THE GR IP O F S E X UAL VI O LE N CE IN CO NFLI C T Stanford Studies in Human Rights The Grip of Sexual Violence in Conflict Feminist Interventions in International Law Karen Engle S tanford Univer sit y Press Stanford, California Sta nf ord Un iv e r sit y Pre ss Stanford, California ©2020 by the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of Stanford University Press. Printed in the United States of America on acid-free, archival-quality paper Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data available upon request. ISBN 978-1-5036-0794-1 (cloth) ISBN 978-1-5036-1124-5 (paperback) ISBN 978-1-5036-1125-2 (electronic) Cover design: Rob Ehle Cover art: Vanja Hamzić, The Aftermath, acrylic on canvas, 2010 (private collection). Typeset by Kevin Barrett Kane in 10/14 Minion Pro To Sissy Farenthold This page intentionally left blank Table of Contents Foreword xi Acknowledgments xiii Introduction 1 I. The Common Sense: An Illustration 3 II. Unpacking the Common-Sense Narrative a. The “Worst Crimes” 7 7 b. Perpetrated by Male Monsters against “Innocent” (Female) Victims 10 c. Criminal Law Will End Sexual Violence in Conflict 12 d. Sexual Violence Prevents Peace 15 III. Countering the Common Sense: A Preview 15 1. Sexual Violence in Conflict and Women’s Human Rights: A Genealogy I. Mainstream Responses to Wartime Rape in the Former Yugoslavia 20 II. Early Feminist Engagement with Human Rights 21 a. Liberal Inclusion Approaches 23 b. Structural-Bias Critiques 23 c. Third World Feminist Critiques 26 18 viii Contents III. “Women’s Rights Are Human Rights” at Vienna 28 a. Culturally Sensitive Universalism 32 b. Violence against Women 34 c. Sexual Violence in Conflict 37 IV. The Turn to Criminal Law 44 V. Unintended Consequences: A Prelude 48 2. Calling in the Troops 50 I. Military Humanitarian Intervention after the End of the Cold War 51 II. Feminist Debates over the Meaning of Rape in the Yugoslavian Conflict 55 a. Genocidal Rape versus Rape on All Sides 56 b. Genocidal Rape and Ethnic Essentialism 62 c. Shared Assumption: The Force of Shame 67 III. The Military Stakes of Finding Rape: The Case of Libya 70 IV. The Continuation of Crisis Governance 77 3. Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 80 I. Feminist Engagement with the ICTY Statute and Rules 83 II. The Mediation of Feminist Disagreements 86 III. Solidifying the Common Sense: Jurisprudence on Rape and Sexual Violence 90 a. The Worst Harm 90 b. Sexual Agency and Ethnic Difference 94 IV. Adding to the Common Sense: Male Victims 98 4. Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 101 I. The Doctrinal Function of Shame 104 a. The ICTR Charges against Akayesu b. The ICTR’s Reasoning in Akayesu 105 107 Contents c. Feminist Reasoning and Akayesu ix 110 d. The Legacy of Akayesu in Subsequent Jurisprudence 112 II. Shame as Prosecutorial Alibi 116 III. The Redistribution of Shame 120 5. Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 122 I. Overview: Human Security, the WPS Agenda, and Beyond 125 II. Naming the Victims and Types of Violence 132 a. Victims: Gender Specificity versus Gender Neutrality b. From “Gender-Based Violence” to “Conflict-Related Sexual Violence” 132 134 III. The Shame of Sexual Violence in Conflict 136 IV. The Carceral Turn: Calling in the Judges 140 V. Counterterrorism: Calling in the Troops 147 Epilogue: Beyond Social Death I. Women at War 151 155 II. Women and Sex at War 160 III. The Force of Shame Revisited 162 IV. The Context of War Foregrounded 168 V. The Redistribution of Shame Reconsidered VI. Conclusion 171 Notes 173 Bibliography Index 255 233 170 This page intentionally left blank Foreword Karen Engle’s The Grip of Sexual Violence in Conflict works to unsettle and reorient human rights studies at three different levels. On the first, the book confronts head-on what Engle describes as the “common-sense” narrative about the causes, consequences, and ethical implications of sexual violence in conflict. What Engle demonstrates—from historical, theoretical, and empirical vantage points—are the ways in which the problem of wartime sexual violence underwent profound discursive transformations as a key pillar in the development of women’s human rights during the critical early post–Cold War period. In the effort to ensure that violence against women was given heightened prominence by the international human rights community, sexual violence in conflict came to symbolize the unique vulnerabilities that women around the world experienced. In Engle’s clear-eyed analysis, the symbolization of wartime sexual violence against women eventually came to dominate international activism, thereby obscuring or diminishing—however unintentionally—other ways in which women experienced structural, ethnic, and class-based violence. This symbolization of sexual violence in conflict became doubly problematic when it was made the basis for criminal prosecutions within the embryonic international tribunal system. As Engle shows, the rise of international criminal tribunals as the mechanism for tackling the problem of sexual violence in conflict must be understood as an expression of a broader trend toward carceral governance, which fundamentally depends on what she describes as the “strong arm of the state.” In Engle’s analysis, the over-reliance on criminal tribunals puts the complicated and highly diverse phenomena underlying sexual violence in the hands of institutions that are distinctly unable to carry such a “heavy burden.” xi xii Foreword At another level, The Grip of Sexual Violence in Conflict is a penetrating study of how cultural and legal categories that form the basis for humanitarian intervention and human rights activism are constructed and mobilized in ways that can run counter to underlying intentions. In this, Engle is inspired by the example of the historian Joan Scott, who was careful to emphasize the fact that her account of the politics of the veil in France was not principally about French Muslims themselves, but about the ways in which they were perceived through dominant French historical and cultural discourses. So too with Engle’s unraveling of sexual violence in conflict: instead of focusing on victims or the nature of sexual violence, her account foregrounds what she calls the “particular imaginaries” that have shaped global understandings of both sexual violence in conflict and the legal and political responses to such violence. And just as Scott’s study revealed the ways in which dominant narratives of citizenship in France worked to constrain and even pervert the background values from which these narratives emerged, so too with the particular imaginaries about sexual violence in conflict that form the core of Engle’s book. As Engle demonstrates, dominant approaches to sexual violence in conflict—while animated by a laudatory spirit of global solidarity and a desire to improve women’s lives—likewise are based on distorted understandings of gender, sex, sexuality, and ethnicity. And finally, The Grip of Sexual Violence in Conflict takes its place as a powerful intervention within contemporary debates over both the limits and the future of human rights. If scholars like Samuel Moyn have focused on the ways in which the existing human rights system provides insufficient responses to major global problems like economic inequality, Engle’s study shines a critical light on two other dilemmas: first, the ways in which rights frameworks are always and necessarily reductive in relation to the complex cultural and psychological phenomena that get classified as “violations”; and second, the fact that the pervasive turn to international criminal law as the primary response to human rights violations constitutes what Engle describes as an “individualized approach to human rights,” something that strips the social context from conflicts and in the process elides the importance of a wider range of relevant actors, including “bystanders and beneficiaries.” Mark Go odale Series Editor Stanford Studies in Human Rights Acknowledgments This book is the culmination of countless conversations and engagements over the past decade with an enormous list of remarkable people to whom I am extremely grateful and to whose contributions I cannot possibly do justice here. I am especially thankful to Janet Halley and Dianne Otto for invaluable contributions at multiple levels. They each provided important scholarly spaces for me to develop my thinking and also offered detailed and insightful comments on multiple chapters that always pushed me to a higher level. Others who have influenced the book and its direction since nearly the beginning include: Helena Alviar García, Doris Buss, Hilary Charlesworth, Joshua Clark, Dennis Davis, Vanja Hamzić (whose art graces the cover), Gina Heathcote, Neville Hoad, Ratna Kapur, David Kennedy, Duncan Kennedy, Ranjana Khanna, Helen Kinsella, Karen Knop, Frédéric Mégret, Zinaida Miller, Vasuki Nesiah, Fionnuala Ní Aoláin, and Patricia Viseur Sellers. Thank you all! The project benefited from a variety of residencies, fellowships, workshops, and conferences. I am particularly grateful to the Rockefeller Foundation for the use of the Bellagio Center, which provided the perfect space and surroundings to begin to structure the book, and to the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, the ideal community and atmosphere for completing a draft of the manuscript. I received terrific feedback from presentations of various parts of the work at both of those institutions as well as at Berkeley Law School, Cornell Law School, Duke University, Fudan University Law School, Harvard Law School, Melbourne Law School, Rutgers University, SOAS University of London School of Law, Temple Law School, Ulster University School of Law, the University of Cambridge Lauterpacht Center for International Law, the University of Los Andes Faculty of Law, the University of Texas, the University of Wisconsin-Madison, the United States Institute of Peace, Yale Law School, and Yale University. xiii xiv Acknowledgments Along the way, I interacted with many people who helped me improve the work. I am especially indebted to engagements with Aziza Ahmed, William Alford, Lori Allen, Elizabeth Anker, Roland Betancourt, Gabriella Blum, Amy Borovoy, Linda Bosniak, Cynthia Bowman, Lina Céspedes Baez, Nick Cheesman, Madelaine Chiam, Jeffrey Dunoff, Maria Elander, Didier Fassin, Laurel Fletcher, Peter Goddard, Inderpal Grewal, Bernard Harcourt, Isabel Cristina Jaramillo Sierra, Nam Li, Alice Miller, Samuel Moyn, Sarah Nouwen, Ayşe Parla, Mark Pollack, Jaya Ramji-Nogales, Rachel Rebouché, Peter Redfield, Joan Scott, Columba Stewart, Miriam Ticktin, Elizabeth Wood, and Emily Zackin. I have had the privilege to engage with a number of University of Texas students on this project over the years. Those who served as research assistants for extended periods and had significant impact on both substance and form are Maddy Dwertman, Simone Gubler, Helen Kerwin, and Kyle Shen. I am grateful to them, as well as to Anne Quaranto, who, over the final year and a half of the project, provided outstanding research and editing assistance, fresh insights, and meticulous organization that was indispensable to propelling the project over the finish line. Thanks also to Karen Lee, Liz Rowland, and Emily Spangenberg. Supportive friends, family, and comrades abound. While writing the book, I have been codirector of the Bernard and Audre Rapoport Center for Human Rights and Justice at the University of Texas. My colleagues there have been unbelievably encouraging and accommodating. Thanks especially to Daniel Brinks, William Chandler, Julia Dehm, Sarah Eliason, and Kate Taylor for their involvement with the book at multiple stages and, just as importantly, for ensuring that the center kept going when I was away. Ana Almaguel has been my constant companion in this endeavor as in life. I could not have written the book without her support, intellectual engagement, and willingness to keep our world running during my physical absences. I am grateful to Michelle Lipinski at Stanford University Press and Mark Goodale, series editor of the Stanford Studies in Human Rights, for their enthusiasm for the project. Michelle did a fabulous job of shepherding the manuscript through its various stages, while providing useful editing advice and staying in touch along the way. I am fortunate for the influence and friendship of Sissy Farenthold, to whom I dedicate this book. I learn something new in every conversation with her, and will always be inspired by her anti-imperial and anti-militarist feminist politics, grounded in grassroots collaborations across class, race, and nation. Acknowledgments xv Two dear friends and colleagues who had tremendous influence on my intellectual path left this world entirely too early. This book is in memory of them— Srinivas Aravamudan and Barbara Harlow. I hope there is some evidence of their legacy in these pages. This page intentionally left blank THE GR IP O F S E X UAL VI O LE N CE IN CO NFLI C T This page intentionally left blank INTR O D U C TI O N T H I S B O O K I S A B O U T T H E G R I P O F S E X U A L V I O L E N C E on legal and political discourse about gender and conflict. It explains how and why sexual violence in conflict emerged and persists as a dominant concern for many feminists engaged with international law and many international lawyers engaged with feminism. It therefore concentrates on those who advocate for, design, and implement legal and political responses to sexual violence in conflict, and on their understandings of why, where, how, to whom, and by whom such violence occurs. It considers the effects of their work on both feminism and law. International institutional attention to what is now referred to as “sexual violence in conflict” or “conflict-related sexual violence” dates to the early 1990s, when the world began to learn of rapes taking place during the conflict in the former Yugoslavia. Feminists inside and outside the region were among the first to bring attention to the rapes, but they were assisted by nongovernmental and intergovernmental inquiries, as well as by journalists and policy-makers. A confluence of factors—from concerted organizing of women’s human rights advocates around violence against women (VAW) to Security Council–sanctioned collective action partly made possible by the end of the Cold War—meant that the treatment of rape would play an important role in the post–Cold War development of feminist advocacy as well as of international law and politics. Indeed, I contend, it has played too large a role in each. As feminists from around the world, especially through the women’s human rights movement, began to pay an enormous amount of attention to wartime rape and what they would eventually construct as a broader category of sexual violence in conflict, they often did so at the cost of attention to other issues with which they had previously been concerned. In particular, the convergence of 1 2 Introduction their efforts on sexual violence in conflict displaced much of the anti-militarism of the women’s peace movement, the sex-positive positions of many feminists involved in debates about sex work and pornography, and Third World feminist critiques of economic maldistribution, imperialism, and cultural essentialism. This book offers a detailed examination of how these feminist commitments were not merely deprioritized, but often undermined, by efforts to address the issue of sexual violence in conflict. Sexual violence in conflict emerged as an important issue in a post–Cold War moment that was critical for the future of both international human rights advocates and internationally engaged feminists. Together, the two groups reached a general and enthusiastic consensus around the need to combat sexual violence in conflict. But they did little to indicate that the topic would eventually occupy as much feminist energy as it did, or that its treatment would result in the ascendance of one feminist approach at the expense of others. My concern is not only that anti-militarist, sex-positive, and Third World feminist critiques took a backseat as eyes turned toward sexual violence in conflict. In ways both overt and stealthy, prevalent understandings of the nature of sexual violence, and the proper responses to it, came to be shaped by a particular form of what I term “structural-bias feminism.” This approach largely emerged from the work of feminists in the global North, and characteristically held that male sexual domination and female sexual subordination constitute the greatest structural impediment to women’s emancipation. I contend that the success of this perspective has had negative effects on international law and politics as well as on feminism. Its influence helped to consolidate the components of an international, mostly institutional, “common sense” about sexual violence that relies upon and reinforces negative images of sex and sexuality, and problematic understandings of gender, ethnicity, and war and peace. That common sense includes the following propositions: rape and sexual violence are the worst crimes committed during conflict; much of their harm is due to the shame they inflict on individuals and communities; they are perpetrated by individual male monsters; they are committed against innocent women, girls, men, and boys, though they are primarily aimed at women and girls; and investigation, prosecution, and punishment of individual perpetrators offer the best recourse, not only for ending sexual violence in conflict but also for promoting peace. I trace the development of this common sense to the success of a certain form of feminism, but also to its interaction with particular approaches to international Introduction 3 human rights, humanitarian, and criminal law. I am critical of the ways in which, together, they have brought a hyper-attention to sexual harm, and often have pursued extraordinary measures to respond to it. When some feminists began to call for military and criminal intervention to respond to rape and sexual violence, they drew upon and strengthened relatively new approaches to human rights and humanitarian law that rely upon force and courts for enforcement. Human rights advocates and scholars today continue to debate