunately.” Our author thinks it’s a good thing that the boundaries are starting to break down. The rest of the paragraph (and, indeed, the rest of the passage) is devoted to the example of Rita Dove, an author whose work blends elements traditionally associated with poetr y and those traditionally associated with fiction. Here, the Scope and Purpose finally come into sharp relief. The Scope, or aspect of the poetry/fiction rift our author is most concerned with, is the move toward the breakdown of the barrier between the two, as represented by Rita Dove. The author’s Purpose is simply to illustrate the trend toward breaking down the poetry/fiction divide that Rita Dove exemplifies. The author’s attitude seems to suggest that he advocates for further breakdown of the barrier, but the rest of the passage doesn’t quite go that far. Rather than advocating anything, the last paragraph simply explains how Dove bridges the gap between poetry and fiction in her work. Roadmap: ¶ 1: Rift b/t poetry and fiction; supported by poets & fiction writers ¶ 2: Why? U.S. suspicion of generalists ¶ 3: Fortunately (author) breaking down; Rita Dove ex. ¶ 4: How Dove blends genres/bridges gap 34 1. (E) Global (Main Point) Use your Roadmap to predict the answer to a Main Point question up front—never jump into the answer choices blind. Reviewing T/S/P and our Roadmap, what’s the primary thing the author wants us to know? The rift between fiction and poetry is diminishing, as Rita Dove’s work illustrates. That’s a match for (E), and for the neutral illustration that finishes the passage. (A) is a distortion: The author makes no claim that the blending of elements is the reason Dove’s work has been well received. (B) The particular elements of Dove’s writing are just details. A list of subsidiary details will never be correct when a question asks you for the main point of the entire passage. (C) Lyrical use of language in narrative fiction is just one illustration of the crossover between genres, not a main point. (D) is too narrow—there’s no mention of the poetry/fiction rift that forms the foundation for the passage. 2. (D) Logic (Parallel Reasoning) When asked to draw a parallel, generalize the references piece of the passage before examining the answer choices. The first thing we need to do is go back to the passage and get a nutshell version of what the author says about Dove’s literary achievements. Our Roadmap tells us that’s probably in Paragraph 4. There, the author tells us that Dove uses techniques typically associated with poetry in her narrative fiction and vice versa. Our correct answer, then, will be about crossing genres, drawing elements from two different ones. That most closely matches (D), in which a choreographer combines elements of two very different types of dance. (A) The combination element might be tempting, but this ultimately distorts the author’s point—Dove’s writing doesn’t combine ‘traditional and nontraditional’ methods. (B) “Theoretical knowledge” is outside the scope of the passage. (C) There’s no true blending here; instead, one medium is consciously used to promote another. (E) There aren’t two genres here, either; guitar solos aren’t exactly a depar ture from rock. (E) also Section 4: Reading Comprehension introduces the element of work that’s not original, something that doesn’t come into play at all in the passage. 3. (A) Detail “According to the passage” is your cue to research the relevant text—don’t operate from memory. The author talked about widely held views in the U.S.in both of the first two paragraphs. There are only two possibilities: from the first paragraph, that poetry should be lyrical and elliptical while fiction is rooted in character and narrative; from the second paragraph, we’re suspicious of generalists. Scan the answer choices for either of those things. (A) is a match for the last sentence of the first paragraph. (B) Distortion—the author discusses the differences between the genres, but he never makes a value comparison (C) Another distortion; the first paragraph says they tend to be operated independently, but says nothing about the balance. (D) “Most aesthetically effective” is too strong; the author does speak favorably of the outcome when fiction—at least, Dove’s fiction—incorporates lyrical elements, but makes no comparison. (E) Distortion—it’s U.S. culture the author says is suspicious of generalists; this is a trap for test takers who skim the answer choices or who try to rely on memory to answer detail questions. 