What are the Moral Connotations of Living in a World Without Free Will? While it is evident that we, as humans, do, at the very least, seem to have choice in what we do; it is a significant step further to say that we most certainly do possess free will. To effectively consider all the possibilities regarding this question of whether we have free will or not and arrive at a cogent conclusion would require a body of text far more significant than this one. The potency of the question however, shall not be ignored. If one were to consider for a moment what the effects on our ways of thinking, and our moral views would be, if it were known that we possessed total free will, the scale of the ramifications is undeniably gigantic. So too then, is the scale on the opposite side of the coin. Suppose we knew nobody actually had any control over their actions. Suppose a1gain, that they did not even have any real control over their thoughts. In what ways would the world change? Perhaps more pertinently, in what ways should the world change? Indeed, the most prominent shock waves of such a realisation would be felt in the fields of morality, particularly on dispatches regarding responsibility. These are the issues that this work will primarily be concerned with. I will then engage on a discourse concerning whether morals are a concept that could be considered to have any meaning at all given a world without free will, and will formulate my own argument as to why this is not something we should be worried about, despite the concerning nature of the issue. Defining Free Will Before any real headway can be made on the main body of this investigation, there are several important distinctions that must be made regarding some key terms. The most prudent one to begin with would be regarding the term free will itself. It should first be noted that when the term 'free will' is used in philosophy, it could be referring to one of many things. Perhaps the most important discrimination to analyse is the one between the compatibalist definition, and the incompatibalist definition. Let us draw a distinction between the two now. The main point at which compatibalists and incompatibalists differ is on the reconciliation of free will in a universe that is deterministic. That is to say, a universe where the events occurring in the present, and all events that will occur in the future, are entirely determined by those that have occurred in the past. Or, to put it in a more concise fashion, “same past, same future” (Kane, p. 16, 2005). Now regardless of the nature of the universe, it is evident that some form of freedom is present. Indeed, if you are low on food, you can choose what shop to go to to replenish your grocery supply, and you can even choose what groceries it is that you restock with. It seems that, in fact, we can do whatever it is that we will at any given moment. This notion is sufficient to advocate a form of free will for some compatibalists. Indeed, let us suppose that somebody needs to go to the shops to get some bananas, and so they go. While it is true that they went to the shop because they felt they needed some bananas, it seems rather strong to say that they had to go – that they had no choice in the matter. They could have done otherwise. Of course, this would not obtain if there was some form of impediment preventing them from going to the shop, such as being locked inside their house, for example. These two premises form the essential definition of freedom for a classical compatibalist – that we have the ability to do what it is that we want to do, and that there is no form of constraint preventing us from doing it.¹ While this is enough to keep many people untroubled in every day life, it is essentially a very superficial form of freedom. Robert Kane describes how this is not necessarily sufficient to justify the notion that we have free will, by hypothesising that what it is that we willed may not necessarily be up to us. “We would be free to act or to choose what we willed, but we would not have the ultimate power over what it is that we willed.” (Kane, p. 2, 2005). This deeper notion of freedom, to have some form of overbearing authority on what it is that we want to do in the first ¹ Robert Kane provides a clear and concise run through of the compatibalist and incompatibalist definitions of free will in his book, A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will place, is more in line with an incompatibalist's definition of freedom, and, clearly, is a much harder concept of freedom to argue for. It is this idea of freedom that will primarily be dealt with in this essay. Indeed, how far can it be said that somebody freely chose to go and buy some bananas, if it was not up to them to want some bananas in the first place? While this example of going out and buying bananas clearly doesn't hold much moral weight, it is clear that there are countless examples of choice that do. For the purposes of this investigation then, we are supposing that the universe is deterministic, and that the notion of free will is incompatible with this. As is aforementioned, whether or not this is in fact the case is not of our concern – this position, which we shall hereby call hard incompatibalism, is presupposed. What is of concern is what the ramifications of such a realisation could, or should, be. With these definitions now made somewhat more concrete, it is possible to move forward in our discussion taking more certain steps with these things in mind. The following section of our investigation will be concerned with what the ramifications of our position might be when dealing with people who are committing wrong. Our first port of call will be the retributive theory of justice, which is so pronounced today. Let us proceed thus. Potential Problems With the Retributive System Our current conception of a judicial system is primarily based around something called the retributive system. The following section of this work will deal with outlining and defining exactly what this system is, and it's basis for being in place, before discussing how this may (or may not) fit in in a hard incompatibalist world. “Most philosophers suppose that the concept of free will is very closely connected to the concept of moral responsibility. Acting with free will, on such views, is just to satisfy the metaphysical requirement on being responsible for one's action.” (O'Connor, 2013). This is a very poignant notion for our discussion. Indeed, it is this idea that is the cornerstone of what makes free will so important and relevant to the world we live in, particularly when it comes to civilised societies, that have systems in place appropriated to deal with issues such as blame, responsibility and punishment. Strawson provides us with a clear explanation of why this is such a relevant dispatch, granted that we do not have free will, and simultaneously highlights exactly why it is the case that it is such a widely accepted proposition: “In the end, whatever we do, we do it either as a result of random influences for which we are not responsible, or as a result of non-random influences for which we are not responsible, or as a result of influences for which we are proximally responsible but not ultimately responsible.” (Strawson, p. 19, 1994) Perhaps the most obvious of the aforementioned systems