whether and when to use military force in the name of human rights. Yet they widely agree that criminal law, including international criminal law, should constitute the principal response to certain violations of human rights and humanitarian law, including sexual violence in conflict. This near consensus around criminal accountability has reinforced an individualized approach to human rights and humanitarian law violations, losing much of the context of conflicts, including the roles of bystanders and beneficiaries.1 Relatedly, it has also provided a new avenue for the human rights movement to strengthen its condemnation of certain conduct during wars, rather than condemning the fact or causes of the wars themselves.2 Although this individualization and decontextualization might appear to run counter to the structural-bias emphasis of the feminism that eventually prevailed in legal and political discourse about sexual violence in conflict, some of the strongest supporters of criminalization have also been loyal adherents to, and even pioneers of, that feminism. Through an account of feminist engagement with international law over the past twenty-five years, I aim to show that sexual violence in conflict was not as obvious a focus as it may now appear to be. Further, I argue that once sexual violence became central, it was not inevitable that feminists would encourage or acquiesce to mainstream representations concerning the harm of rape or the deployment of militarism and criminal law to address it. I am thus as interested in what has been lost or displaced by this emphasis on and approach to sexual violence in conflict as I am in what has been gained. As I detail in Chapter One, the development of the common sense around sexual violence in conflict had the effect of suppressing earlier productive disagreements among feminists over a variety of issues. I revisit those debates with the hope of contesting that common sense and its embeddedness in the institutional spaces that the remainder of the book explores. I. The Common Sense: An Illustration Let me begin with a vivid illustration of the common sense, by describing and contextualizing in some detail a 2014 video released by the UK Foreign and Commonwealth Office. The video was meant to set the stage for the Global 4 Introduction Summit on Sexual Violence in Conflict, hosted by William Hague, who was then UK Foreign Secretary, and Angelina Jolie, who—in addition to (or perhaps as a part of) being a celebrity—serves as Special Envoy of the UN High Commission on Refugees. The summit was the culmination of work that Hague and Jolie had done together, in coordination with Zainab Bangura, who was then the UN Secretary-General’s Special Representative on Sexual Violence in Conflict. That work began in 2012, when Hague and Jolie announced their Preventing Sexual Violence Initiative (PSVI). It picked up steam in 2013, under the UK’s presidency of the Group of Eight (G8). In April of that year, following the G8 Foreign Ministers’ annual meeting, Hague shared the stage with Jolie and Bangura for a press conference. Although the ministers had considered a wide range of issues during their meeting, Hague announced that he had succeeded in achieving his personal priority, which was the G8 Declaration on Preventing Sexual Violence in Conflict signed by all G8 Foreign Ministers.3 Calling sexual violence in conflict “the slave trade of our generation,” Hague stated: “We know that this violence inflicts unimaginable suffering, destroys families and communities, and fuels conflict.” For Jolie, sexual violence victims are the “forgotten victims of war: responsible for none of the harm, but bearing the worst of the pain.” Hague presented the G8 Declaration as “historic” in its statement that rape and sexual violence constitute war crimes and grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions. Although the G8’s response to sexual violence in conflict was multipronged, the press conference largely focused on criminal sanctions. Hague noted in particular the responsibility of states to bring to trial or extradite those accused of such crimes and to refuse to include amnesty for sexual violence in peace agreements. He emphasized that the G8 agreed to develop a protocol for criminal prosecutions and to “help build up the judicial, investigative and legal capacity of other countries in the area.” Bangura acknowledged the health, legal, psychological, and social needs of survivors of sexual violence, but noted that “we now also throw a more concerted spotlight on the perpetrators.” For them, “there can be no hiding place, no amnesty, no safe harbor.”4 Shortly after the passage of the G8 Declaration, Hague, Jolie, and Bangura successfully advocated for a new UN Security Council resolution on sexual violence in conflict, which recognized the G8 Declaration.5 Six months later, at the General Assembly, Hague and Bangura launched the Declaration of Commitment to End Sexual Violence in Conflict, which at least 156 UN member states eventually signed.6 In June 2014, Hague and Jolie cohosted their Global Summit in London, where they officially introduced the PSVI. Introduction 5 Days before the Global Summit, the UK Foreign and Commonwealth Office posted on its website a short (just over one minute) animated video titled “Don’t believe the thumbnail, this video is the stuff of nightmares.”7 The animation is two-dimensional, resembling the work of a child. It portrays a wartime rape. The voice of a girl narrates the story, although a caption appearing in the opening seconds of the video announces that it “may not be suitable for under-16s.” Even as it is framed as a child’s view of sexual violence in conflict, the video includes common language from international legal and political discourse on the subject. The animation opens with an apparently nuclear family—father, mother, boy, girl, and dog—in front of a house surrounded by green trees and blooming flowers (see Figure I.1). On one side of the screen, the father grills on a barbecue. On the other side, the rest of the family plays. Birds chirp and the dog makes frisky noises. The sun is shining, and the sky is blue. This image is the thumbnail that the line from of the video instructs its viewers not to believe.8 By the third second of the video, the scene changes dramatically. As the narrator declares, “There is a weapon that doesn’t just leave physical wounds, it leaves emotional wounds,” the blue sky disappears, and black clouds move in, followed by military helicopters. The family members, except for the dog, run into the house, as military ground vehicles arrive. Male soldiers exit the vehicles. One shoots the dog. The soldiers enter the house, and the narrator continues: “A weapon of power, violence, and control.” The animation then shows the perspective from inside the house, before the soldiers have entered. The male head of household escorts his wife and children inside. Behind a kitchen table sits a shelf with art objects. Above it hangs a framed painting of the family outside the house—the same image with which the video began (the thumbnail). After moving his family into the room, the man stands in front of the door, attempting to bar it with his body. But his chivalrous efforts are outdone. The narrator says: “A weapon that is just as scary as bombs and bullets, but invisible—rape.” At the moment the narrator says “rape,” the armed soldiers enter the house and one hits the man on the head with his gun. They begin to fire their guns into the air. Someone screams. The narrator explains that “rape and sexual violence are used against women, girls, men, and boys.” The perpetrators surround the kitchen table, visually obscuring the rape that begins to take place. There are sounds of clothing being ripped and of evil laughter. Through the gaps between the soldiers, one can see that the person being raped is wearing blue, just like the mother, and only the mother, in the earlier scenes, leaving little doubt that she is the victim. 6 Introduction Figure I.1. A still from “Don’t believe the thumbnail, this video is the stuff of nightmares.” “Victims are sometimes abandoned by their families,” the narrator continues. The face of one of the perpetrators mutates into that of a monster. He bares his teeth and growls in the foreground, while from the background another scream is heard, followed by wailing. Over the wailing, the narrator says: “And the anger and shame left behind can tear communities apart and make wars last longer. Especially when the monsters who do it are allowed to get away with it, even live near their victims.” During this last statement, the perpetrators have left the house, and the girl of the family stands at the window holding a teddy bear. A male figure walking by outside suddenly turns his head and moves toward the window as the narrator says, “even live near their victims.” He again transforms into a monster, baring his teeth and growling. The young girl recoils and pulls down a yellow window shade. Black scribbles begin to be drawn over the shade and eventually take over the screen, as the narrator states: “But it doesn’t have to be this way. Rape and sexual violence are the worst crimes you can imagine.” Suddenly the black becomes the robe of a judge (of uncertain gender) in a courtroom. The judge gesticulates toward the defendant, who is one of the monsters now wearing his human face. The narrator states: “But they are not an inevitable part of war.” The screen then zooms in on the perpetrator. “It’s time to end sexual violence in conflict.” Prison bars drop in front of him. The screen zooms out and is filled with repeating identical images of him behind bars. The narration continues: “Time to bring Introduction 7 those responsible to justice.” The video moves to a new image, with a number of civilians, including the family we originally encountered, holding a banner that reads “no moar nightmare” (intentionally misspelled and in a child’s writing). “Time to act to let governments know enough is enough. Time to act so that those who live in fear of sexual violence have a chance to feel safe.” With this last sentence, the original idealized image of the house and family returns. This time, the husband and wife stand happily at the door together, while the children and dog once again play in the front yard. Only the dog, which is bandaged, shows any visible signs of the attack. The family has apparently bounced back from the otherwise devastating harm because of the healing effects of criminalization. In any event, the image is one of a family that feels safe, despite the war that we can only assume continues to rage, even if the video tries to make us forget it. II. Unpacking the Common-Sense Narrative Nearly every aspect of the common-sense narrative suggested by these G8 and UN actions, including the video, can be traced to or found in the institutional and discursive spaces around which I have organized this book—spaces concerned with international human rights, military intervention, international criminal law, and international peace and security. While the video itself might seem overly simplistic, even too easy a target, I take it seriously because of its basis in both the feminist advocacy and the international legal and political discourse that have developed on sexual violence in conflict. I use it here to introduce some of the arguments I make in the book—arguments about the sources as well as the consequences of the narrative. A. The “Worst Crimes” The video describes rape and sexual violence as the “worst crimes you can imagine.” In doing so, it participates in a problematic rhetorical refrain casting rape and sexual violence as a “fate worse than death.” In addition to downplaying other harms of war, including death, the insistence that rape and sexual violence cause the ultimate harm depends upon an understanding of victims as forever condemned by those actions to shame and stigmatization. Although the video states that rape is invisible, it also suggests that much of its harm in fact comes from its visibility, which is required for “the anger and shame [it leaves] behind.” That anger and shame are felt not only by the victims. If families sometimes abandon victims, it is because the families bear 8 Introduction shame. Indeed, the anger and shame “tear communities apart.” While the video images show us an ideal victim family that does not seem to be torn apart by the rapes, its words best depict the dominant message. Rape presumably works as a tool of war because it can cause targeted groups to turn on their own members who are victims of sexual violence. This message is far from new. Traditionally, rape was seen as useful in war because, like pillage, it destroyed the enemy’s property. It also constituted an attack on the honor of families and communities.9 Indeed, partly for these reasons, rape has long been considered a war crime, and has even been prosecuted as such at various times through the centuries.10 In the mid-twentieth century, international humanitarian law arguably began to acknowledge rape as causing harm to individual victims. But honor continued to play an important role. For example, the Fourth Geneva Convention of 1949, on the treatment of civilians, provides: “Women shall be especially protected against any attack on their honour, in particular against rape, enforced prostitution, or any form of indecent assault.”11 The 1977 Additional Protocol II to the Geneva Conventions listed rape as a specific example of prohibited “outrages upon personal dignity,” placing it alongside “enforced prostitution and any other form of indecent assault.”12 When feminists began to consider rape in conflict in the early 1990s, many insisted that international law in the late twentieth century should differ from these earlier legal prohibitions by considering the rapes as harmful to women in ways that did not center around loss of honor to themselves or their communities. At some level, as the video demonstrates, feminists succeeded in changing the narrative, by introducing recognition of the physical and emotional wounds to rape victims themselves. But shame and dignity continue to be central to those emotional wounds, and are connected with presumed harm to communities. The staying power of shame and stigma as the predominant harms of rape manifests itself in nearly every chapter of this book. Journalists, human rights advocates, UN actors, diplomats, prosecutors, and judges all assume that rape causes both individual and communal shame, including when they are unable to find individuals who will attest to having been victims of it. Chapter Four, on the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR), most clearly demonstrates the operation of these assumptions in law. The ICTR jurisprudence finding rape to have been a constitutive act of genocide, widely considered pathbreaking by feminists and non-feminists alike, makes the presumption of communal stigma and shame central to its analysis. Because genocide requires an intent to destroy Introduction 9 an ethnic group, the finding of genocidal rape ties into the refrain that sexual violence in conflict “destroys families and communities.” The commonly stated view that rape victims and their communities are forever and uniquely devastated by rape is dangerous not only for the many other harms of war it overlooks, but also for the understandings of ethnic conflict—and ethnicity—it promotes. The idea that rape “tears communities apart,” by turning communities against their own members who have been raped, partially places the blame for the harm suffered by rape victims on the very groups that have been subject to crimes against humanity, ethnic cleansing, or even genocide. While the common sense might see “rape culture” as contingent, it takes for granted shame culture, especially in the predominantly Muslim and African communities that tend to be the focus of investigation. As such, it relies upon ethnic and cultural essentialisms to define the harm of rape, while also limiting the repertoire of “normal” individual and communal responses to it. To the extent that the various actors considered in this book attempt to respond to the shame they imagine is pervasive, they generally try either to manage it in order to facilitate victim testimony (having attributed the failure of such testimony to shame) or to shift the shame from victim to perpetrator through criminal prosecution or other sanctions. Both efforts reinforce the presumption of shame, and in fact rely upon it to justify other projects. With regard to the first, when they are unable to find women who will attest that they have experienced sexual violence, investigators and prosecutors often use shame to explain that failure. As to the second, proponents of criminal prosecutions for sexual violence in conflict have to grapple with the dearth of empirical evidence demonstrating that their efforts have had any deterrent effect. Pointing to other benefits of criminal prosecutions helps to justify the enormous amount of time and attention invested in them. Although they provide no causal explanation for how shaming one individual through public naming, prosecution, or punishment might alleviate the shame felt by another, advocates for greater criminalization often assert, much as Hague did in his remarks at the Global Summit: “We want to shift the stigma from survivors onto the perpetrators of these crimes, so that they—not the innocent victims—bear the stigma.”13 In the Epilogue, I propose some alternative ways to think about and address shame in the context of wartime rape, drawing on literary examples as guides for building narratives counter to what has emerged as the common sense. I suggest that, while not denying the ways in which many women often experience shame and stigma from rape, we acknowledge that not all women are, or need be, forever 10 Introduction ruined by it. I highlight instances in which women who have been raped during conflict see the rape or their responses to it as a part of their political or military struggle, or treat it as but one facet of their wartime experiences. I also consider one instance in which even a conservative religious community self-consciously chose not to shame or stigmatize those who had been raped. I