4. (E) Inference (Author’s Attitude) Zero in on the piece of the passage where the author revealed himself. We could probably answer this question based on just one word of author opinion—that “fortunately” where he talks about the turning tide. From that, we can tell that the author’s not a fan, and he’s glad to see it changing. We only get author opinion in two other places, and in the final paragraph it’s about the appeal of Dove’s work, which won’t help us answer this question. But in paragraph 2 he let us know that he thought the U.S. culture’s suspicion of generalists— which he believes feeds the rift—was unfounded. That’s one of those “attitudes and presuppositions underlying the rift” that pop up in (E). (A) The author isn’t perplexed about what caused the rift; he tells us in the second paragraph. (B) “Astonishment” is a strong word, and we have no reason to believe that the author thinks academics are unaware. (C) There’s no sign of ambivalence; the author makes his position on the division crystal clear. (D) The final sentence of the passage announces that one writer, at least, bridges the gap. 5. (D) Detail Use your Roadmap to help you find the answer to Detail questions. Conveniently enough, we have a paragraph that we labelled “Why?”, so we know right where to find the author’s view of the cause. Paragraph 2 tells us that the author believes our skepticism about generalists is behind the division, and we find that in (D). (A) Beware of answer choices that sound true, but don’t come from the passage. Our author never makes this claim, so it’s outside the scope of the passage. (B) The author does tell us that the programs for poetry and fiction are usually segregated, but he doesn’t say (or imply) that it’s the cause of the rift. In addition, “other literary fields” is outside the scope— this is just about fiction and poetry. (C) Entirely out of left field: the author doesn’t blame publishers, doesn’t mention pressure, and “best” doesn’t come into play at all. (E) Maybe it is—or maybe that’s the perception—but our author doesn’t advance that view. 6. (B) Logic (Function) Context is everything in determining the purpose of a particular line, detail, or example. In order to understand the author’s purpose in mentioning a par ticular experience, we have to understand the purpose of the passage as a whole and of the paragraph in which the reference occurs. This particular experience is mentioned in the midst of the longer example of Dove, and comes on the heels of a description of how she couldn’t understand the aversion to blending genres. The Germany reference simply builds on that, providing some background and context for her different perspective on crossing genre lines. That’s (B). (A) The author specifically references U.S. attitudes, but there’s no indication that this perspective is common to English speaking societies; in any case, the 35 Test 4 Explained focus of the paragraph in which this detail falls is on the shift away from the clear division. (C) Again, the paragraph is about the shift away from a hard poetry/fiction dividing line; it’s not about Dove’s skills in general. (D) The focus isn’t on Dove (or human interest), but on the trend away from clear fiction/poetry boundaries. (E) We have no indication in the passage that Dove believes this to be the origin; she references growing up reading both genres. 7. (A) Inference When an Inference question is wide open, with no direction in the question stem, work from the answer choices. You should be able to predict an answer for most Reading Comprehension questions, even Inference questions. But when an Inference stem doesn’t give you any clues to help you research the passage, that doesn’t mean you need to work from memory or guess at the correct answer. Use the Hot Words or other clues in the answer choices to guide your research, like so: (A) Correct—in paragraph 4, the author refers to each of the works he mentions as either poetry or fiction, even while describing how it incorporates elements of the other. For the record: (B) is a distortion. The author talks about these elements in paragraph 4, but he’s focused on the value of the blend, not comparing one to the other. (C) is too extreme. “Without precedent” is a tip-off; such strong language is rarely warranted in an Inference question. Here, the passage itself says nothing so categorical; although he doesn’t specifically reference another writer who blends elements of the two genres, he indicates that the division overall is breaking down. (D) is a comparison that’s outside the scope; the author doesn’t set up any “better than” relationships among the various types of writing and hybrids he discusses. (E) It seems reasonable that they might, but beware that kind of thinking! The only place the author talked about other forms like drama was in the reference to Dove’s experience in Germany, and that isn’t tied in specifically to the writers who successfully cross the fiction/poetr y boundar y—it’s just an example of boundary crossing. 36 8. (A) Inference Don’t let unfamiliar formatting in a question stem throw you off; stay focused on the familiar. The format of the question is a bit unusual, but take a moment to understand what it’s really asking: What would the author be likely to say about the future of U.S. literature? That’s just a standard Inference question, and one we can answer pretty quickly using our Roadmap. The author says it’s “fortunate” that the division is deteriorating; he says Dove is “one example” of writers bridging the gap. What does he expect from the future? Apparently, a continuation of that trend. That’s (A). (B) Markets are outside the scope. (C) goes too far; the author doesn’t talk about the specifics of the relationship between the two or about one or the other as primary—we only know that he thinks the boundaries are coming down. (D) Contradicts the passage—that’s the trend the author says we’re finally breaking free of. (E) Extreme and outside the scope; the focus throughout