is the judicial system, and the branch of this that carries the most moral baggage in society is almost certainly criminal law. Let us de-construct the moral side of this part of our society – what sort of freedom it presupposes, and perhaps how it may be different, if it were given that we do not possess free will. For the sake of clarity, let us use an extreme example, one that in normal circumstances would be very black and white. Suppose an adult male defendant has somewhat brutally murdered somebody, and as such finds themselves in criminal court to 'take responsibility' for their crime. In most Western criminal courts, the defendant is presumed innocent until proven guilty, and as such the prosecution aims to achieve this – to bring to light the defendants criminal responsibility for whatever it is they may have been accused of doing – in this case murder. The defendant, on the other hand, unless they are pleading guilty, is left to try and show that they were not in fact responsible for the murder. He can do this in a number of ways. He may, “adduce evidence that although (or even if) he committed the crime charged, he was at the time suffering from responsibility-negating insanity or automatism; but the burden of introducing and establishing such a defence lies on the defendant.” (Duff, p.178, 2011) This is of course, a very concise explanation of what the defendant is required to do, in order to walk free, or at the very least reduce the severity of his punishment. It almost goes without saying that if he is able to prove that he did not in fact partake in the murder of the victim in any way at all, then he cannot rationally be marked as responsible in any set of circumstances, and so should not be punished.¹ In our example though, the defendant most certainly did partake in the murder. In fact, he did it alone, and there is overwhelming empirical evidence that this is the case. As such, arguing that he did not do it is out of the question. He does not wish to plead guilty either however, and so this only really leaves one plausible course of action – to attempt to show that he was not entirely responsible (or not even responsible at all) in some other sense. The way things are at the moment, this would usually mean making some sort of plea for the conditions outlined above by Duff – either he was insane at the time of the crime, or the acts were performed unconsciously, for whatever reason. In the overwhelming number of criminal cases, to make a plea for such conditions is not an easy thing to do. Indeed, in today's day and age, any mental conditions that a person is suffering from (especially if they are an adult), will have been diagnosed and made aware of for some time, and so if they do not have something on their medical records suggesting that they are of suitable mental illness, any sort of plea for insanity usually does not come to fruition. Our defendant also was of apparent sobriety when murdering the victim. There is nothing to suggest that the murder was done 'automatically', so to speak. For all intents and purposes it was a cold blooded murder of an especially heinous nature. “...most [criminals] are well aware that what they are doing is defined by the criminal law, and by ¹ Duff provides a good discussion on this topic in his paper, “What kind of Responsibility Must Criminal Punishment Presuppose?” the morality of those around them if not by their own morality, as ‘wrong’. The law treats them accordingly as responsible agents, and convicts and punishes them for their crimes.” (Duff, p.179, 2011). The key things to consider here are the law's justifications for punishing the criminal. The most important ones are the following: the criminal knows that what they are doing by the morality of those around them and perhaps by their own is 'wrong', and secondly, that in light of such, the law treats them as responsible agents. Let us first consider the second one. “... without the robust conceptions of agency that are ruled out if hard incompatibalism is true, it would appear unacceptable to blame criminals for what they have done, and we would therefore seem to have inadequate justification for punishing them.” (Pereboom, p. 158, 2001). The law as it stands, is presuming, if all of the conditions in our example obtain, that the criminal is a responsible agent. However, if we employ a stance of hard incompatibalism, then seemingly it would not matter how premeditated, brutal and cold blooded the murder may have been, or what mental state the murderer was in at the time of the crime. Indeed, the criminal would have done what he willed, but the power to mediate between what he willed and what he didn't, was not up to him. Hard incompatibalism removes the conceptions of agency that make the criminal a responsible agent, in this sense. Let us now return to the first key point from the Duff extract – that the criminal is aware of the moral 'wrongness' of their actions. This is important because it gives some insight into why criminals are punished for what they do. For breaking the law, of course, but why is the law there in the first place? It would seem by the above statement that there is some form of moral grounding for it – they are punished because what they did was morally wrong, and they knew it, therefore they deserve some form of punishment. Indeed, suppose that our example was a real case, and made national news. If our defendant was found guilty and put in jail for life, say, it isn't too hard to imagine what quite a few people might say: “Jail is too good for him. What he did is disgusting and wrong. He deserves to be killed.” (or something to similar effect). All this implies that our defendant is punished because he somehow deserves it, based on the moral abhorrence of his actions. While there are some cases involving 'moral grey areas' in crime and punishment, a brutal cold blooded murder tends to be considered deprived whatever moral rule book you're following. Hard incompatibalism seems to have a somewhat profound effect on this theory of punishment. The reason for punishment outlined above is what may be called a retributive theory of punishment. That is, that a criminal is punished as some form of retribution – almost an 'eye for an eye' type attitude to take on the matter. At the heart of it, this does not seem intuitively to be a particularly good theory of punishment, whatever the situation regarding free will is. It seems to be one rooted in some kind of vengeance, which is not morally appealing anyway. After all, 'an eye for an eye and the whole world goes blind'. Indeed, a retributive punishment would have to be epistemically justifiable in the sense that it works on the notion of desert. It would not be hard to accidentally punish somebody too severely, for example, or not severely enough. Hard incompatibalism seems to do nothing but further any negative thoughts that are associated with this idea, “since if agents do not deserve to be blamed just because they have done wrong, neither do they deserve to punished just because they have done wrong. Because retributivism justifies punishment solely on the grounds of a basic notion of desert, hard incompatibalism is incompatible with retributivism for the reason that it rejects this notion of desert.” (Pereboom, p.160, 2001). While it would be possible to argue for some degree