use these narratives to call for a discursive and doctrinal shift away from the assumption that sexual violence is inherently shameful to individuals and communities as well as the belief that shame, when it exists, necessarily leads to destructive actions against self and others. Sexual violence should not be addressed, in criminal law or elsewhere, in ways that reinforce the presumption of shame, justify the unwillingness of victims or imagined victims to testify, or claim to transfer the shame from victims and communities to individual perpetrators. B. Perpetrated by Male Monsters against “Innocent” (Female) Victims The animated video makes vividly clear that the perpetrators of sexual violence are monstrous men, and that their victims are innocent or, as Jolie puts it, “responsible for none of the harm.” This view relies on two assumptions about women in war. First, they are nearly always victims or potential victims of sexual violence in conflict. Second, they are innocent; not only do they not perpetrate sexual violence, they rarely play any political or military role in war. A 2009 speech to the UN Security Council by then US Secretary of State Hillary Rodham Clinton demonstrates how the two assumptions work in tandem. Speaking in favor of a Security Council resolution on sexual violence in conflict, Clinton said, “Even though women and children are rarely responsible for initiating armed conflict, they are often war’s most vulnerable and violated victims.”14 This view is also not new. Helen Kinsella demonstrates that women have been coded for centuries as innocent civilians.15 The international treatment of sexual violence in conflict reinforces that coding. By focusing on an area in which men are by far the most visible perpetrators, the concentration on sexual violence further facilitates the perception that only men participate in the production and harms of war. Of course, women participate in and even order violent acts, including acts of sexual violence. Yet the few instances in which women have been criminally charged with war crimes, crimes against humanity, or genocide have yet to be treated as occasions for rethinking the common sense. These cases are instead treated as aberrational, involving almost unthinkable female monsters—worse even than their male counterparts.16 Introduction 11 More importantly, the focus on sexual violence in conflict, or even more broadly on crimes committed during conflict, diverts attention from many other factors at the root of war, including women’s political roles in them. Many women actively participate in, are bystanders to, or benefit from nationalist, racist, and ethnic- and class-based politics and violence. As Third World feminist critics have long pointed out, even feminists in the global North are often structurally implicated in the causes and consequences of wars in the South.17 The negation of women’s participation in wars is not merely a symbolic failure. Those who promote policies, whether broadly for preventing conflict or more narrowly for deterring international crimes in conflict, will not succeed if they do not attend to the variety of roles that women, as well as men, play in war and politics (in both the public and the private spheres). The common-sense approach to sexual violence in conflict misses more than women’s complex political and military roles in and in relationship to conflict. The idea that women are the “most vulnerable and violated” figures in war negates women’s sexual agency as well. Journalists, investigators, and others, for instance, often do not believe women who deny they have been raped during war. Indeed, sometimes they read the denials as proof of rape, given the categorical ascription of shame to rape victims. International criminal rules and jurisprudence that essentially disavow the possibility of consensual sex between civilians and combatants on opposing sides of a conflict also diminish women’s sexual agency. As we see in future chapters, such law, which largely resulted from successful feminist advocacy, at least in some cases builds upon and reinforces rigid and highly contested ideas about ethnic hatred. Though women are generally thought of as victims or potential victims of sexual violence in conflict, the common sense acknowledges that they are not the only victims. Indeed, the victim category has proved to be more elastic than the perpetrator one. As the narrator of the animated video explains, “Rape and sexual violence are used against women, girls, men and boys.” The statement coincides with UN institutional discourse over the past few years as well as international criminal law, both of which recognize sexual violence against men and boys. In fact, it has become increasingly commonplace, even good politics, to list men and boys in the category of potential victims, or to use gender-neutral terms when discussing victims of sexual violence. But the texts also often make clear that most of the victims are women and girls—or sometimes women and children—and the largest portion of the examples are female. The video illustrates how the words and representations often diverge. The man is knocked unconscious with the butt of a gun (for which 12 Introduction no one seems to be arrested), but the woman is raped. And the monster at the window threatens the girl, not the boy. A number of international criminal law prosecutions have included charges of sexual violence against men. But institutional actors and commentators have paid relatively little attention to what exactly counts as sexual violence against men, what the harm of that violence is, and whether and how it is “gender-based.” Advocates for male victims believe it is not taken seriously enough. While many feminists simply assimilate it to sexual violence against women, some argue that sexual violence against a man—at least for the man—causes worse harm than sexual violence against a woman, either because the former loses the power that comes with male privilege by being treated sexually as a woman18 or, somewhat relatedly, because of the stigma, often exacerbated by homophobia, that comes with such treatment.19 I contend that this relatively new mainstream acknowledgment of male victims of sexual violence stems less from a resistance to the gendered binaries underlying prevailing assumptions about the perpetrators and victims of war than from the hyper-attention to sexual harm in considerations of gender and armed conflict. As discussed in Chapter One, feminists were divided for some time over questions about the extent to which sexual violence was paradigmatic, as opposed to being one of many categories, of gender-based violence. When women’s human rights advocates began to approach sexual violence in conflict—and even constructed the category as they expanded it beyond rape—the former position prevailed, particularly as they examined the issue in the context of international humanitarian and criminal law. Other institutional spaces followed suit. Chapter Five describes, for example, how the UN Security Council’s Women, Peace and Security agenda (WPS agenda) moved in a relatively short time from treating sexual violence as but one form of gender-based violence, to conflating the two types of violence, and finally to separating them to concentrate solely on the sexual. This shift from “gender-based violence” to “conflict-related sexual violence” went hand in hand with at least the rhetorical inclusion of male victims. Chapter Three shows that a similar, if less explicitly articulated, strategy was at play in the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY). In both instances, ironically, the analysis of gender as a structuring category of power largely fell out of the picture. C. Criminal Law Will End Sexual Violence in Conflict The endpoint of the video’s animation is punitive action against the monsters who perpetrate sexual violence in conflict. While the perpetrators might appear Introduction 13 to be ordinary—even if ordinarily cruel—soldiers, it becomes clear that they are monsters when they commit or threaten rape. The narrative makes no room for the concept of the “banality of evil.”20 However widespread rape might be, the video insists, normal people do not commit it; it is “the monsters who do it.” The problem to be addressed is that they “get away with it.” Criminal punishment will “bring those responsible to justice.” This common-sense reliance on criminal law has had multiple effects that I consider throughout the book. Feminists, even those who were internationally engaged, did not always see international criminal law as an obvious or favored site for their work. When they began to theorize women’s human rights in the mid- to late 1980s, primarily around violence against women, they did not place armed conflict high on their agenda.21 International humanitarian law and international human rights law were still relatively distinct fields. International lawyers generally approached the former as delineating unlawful conduct during wartime and, at least with regard to international conflicts, governing relations between (warring) states. They saw the latter as principally concerned with a state’s relationship to its own citizens during times of peace. Human rights advocates and scholars were only beginning to concern themselves with the ways in which international humanitarian law, particularly the part that applied to non-international conflicts, might be usefully deployed to combat human rights violations during internal strife, especially in instances when states had suspended certain derogable human rights protections due to war.22 Even more importantly, in the mid-1980s, modern international criminal institutions were yet to be created. Thus, to the extent that feminists called on human rights law and discourse to address VAW, they primarily demanded that states that did not prevent such violence be “named and shamed”—the principal attempt at the enforcement of human rights law through the end of the 1980s. Many were also involved, however, in networking around local efforts to support victims of VAW in self-help and political work, through the establishment of shelters, work training, and consciousness raising aimed at addressing cultures of violence. It was not until the early 1990s, when women’s rights advocates turned much of their attention not only to sexual violence but to sexual violence in conflict, that criminal law emerged as the preferred response. It did so as part of two broader trends: first, increasing feminist reliance on criminal law to respond to domestic violence and sex trafficking, akin to what Elizabeth Bernstein identifies as “carceral feminism”;23 and, second, what I have termed elsewhere “the turn to 14 Introduction criminal law in human rights.”24 The carceral turn in both feminism and human rights has meant that feminists have spent much of the past two decades calling upon the strong arm of the state and of powerful international governmental alliances to address sexual violence in conflict, primarily through criminal accountability and the development of international criminal law (although, as we see in Chapter Two and again in Chapter Five, some have also called for military responses). Feminist criminalization efforts have been relatively successful. As part of a move that Janet Halley and collaborators call “governance feminism,”25 feminists and feminist ideas entered many of the halls of power of those very state and international institutions on which they called. In the process, support for expanded criminalization of sexual violence in conflict became mainstreamed, with little or no resistance. Indeed, even relatively early on in the development of international criminal institutions, mainstream players largely deferred on issues of sexual violence to the feminists involved. In addition to missing many more-structural causes of violence in war, this prioritization of the incarceration of individual monsters makes criminal prosecution carry a heavy burden. I mentioned above that some actors invoke prosecution and punishment as means for eradicating the shame that victims are presumed to experience, by shifting that shame to perpetrators. Most also imbue criminal law, as in the video, with great deterrent power. The prison bars will “end sexual violence in conflict.” Those who otherwise would fear sexual violence now “will have a chance to feel safe.” Deterrence is perhaps the most commonly invoked claim about the effect of criminal punishment in this context. At the G8 Foreign Ministers press conference, UN Special Representative Zainab Bangura contended that the G8 Declaration represented a “resolve to match the ruthlessness of those who would commit such unthinkable crimes, with our own relentless and unwavering pursuit of accountability, and ultimately deterrence and prevention.” Hague stated: “Our goal must be a world in which it is inconceivable that thousands of women, children and men can be raped in the course of a conflict—because an international framework of deterrence and accountability makes it impossible.” For Hague, as in the video, the presumed deterrent effect of criminal law means that rape might not need to be an inevitable part of war.26 This presumption of deterrence, which is rarely backed up with any evidence or rationale,27 is perilous for at least two reasons. First, it promises something it cannot possibly achieve—to eliminate sexual violence in conflict. Second, through that promise, it facilitates a transfer of energy and resources toward Introduction 15 criminal punishment mechanisms and away from other social, political, and economic interventions—including through law—that might better address the structural causes of violence. D. Sexual Violence Prevents Peace The video’s claim that sexual violence makes wars “last longer” is also a common refrain. Much like deterrence, its proponents often assert the claim with little support or explanation. In the video’s narration, the “anger and shame left behind” cause the continuation of armed conflict. Yet, once the monster is imprisoned, the nuclear family again plays in the yard, perhaps with the shame (and anger) displaced onto the monster. Earlier, I said that we must assume that the war continues to rage, but perhaps not. Maybe the scene is meant to depict the absence not only of the threat of sexual violence, but also of the threat of war. It suggests that if incarceration can deter sexual violence and lock away the shame and anger, peace will ensue. If, in this telling, criminalization leads to peace, failure to criminalize leads to war. At the very least, the absence of criminalization (or the presence of impunity) precludes “lasting” or “sustainable” peace. This view is often found in calls for prohibiting amnesties for sexual violence crimes in peace agreements, as in the G8 Declaration. Chapter Five demonstrates the prevalence of the insistence on this prohibition in UN Security Council resolutions and other UN pronouncements. But what if a peace agreement might be jeopardized precisely by such an exclusion? At the G8 press conference, Jolie followed a broader trend within human rights law and advocacy to deny any conflict between peace and prosecution. Specifically, she lauded the G8 Declaration’s position on amnesty, stating, “There is no choice between peace and justice: peace requires justice.” Wishing away the conflict between peace and justice, however, does not make it so. In fact, the threat of criminal accountability can sometimes preclude peaceful settlement, making this position conflictogenic. If relying on criminal punishment to end sexual violence is problematic, suggesting that ending sexual violence will lead to peace is equally so. Since the latter requires the former, it doubly justifies the extensive resources spent on criminal punishment mechanisms and the downplaying of its adverse consequences. III. Countering the Common Sense: A Preview The book has two primary aims: to chronicle and attempt to disrupt the common sense that I have just described. Organized around various sites of feminist 16 Introduction engagement with international law and institutions, each chapter demonstrates the particular aspects of the common sense that were forged through the interaction. Each also considers which feminist arguments or approaches were sidelined by, or at least alongside, the rise of a form of structural-bias feminism that ascribes women’s oppression to their sexual subordination. Together the chapters illustrate just how entrenched the common sense has become across a wide range of legal doctrines and institutions. Chapter One, “Sexual Violence in Conflict and Women’s Human Rights: A Genealogy,” sets the stage. It begins with women’s human rights advocacy in the late 1980s and early 1990s, situating it in the context of feminist and human rights theory and practice at the time. It pays particular attention to struggles among feminists as they attempted to formulate the meaning of women’s human rights, and considers what was lost and gained in perspective with the recognition of women’s human rights at the UN World Conference on Human Rights in Vienna in 1993. It was there, I argue, that the emphasis on sexual violence in conflict emerged and paved the way for what I refer to as the sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism to play a governance role in the international legal and political spaces that much of the rest of the book considers. Chapters Two through Five examine in detail a number of ways in which those feminists invited and deployed international legal and institutional power to address sexual violence in conflict. Some feminists turned to military intervention, “calling in the troops” on behalf of women who had been raped. Others pursued the development of international criminal law, advocating for and taking advantage of the international criminal tribunals developed in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda. Still others worked through the UN Security Council’s WPS agenda, which had initially been promoted by the women’s peace movement, to prioritize sexual violence as the greatest harm to women in conflict. As they fostered international attention to sexual violence in conflict, not only did they deploy the force