the passage is on the writers, not the audience. Section 4: Reading Comprehension Passage Two: “Scientific Research on Music” In a comparative passage, our work with the passages is somewhat abbreviated—there’s less text in each passage, so less to cull through to discern the key points. There’s also an added element, though: after determining Purpose and Main Idea for each passage, we have to understand the relationship between the two passages, and understand it explicitly. This passage has six questions and every one of them focuses in some way on the relationship between the passages. That understanding will be critical. We’re told up front that both passages relate to research on music. Passage A begins with a question that reveals the Scope of the passage for us: the question as to whether music and language developed together. The paragraph structure is straightforward: Question in paragraph 1; data indicating the similarities (and one discrepancy) in paragraph 2; conclusion in paragraph 3 that it is likely that music and language evolved together, but that language is the primary driver of natural selection. Purpose: To set for th evidence that music and language likely developed in tandem. Main Idea: Given the common neurological basis for music and language, it seems likely that they developed together as brain size increased, but music developed “on the coattails of language.” Passage B starts out with a quote and isn’t quite so clear, but we get a strong statement of the author’s belief before the end of paragraph 1: music has evolutionary benefits in the bonding of mothers and infants. The second paragraph is devoted to evidence of that use, and paragraph 3 to the possible evolutionary benefits. Purpose: To argue that the ability to produce music has evolutionary benefits related to emotional bonding between mother and child. Main Idea: Music is likely a bonding mechanism that has conferred evolutionary advantage. Remember that our work isn’t done—define the relationship between the passages before moving on! The author of passage A believes that music developed in tandem with language, but regards music as almost an unnecessary side effect of language with no evolutionary benefit. The author of passage B believes that music represents a useful ability that confers an evolutionary benefit by solidifying the mother/infant relationship. The authors thus differ on the major part of their conclusion regarding the evolutionar y significance and advantages of music ability in humans. Both passages have the same topic (music) and both are concerned with the development of musical ability in humans, but the data presented differs greatly: Passage A focuses on neurological data, while the author of Passage B concerns himself primarily with human behavior. 9. (C) Global In a comparative passage, the relationship between the passages will often be key to answering Global questions. Although the question refers to both passages, it’s only asking you to use the work you’ve already done, just like every other Global question in the RC section. We’ve already determined that the question both passages are concerned with is how/why our musical abilities developed. If you don’t let yourself get drawn into analyzing the answer choices, it should be quick work to scan and pick out (C). (A) Too broad—we’re concerned specifically with the development of music; there are presumably many advantages of larger brain size outside the scope of these passages. (B) The bonding issue is only addressed in passage B, so this can be quickly eliminated; if it required a closer look, it could also be knocked out because the focus of even passage B isn’t on why humans behave this way, but on why we evolved musical abilities. (D) This question is answered in Passage A (though not passage B), but only in the interests of answering the larger question posed in the first paragraph—it’s a supporting detail, not the purpose. (E) Again, this can automatically be eliminated because it’s discussed only in one passage, but even there it isn’t the focus of the passage. 10. (B) Detail Relying on memory is even riskier than usual in Comparative Reading, because there’s always the chance of remembering familiar language but not which passage it appeared in. (A) Bonding between humans is mentioned only in passage B. Eliminate. 37 Test 4 Explained (B) Correct—and it’s easy to overlook. Passage A doesn’t delve deeply into the emotional ramifications of music as Passage B does, and it’s easy to gloss right over the reference in the second sentence of the first paragraph. (C) Only passage A provides neurological data. Eliminate. (D) Only passage B, which addresses the bonding value of music. Eliminate. (E) Passage A only; Eliminate. 