of fairness in the retributive theory if the criminal may be considered a responsible agent, hard incompatibalism totally dissolves the premises necessary to qualify as one, and so in a world without free will it seems as though retributivism is not necessarily the most suitable path to take. Of course though, it would be somewhat short-sighted to assume that the only reason a judicial system exists is out of some sort of spiteful human condition to seek vengeance on those that we feel have done wrong, although it is the reason for punishment that is most prominently displayed if a crime has appealed to somebodies emotions of disgust and contempt. Let us consider now what other potential reasons there are, or could be - not necessarily for punishing somebody for their actions, but for having a system of punishment in place regardless, and how these systems may tie in to the free will debate. One the surface of it, a retributive theory of punishment is the only one to which hard incompatibalism is obviously problematic to, for all other reasons for punishment seem to have some sort of consequential goal in mind when they are executed. These goals do not seem to be so directly affected (indeed, if at all) by whether we really do possess moral responsibility, or not. “Justifying the practice or institution of punishment must be kept distinct from justifying any given act of punishment” (Bedau and Erin, 2010). What is being alluded to here is that while the actual act of punishing someone for wrongdoing may not necessarily be just, seeing as in a world without ultimate responsibility they do not really deserve it, it does not necessarily follow from this that having an institution of punishment is unjustified. Consider the example of a teacher, who is about to give her class a test. However, the morning of the test, it comes to light that the test papers are missing – clearly because one of her pupils has stolen or hidden them. If we assume free will exists for this hypothetical situation, then clearly one of the pupils (whichever one took the tests) deserves some form of punishment. However, the teacher has no way of finding out who this is. So all of her pupils bar one are totally undeserving of any form of punishment – however, she decides to give the entire class detention anyway. Clearly, she is not doing this based purely on a notion of desert. She is fully aware that she is punishing people that do not deserve to be punished. What then, might her reasons be for punishing the whole class anyway? Let us analyse what reasons we might have for having systems of punishment in place despite a lack of desert. Theories of Punishment Isolated from Desert¹ “...most human societies can be classified either as 'guilt cultures' or as 'shame cultures'. It is true that neither of these two fundamental moral emotions necessarily presupposes a conception of oneself as truly morally responsible for what one has done. But the fact that both are widespread does at least suggest that a conception of moral responsibility similar to our own is a natural part of the human moral-conceptual repertoire.” (Strawson, p. 9, 1994) What Strawson highlights here is a humans tendency to feel guilt or shame for their actions, or even the actions of others that they somehow associate themselves with. He correctly points out that these emotions exist independently of the existence of free will or real moral responsibility, and independently of a deterministic universe. He gives the example of walking down the road with some money, and pausing as you pass somebody asking for money for charity, deliberating whether to donate or not. He states that, “it seems to you that you are truly, radically free to choose, in such a way that you will be ultimately morally responsible for whatever you do choose. Even if you believe that determinism is true, and that you will in five minutes time be able to look back and say that what you did was determined, this does not seem to undermine your sense of the absoluteness and inescapability of your freedom, and of your moral responsibility for your choice.” (Strawson, p. 10, 1994) What this essentially means is that regardless of the metaphysical state of the universe or the nature of freedom of will, there seems to be an inescapable emotional reaction to the choices that we, as humans, make, that is embedded in our psyche. If we apply the first Strawson extract with the second, you may easily suppose that if you made the choice to walk past the person with the charity pot without donating, you would possibly feel some sense of guilt. If you didn't, then it is plausible to suppose that that is either because you are morally destitute somehow, or because ¹ For an analysis of a wide variety of theories of punishment with regard to hard incompatibalism, read the second to last chapter of Living Without Free Will by Derek Pereboom you are simply not aware of how little you actually needed that money and how much the people the charity is helping do need that money. This leads us on to a theory of punishment that is perhaps much more compatible with hard incompatibalism. The theory of punishment being alluded to here is one more concerned perhaps with criminal rehabilitation or reform. Indeed, if a criminal is considered to have been properly rehabilitated, they are often released early from their sentence, because they are deemed to no longer be a danger to society. To link this concept to the example just used, let us draw comparison to the murderer described earlier. Suppose that when you walk past the person holding out a charity tin you decide not to donate. You are of course perfectly entitled to do so, but when you get home in the evening you watch a documentary describing the plight of some people in Africa, and showing you just how far a donation of ten pounds from you would go to helping their life. With this newly attained knowledge, you may well feel an overpowering sense of guilt, especially as you just spent ten pounds on chocolates that you didn't actually need in any way at all. As Strawson points out, even if you believe in a deterministic universe and you think that you could not have done other than walk past the charity tin, the feeling of guilt is still somehow inescapable. As such you vow that next time you walk past a registered charity official asking for money to give aid to those less fortunate in Africa, that you will donate ten pounds. It seems that a restorative process has taken place here, you made a moral decision, and whether this was ultimately in your control or not, due to some educative enlightenment about exactly how your decision may have affected others, you became morally reformed in some way. Consider now our criminal who committed murder in cold blood. While it would be true that he could not be said to entirely deserve a punishment, given the non-existence of free will and ultimate moral responsibility, it does not necessarily follow from this that he shouldn't go through some form of process to make sure that something such as the crime he committed does not happen again. There is a relatively new process in some countries called victim-offender mediation¹ (henceforth VOM). “...crime victims... meet face-to-face with the persons who victimized them. They are able to let the offenders know how the crime affected their