of international law, but they also acquiesced in particular understandings of sex, gender, and ethnicity that contributed to and reified the common-sense narrative. In the Epilogue, “Beyond Social Death,” I turn to more nuanced accounts of gender, sex, and war than those found in most of the legal, political, and discursive sites I study throughout the book. I mine literary sources—from Ernest Hemingway’s For Whom the Bell Tolls to Yazidi activist and Nobel Peace Prize winner Nadia Murad’s memoir centered around her time in ISIS captivity—in order to highlight the complex and overlapping facets of women’s (and men’s) Introduction 17 lives that are often elided by the grip of sexual violence in conflict. I also use these alternative accounts to discourage advocates from assuming that shame and stigma are the natural responses to rape. That assumption both limits our ability to understand and combat shame and stigma where they do occur and makes many of those who have encountered sexual violence but have not experienced or expressed the expected shame or stigma illegible to the system. Ultimately, the book argues that the common-sense approach to sexual violence in conflict at worst misunderstands and at best oversimplifies the problem: its causes, its harms, and the range of effective responses to it. But the book is less about the victims and the nature of sexual violence in conflict than it is about the ways in which particular imaginaries about them have gripped international legal and political discourse—on gender, sex, sexuality, and ethnicity on the one hand, and on militarism, criminal law, and international peace and security on the other. In this sense, I approach the victims of sexual violence in conflict in much the same way that historian Joan Scott treats French Muslims in The Politics of the Veil when she says, “This is not a book about French Muslims; it is about the dominant French view of them.”28 By detailing how the common sense developed, and dwelling on moments when the path was uncertain, I hope to revive earlier productive tensions among feminists within and between the global North and the global South over issues of sex and gender, but also over race and ethnicity, economic distribution, peace, and culture. And in doing so, I hope to open a conversation about what the alternatives might be going forward. CHAP TE R O NE Sexual Violence in Conflict and Women’s Human Rights A Genealogy I N 19 93, D I S C U S S I O N O F S E X U A L V I O L E N C E in conflict made its way onto the world stage, not coincidentally at the same time that “women’s human rights” gained traction within mainstream human rights discourse and institutions. In this chapter I consider how the two issues became enmeshed and sometimes even conflated over time, by analyzing the UN World Conference on Human Rights held in Vienna in June 1993 and events as well as scholarly and activist literature leading up to and following the conference. In particular, I begin to link early women’s human rights advocacy to legal and policy changes that took place in ensuing years, changes that I critique throughout the remainder of the book—from military intervention to international criminal law. This chapter also looks closely at two feminist approaches that were sidelined in the process—Third World and sex-positive. Chapter Five details how a third, anti-war, feminist position also failed to maintain significant traction as the women’s human rights movement turned its attention to sexual violence in conflict and to military, security, and criminal responses to it. The Vienna Conference was only the second world conference on human rights, and it was the first to be held since 1968. When the UN released its initial planning documents for the conference, some feminists noticed that the agenda contained no mention of women’s human rights, despite nearly a decade of feminist organizing under that banner. They responded by engaging in a successful internationally coordinated lobbying effort to put women’s rights on the conference agenda. They then went to Vienna determined to have women’s rights broadly acknowledged as human rights. They succeeded in that effort as 18 Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 19 well, as the slogan “Women’s Rights Are Human Rights” took off and began to receive mainstream recognition. In the years immediately preceding 1993, women’s human rights advocates had made violence against women (VAW) one of their primary issues. In Vienna, it became their paradigmatic issue. At the time, war was under way in the former Yugoslavia, and the mainstream media were reporting that rapes were being committed as a part of the conflict. These reports affected the official governmental conference as well as the NGO activities that ran parallel to it, both of which addressed rape in armed conflict as an important form of VAW. The Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, the outcome document of the conference, named a broad range of women’s human rights. It also reflected the extent to which rape and other forms of sexual harm in conflict were condemned in the official sessions. The document stated, “Violations of the human rights of women in situations of armed conflict are violations of the fundamental principles of international human rights and humanitarian law.” Then, listing specific violations, it continued, “All violations of this kind, including in particular murder, systematic rape, sexual slavery, and forced pregnancy, require a particularly effective response.”1 The conference report also included a declaration on Bosnia, which called for international action in the former Yugoslavia and noted that “over 40,000 Bosnian women have been subjected to the gruesome crime of rape.”2 While this kind of language around women’s human rights might not be controversial today, it is remarkable that it was also relatively uncontroversial at the time, given that women’s human rights had yet to gain mainstream recognition, as demonstrated by the UN’s failure to include the topic in the conference’s original mandate. It is also remarkable that feminists largely agreed on the document’s language on women’s human rights, given that internationally active feminists had been embroiled in a number of debates for some time. One such debate manifested itself primarily, but not only, in competing approaches to the treatment of sex work. It divided sex-positive feminists from those who condemned a broadly defined category of “female sexual slavery.” A second debate took place more directly within the women’s human rights movement, although it appeared in many other sites as well. It pitted structural-bias feminists, who centrally focused on gender—and sometimes sexual—oppression as the most important sociopolitical structure to address, against Third World feminist critics, who insisted that colonialism could not be delinked from gender bias. 20 Chapter 1 In the early to mid-1990s, Third World feminism was arguably poised to prevail, or at least seriously affect the ability of structural-bias feminism to get a stronghold on human rights. But the end of the Cold War, a compromise around what I call “culturally sensitive universalism,” the turn to sexual violence as the principal harm of conflict, and the pursuit of criminal law as the primary remedy, all functioned to subdue much of the Third World feminist critique, especially its material dimensions. These last two developments did the same to sex-positive feminism. All four of the developments can be traced to the Vienna Conference, even though their effects might not have been apparent at the time. In what follows, I trace the genealogy from liberal to carceral feminist approaches to international law in an effort to understand how and why a particular form of structural-bias feminism became empowered over the years, as well as to track what was lost in the process.3 I begin with the international reaction to the conflict in the former Yugoslavia, as the discourse around this conflict played a key role in the development of an apparent consensus, as well as in the perceptions of women’s human rights that this consensus concretized and perpetuated. I. Mainstream Responses to Wartime Rape in the Former Yugoslavia In April 1992, as a part of the disintegration of Yugoslavia, fighting broke out in Bosnia. It was not long before the international media began to report on rapes taking place there and elsewhere in the region. Feminists of various stripes inside and outside the country condemned the rapes, as did a number of nongovernmental and intergovernmental organizations. In December 1992, the UN Security Council passed a resolution stating that it was “appalled by reports of the massive, organized and systematic detention and rape of women, in particular Muslim women, in Bosnia and Herzegovina,”4 and condemning “these acts of unspeakable brutality.”5 It demanded “that all the detention camps and, in particular, camps for women should be immediately closed.”6 The first half of 1993 saw further responses by nongovernmental and intergovernmental organizations. For instance, Amnesty International, the UN Commission on Human Rights, and the European Council all issued reports finding systematic rape in Bosnia.7 The UN report explicitly linked rape in both Bosnia and Croatia to ethnic cleansing.8 In May, the UN Security Council unanimously passed a resolution establishing the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) to prosecute serious violations of international Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 21 humanitarian law, based in part on reports of “systematic detention and rape of women.”9 These reports and resolutions helped pave the way for official discussion of and response to rape in conflict at the Vienna Conference, as actors at multiple levels agreed that rape constituted a violation of international human rights and international humanitarian law. The reports and resolutions also helped to propel advocacy for the various types of international interventionist responses to wartime rape and other forms of sexual violence that I consider in the rest of the book: military intervention, international criminal law, and the UN Security Council’s Women, Peace and Security agenda (WPS agenda) and related activity. Feminists, in particular women’s human rights advocates, were involved at every level in these responses. As I discuss in greater detail in Chapter Two, rape in the former Yugoslavia received significant reporting and attention at an important historical moment— the early years after the end of the Cold War. In those years, the UN Security Council was newly poised to use its intervention power, including military force, to respond to threats to international peace and security. Because invoking that power, found in Chapter VII of the UN Charter, requires the acquiescence of all five permanent members of the Security Council, the Cold War stalemates had largely prevented its use.10 The end of the Cold War helps to explain why, once states began to recognize rape as a part of the Yugoslav conflict, they were willing to use the Security Council to respond. As we will see, states disagreed over the type of action the Security Council should take (military intervention versus criminal tribunals, for example), but they mostly agreed that the situation warranted some type of intervention. That history, however, explains neither why feminists were poised to zero in on sexual violence to begin with nor why they would be attracted to the use of the Security Council, particularly its Chapter VII coercive powers, as a response. It also does not explain how feminists were able to get nongovernmental and intergovernmental organizations to attend specifically to the rapes. For those explanations, we need to turn to late twentieth-century international feminist organizing, particularly through the women’s human rights movement. II. Early Feminist Engagement with Human Rights International human rights law is a relatively new field, taking off in the late 1970s and early 1980s.11 International criminal law, as we know it today, is even younger, emerging in the 1990s. While feminists began to make gains in international 22 Chapter 1 human rights law only in the early 1990s, some of their successes in that arena, including at Vienna, positioned them to influence international criminal law from its early stages onward. They were also able to have some impact on other post–Cold War developments, including military interventions and other forms of UN Security Council activity. The women’s human rights advocates who came to Vienna were led mostly by structural-bias feminists from the global North and their allies on VAW in the global South, with whom they had been working since the mid-1980s. They presented a largely united front, despite the fact that they had spent years in disagreement with each other over various issues, some common to the feminist movement at large and others more specific to international law and policy. Even structural-bias feminists were at that very moment tangled in an intense dispute among themselves over how to understand the rapes taking place in the former Yugoslavia. In the next section of this chapter as well as in subsequent chapters, I explore the various modes of consensus-building in which these women’s human rights advocates engaged as they turned to UN mechanisms, beginning with the Vienna Conference, to respond to sexual violence in conflict. But first, I consider the theoretical and political dissensus that preceded the period of collaboration. I do so in order to recover some of the critiques that were lost as an apparent consensus in 1993 reduced a number of tensions, not only among feminists but between feminists and mainstream human rights advocates as well. The mid- to late-1980s and early 1990s saw the first wave of feminist approaches to international human rights. As feminists began to consider ways in which human rights law—and related international institutions and nongovernmental advocacy—could respond to women’s concerns, two primary sets of approaches emerged, one liberal and another, more radical, focused on structural bias. Soon thereafter, Third World feminist critiques developed, largely in response to the structural-bias feminist critics but with roots in older North-South struggles. In mapping these positions, I read them primarily as approaches rather than as people because, over time, a number of individuals took more than one approach. And although I focus on feminist scholarship related explicitly to human rights law and discourse, both feminist theorists and advocates (two groups with significant overlap) had in fact been engaged for some time with international issues such as peace, education, and labor, dating back at least to the period between the World Wars.12 When the Universal Declaration of Human Rights was drafted in 1948, women’s activism played a role in ensuring, among other Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 23 things, the use of mostly gender-neutral language.13 Women in both the global South and the global North also participated, sometimes self-consciously through women’s solidarity movements, in international emancipatory struggles against colonialism and apartheid. As early as the 1970s, they advocated for the inclusion of women in development programs.14 Some of the outlets for these issues were the UN World Conferences on Women, held in Mexico City in 1975, Copenhagen in 1980, and Nairobi in 1985. In fact, many of the tensions and debates around women’s human rights from the late 1980s onward had roots in earlier debates among women in these forums. A. Liberal Inclusion Approaches Early feminist approaches to international human rights argued that women should and could be included in international human rights law. Women were as much subjects of human rights law as were men, and thus, if properly applied, human rights law and institutions could assimilate women’s concerns. These approaches dominated women’s human rights advocacy and scholarship in the 1980s.15 Liberal inclusionists argued that international human rights law required the formal equal treatment of women and men, and many also maintained that it guaranteed women economic and social rights, as well as civil and political rights. For proponents of inclusion, the legal instruments that were needed to assimilate women into international human rights law and institutions already existed. Any failure to protect women’s rights, in this view, could be attributed to a lack of will or enforcement, not a lack of law. Some liberal inclusionists criticized international institutions for their failures to address women’s issues. While some argued that increasing the number of women in these organizations would lead to greater attention to women’s needs, others believed the institutions just needed to take seriously their legal mandates, which included women’s human rights. For both positions, existing institutions could address women’s human rights without major structural change. That is, the right people or the right attention within the institutions would suffice to bring the proper consideration to women’s human rights. B. Structural-Bias Critiques Proponents of another type of feminism, which would soon shape much of the women’s human rights movement, argued that simple inclusion of women in international human rights law, or even in international institutions, was much 24 Chapter 1 more difficult than liberal inclusionists had imagined. For structural-bias feminism, human rights law—and international law more broadly—was constructed by and for men, with structural features that prevented its application to women. Because the structure of human rights prevented women’s assimilation, women’s human rights advocates needed to change the regime significantly for women to be accommodated.16 As Charlotte Bunch put it in an early example of this view in 1990, “while this [liberal] approach of adding women and stirring them into existing first generation human rights categories [of civil and political rights] is useful, it is not enough by itself.”17 Another advocate later explained, “The fundamental challenge for the movement for women’s human rights is that it not become