11. (D) Inference To identify a likely point of disagreement, we need to know what both authors think about the issue. This question might lend itself well to prediction; the authors have addressed the question of musical abilities very differently, which means that the pool of issues we’ve heard addressed by both of them are fairly small. They disagree about the reason for the development of musical ability: Author A sees it as a tag-along to language which doesn’t serve much if any purpose of its own, while Author B thinks it’s an important evolutionary benefit. (D) paraphrases this particularly well. (A) We have no idea what the author of passage A thinks about this. Eliminate. (B) Passage B doesn’t tackle the neurological data at all, so we can’t draw conclusions about what Author B thinks about this. Eliminate. (C) Passage B says directly that brain size evolved rapidly; passage A says only that it evolved. That’s a difference, but not a disagreement—we don’t know that Author A thinks about the rate of increase. Eliminate. (E) Mother/infant bonding isn’t mentioned in Passage A. Eliminate. 12. (C) Inference The correct answer in a “likely to agree” question must be inferrable from each passage independently; lack of evidence of disagreement is not sufficient. Like Q. 11, this question requires us to focus in on something addressed by both authors. This time, though, their positions will agree. Again, the area of overlap between the two passages is small, so this might be predictable, but it’s also easily vulnerable to elimination. Let’s work through the choices: (A) Author A doesn’t take a position. Eliminate. 38 (B) Author A doesn’t take a position. Eliminate. (C) Correct. Although the authors interpret the role of brain size increase differently, each points to a role that development had in the evolution of musical ability. For the record: (D) Author B didn’t talk about neurological system at all. Note that passage A doesn’t address exactly the question asked here, either, but you shouldn’t waste time making that fine distinction when the answer choice can be readily eliminated based on the complete lack of reference in passage B. (E) Neither author addresses the “why” of this discrepancy, though Author A does mention it. Eliminate. 13. (E) Logic (Principle) Use your LR skills to answer parallel question types in RC. We’re looking for a general idea that underlies both passages. Principle questions are usually naturals for prediction, but it might be a little tough in this case. Still, we can rely on the fact that the principle must underlie both passages: that is, anything that is mentioned in only one of the passages is out, and the principle will probably deal with the relationship between the passages. Both passages come to conclusions about the evolutionary significance of music, and the likelihood that music conveyed evolutionary advantages. We might predict something like “modern traits can be explained on the basis of the evolutionary advantages they might convey.” (E) is the closest to that prediction, and has the additional advantage of referring to modern-day humans, another overlap between the passages. (A) If this principle was embraced by our authors, how would we know? Well, they’d be talking about nonhuman animals as part of their data. That’s not happening, so we have no evidence that either believes this. Eliminate. (B) “All human capacities” should send up a red flag right at the outset; this is close to the principle that is ultimately correct, but is too extreme. Eliminate. (C) Neurological facilities are addressed in passage 1 only. Eliminate. (D) Again, passage 2 does not address the neurological basis. Eliminate. Section 4: Reading Comprehension 14. (A) Global (Relationship) The relationship between the passages should be clear in your mind before you ever attack a question. Don’t re-invent what you’ve already done. We noted up front that the data presented by the two authors was very different in nature; their conclusions differed as well. The key difference is their view of the evolutionary significance of evolution; even though the answer choices are general, knowing that they fundamentally disagree on their main point eliminates all but one of the choices. (A) sums up the relationship neatly. (B) Passage B actually sets out to answer a slightly different question—the question as to whether music has evolutionary benefit. Eliminate. (C) Passage B doesn’t support passage A—it reaches an entirely different conclusion. Eliminate. (D) Both authors are clear and consistent in the presentation of their cases; if anything, passage B is more strongly worded, since Author A uses language like “it would seem”. Eliminate. (E) We’ve already determined that the conclusions differ. Eliminate. 39 Test 4 Explained Passage Three: “Intellectual Property on the Web” Beware of familiar topics! Intellectual property on the Internet, the Topic of this Laww passage, is a hot topic and nearly everyone has an opinion; remember to stay focused on what’s presented in the passage, not your own opinions. Paragraph 1 sets forth the conflict: Some owners of intellectual property rights feel stronger protection is required, but web users fear this will limit the potential of the Internet. We leave the first paragraph with a strong sense of the Scope (the conflict over strengthening copyright law: intellectual proper ty owners want stronger copyright, and Web users worry that stronger copyright will destroy the Web). The author’s purpose doesn’t emerge right away, but we can guess that he’ll probably take a side. Paragraph 2 explains the root of the issue: Linking. He also poses what he sees as the underlying question in the debate over increased protection—is linking to someone else’s web