lives, to receive answers to many lingering questions, and to be directly involved in holding offenders accountable for the harm they caused. Victim-offender mediation is recognized as a viable alternative to more traditional retributive response for serving victims' needs...” (Greenwood & Umbreit, 2000). It is described as a viable alternative here, and this is in a word where we do assume people can be wholly responsible for their actions – if we apply hard incompatibalism to this notion, it's viability over retributive ideas can only increase. Indeed, if we take the case of our murderer brutally killing somebody, the question is inevitably raised: why did he do it? Perhaps he felt like he was wronged in some way by the victim and so decided to kill them, or perhaps he was just having a hard time with his life at that point in time and the tension had to be released somehow, so he murdered somebody. Regardless, it is plausible to think that our murderer did not take fully into consideration exactly how widespread and significant the damage from his crime would be, just as you may not have considered just how far your ten pounds would go if you donated it to that charity. Suppose now he took part in VOM with the spouse or a direct family member of the person that he murdered. The 'victim' here could safely discuss with the murderer the full extent of emotional damage and distress that he caused with his crime by engaging in direct dialogue with him. “This dialogue addresses emotional and informational needs of victims that are central to both the empowerment of the victims and the development of victim empathy in the offenders, which can help to prevent criminal behaviour in the future.” (Greenwood & Umbreit, 2000) The most important point to note here is the one ¹ More information on victim offender mediation can be found at www.voma.org regarding the development of empathy in the offender. Given that he is of (relatively) good mental health, he, too, would likely experience some form of guilt or remorse, similar to the way you may have done after learning just how much your ten pounds could have done, were you to donate it to charity. This feeling would, or at the very least you'd imagine, should, occur, regardless of whether he was ultimately responsible for his actions when he committed the crime, or not. The hope is that this procedure, or other procedures like this, would reform a criminals behaviour in some way, and prevent them from doing things considered morally deprived in the future. Of course, there doesn't even necessarily need to be such a brazenly restorative process as this to gain the desired effect. Indeed, if somebody commits a crime and goes to jail for a significant length of time, they may well deem future crimes not worth the risk, having experienced what prison is like, and be reformed in that sense. Further to this, the prospect of punishment can also be said to have a deterrent effect. It prevents people from becoming criminals in the first place. This is an idea that is totally compatible with hard incompatibalism. While it may not be just to punish somebody for any 'bad' acts that they perform purely for the reason that they performed the act, if they cannot be held truly responsible for it - there is certainly a case to be made for following a course that would prevent any such acts being committed in the future. Why is this the case? “...potential offenders can be deterred from crime by the prospect of punishment: but the causal efficacy of the threat of punishment clearly does not depend on our having ultimate responsibility; some might indeed argue that it depends on the absence of such responsibility, since it depends on our susceptibility to the causal influence of deterrent threats.” (Duff, p.180, 2011). An intriguing point is raised here. It seems to reinforce the notion that some form of deterrent should be present in a world without free will because it's efficacy would be greatly increased because of such a scenario. Indeed, if we consider what determinism is – the future being determined by the past – then it follows from that that in such a universe our actions are entirely susceptible to influence. To look at it the other way, if we possessed free will then in at least some respects we would be immune to influence. If the knowledge that the performance of a certain act will likely lead to some form of unpleasantness has been acquired in a persons past, then in a deterministic universe it follows logically that granted that they do not desire unpleasantness, they will be deterred from performing whatever that act may be, because they are directly influenced by the past. Indeed, if we return to the example of the teacher – if she had made clear as soon as she had announced the test that if the test sheets were to go missing for any reason, then the whole class would be placed in detention, then it is plausible to suppose that it is at the very least much more likely that no student would have stolen the tests. This is because not only would any 'would-be thief' be deterred from doing the act for fear of the punishment it would bring on themselves, but also because they likely would not want the other members of his class to suffer a punishment either. Indeed, if they decide to go ahead and steal the tests anyway, the whole class, including them, would go through detention. In this way, they would be, “made to endure an unpleasant experience designed, in some sense, to 'represent' the pain suffered by her victim(s)” (Hampton, p. 227, 1984). This system of punishment again seems to rely somewhat on the presence of a kind of empathy in wrongdoers. However, if it were global knowledge that nobody were truly responsible for their actions, it does seem as though it would be easier for wrongdoers to rationalise a mode of thought where they could try and isolate themselves from such emotions as empathy and guilt. While it is true that, as mentioned earlier, we live in a culture of shame or guilt, and these emotions exist regardless of whether we have free will or not, it seems as though some fallacious reasoning would be being used to say that these things would still exist to the extent they do now if it was known that we were not truly responsible for our actions. This raises an interesting thought. While in a world without true responsibility it does not seem just to punish people purely because they performed an act, attempts at reform based on feelings of guilt and empathy may have their effectiveness reduced as well. If we are to put ourselves into the mind of a criminal, the thought process of eliminating any feelings of guilt or shame that may have been caused by any morally destitute acts they performed, by being aware that it wasn't exactly their fault that they did something morally abhorrent, isn't too absurd to imagine. However, it does not follow from this that there should be no systems of punishment in place for just the same reason. Indeed, somebody may feel no guilt for wrongdoing if they know that they were not ultimately responsible for doing it, but they likely still do not want to be punished, and so the deterrent effects of the systems of punishment described earlier still remain valid. However, these worrying thoughts are not so insignificant as to not be considered further, and so the following section