a reformist project: its recipe should not read, ‘Add women and stir,’ but ‘Add women and alter.’”18 The assumptions at the analytical core of structural-bias critiques were that male dominance and female subordination were universal—even if they manifested themselves differently in different places among different groups of people—and that they constituted the greatest impediment to the realization of women’s rights.19 That dominance structure, according to these critiques, could be found in human rights law, and thus in the institutions and movements that aimed to enforce it. For one strand of structural-bias feminism, the dominance structure was organized around sexuality, specifically around male sexual dominance and female sexual subordination. Structural-bias feminists identified a series of dichotomies in international law that they believed perpetuated human rights law’s neglect of women. International law, for instance, prioritized the state over civil society,20 and civil and political rights over economic and social rights.21 These two dichotomies were related for some. As Bunch argued, “Some important aspects of women’s rights do fit into a civil liberties framework, but much of the abuse against women is part of a larger socio-economic web that entraps women, making them vulnerable to abuses which cannot be delineated as exclusively political or solely caused by states.”22 The most commonly discussed of these dichotomies, and the apparent ground of many of the others, was the public/private distinction. According to some structural-bias critiques, the public/private distinction was a concrete reality for women. And because human rights law excluded the private, or domestic, sphere from its scope—the very space in which women were presumed to operate—it could not include women.23 The international legal definition of torture, for example, required direct state action and could not apply to private relations within Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 25 the home. Thus, human rights law needed to be reconceptualized to include the private sphere or attend to the acts of non-state actors. Other structural-bias challenges to the public/private distinction tended to characterize it as a product of ideology, rather than as embedded in the doctrine of human rights or international law. Some critics pointed out, for instance, that few would contend that the international legal regime lacked the authority to intervene to ensure that states end certain forms of “private” violence, such as cannibalism or slavery.24 In this telling, the public/private distinction was structural, but perhaps not as intransigent as the other view suggested.25 These critics therefore argued that a state’s failure to protect rights in the private sphere was akin to state action, and therefore should be within the purview of human rights. For some, sexual subordination was at the core of what was labeled the private sphere. Catharine MacKinnon, for example, entered the international human rights discussion in 1990 with a lecture called “On Torture,” in which she argued that human rights law and discourse problematically embodied a distinction between what is “sexual or intimate” and what is a political act by the state: “When the abuse is sexual or intimate, especially when it is sexual and inflicted by an intimate, it is gendered, hence not considered a human rights violation.”26 Noting that “all around the world, women are battered, raped, sexually abused as children, prostituted, and increasingly live pornographic lives in contexts saturated more or less with pornography,”27 MacKinnon contended that intimate sexual violence is indeed political because “the state is not all there is to power.”28 That said, in line with those who argued that the public/private distinction is an ideological construct, she also pointed out that “the state actually is typically deeply and actively complicit in the abuses mentioned.”29 Whether or not they saw sexual dominance and subordination as constituting what was often labeled the private, and regardless of whether they saw the public/private distinction as inherent to human rights law and discourse (versus as an ideologically driven manifestation of its implementation), structural-bias feminists tended to locate women’s oppression in what is commonly seen as the private sphere. That is, they considered women to be at least as oppressed by their families and communities (or “culture”), as they were by direct government action. Despite their insistence that gender oppression was universal, structuralbias feminists tended to concentrate on posited Third World cultural practices as particularly harmful. Some of their most prominent examples were female genital mutilation (as they called it), dowry deaths, and even apparent food 26 Chapter 1 taboos that kept women undernourished.30 Structural-bias feminists also generally assumed that First and Third World feminists shared a common goal. As Hilary Charlesworth, Christine Chinkin, and Shelly Wright put it in 1991 in one of the earliest pieces to be published on feminist approaches to international law, this common goal was to challenge “structures that permit male domination,” even though the “form of the challenge and the male structures may differ from society to society.”31 The focus on the victimization of Third World women and the assumption of solidarity were at least partly responsible for the (re)emergence of critique from women in and aligned with the global South. These Third World feminist critiques did not challenge human rights law as much as they questioned the particular assumptions and priorities of the structuralbias feminist approaches to it.32 C. Third World Feminist Critiques Since at least the 1970s, there had been significant disagreement in international forums between women from the global South and the global North (which were then referred to as the Third World and First World). Much of that discord mirrored that between developing and developed countries more generally at the time. That is, at least some women from the global South aligned with their governments’ resistance to racism, colonialism, and apartheid, along with their related commitment to a New International Economic Order (NIEO). The NIEO, initially proposed in the 1970s by a coalition of recently decolonized and other Third World states, had a broad agenda but was primarily aimed at the maldistribution of wealth and resources among countries.33 These women from the Third World often saw those from the First World, including feminists, as implicated in the economic and other forms of exploitation faced by those in the Third World. At a minimum, they saw First World feminists as focused on the wrong issues. The resulting tensions often played out at intergovernmental meetings, such as the early UN World Conferences on Women. Even when feminist activists came together through nongovernmental meetings at the conferences, they often reproduced many of the same debates that were happening in intergovernmental forums. The turn of feminists, particularly of structural-bias feminists, to human rights law and discourse in the late 1980s and early 1990s both revived and transformed the debates. In an earlier era, it could be argued that feminists in the global North simply had different priorities for themselves than women in the global South did for themselves, though many in the South were quick to Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 27 note that the global economy and history of colonialism made such a distinction impossible. International human rights law provided a new platform for feminists in the North to address what they considered to be the needs and rights of their “sisters” in the South. The Vienna Conference in 1993 and the UN World Conference on Women in Beijing in 1995 offered opportunities for structural-bias feminists both to provoke anew and to respond to some Third World feminist critiques. Third World feminist critiques questioned the solidarity assumed by many structural-bias feminists on a variety of grounds, ranging from the cultural to the economic.34 To begin with, many Third World feminist critics called attention to cultural differences that they believed were either omitted in structural-bias universalizing claims about gender oppression or misunderstood in the condemnations of certain cultural practices in the Third World. Some criticized the failure of feminists in the First World to distinguish their own interests from those of women in the South, arguing for the need to take seriously differences in culture that may underlie differences in interests. Anthropologist Aihwa Ong asserted, for example, the need for feminists in the North to recognize the “alternative political moralities that shape the ways women in other societies make moral judgments about their interests and goals in life, and use other cultural criteria about what it means to be female and human.”35 Others called on First World women’s human rights advocates to reexamine their own cultures for forms of oppression that they may have failed to identify.36 Third World feminists also often argued that structural-bias feminism represented Third World women in ways that denied their agency. Leslye Obiora argued, for example, that structural-bias feminists “tend to conflate the specificities and meanings of women’s experiences and to perpetuate the dubious portrayal of women as mere epiphenomena or passive objects of male transactions.”37 That argument had begun to be made about structural-bias feminist representations of First World women as well, but Third World feminists saw its effect as particularly insidious, and imperial, in the context of women in the global South. As Vasuki Nesiah explained, “A discourse about the experience of oppression often participates in the imperially charged agenda of defining ‘Third World’ women as victims of oppression.”38 Ratna Kapur would later point out that such a perception of Third World women had “serious implications for the strategies subsequently adopted to remedy the harms.” Specifically, it encouraged “some feminists in the international arena to propose strategies which are reminiscent of imperial interventions in the lives of the native subject and which represent the 28 Chapter 1 ‘Eastern’ woman as a victim of a ‘backward’ and ‘uncivilized’ culture.”39 If white men had, during colonial times, sought to “sav[e] brown women from brown men,” in the words of Gayatri Spivak,40 Third World anti-imperial feminist critics often charged structural-bias feminists with attempting to do the same through the women’s human rights movement. Relatedly, Third World feminist critiques also questioned the structural-bias focus on the private sphere—or family, community, and culture—as the primary locus of women’s oppression, and the way in which that focus displaced other issues central to the lives of Third World women. As Obiora later put it: “The truth of the matter is that, despite popular feminist discourses, culture may not be the dispositive influence on the responses of women.”41 She also explained that “campaigns for sexual rights and freedoms [have been] disparaged as the trite obsession of privileged Western feminists by some feminists who preferred to emphasize economic concerns.”42 Even when structural-bias feminists from the global North attempted to address economic issues, such as the rights of female workers in the global South, some Third World feminists argued that they missed the source of the problems by analyzing them through a structural-bias lens. Ong, for example, questioned Northern feminists’ sense of solidarity with women in the global South, along with their understanding of the effects of global capital. Contending that “local patriarchal norms” are not alone responsible for the mistreatment of female workers, she argued that “strategic sisterhoods will have to confront not only cultural practices in Third World countries, but also metropolitan capitalist enterprises that are driven by profits to seek cheap female labor in the South.”43 Although the tensions between North and South were, in many ways, mediated by the women’s human rights movement as it developed over time, structural-bias feminists did not abandon their universalizing assumptions about gender oppression or their focus on and essentialized assumptions about many (Third World) cultures. Indeed, as every chapter of this book demonstrates, attention to sexual violence in conflict both guided and arguably reinforced those assumptions. Yet, they have operated in ways that have largely resisted criticism from most other strands of feminism, even while garnering significant mainstream appeal. III. “Women’s Rights Are Human Rights” at Vienna The UN World Conference on Human Rights in Vienna was initially planned in 1989, with the belief that the ensuing end of the Cold War would bring expanded Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 29 opportunities for promoting human rights. When the preparatory meetings for the conference began in September 1991, new disagreements developed that called into question the anticipated consensus. As the UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights put it, there were “many difficult, sometimes divisive, issues regarding national sovereignty, universality, the role of nongovernmental organizations and questions concerning the feasibility, viability, and impartiality of new or strengthened human rights instruments.”44 Asian countries, in particular, came together to champion economic and social rights and the right to development, and to oppose the conditionality of development assistance on human rights. In doing so, they sparked a debate around “Asian values” that would animate much of the conference and the preparatory meetings leading up to it.45 Feminists also organized, beginning in December 1991, via the campaign to have women’s human rights included in the Vienna Conference. Rutgers University’s Center for Women’s Global Leadership, headed by Charlotte Bunch, launched the Global Campaign for Women’s Human Rights, which helped initiate a petition calling on the conference “to comprehensively address women’s human rights at every level of the proceedings.” It demanded in particular that “gender violence, a universal phenomenon which takes many forms across culture, race, and class, be recognized as a violation of human rights requiring immediate action.”46 The petition garnered more than 300,000 signatures from more than 120 countries.47 By the time it was presented on the floor of the conference, according to Bunch, half a million people had signed it.48 Moreover, women around the world organized to define their issues and to lobby both governments and human rights NGOs at regional preparatory meetings for the conference.49 This organizing was done primarily under the “Women’s Rights Are Human Rights” banner. If women’s rights had been largely missing from the mainstream thinking about human rights at the time, the human rights lens was also relatively new for feminists and others concerned with women’s issues. Remarkably, there had been little consideration of women’s rights as human rights at the three UN world conferences on women up to that time, which were centered on the themes of equality, peace, and development. The words “human rights” seldom appeared in any of the formal documents produced at those conferences, and when they did, they referenced women more often as advocates for, rather than subjects of, human rights. Indeed, the terms “women’s human rights” and “human rights of women” were rarely used at all before the late 1980s. (See Figure 1.1.) 