page copyright infringement at all? Paragraph 3 provides a long analysis, by analogy, that demonstrates the author’s view that linking to a web page is not copyright infringement, ending with a strong statement of author’s opinion: Changing copyright law to further protect owners would impede development of the web and is ill-advised. This is where we pick up the author’s Purpose: to analyze the need for increased copyright protection and advise against it. Roadmap: ¶ 1: Conflict b/t interests of owners and web users; tighten copyright law? ¶ 2: Problem: Linking—is it copyright infringement? ¶ 3: Telephone analogy; not copyright infringement; author’s view—d/n change law 15. (A) Global (Main Idea) Don’t allow yourself to be distracted by details in addressing a Global question. The passage sets up a critical question in the debate over the need for increased copyright protection: are an owners rights even infringed by someone linking to his web page? His answer is that they are not, and thus there is no reason to increase protection. (A) sums that up nicely. 40 (B) goes further than the passage does—there’s no talk of amplifying free exchange, only the risks of limiting, and the argument is confined to the development of the web, not “a democracy”. The author might agree to this “unless,” but it’s outside the scope of the passage. (C) is a Faulty Use of Detail. Don’t fall into this trap because the passage mentioned specifically. (D) is far too broad. The passage isn’t about resolution of problems concerning intellectual property rights in the electronic age generally, but about one specific issue. (E) The author does argue against changing the law, but (E) has the focus in the wrong place, on balancing interests rather than on whether or not there was copyright infringement at all. This is a Distortion. 16. (A) Logic (Function) The key to a Logic Function question is context. Knowledge of the word itself won’t help; go back to the text and determine how it’s used before tackling the answer choices. The referenced text says that unless copyright law is “strengthened”, some owners will not be protected. The immediate counterpoint is that web users don’t want their access reduced. So “strengthened”, here, means to create additional limitations on access. That’s a match for (A). (B) and (C) Worldwide restrictions are outside the scope of the passage, as are penalties for copyright infringement. (D) and (E) Again, enforcement is not an issue, nor is the legitimacy of current intellectual property law; the passage focuses on the desire for additional restrictions in the law, and the arguments against them. 17. (E) Inference Use the information contained in the question stem to guide your research. The author told us a few things about documents placed on the web in paragrah 3: they’re still controlled by their owners (lines 41–42), linking to them isn’t copyright infringement (42–44), and we restriictions on access to them “would compromise the openness of the Web,” as would copyright infringement litigation (49–51). (E) is a match for the last point. Section 4: Reading Comprehension (A) The opposite of our author’s view—he explicitly states that copyright laws should not be strengthened. Eliminate this 180. (B) is a fairly subtle Distortion: the passage says that password protection would compromise the openness of the Web “somewhat,” not that it would “significantly dimishing the potential of the Web to be a widely used form of communication.” (C) Our author has provided a suggested means of limiting access, so he can’t agree that limiting access is impossible. (D) contradicts the authors view. 18. (C) Logic (Parallel Reasoning) Before attacking a question that asks you to draw a parallel, go back to the passage and get a firm handle on the original text. The author sees tightening the laws as far more damaging to the potential of the Internet than password protection; password protection restricts access and creates some limitations on free exchange and development, but it’s better than changing the law and creating even greater limitations. The correct answer will deal with the relationship between a legal and non-legal, self-help solution to unrestricted access. The only choice that does so is (C)—prohibiting a sport is a restrictive legal remedy, and relying on participants to play safe is a self-help remedy that allows greater access. (A) only addresses the password issue (the self-help remedy), not the relationship to strengthening current copyright laws (the legal remedy). Eliminate. (B) Might be tempting at first, since it’s two different plans of attack on restricting the same activity, but they’re both laws—in our original scenario it’s law versus letting owners create their own protections. (D) Where’s the self-help from our initial scenario? Eliminate. (E) Again, the restriction here is analogous to the password protection option, but the law option is not addressed by unrestricted access. Eliminate. 