will be concerned with discussing any further potential problems with the theories of punishment just now introduced. Problems for Deterrence and Reform Some further issues regarding, ironically enough, fairness, seem to arise if we take these theories of punishment absolutely. Indeed, it has been aforementioned that a legitimate theory of punishment may be based around deterrence. Indeed, this idea is the one that would still be most likely to have the greatest effect despite any new found ability to isolate themselves from shame or guilt that criminals might have acquired, living in a world without true responsibility. Let us analyse what a utilitarian standpoint on a deterrent theory of punishment may consist of, and why it may not exactly be fair. “Utilitarians have tended to concentrate on deterrence, turning away from the actual criminal act except as one of a class of actions that might be prevented by punishing the particular instance severely enough (but only just enough) to make the actions unattractive to the offenders and to possible future offenders” (Murphy, p. 26, 1973). Though this seems like a sound enough hypotheses at first glance, there are in fact several rather severe problems with it. Suppose that we are trying to deter people from parking on double yellow lines in the UK, for example. Generally speaking, if you were to do such a thing in society today you would be given a fine of some kind. This punishment seems suitable and likely comes around from a retributive theory of punishment, funnily enough – 'the punishment fits the crime', or an 'eye for an eye', so to speak. Suppose now though, that the punishment for parking on a double yellow line was twenty years in jail. It seems that this would be a far more effective deterrent for preventing people from doing this act of wrongdoing, yet it is undeniable that this seems like an intuitively unfair punishment for what is not the most appalling crime in the world. However, this sense of unfairness would only ever actually come to fruition if somebody actually did park on a double yellow line and underwent this somewhat severe punishment. However, as Murphy points out, “Unfortunately, there are always people who cannot be deterred or reformed. Beyond a certain point the additional suffering one would have to inflict on all offenders to reduce their number might be so great as to exceed the suffering thereby averted.” (Murphy, p. 26, 1973). It would seem then, that such a theory of punishment would mean finding some sort of elusive equilibrium for the severity of punishment to effectively deter people from parking on double yellow lines, without being so severe that net suffering is in fact increased. This equilibrium would have to be found for every single crime or wrongdoing and would be susceptible to various factors that could change what it might be. Indeed, there are different areas of the UK for example, where there are more incidents of parking on a double yellow line per person – and thus it would be intuitively unjust to have the same severity of punishment for people all over the country for the same crime. There are other difficulties that arise for theories of punishment based around deterrence as well. Another one of these can be highlighted by Pereboom's quarantine model. Again, on the surface of it this seems like a sound enough theory of deterrence. He draws a comparison to the manner in which we quarantine people with communicable diseases - “...if in order to protect society, we have the right to quarantine people who are carriers of severe communicable diseases, then we also have the right to isolate the criminally dangerous to protect society.” (Pereboom, p. 174, 2001). There are several questions that this notion raises at first glance. Perhaps most obviously: how is this idea any different to putting people in prison? The difference lies in the sense that somebody only goes to prison once they have actually committed an act that is deemed bad enough to merit them going there. If we continue the analogy with a communicable disease, this distinction becomes more clear. Indeed, some diseases are passed from mother to child, for example. Evidently, the child has absolutely no moral responsibility for the disease they have contracted, yet it may easily be construed that it would be beneficial to society to quarantine them anyway, to prevent further infection. Likewise, if we suppose that somebody is the child of two known and dangerous criminals, then it would be plausible to consider them criminally dangerous in some sense, despite the fact that they have yet to commit a crime. Again, this seems somewhat unfair. Indeed, the retributive theory of justice that was critiqued earlier in this work due to issues about fairness was done so because it seemed unfair to punish somebody for committing a crime that was not, ultimately, their fault. However, if we use Pereboom's quarantine model and follow it through to it's end then we are seemingly justifying punishing people who have not even done anything. Indeed, in reference to the quarantine model: “Retributivists might argue, in response, that practices of punishment are bound to be unfair if we do not focus on who deserves to be punished, but instead only focus on what punishments will deter crime or protect society. If the focus is entirely on deterrence and protection rather than retribution, injustices are bound to arise.” (Kane, p. 76, 2005). This seems to be somewhat true – however, if we are living in a world where nobody is truly responsible for their actions, then a theory of punishment based on desert could be construed to be unfair as well. Indeed it has been shown that it would be unfair, at east to some extent, in all cases, whereby a deterrent theory of punishment is, at least, only unfair in some cases (hopefully a minority). It would seem that if we do not use a theory of punishment that is based on desert, then we are almost forced to endorse some sort of utilitarian view on the matter. We would have to use a theory of punishment that just worked best to maximise utility and to reduce suffering as much as possible for the greatest number of people. Notions such as this utilitarian one fall foul to the classic utilitarian problem however.