30 Chapter 1 Figure 1.1. An N-gram, based on eight million of the titles published from 1940 to 2008 and digitized in Google Books, demonstrating an increase in references to “human rights of women” and “women’s human rights” beginning in the mid-1970s. See generally Michel et al., “Quantitative Analysis of Culture Using Millions of Digitized Books.” I do not use this and subsequent N-grams as proof of my analysis, only as some further confirmation of it. Bunch dates the use of the “Women’s Rights Are Human Rights” slogan to a campaign launched in the Philippines in 1988 by the anti-Marcos women’s coalition GABRIELA.50 As indicated above, feminist critiques of human rights had begun a bit sooner, but they were relatively rare and largely took place at the margins of academic and non-academic endeavors alike. In 1987, for example, I attended the Inter-American Institute’s annual course on human rights in San José, Costa Rica, aimed largely at human rights practitioners in the region. The institute offered, for the first time ever, an elective seminar titled “Human Rights and Nondiscrimination.” It was led by Costa Rican feminist and human rights advocate Alda Facio, who was clearly ahead of the curve, as the seminar topic attracted very few participants. Even within our small group, there was significant resistance to the concept of women’s human rights, particularly by those who had chosen to attend the seminar to discuss the rights of indigenous peoples. They were skeptical of rights in general because of their historical association with the imposition of Western cultural standards, and they saw women’s rights as exacerbating the extent to which human rights might encroach upon indigenous rights. When, as a law student in 1988, I worked with some fellow students to persuade the Harvard Human Rights Program to sponsor a conference that we titled “Women’s Human Rights: Possibilities and Contradictions,” my sense of the marginality of the topic was confirmed. With the help of women’s human Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 31 rights advocates and scholars Arvonne Fraser and Rebecca Cook, we assembled an array of feminists who were speaking in human rights terms. But we also invited representatives from a number of mainstream human rights NGOs to participate, though few took the conference seriously. The director of one major human rights NGO in the United States turned down the invitation, stating that he did not see the need for a separate conference on women. The director of another attended and, during his talk, explained that violations of women’s rights were a part of his organization’s mission, so long as they were committed by state actors in their public roles. Not surprisingly, much of the discussion at the conference focused on how to convince mainstream nongovernmental and intergovernmental human rights organizations that they should attend to women’s rights, particularly by holding state actors accountable for violations by non-state actors in the private sphere.51 Especially given the resistance we encountered in 1988, it is surprising how quickly the women’s human rights movement caught on. Bunch, who was one of the main speakers at the Harvard conference, notes that in the early 1990s, “women’s caucuses formed within human rights organizations like Amnesty International, and Human Rights Watch established its own Women’s Rights division to research global abuses against women and girls in the context of international law.”52 These and related activities, according to her, helped facilitate the organizing that took place to put women’s human rights on the agenda in Vienna. The Women’s Rights Are Human Rights campaign succeeded at Vienna. Even while the intergovernmental conference and preparatory meetings revived North-South—as well as East-West—debates about culture, development, and the prioritization of civil and political rights, few opposed the inclusion of women’s rights. As Bunch noted, “the text on women came to the conference almost free of brackets, to the surprise of some men in human rights organizations where the issue was still seen as marginal, if about human rights at all.”53 And, according to Bunch and collaborator Niamh Reilly, “gender-based violence and women’s human rights emerged as one of the most talked-about subjects, and women were recognized as a well-organized human rights constituency.”54 They pointed, in particular, to the significant number of pages of the Vienna Declaration devoted to the equal status of women and to its call for the elimination of violence against women in both the public and the private spheres.55 As already mentioned, the final official document named systematic rape and other forms of violence committed against women during armed conflict as human rights violations.56 The timing of the conference and the geographical 32 Chapter 1 proximity of Vienna to the former Yugoslavia meant that the conflict loomed large in both the governmental and the nongovernmental portions of the conference. Much discussion of the conflict took place in the context of the Global Tribunal on Violations of Women’s Human Rights, a sort of people’s tribunal organized by the Center for Women’s Global Leadership and held on the second day of the conference. The tribunal aimed to call “international attention to a pattern of female human rights abuse which must be taken seriously if human rights are to be an effective and credible component of the global political and economic order for the 21st century.”57 In general, the Global Tribunal and the feminist advocacy leading up to it played an important role in articulating the understanding of women’s human rights that would be pursued two years later in Beijing at the UN World Conference on Women. But its specific attention to rape and other forms of sexual harm also set in motion an understanding of the harm of and necessary responses to rape and sexual violence that would manifest themselves in the soon-to-be-developed instruments of international criminal law, as well as in debates about military intervention. The few histories that have been told of feminist efforts to bring women’s rights to the human rights table in Vienna, and human rights to the women’s table in Beijing, suggest that little debate occurred among feminists at or leading up to the meetings. Those accounts contrast sharply with descriptions of other international meetings, namely earlier UN conferences on women. Some of the Third World feminist critiques articulated in the aftermath of the Vienna and Beijing conferences make it clear that disagreements continued, at least at the academic level. But women’s human rights advocacy at both Vienna and Beijing functioned on multiple levels to neutralize Third World critiques. Some of this neutralization came with the consensus-building that was necessary to attempt to bring the margin (women) to the center (human rights) in Vienna. That consensus was achieved through three different, albeit related, moves: (1) the creation and invocation of what I have termed “culturally sensitive universalism”; (2) a strategic focus on violence against women, building on international feminist networks that had been developing since the mid-1980s; and (3) the attention to rape in conflict, and eventually to the larger category of sexual violence in conflict. Let me consider each in turn. A. Culturally Sensitive Universalism Perhaps the Third World feminist critiques that had the greatest impact on Vienna were those that called for the recognition of differences in cultures (and Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 33 gender relations). Feminists from around the world played important roles in women’s human rights advocacy at Vienna, and they did so in ways that avoided some of the controversies of earlier UN conferences on women. The recognition of difference in fact helped facilitate solidarity between women of the global South and North, and it was manifested in a compromise on culturally sensitive universalism that emerged in Vienna and was continued in Beijing.58 In Vienna, the Asian values debate that had captured a great deal of attention leading up to the conference provided the backdrop to the compromise. On the surface, at least, that debate was largely over the question of whether and how differences among cultures (often conflated with states, in the Asian values version of it) could be effectively addressed by a universal human rights system. The Vienna Declaration demonstrated the compromise in Paragraph 1, stating that “the universal nature of these rights and freedoms is beyond question,”59 and Paragraph 5, noting, by contrast, that “the significance of national and regional particularities and various historical, cultural and religious backgrounds must be borne in mind.”60 Paragraph 5 went on to state, however, that “it is the duty of States, regardless of their political, economic and cultural systems, to promote and protect all human rights and fundamental freedoms.”61 Hence, the paragraph arguably ended with universality, but a universality that recognized difference. The inclusion of both universal and particular language seemed to satisfy many participants at the conference; its ambiguity could be claimed as a victory by both sides.62 The Beijing Declaration and Platform, which resulted from the UN World Conference on Women held in 1995, repeated this language verbatim, ensuring its application to women’s human rights.63 For some, the culturally sensitive part of the compromise signaled at least a partial success for the Third World feminist assertions of cultural specificity and for their wariness of Western feminist assertions of universal values. Obiora, for instance, read the combined universal and particular language in the Beijing Declaration as containing “a problematic element of contradiction,” but she suggested that the ambiguity was nevertheless an improvement over the language in other women’s rights documents that had expressly disavowed the significance of cultural difference for women’s human rights.64 If the compromise in the declarations represented a nod toward cultural difference for some, others claimed it supported universalism.65 In response to seeing such different interpretations of the language, Dianne Otto argued that the ambiguity “reflects the paralysis of the debate and leaves the issue firmly on the international human rights agenda for another day.”66 34 Chapter 1 Over time, however, the spirit of the compromise seemed to stick. That is, the culture issue did not re-emerge as an explicit site of contestation, at least not in the same way as it had in the past. In the five years following 1995, feminists in both the global North and the global South wrote many scholarly articles with the aim of finding a middle way between universalism and relativism.67 They often offered human rights as a unifying tool. While the newly culturally sensitive language and literature might have responded to some of the Third World feminist critiques of structural-bias feminism’s approach to culture, it failed to respond to the most radical of the critiques, which was aimed at the unwillingness or even inability of structural-bias feminism to take seriously the role of the global North (including women who live there) in the exploitation of women in the global South. Taking that anti-imperial critique seriously would require attention not only to the gendered and cultural dimensions of the global distribution of wealth, but also to the economic dimensions of politics about gender and culture. The anti-imperial part of the Third World critique has continued in a variety of contexts, but it has had little influence on the subsequent development of the women’s human rights movement or, as we see in subsequent chapters, international criminal law or the UN’s Women, Peace and Security agenda.68 That result was not wholly unintended. Indeed, even before Vienna, as we see in the next section, feminists sometimes coalesced around VAW in a deliberate attempt to displace attention from global economic inequality. B. Violence against Women From the beginning of feminist efforts to add women’s human rights to the Vienna Conference agenda, combating VAW was a central goal. Indeed, the Center for Women’s Global Leadership initiated the 1991 petition drive during the launch of its 16 Days of Activism against Gender Violence, a campaign named to mark the days between the International Day of Violence against Women on November 25 and International Human Rights Day on December 10.69 While the petition called for women’s human rights to be addressed comprehensively, gender violence was the one issue it specifically named. The Global Tribunal continued that focus, with hearings on “human rights abuse in the family,” “war crimes against women,” “violations of women’s bodily integrity,” “socio-economic violations of women’s human rights,” and “political persecution and discrimination.”70 Much of the testimony presented under these categories concerned physical violence, and often—as I discuss further Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 35 below—sexual violence. Even the session on socioeconomic violations, according to the summary provided by Bunch and Reilly, concentrated on how such violations make women more vulnerable to physical and sexual exploitation.71 This approach to women’s economic and social rights was in line with Bunch’s concerns discussed above about the “socio-economic web that entraps women.”72 Although the discussion of VAW as a human rights issue was relatively new in the early 1990s, VAW had been a subject of international women’s organizing at least since the UN World Conference on Women held in Nairobi in 1985.73 Indeed, the Nairobi Conference is often discussed as the site at which VAW first received significant international recognition. The Nairobi Forward-looking Strategies, the official document produced by the governmental delegates, stated: “Women are beaten, mutilated, burned, sexually abused and raped.”74 That language appeared in the section on peace (recall that the World Conferences on Women had peace, equality, and development as their triple mandate), declaring that violence against women “in everyday life in all societies” constitutes “a major obstacle to the achievement of peace and the other objectives of the [Women’s] Decade.”75 The NGO Forum that ran parallel to the governmental conference paid even greater attention to VAW, with nearly one-third of the workshops devoted to the topic.76 According to Arvonne Fraser, who was active in the NGO Forum after having been an official U.S. delegate to the first two UN World Conferences on Women, VAW was a unifying topic. She observed that at the Peace Tent, which was part of the unofficial forum and particularly intended to bring together women whose countries were at war with one another, “women in chadors conversed with Israeli women, violence against women being the meeting ground.”77 Not all would agree that VAW, rather than the promotion of peace, provided the common ground for the Peace Tent.78 Yet, finding a “meeting ground” for women from the global North and the global South provided one of the motivations for the emphasis that women’s human rights advocates placed on VAW. In an account of the origins of the 16 Days of Activism campaign, for example, the Center for Women’s Global Leadership notes that it convened a group of activists from a number of different countries in 1991 to discuss gender and human rights and to begin to develop “strategies to increase international awareness of the systemic nature of violence against women and to expose this violence as a violation of women’s human rights.”79 The aim of overcoming cultural difference was at the forefront of their decision: “While violence against women takes different forms according to its cultural context, the problem exists everywhere and 36 Chapter 1 working on the issue offers unique opportunities to build bridges across cultures, to learn from both similarities and differences, and to link strategies globally.”80 According to Margaret Keck and Kathryn Sikkink, this strategy intentionally responded to the disillusionment in the mid-1980s of those who had been working on women and development issues for some time. Although development had provided the first context for bringing women from the North and South together, they point out, “the issue of women and development never spawned a major global network or campaign,” in part because the “concerns were so systemic that they defied individual or group efforts to effect change.”81 Contending that VAW “appeared to offer clearer avenues for activism,” they quote Bunch: “Sometimes deceptively, sometimes usefully, you feel like you can do something about it. There are everyday things you can do about it, from wherever you are.”82 They also note that “some of the most innovative groups to take on the women and development issue . . . later became leaders in the campaign for human rights.”83 The simultaneous rise of human rights advocacy and decreased attention to economic development was not unique to issues of gender or women. In fact, it could be seen shortly after the end of the Cold War, before women’s human rights had made it into the mainstream. An N-gram, depicting the percentage of digitized books in English from 1940 to 2008 that reference “economic development,” on the one hand, and “human rights,” on the other, offers a visual approximation of this change in both practice and theory during this period. Figure 1.2 shows the lines representing the frequency of each of those terms crossing between 1989 and 1990. Combined with end-of-the-Cold-War market fundamentalism, the women’s human rights movement’s centering of VAW provided a new way to mediate debates about culture. It also contributed to the displacement of attention to (and disagreement over) Third World economic development, in part by subsuming the issue. Indeed, early discussions of VAW were often articulated in terms of development, but in ways that Jennifer Suchland argues “deprioritize[d] feminist economic analysis.”84 She critiques two approaches by Bunch and others that deliberately attempted to link development and VAW and that, according to Suchland, rely on the “logic of agency.”85 One approach considered VAW to be an unanticipated outcome of development programs, as male retaliation for the female economic power resulting from those initiatives. The other viewed VAW as preventing women from participating in development. In these and Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 37 Figure 1.2. An N-gram based on eight million of the titles published from 1940 to 2008 and digitized in Google Books, comparing references to “human rights” and “economic development.” other linkages between VAW and development, Suchland persuasively argues, development discourse “operates in conjunction with, rather than as a critique of, neoliberal governance.”86 It is a far cry from earlier Third World feminist (and other) critiques of the international global order. C. Sexual Violence in Conflict The Nairobi Conference might have set in motion this significant attention to VAW, but it did not address the issue in the way that it would be taken up several years later in Vienna. As the UN Division for the Advancement of Women explained in a 1998 report, “The general vulnerability of women to sexual abuse and rape in everyday life was recognized” in the 1985 Nairobi Forward-looking Strategies, “but sexual violence was not specifically linked to armed conflict.”87 The Vienna Conference simultaneously addressed that link and the earlier lack of “explicit recognition that violence against women is a human rights issue.”88 Three moves took place at the governmental and nongovernmental meetings in Vienna that facilitated the heightened consideration of sexual violence in conflict: (1) an attention to armed conflict as a site of human rights violations and to the international humanitarian law that governs conduct in war; (2) a focus on the particular effects of armed conflict on women; and (3) the spotlighting of sexual violence as constituting the greatest harm that women experience in conflict. With regard to the first move, we have already seen that the armed conflict in the former Yugoslavia was very much on the minds of participants at the Vienna 38 Chapter 1 Conference. Discussion of atrocities committed during the conflict undoubtedly affected the drafting of the Vienna Declaration. The declaration included multiple references to violations of human rights committed in armed conflict, and called upon states to observe international humanitarian law. The second and third moves brought together the focus on armed conflict and the broader attention to VAW promoted by women’s rights advocates. Those advocates presented the reported rapes in the Yugoslav