19. (B) Inference An Inference is something that must be true based on the information in the passage. Where there’s no direction in the stem of an Inference question, we have to work with the answer choices. Don’t just start skimming the passage; we should use material in the choices to guide us back to specific parts of the passage that will tell us whether the answer choice is supported by the passage or not. Without further ado, let’s get to work: (A) ”Creators of links to Web pages” and “owners of intellectual property” are discussed as two different groups in paragraph 3, but the passage gives no reason why there couldn’t be people who are members of both groups. Eliminate. (B) Correct! The author’s analogy in ¶3 is aimed at establishing that control remains in the hands of the owner and linking is thus not copyright infringement, which hinges on distribution. For the record: (C) Privacy rights aren’t at issue; this is about copyright infringement. Eliminate. (D) Contradicts the author’s view, illustrated by his analogy in paragraph 3. Eliminate. (E) Totally outside the scope; the issue here isn’t format but control. 20. (E) Detail A long question stem means a lot of information to direct your research—use it rather than being intimidated by it! The “outgoing messages left on telephone answer machines” are discussed starting on line 31. Revisit these lines to see where the author’s focus is: on the owner being the one who makes the message available to anyone who chooses to access it, which is reflected in (E). (A) The author doesn’t really care that both telephones and Web pages are electronic means of communication. Eliminate. (B) Not only does the author not address legal protections for phone messages, he states that no unauthorized distribution takes place. Eliminate. (C) The author’s reference to instantaneous distribution is in paragraph 2, not related to the phone message analogy. Eliminate. (D) Recording isn’t at issue; the issue is access and distribution. Eliminate. 21. (D) Logic (Function) The author’s purpose for including a detail or example can always be predicted from the context. The author offers the telephone analogy as a means of illustrating that no unauthorized distribution occurs when one provides a link to an existing web page. 41 Test 4 Explained That’s (D), although the answer is phrased in more general terms. (A) Remember the context—the whole passage is about whether increased copyright protections are required for web pages. The second medium is relevant only as an analogy. Eliminate. (B) The analogy is offered in support of the author’s position, not the other side. Eliminate. (C) The author uses the analogy more to illustrate that there is no legal problem than to suggest that it’s an old one. Eliminate. (E) Quite the opposite is true—the author offers the opinion that it wasn’t a problem with phones and it’s not a problem now. Eliminate. 22. (D) Detail Use the information in the question stem to direct your search—research is a time saver when it’s done efficiently. Current copyright law is discussed primarily in the 2nd paragraph, and the exact phrase appears only in line 20. That line gives us only one piece of direct information—copyright holders can sue for unauthorized distribution. That’s (D). (A) distorts the author’s view: there are some new issues with content on the web, but current law clearly prohibits unauthorized distribution (the issue is what that means). (B) Contradicts the author’s view that the owner/publisher controls access. (C) is a trap for those prone to bringing in outside knowledge—the profit issue is batted around a lot in the debate over copyright issues, but it’s NOT mentioned in this passage! (E) The author advocates leaving copyright law as it is, not loosening its restrictions further. 42 Section 4: Reading Comprehension Passage Four: “History of Irish Landscape” The first paragraph of this Natural Science passage introduces limitations on the traditional study of the development of Ireland—the fact that accounts of the landscape are scarce, and where they do exist, they are incomplete. That provides our Topic—the historical Irish landscape—but Scope and Purpose are still wide open. The second paragraph introduces a supplemental source of information that will eventually become the Scope of the passage—studies of fossilized pollen grains, and what they can tell us about changes in vegetation and thus the landscape. The paragraph outlines how pollen grains can tell us about the landscape, which will serve as a guide to the rest of the passage. Paragraphs 3 and 4 provide examples of how pollen grain information has changed beliefs about some aspects of historical land development. Don’t worry too much about the details of these paragraphs—you can come back to them if a question asks you to. Finally, paragraph 5 notes that the pollen system isn’t without its own limitations and gives an example. It’s not until the end that we can be sure of the author’s Purpose, which is largely informative: to explain the impact of a new information source on our understanding of the evolution of the Irish landscape. The answers to Global questions must reflect this neutral objective: the author doesn’t advocate a particular viewpoint, he just informs us that studies of pollen grains can be useful tools. Roadmap: ¶ 1: Tracing changes in Irish landscape; limits on using historical records ¶ 2: New source (fossilized pollen) supplements ¶ 3: Example of misunderstanding set right by pollen data: cereal in C.D. ¶ 4: Example #2: flax ¶ 5: Limitations on pollen info (madder) 23. (A) Global (Main Point) Predict Global questions explicitly, with a sentence— relying on a general understanding of the passage is not enough. We’ve already broken down this passage, and it’s all about the fact that fossilized pollen records can help make more accurate determinations about the landscape development. A strong prediction will note both the strengths of pollen record analysis and the limitations mentioned in ¶5. That’s a match for (A). (B) is a Distortion—this takes in only the pollen information in paragraphs 3 & 4 and adds too much of the historical documents in paragraph 1. (C) Identification of ancient plant species? We’re interested in the development of the landscape. (D) is a Faulty Use of Detail and is not even an accurate description of some of the details it cites. (E) “Severely limited” is too Extreme, and the tone of (E) is all wrong: the author presents the pollen analysis as a valuable additional tool, although it has some limitations. Plus, ¶5 tells us that the species/genus limitation only applies to some plants. 24. (B) Detail Think through the clues the stem is offering you and make use of them. The question asks for a view pollen data has “provided evidence against”. There are only 2 possibilities, one in paragraph 3 and one in paragraph 4. Look them up. Paragraph 3 refutes the view that soils weren’t successfully tilled and cereals cultivated before the 7th century, and paragraph 4 refutes the view that flax was cultivated in Down before the 18th century. (B) is a match for the paragraph 3 example. (A) The moldboard plough is referenced in the same paragraph and example, but isn’t part of what the pollen evidence contradicted. (C) The evidence presented relates to the period predating the plough, not after. (D) That’s a fact—the new information related to how early people had figured out a way to till the rough soil. (E) is a tempting 180, because this is the information provided by the pollen fossils—but it’s not what we were asked for. We were asked for the view the pollen fossil evidence argued AGAINST, not what it argued FOR. 25. (D) Logic (Function) Questions with line references require context. Don’t limit yourself to just the line mentioned, but be willing to delve into the rest of the passage as needed. There are two references to the “documentary record” cited in the question stem, but they both refer back to an earlier part of the passage: the “fragmentary record” provided by “documentary sources.” (line 4). 43 Test 4 Explained This is the record that the fossil data is supplementing; it’s the history that was recorded at the time, much of it military and commercial. That’s (D). Usually your research into context won’t take you to a completely different part of the passage, but here, being willing to look at more than just the cited lines pays off big for the few test-takers who are ready to do it. (A) and (B) The pollen evidence is supplementing the documentary record, not comprising it. (C) “Current historians” kills this one—the documentary record was created during the relevant time period, not reconstructed later. (E) Again, “current historians” nixes this one; we’re looking for records from the actual time and events. 26. (E) Detail Use your previous work—we’ve seen the content of this question before in another format, and that’s not unusual. Although the language is different, all we’re being asked for is another idea that was debunked by the pollen evidence. We found two when researching Q. 24: soils weren’t successfully tilled before the 7th century, and flax was cultivated in the County Down before the 18th century. The first was the answer to Q. 24, and the second is a match for (E) here. (A) The seventeenth century is mentioned only in connection with recordkeeping, in the first paragraph. (B) Close, but it wasn’t “anywhere in Ireland”—just a specific location where the soil was hard to till. (C) Nope—our author says right from the outset that they were “selective”. (D) Madder is mentioned, but in the context of the limitations of the pollen evidence (last paragraph)—we don’t find conclusive information about it through the fossils. 27. (C) Logic (Function) Use your Roadmap in questions that refer to whole paragraphs. A simple look at the purpose of each paragraph in the context of the overall purpose of the passage answers this question. We can predict that the last paragraph, which talks about the limitations of pollen fossil data, is intended to qualify the second paragraph, which introduces pollen fossil data as a valuable new addition to the analysis of the development of the Irish landscape. That’s (C). 44 (A) The last paragraph doesn’t support the idea set forth in paragraph 2, but explains its limitations. (B) “Problem” might be tempting, but this one isn’t going to be solved; it’s simply a limitation on the information that’s available through this method. (D) is Outside the Scope—the author never argues against the view that the pollen fossil is a valuable addition to the record. (E) No procedures in the last paragraph, just some qualifications. 1-800-KAP-TEST | kaptest.com LL IN TK *LSAT is a registered trademark of the Law School Admission Council. Printed in USA ©2008 Kaplan, Inc.