¹ If we aim to maximise the greatest good for the greatest number, then there will inevitably be some scenarios that intuitively play on the conscious a little. Consider the classic example of the fat man in the cave: “...a group of potholers imprudently allow a fat man to lead them out of the cave. Unfortunately, he gets stuck in the mouth of the cave. As it happens, high tide will soon be upon them, and the rising water will drown all of the explorers except the fat man. However, someone has a stick of dynamite. So the potholers have two alternatives. They can do nothing and all of them except the fat man will be drowned; or they can use the dynamite and blast the innocent fat man from the mouth of the cave, thereby killing him but saving the rest of them.” (McConnell, 1981). This is a hypothetical scenario where the utilitarian principle would dictate that the fat man should be blasted from the mouth of the cave with dynamite, but it's an action that seems to intuitively be morally repulsive somehow. Indeed, if the other potholers asked for a volunteer to actually be the one to blow the fat man up, you would not think that whomever stepped forward would leave the cave with an entirely clear conscience. Of course though, an important thing to ¹ For more information on utilitarianism and what the classic utilitarian problem is, read Understanding Utilitarianism by Tim Mulgan note is that this is a very extreme example. After all, how often have people actually been faced with the choice of drowning or blowing up a fat man with dynamite in reality? You would suspect it is not the most common occurrence. In the same fashion, it's plausible to assume that a purely consequentialist theory of punishment would, in fact, at the very least work for the most part, without any moral dilemmas being forced upon us. The problem remains however, who would be given the authority to dictate what course of action should be taken if any such situations were to occur? If we refer back to the quarantine model once again, it would be hard to please everybody. For some people would likely instantly support the idea of quarantining the child of two renowned criminals, but there would be others who would totally be against it. It is clear then, that to find a perfect theory of punishment for a world in which there is no free will is not the simplest of tasks. Evidently it would be hard to justify an entirely retributive theory, but so too has it been shown that other theories are not without their problems as well. However, it is evident that some theory of punishment should be in place. If we consider the example of the teacher again – suppose that she did not let the students know there would be a punishment for stealing the test papers. As such, the test papers get stolen, but suppose now that due to her deeming it unfair to punish anyone for the test papers getting stolen, she enforces no consequences. What then, would prevent somebody from stealing the test papers every single time she announced that there would be an exam? In layman’s terms, she would never get to give the test. Crude as this analogy is, it is an idea that can easily be applied to a much larger scale. If there were no deterrent systems in place to stop people from doing wrong in the world, then it would be all too easy for the selfish part of the human condition to take over, and for society to break down. Anarchy would likely ensue and human progress would effectively come to a stop – the entire planet would become a 'dog eat dog' world – a notion which is rather unappealing. As such it would seem that in a world devoid of free will, and thus ultimate responsibility, a theory of justice based around deterrence would be ideal, and to those who would not be deterred, systems of reform should be implemented as well. While it would not be a perfect system by any means, it should be noted that the systems in place at the moment, in a world where we do assume some sort of free will and responsibility, are not without their flaws either. They are also not without their extreme cases that seem to prey on the conscience as well. Consider a man with a starving family stealing a loaf of bread from the open window of a millionaire – is it really just to punish him for stealing in the same way as somebody else doing it just because they were a bit hungry, for example? It seems not. To find a perfect theory of punishment then, is not really a practical undertaking whatever the situation regarding free will is in the world, and as such, it seems like the most prudent course of action is just to use the method that works best, with the least negative moral ramifications. On Morality in a More General Sense Of course, punishment is not the only system that would be affected if it became common knowledge that we did not possess free will. There is of course, the polar opposite to consider. Should people really be praised for doing anything? This is somehow almost a more bizarre thought to get your head around. If we return to Galen Strawson's example regarding the charity tin once again – suppose that you were with a friend when you walked past the charity tin, and you did decide to donate – say ten pounds. This is quite a sizeable sum of money to just give to charity on a whim as you bump into the opportunity walking down the street. It is no doubt a noble act and intuitively we as humans would think that such a thing would deserve some form of praise. Strawson highlights the dilemma we would face here: “It is exactly as just to punish or reward people for their actions as it is to punish or reward them for the (natural) colour of their hair or the (natural) shape of their faces. The point seems obvious, and yet it contradicts a fundamental part of our natural self-conception, and there are elements in human thought that move very deeply against it”(Strawson, p.16, 1994). Indeed, in a world devoid of free will and true responsibility, it would be as much up to you what colour your natural hair colour is as it would be that you gave that money to charity. We don't often go around telling people that we are proud of them for the fact that they have natural blonde hair, and by the same logic, if it were not ultimately up to you to donate that ten pounds to charity, it would almost be nonsensical for your friend to be proud of you for that. Of course though, there seems to be a fundamental difference between having natural blonde hair and giving to charity, and this distinction seems to be a moral one. Indeed, having natural blonde hair doesn't hold any more moral credibility than having natural ginger hair, for example, whereas a case could potentially be made for saying that giving ten pounds to charity is somehow morally 'better', than not giving ten pounds to charity. This distinction might not be one that holds up very well when faced with hard incompatibalism, though. Indeed, consider the question: 'what makes a person a good person?' The answer to this question is one that still does not have a concrete answer today but at the very least it seems as though it would have some sort of grounding in the decisions somebody makes. If nobody were truly responsible for anything, then once again it seems unfair to say that any one person is morally superior in any sense to another. Just as it would seem unjust to punish somebody for committing a morally 'wrong' action, it is equally unfair to say that somebody should be rewarded or praised for doing something morally 'right'. At this point in our investigation it would be quite easy to be drawn into some rather worrying thought patterns. Is there any 'right' or 'wrong' at all? This conclusion can readily be arrived at by following the logical path laid out by several premises: We define a persons moral worth by the decisions they make. We are not truly responsible for any of our actions or decisions. A persons moral worth cannot be defined by their actions or the decisions they make. We have no way of distinguishing between a good person and a bad person. Our current conceptions of morals become redundant. Now there are a countless number of moral theories that it is possible for a person to follow, and each one is usually based around a standard of good. There are many different standards of good against which to measure the moral worth of something but they do all seem to rely on some notion of responsibility for a persons actions – or at the very least