conflict as symptomatic of the type of violence that they urged human rights NGOs and governments to address. Indeed, the 1998 UN report described Vienna as a “watershed for women’s human rights,” in large part because of its focus on sexual violence in conflict, explaining that “at that time, reports of sexual violence committed against women in the former Yugoslavia had flooded the media. The accompanying worldwide outrage provided powerful support for NGO arguments that violence against women is a fundamental human rights violation, of concern to the international community at large.”89 Even if discussion of sexual violence in conflict began as a compelling example of VAW, the issue soon dominated. According to the Vienna Declaration, “violations of the human rights of women in situations of armed conflict are violations of the fundamental principles of international human rights and humanitarian law.” That statement showed attention to particular harms to women during conflict, demonstrating the second move, but the third move came in its list of examples: “murder, systematic rape, sexual slavery, and forced pregnancy.”90 With the exception of murder, the condemned violence is all sexual in nature. The inclusion of that language in the official Vienna Conference document tracked a much more detailed discussion of sexual violence in conflict that had taken place at the Global Tribunal. As previously mentioned, a large percentage of the testimony in each of the sessions dealt with VAW. But, as Alice Miller has demonstrated, much of that VAW testimony was about sexual violence.91 The Global Tribunal devoted its first session to “war crimes against women.” Bunch and Reilly identify three themes that emerged, as some women testified about being “comfort women” during World War II and others spoke of their experiences during conflict in the former Yugoslavia, Palestine, Peru, Russia, and Somalia: “women’s bodies are figuratively and actually the site of combat in wartime; women’s human rights are violated through the exploitation of familial relationships; and, women suffer diproportionately from economic and social dislocations caused by conflict.”92 Notwithstanding that these three themes do not explicitly reference sexual violence (and that there was testimony on other Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 39 matters), the bulk of Bunch and Reilly’s written description of the testimony is about it.93 For instance, their discussion of the first theme—women’s bodies as the site of combat—is exclusively about sexual violence, and they devote three times more space to it than they do to the other two themes. This emphasis was true in other areas as well. As Miller concludes, after viewing a video made available of some of the testimony from the tribunal as a whole, “Of the 15 or so testimonies shown, at least 10 deal with sexual assault in detention, incest, rape in marriage, trafficking for forced prostitution, or rape in armed conflict.”94 The sexual violence testimony also captured the attention of Canadian politician Ed Broadbent, whom the organizers selected as the judge for the war crimes session. Broadbent began his response by noting that he was the first man to speak all day and then zeroed in nearly exclusively on the testimony of rape. He labeled the acts of rape that he had heard about during the session as crimes against humanity, and even stated that they had been used as an instrument of ethnic cleansing.95 He did not mention the other two themes. The official (unofficial) judgment on the effects of war on women at the Global Tribunal therefore solely concerned sexual violence. This near-singular attention to sexual violence in the context of women and armed conflict further submerged the Third World feminist critique of economic distribution. As Miller puts it, “Once sex was accepted as an area of concern, a ‘hyper-attention’ to sex perversely operated to exclude attention to other aspects of harm,” such as “global labor equity,” “participatory equality,” and “life-saving health interventions and systems for women and men.”96 The focus on sexual violence in conflict also became another way to avert, even suppress, the debates over culture, given that no one—feminist or otherwise—could claim that rape in war was culturally defensible. And few would even suggest that it demanded a culturally sensitive response. Moreover, the fact that the rapes were taking place in Europe meant that Northern feminists could attest that they were attending to issues “at home.”97 Beyond sidelining these Third World feminist critiques, the prioritization of and near-agreement on sexual violence in conflict facilitated the dominance of the sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism within human rights, humanitarian law, and eventually international criminal law. Prior to Vienna, little of the VAW work had been about conflict-related violence.98 Yet, as already noted, many of the structural-bias feminists who turned to women’s human rights advocacy had long emphasized sex-related violence against women in their work. The “W” in “VAW” makes clear that women were its focus. But 40 Chapter 1 that focus rested upon a theory of gender. As Bunch explained in her 1990 article calling for a transformative approach to human rights: Victims are chosen because of their gender. The message is domination: stay in your place or be afraid . . . [Such violence] is profoundly political. It results from the structural relationships of power, domination, and privilege between men and women in society. Violence against women is central to maintaining those political relations at home, at work, and in all public spheres.99 Though Bunch noted that her transformative approach could be applied to any issue, she stated that those who pursued it “have tended to focus most on abuses that arise specifically out of gender, such as reproductive rights, female sexual slavery, violence against women, and ‘family crimes’ like forced marriage, compulsory heterosexuality, and female mutilation. These are also the issues most often dismissed as not really human rights questions.”100 “Sexual violence” was not then a term commonly in circulation. (See Figure 1.3.) Yet nearly all of Bunch’s examples would fit into that category as it became constructed. In fact, those working to end VAW had been mired for some time in a controversy about how central sexual violence should be to their agenda. Even before Nairobi, some feminists had organized against what they called “female sexual slavery.” That term is generally attributed to Kathleen Barry, who published a book in 1979 on the topic.101 Bunch worked with Barry in the early 1980s to organize an international network against female sexual slavery, hosting a global workshop on sex trafficking in Rotterdam in 1983.102 Although the focus of the conference was what the organizers called “forced prostitution,” Barry’s refusal to share the stage with Margo St. James, who was a sex worker and noted advocate for the decriminalization of prostitution, suggested a refusal to acknowledge the possibility of consensual sex work.103 Moreover, the conference emerged from earlier meetings that reached well beyond prostitution.104 As Barry explained, female sexual slavery incorporated women “who are the victims of sex tourism, who are the victims of gangs that traffic women from South America to Europe, women who are sexually tortured and enslaved as political prisoners in totalitarian dictatorships and women enslaved in their own homes.”105 Sex, of course, was seen as the basis of all of these oppressions, and the aim was to connect the “force, coercion and violence in prostitution to the violence in women’s lives around the world, in wife battery, rape, incest, bride burning, excision and pornography.”106 Another group, called sex-positive or sex-radical feminists, criticized the Rotterdam meeting and other work around “sexual slavery.” Many sex-positive Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 41 Figure 1.3. An N-gram, based on eight million of the titles published from 1940 to 2008 and digitized in Google Books, charting the steady rise of mentions of “sexual violence” beginning in the 1970s. feminists allied with sex workers who were concerned that their livelihoods would be affected even by those campaigns aimed solely at forced prostitution, as evidenced by St. James’s attendance at Rotterdam. Some used rights discourse to make their arguments. Indeed, in 1985, St. James and Gail Pheterson founded the International Committee for Prostitutes’ Rights (ICPR), which held a World Whores Congress that same year in Amsterdam. The ICPR adopted a World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights, which included rights that would provide economic security, both by allowing prostitutes to do their jobs and by providing a safety net. The World Charter, for example, guaranteed prostitutes “all human rights and civil liberties, including the freedom of speech, travel, immigration, work, marriage, and motherhood and the right to unemployment insurance, health insurance and housing.” Further, it connected the rights talk with larger efforts to decriminalize consensual sexual conduct, calling for the granting of “asylum to anyone denied human rights on the basis of a ‘crime of status,’ be it prostitution or homosexuality.”107 Notwithstanding their relatively early use of rights language, sex-positive feminists ultimately had little effect on the discourse that prevailed at the Vienna Conference. When they discussed rape, for instance, sex-positive feminists did believe its criminal prohibition should be enforced, but they placed it alongside a very different list of crimes than those enumerated above by Barry, or similar lists that would make it into the Vienna Declaration and, as we will see, the Rome Statute. Specifically, the World Charter called for the enforcement of “criminal 42 Chapter 1 laws against fraud, coercion, violence, child sexual abuse, child labor, rape, racism everywhere and across national boundaries, whether or not in the context of prostitution.”108 Not only were child sexual abuse and rape the only sexual crimes mentioned, but the World Charter suggested Third World feminist stances as it took on racism, violence, and all forms of fraud and coercion. To be fair, some of the anti–sexual slavery feminists were, at least initially, somewhat open to the Third World feminist critiques as well. In her own writing about the 1983 Rotterdam meeting, for example, Bunch pointed out that the trafficking workshop looked at how “the exploitation of women in prostitution and . . . violence against women” are connected to “oppression by class, race, militarism, and neo-colonialism.”109 Bunch, along with Shirley Castley, insisted that feminism incorporate the need for “the achievement of women’s individual dignity and freedom” and control over their bodies and lives, alongside “the development of a just social and economic order, nationally and internationally.”110 That said, they ultimately thought it was important to address “issues like those of poverty, cultural devaluation of women, and sexual abuse in the home” because they were “major conditions which make women and girls vulnerable to these practices [of female sexual slavery].”111 When Bunch turned to VAW and then to the woman’s human rights movement, she took with her a central focus on sexual subordination. And there, too, that focus affected the approach to economic and social rights. Indeed, the language above is strikingly similar to Bunch’s later discussion of the need for economic and social rights at the Global Tribunal and elsewhere: economic deprivation makes women vulnerable to sexual exploitation. Bunch would later say that “it was the issue of sex trafficking presented as an example of violence against women that highlighted the need to stake out women’s human rights.”112 Although it might not have been the dominant example offered by many women’s human rights advocates, the theorizing that helped construct the category of female sexual slavery made its way into VAW discussions. As Suchland argues, the VAW category is in many ways “the heir to sexual slavery—and this legacy is certainly important for understanding why such a range of issues (wife battery, trafficking, rape, prostitution, and pornography) became subjects of one composite category ‘violence against women.’”113 For Suchland, the Vienna Conference solidified rhetorically the connection between sexual violence and sex trafficking. More importantly for my purposes, it solidified the connection between VAW and sexual violence, by recognizing the former, largely defined by the latter, as the quintessential violation of women’s human rights.114 Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 43 Given the sex-positive critique, it seems that the move to narrow VAW to sexual violence should have been more controversial than it turned out to be. I have already suggested some reasons for the relative lack of controversy over the prioritization of VAW more generally: namely, the explicit attempt to choose VAW as a North-South unifying topic and the acceptance of culturally sensitive universalism. But the narrowing of VAW to sexual violence in the context of armed conflict was established a bit more stealthily. The Global Tribunal, for example, appeared to cover a number of topics, but continued to prioritize sexual harm without ever articulating the connection between it and gender-based violence as clearly as those who campaigned against female sexual slavery did (even though many of the same actors were involved). The narrowing of VAW to sexual violence was perhaps less conspicuous because it took place primarily in the context of discussions around armed conflict. The example of rape in conflict provided an opportunity to persuade official delegates to the Vienna Conference that women’s rights were human rights. Rhonda Copelon later wrote that, along with other testimonies of “gender violence,” “the very concrete fact, brought home by the participation of women from Bosnia and the former Yugoslavia, that women were being raped systematically in Bosnia—just hours from the site of the Conference—prevailed over objections to incorporating gender violence as a human rights problem.”115 Sexual violence also more easily entered the mainstream when presented in the context of armed conflict because, though no one emphasized it, that context puts sexual violence more clearly in the public sphere than many other forms of gender-based violence. It is therefore not surprising that “sexual slavery” made its way into the Vienna Declaration in reference to armed conflict. While in general, the declaration uses the language of “gender-based violence” and “violence against women,” “sexual slavery” is listed as something to be condemned in war, alongside rape and forced pregnancy.116 If the turn to sexual violence in conflict at Vienna seemed to mediate debates over culture and signal a victory for the sexual subordination strand of structuralbias feminism, it also managed another bitter division that had emerged among feminists during the months leading up to Vienna. As we see in detail in Chapter Two, feminists, mostly in the United States and the former Yugoslavia, disagreed over whether rapes by Serbs, particularly rapes of Bosnian Muslims, were qualitatively and legally different from those committed by Bosnian Muslims or Croats. In the United States, even those structural-bias feminists who focused on sexual subordination split on the issue, as illustrated by Catharine MacKinnon’s 44 Chapter 1 insistence that rapes by Serbs were uniquely genocidal and Rhonda Copelon’s forceful advocacy that rape on all sides of the conflict should be condemned. At Vienna, those on both sides of the divide largely kept to their own corners, even as they worked in their own ways to urge the conference to name sexual violence in conflict as a violation of human rights and humanitarian law. When they left Vienna, their disagreements were still alive, but, as we see in Chapter Three, the discord began to dissipate as they concentrated their efforts on ensuring that the ICTY would be responsive to wartime rape. IV. The Turn to Criminal Law In February 2013, Navanethem (Navi) Pillay, then UN High Commissioner for Human Rights, gave a speech to the General Assembly reflecting on the twenty years that had passed since the Vienna World Conference on Human Rights. She discussed three principal achievements of the Vienna Declaration, two of which were “its role in advancing women’s rights” and “its impact on the fight against impunity.”117 Regarding the first, she attributed it in part to the success of the Women’s Rights Are Human Rights campaign at the conference and the institutional gains it spawned with respect to VAW. As for the second, she noted that “perhaps most significantly, just one month after the establishment of the first ad hoc tribunal since Nuremberg [the ICTY], the Declaration nudged the International Law Commission to continue its work on a permanent international criminal court.”118 Although Pillay did not connect those two achievements—the recognition of women’s human rights and the fight against impunity through international criminal law—the two were intertwined. The ICTY turned out to be the beginning of a rapid proliferation and development of international criminal justice institutions, including the establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) in 1994 (on which Pillay served as a judge) and the International Criminal Court (ICC) in 2002, which had been opened for ratification in 1998. And some of the most vocal of the sexual subordination strand of structuralbias feminists soon turned to international criminal law as an important site of women’s human rights activism. Even before the Vienna Conference, a coalition of feminists and feminist organizations based in New York had formed a group they called the Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women. That group met regularly, as a New York Times article reported in January 1993, “to discuss how to put pressure on the international law system to bring people responsible for Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 45 rape to justice,” including