the theories are made rather redundant if this concept is removed. Even if you take morals to be completely subjective, this logical reasoning would at best mean that everybody's subjective moral theory was on a completely level playing field, giving none of them any authority over any other, and thus making them seemingly redundant anyway, as morals seem to rely on some sort of relationship with other beings. Of course, this is is undeniably an uncomfortable thought for us to consider. There is something comforting about having a basis on which to judge somebody as morally good or bad. On a much more personal level, it is an effective system for giving yourself some sort of self worth. If we are to suddenly strip this notion of moral value away it leaves us with a feeling of uneasiness. However, I would argue that this feeling of uneasiness is irrational, and shall outline my reasoning in the following section of this work. Why Living Without Free Will Does Not Mean Living Without Meaning As was mentioned before, to have the concept of morals made redundant is a notion that is intuitively unsettling. I pose the question though: why is this the case? There are the reasons mentioned above but if we are honest with ourselves they do not amount to much in any tangible sense. Indeed, if we make reference once again to the example Strawson provides us with regarding the natural colour of a persons hair. It is of course true that it would be employing somewhat fallacious reasoning to praise somebody for the natural colour of their hair, for it is not up to them what the natural colour of their hair is. Having blonde or brown or ginger hair does not grant them any moral credibility. However, it hardly follows from this that all other attitudes towards the natural colour of their hair should be made void as well, and it follows even less that they should not have a reaction to these attitudes themselves. Indeed, suppose your friend has naturally blonde hair. You would not necessarily say that you are proud of them for this fact (why would you be?) but you can still like the fact that they have blonde hair. Further to this, you could even admire the fact they have blonde hair, and perhaps aspire to have blonde hair yourself. To look at it the other way, it's plausible that you see somebody with a particular shade of brown hair, that you do not like. Similarly, you do not blame them for the fact that you do not like their hair, and there is no objective authority defining their hair as worse than your friends blonde hair, but you still find yourself disliking their hair all the same. I would claim that it is not too significant a step to make to draw a comparison between this example and behaviour which is deemed as morally right or morally wrong. Just as a system of punishment can still justifiably be put in place when nobody is responsible for their actions, so too can people still have reactive attitudes to certain types of behaviour, and be justified in having them. Not necessarily because it is objectively right to do so, but because in a practical sense it is useful. Indeed, it was discussed earlier that without some sort of system of punishment in place we as a human race would likely deteriorate significantly. On the same note, rewarding or praising people for behaviour that brings others happiness is likely a useful system to further human progress, or at the very least make people happier. I would thus compare this intuitive uneasiness about the non-existence of morals to an irrational fear of sorts. It seems natural to be concerned about the thought, but usually when we worry about something, as people, it is because we are scared that something is going to happen. I would argue, or at the very least hope, that even if it became common knowledge that we were living in a world where nobody is truly responsible for anything, that people would still (generally speaking) view behaviour that benefits others as praiseworthy and admirable, and still (generally speaking) view selfish behaviour as undesirable, and that this behaviour would still produce negative reactive attitudes in observers. To apply this reasoning to a slightly more appropriate example than hair colour, let us make reference back to our murderer from the opening section of this work. It was established that it would not be necessarily just to punish him for performing the act of the murder in and of itself. Indeed, it couldn't really be said to be his fault that he murdered somebody. However, it seems as though we should follow a course of punishment anyway, to try and deter him from murdering people in the future, and perhaps even reform him. As was mentioned earlier, it would be easy to imagine people being disgusted with him for what he had done. The reasons cited when this was discussed before were based on generally moral grounds, or somewhere close to moral grounds. I would argue that these attitudes should, and would, still exist, even if people knew that it was not necessarily his fault, and even if they had accepted that their previous conceptions of morals were now redundant because of that. They would still be inclined to call him a bad person. Again though, why this would be is for similar reasons that we would still be inclined to punish him. They would not call him a bad person purely because of the fact that what he did was morally wrong (indeed, this may not even be a fact in the circumstances), but they would call him a bad person based on the consequences of his actions. He caused another human being to die for one (generally regarded as a bad thing), and will no doubt have upset a multitude of others in the process. I would argue that from this initially disturbing thought of moral sparsity that this discourse began with, some overriding positive notes can actually be gleamed. It would be easy to think yourself into some form of existential crisis once you isolate yourself from morals and responsibility for your actions, but I believe that to do this is to take a wholly unnecessary pessimistic take on what does not need to be a negative revelation. In the case of the murderer for example, people would still deem him to be a bad person, but they would be much more likely to take his action on a more face value basis. They would not harness any undue hatred that extended over and above the severity of is crime, because their instinct to be repulsed would not be amplified by a moral code which they adhere to. It is not something that is pleasant to admit as a person but I would wager that the vast majority of peoples moral rulebook is often subject to change based on what situation they find themselves in, what mood they are in at the time of consulting it, and a whole plethora of other factors that really shouldn't play a role in their attitude towards things. Hard incompatibalism seemingly forces us to throw this moral rulebook out the window, or at the very least hold it in much less reverence than we do now. Rather we would be left to take a more consequential stance on things. Of course, the temptation is to think that without any morals that we respect as authoritative, there would be no reason to have laws and systems of punishment, because they are seemingly based on what is morally 'right'. This may be so with our views on morals the way they are now. If we embrace this consequentialist view that hard incompatibalism would dispose us to take however, it seems to me that we would be left with a choice. Either a selfless or a selfish one – benefiting others or benefiting yourself. It is in human nature to desire progress – this stems from our somewhat infuriating incapability to be satisfied with anything, and the best way to satisfy our craving for progress would no doubt be to not descend into anarchy and survive in a world of people only out to help themselves, but rather put systems in place that would encourage this progress. A system of punishment would be just one of these. To those of you reading this and still worrying that in a hard incompatibalist universe you would be plagued by existential thoughts and worries, I will provide you with a thought posed by Derek Pereboom: “If determinism is true, everything that happens in ones life can be attributed to God or the universe, and then through one's identification with this entity one can attain an acceptance of anything that happens” (Pereboom, p. 187, 2001). Hardly the most troubling thought you are likely to have. This acceptance of any events that might occur would of course, include the actions of other human beings. The initial reaction to determinism or hard incompatibalism is that it would somehow reduce the richness of our interpersonal relationships. This does make sense on the surface of it. It's nice to think that your best friend is a morally good person for example, and that they are nice to you because of that, and because they think that you are a good person. Pereboom again gives us good reason to withhold any concerns we may have regarding this issue however: “... far from threatening good interpersonal relationships, hard incompatibalism, holds out the promise of better relationships through the release from the anger that underlies so much human misery” (Pereboom, p.188, 2001). This is a good point once again. Though hard incompatibalism may reduce some of the satisfaction gained from getting on with another person really well, it effectively removes a lot of the reason people currently have for not getting on with other people, and the endorsement of this idea could lead to a much happier group of people. What answer then, has been reached, in regards to the question that this text has set out to answer? It would seem that in a wholly practical sense, the moral connotations of living in a world without free will would not be all too radical, if carried out in the way that this work has supposed that they should be. The real moral connotations would not necessarily take place in a physical sense (although there should, and hopefully would, of course, be some), but rather more in the way people view and think about the world and the others that inhabit it, and the more tangible changes that might follow from this are not ones that I have the confidence to predict accurately. It is a romantic thought though, and one that I would hope other philosophers may endorse, that to live in a world devoid of free will would not necessarily make the world one without any sense of justice, satisfaction, or meaning, but rather one that could be a lot more comfortable with the way it is morally – a more forgiving (although still firm enough to keep those not on board with the selfless consequentialist theory in check) world and, who knows? Perhaps even a happier one. Whatever moral code it is that you subscribe to, it seems hard to construe this notion as an entirely negative one. What does this romantic thought comprise of then? It is essentially construed through the notion that people may change their outlook on the world. Of course, for it to ever come to fruition, there must first occur a realisation that we live in a world without free will. ¹ If this ever occurred to a level of significance whereby it became the generally accepted view, I would suggest that the most prudent way for people to deal with it would be to endorse this romantic view. That is, to be more inclined to forgive people for their wrongdoings, considering the fact that people would be aware that it was not entirely their fault for doing wrong. In addition, they might feel less inclined to force their views or morals on others, as they would be endorsed with their knowledge that their moral views held no more authority than anybody else's. Of course throughout human history, attempts to force views on others has been the cause of much human suffering and conflict, and it's plausible to thing that such events would at least occur less frequently, in a world where a lack of free will was common knowledge. Whenever conflict did occur, it is also plausible to think that any bad events that did occur, could potentially be accepted by people in a more graceful manner than perhaps we are used to in today's world, due to an acceptance of whatever may come to happen, ¹ For a compelling argument for this, read “The Impossibility of Free Will” by Galen Strawson through the reasoning mentioned by Pereboom. What this work has shown then, is that a world without free will would bring about significant change, but there is every chance that it could possibly be a change for the better, if we dealt with the realisation correctly. We should end up treating people radically differently, and it should lead to a world that is, in a very basic human sense, more successful, granted that the correct theories of punishment and praise are employed, and a positive outlook is maintained. While the purpose of this paper is not to cause people to hope that we do not have free will, it hopefully will have caused it's readers to not be quite so worried about the possibility, and I hope it has accomplished this. Bibliography: Bedau, Hugo Adam and Kelly, Erin, "Punishment", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/punishment/ Duff, R. A. “What kind of Reponsibility Must Criminal Punishment Presuppose?”, Free Will and Modern Science, Richard Swinburne (ed.), Oxford University Press, 2011, pp.178-180 Hampton, Jean, “The Moral Education Thoery of Punishment”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 13, No. 3, (Summer 1984) URL = http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265412, p. 227 Kane, Robert, A Contemporary Introduction To Free Will, Oxford University Publishing, 2005, pp. 276 McConnell, Terrence C., “Moral Absolutism and the Problem of Hard Cases”, The Journal of Religious Ethics, Vol. 9, No. 2 (Fall 1981) URL = http://www.jstor.org/stable/40014938 Murphy, Jeffrie G., Punishment and Rehabilitation, Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1973, p. 26 Pereboom, Derek, Living Without Free Will, Cambridge University Press, 2001, pp. 158-188 Galen, Strawson, “The Impossibility of Moral Responsibility”, Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, Vol. 75, No. 1/2, Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility, Springer Publishing, 1994, pp. 5-24 URL = https://philosophy.as.uky.edu/sites/default/files/The%20Impossibility%20of%20Moral%20Respons ibility%20-%20Galen%20Strawson.pdf Umbreit, Mark S. and Greenwood, Jean, “Victim-Offender Mediation: A National Perspective”, Guidelines for Victim-Sensitive Victim-Offender Mediation: Restorative Justice Through Dialogue (April 2000), URL = https://www.ncjrs.gov/ovc_archives/reports/96517-gdlines_victimssens/guide4.html