by advocating for the UN to establish a war crimes tribunal.119 Charlotte Bunch, through her Center for Women’s Global Leadership, and Rhonda Copelon were both active in the coalition,120 which saw itself as having played an important role in the ICTY’s creation. Bunch would later state that the “women’s groups were more active in the formation of the new international institution than ever in history.”121 In Chapter Three, I consider in some detail the impact of women’s rights advocacy, both direct and indirect, on the jurisprudence of the ICTY. Here, I simply highlight that women’s human rights advocates began to pursue the international criminalization of sexual violence in conflict at the same time that women’s rights began to be mainstreamed as human rights. That turn to criminal law significantly affected the direction of women’s human rights advocacy in ways that we will see throughout the book. It continued to mediate a number of disagreements among feminists, while at the same time providing certain structural-bias feminists with a new means of implementing their approaches to rape and sexual violence. Indeed, it placed structural-bias feminists among those at the forefront of the development of international criminal law. This reliance on criminal law in the early 1990s was in some ways overdetermined, as feminists and human rights advocates were both headed in that direction. Indeed, in the 1980s and 1990s, as Aya Gruber has documented, U.S. feminist responses to VAW had begun to turn away from social services and progressive grassroots resistance and toward the use and promotion of criminal prosecutions.122 Although the Violence Against Women Act in 1994 was a visible representation of that turn,123 Gruber notes that feminists were in fact aligning themselves with an approach to domestic violence that had been pushed at least since 1984, in the name of “family values” and consistent with the Reagan administration’s broader war on crime.124 Some have argued that feminist critiques of the treatment of rape victims led to harsher penalties for perpetrators, at least for those accused of “stranger” rape. As Dianne Martin put it in 1998, speaking of Canada, “Reform initiatives aimed at supporting complainants fairly quickly evolved into developing means to ease the road to convictions and to increase penalties.”125 Discussing feminist law reform advocacy concerning both rape and domestic violence, she also dates some of the reforms to the mid-1980s, while recognizing that some feminists had begun to acknowledge the trend a decade earlier.126 Although Martin’s focus is Canada, she notes that “feminists around the world identified and addressed the failures of the justice system in regard to wife abuse 46 Chapter 1 in remarkably consistent ways,” so that “an almost irresistible pressure drove the movement toward criminal justice reform and solutions, and to make use of ‘law and order’ arguments to ensure that criminal justice actors will become involved.”127 Jutta Joachim describes how such a shift in attitude at the domestic level manifested internationally at the 1986 UN expert group meeting titled “Violence in the Family with Special Emphasis on Women.”128 Notwithstanding that victims of violence had, only a decade earlier, expressed considerable suspicion of state institutions and that therapy and welfare approaches were still quite prevalent, the experts called for criminal justice interventions. The choice, Joachim surmises, was not coincidental: “Involving the courts and the police had, in the eyes of the experts, symbolic significance.”129 As feminism was moving toward criminal law, so too was the human rights movement. In the early 1990s, international human rights advocates began to express concerns about “the culture of impunity” (a term rarely used before 1991).130 Those advocates would eventually argue that states had an international legal obligation to defy the culture of impunity by criminally investigating, prosecuting, and punishing non-state actors for violations of human rights. They made this argument in part on the basis of a 1988 ruling by the Inter-American Court of Human Rights. In Velásquez-Rodríguez v. Honduras,131 the Inter-American Court held the Honduran government accountable for its inaction related to the disappearance of a political activist. Even though the Honduran government denied any involvement in the disappearance, the court found that state accountability did not rest only on direct state action. Rather, the state owed “a legal duty . . . to use the means at its disposal to carry out a serious investigation of violations . . . to identify those responsible, to impose the appropriate punishment and to ensure the victim adequate compensation.”132 When the women’s human rights movement began to take off, many saw Velásquez-Rodríguez as marking a paradigm shift. Indeed, a number of scholarly articles at the time cited the case as pathbreaking, and noted its great potential use for the women’s human rights movement’s attempt to break down the public/private distinction.133 Of course, as human rights advocates began to pursue this approach to state accountability, they made themselves dependent upon some of the very same state institutions, particularly penal ones, that they had once criticized. This shift within the human rights movement was also in line with a more general trend toward international criminal institutions. Indeed, support for an international criminal court, which had waxed and waned since the end of World War II, had been on the rise since 1989. By the end of the Vienna Conference, Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 47 with the establishment of the ICTY one month earlier and with several provisions of the Vienna Declaration either condemning impunity or calling for criminal sanctions for individual rights violators,134 the future for international criminal institutions looked better than it had in decades. Structural-bias feminists emerged from the conference strengthened in their fight against sexual violence in conflict and prepared to engage with criminal justice systems, particularly international criminal institutions, in the process. As demonstrated in ensuing chapters, structural-bias feminists have in fact played a governance role in international criminal law, beginning with the ICTY, where they were successful in affecting rules of evidence and procedures as well as the interpretation of statutes, particularly with regard to charges of rape as a war crime and a crime against humanity. They also played an important interventionist role in the ICTR, helping to facilitate the first criminal conviction for rape as a constitutive act of genocide. Perhaps the most systematic feminist organizing with regard to international criminal law occurred during the drafting of the Rome Statute for the ICC. There, advocates attempted to make up for some of the flaws in, or lack of specificity about, the treatment of sexual violence that they detected in the earlier tribunals. As Janet Halley describes in significant detail, the sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism prevailed at Rome, as a feminist coalition focused its activism on sexual violence and succeeded in criminalizing a broad range of acts beyond those that earlier statutes had explicitly recognized, including “sexual slavery.”135 For Halley, the lack of disagreement among feminists was striking,136 but even more so was the “placid calm with which male international law elites from the West received this [structural feminist critique] as the voice of sweet reason about how to condemn wartime rape.”137 The criminalization impulses behind the reforms pushed in the 1990s by structural-bias feminists focused on sexual subordination—along with their understanding of the unique harm of rape and other forms of sexual violence—have largely become common sense. Their acceptance by mainstream elites can be seen in a variety of forums well beyond the ICC. One site of repeated commitment to the criminalization of rape and sexual violence in conflict is the UN Security Council, which, as I explore in Chapter Five, has passed numerous resolutions that emphasize the need to respond criminally to sexual violence.138 Another is the Group of Eight (G8), which, as I discussed in the Introduction, made sexual violence in conflict one of its main areas of focus under the presidency of the UK in 2013. 48 Chapter 1 V. Unintended Consequences: A Prelude The success of structural-bias feminists in the many efforts I have mentioned does not mean that their message was received or even eventually pursued in the ways that they might have hoped for in 1993. Even as international legal and institutional developments suggest a victory for those structural-bias feminists who saw sex as the basis of women’s oppression by men, the sexual focus of their advocacy has had long-term consequences for the understanding of rape and sexual violence that they may or may not have considered. One such consequence is that international condemnations of sexual violence generally oversimplify both sexual violence and conflict. In particular, they assume that shame and stigma necessarily accompany sexual violence in conflict, in ways that forever destroy individual victims and their communities. As we see throughout the book, that assumption often contains an ethnic dimension that brings cultural essentialization back to the fore. Furthermore, within the common sense, sexual violence is less frequently portrayed as a gender issue, or even as an issue about male domination and female subordination. Rather, it is represented as a “weapon of war” (a term initially promoted by feminists, particularly in the Bosnian context) that frightens and affects not only women and girls but also men and boys. With the move from the gendered to the sexual aspects of the violence, and the loss of connection between the two, comes a hyper-attention to sex, which might help to explain its mainstream appeal. But it should also give us pause. Seen in this way, much of the feminist work in response to sexual violence in conflict has aided in the production, or at least reinforcement, of particular types of “proper” sexuality (heterosexual, of a certain age, monogamous, within the same ethnic group, etc.). For Alice Miller, neither result was necessarily accidental. Looking back on her own role in making VAW and sexual violence central to women’s human rights advocacy, she says, “In the struggle to gain credibility for women’s human rights groups, many of us struggled to assert respectability at the price of other less respectable women. In doing so, we inadvertently used human rights terms to help reinforce (and not reconsider) the [sexual] hierarchies.”139 Importantly, feminists were not simply co-opted.140 Structural-bias feminists elevated the harm of sexual violence to the status of the principal harm to women in general, and especially in war. When they were debating other feminists, sexual violence was gender violence (and vice versa). And when they went out into the world, their language of sexual violence resonated with political and institutional actors across political, national, cultural, and religious lines. As the rest of the Sexual Violence in Conf lict and Women’s Human Rights 49 book demonstrates, structural-bias feminism has, through acquiescence and sometimes encouragement, supported military, carceral, and security regimes. Not only have these regimes failed to ameliorate, and even arguably have exacerbated, the maldistribution of global power and resources that many Third World feminists had long decried, but they have reinforced negative images of sex and sexuality—primarily, but not only, for women—as well as reductive and damaging understandings of gender and ethnicity. CHAP TE R T WO Calling in the Troops I N 19 9 2 , W H E N B O S N I A N M U S L I M W O M E N arriving in refugee camps in Croatia reported that they had been raped by Serbian men, they captured the attention of local and, eventually, international media. According to Dubravka Žarkov, “media representations of rapes and sexual assaults against women treated the female body as the map on which the new, sexual, geographies of ethnicity were drawn.”1 If the female body provided the media with the map for drawing ethnicity, ethnic conflict in the former Yugoslavia offered feminists the terrain upon which to dispute the political and legal meaning of the rapes.2 In fact, an intense debate ensued among feminists over a number of issues. Most prominently, they disagreed about whether at least some of the rapes were genocidal and, relatedly, whether the rapes by Serbs differed from those perpetrated by other parties to the conflict. This debate took place largely within the sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism. It brought to light significant differences within the strand over two issues, at least in the context of that conflict: first, whether and how ethnicity should affect consideration of the harm of rape; and, second, whether military intervention would be an appropriate response to the rapes. The answers to these questions were generally correlated. Some feminists began to call for outside military intervention against the Serbs, using claims of genocidal rape as justification for that response. They were sometimes opposed by those structural-bias feminists who argued against treating the rapes on one side differently from those on other sides. 50 Calling in the Troops 51 This feminist debate both implicated and affected broader debates over military intervention in Yugoslavia, including by human rights advocates. Indeed, those feminists who promoted military intervention participated in a general turn in human rights advocacy toward calls for military force to respond to serious human rights violations. Notwithstanding that attempts to achieve an international norm on military intervention have started and sputtered in subsequent years, rape has come to be one of the most commonly invoked reasons for use of force. This chapter concentrates on the very different invocations of rape in Bosnia in the early 1990s and in Libya nearly two decades later. Feminists who argued that rapes by Serbs were uniquely genocidal left a legacy beyond calls for military intervention. In making their claims, they began to forge a number of aspects of the common sense outlined in the Introduction. Rape had to constitute the “worst crime” imaginable in order to justify military intervention. And it had to be aimed at the destruction of ethnic communities (tearing them apart) to be seen as genocidal. In these early years, they focused on male-on-female rape much more than on other forms of rape or sexual violence, in part because reproduction, as we will see, was central to some of their arguments that rape was genocidal. Those feminists who sharply opposed this linkage of rape, ethnicity, and genocide—calling for equal attention to rape on all sides regardless of ethnicity—also left their mark on the common sense. They concurred that rape was the worst crime, even if they insisted it was equally harmful to those on all sides of the conflict. Further, their insistence on gender as a distinct category of oppression, regardless of nationality, helped lay the groundwork for its greater inclusion in contemporary international criminal law, as we will see. To trace the development and operation of the debates among feminists about genocidal rape and, relatedly, military intervention, we need to begin with the larger context of post–Cold War military intervention. Feminists were not alone in choosing genocide as a place to stake their claims. I. Military Humanitarian Intervention after the End of the Cold War Beginning in September 1991, the UN Security Council passed a number of resolutions regarding the former Yugoslavia.3 Early resolutions set up a large peacekeeping operation, the UN Protection Force (UNPROFOR), in Croatia and Bosnia.4 Subsequent resolutions imposed a variety of sanctions and declared 52 Chapter 2 “safe” areas under UNPROFOR’s protection.5 But for the most part, the UN and the NATO members that contributed forces to UNPROFOR resisted calls for direct strikes by UNPROFOR and discouraged NATO from acting on its own until mid-1995 when, with UNPROFOR support, NATO engaged in Operation Deliberate Force.6 All of these resolutions followed significant disagreement among and within Security Council member states over whether military intervention should be used to respond to the conflict. Much of that disagreement concerned whether Serbian action in Bosnia could rightly be labeled genocide. By 1992, the Security Council had labeled it “ethnic cleansing,” but not genocide.7 The choice in wording was deliberate, since some members of the Security Council believed that labeling something “genocide” would mean committing themselves to military intervention. Some states turned to the UN General Assembly to encourage the Security Council to go further. Those states achieved the passage of a resolution that not only called Serbian aggression ethnic conflict, but named ethnic cleansing “a form of genocide.”8 The resolution used that finding of genocide to urge the Security Council to authorize the use of “all necessary means” under Chapter VII of the UN Charter, which provides for coercive sanctions including the use of force, to ensure that Serbia and Montenegro comply with Security Council resolutions.9 Even though the United States voted for the resolution—which, as we will see, was a shift in its position—the other permanent members of the Security Council abstained, suggesting the unlikelihood that the Security Council would authorize such intervention.10 Security Council–authorized military intervention in this case was only even conceivable due to the end of the Cold War. Because each of the five permanent members of the Security Council holds veto power over any substantive resolution, the Cold War disagreements had produced a stalemate that generally precluded any significant action by the Security Council labeled as military. In the early 1990s, in contrast, the council was ripe for calls for military intervention. Most pleas for that intervention foregrounded humanitarian justifications, even though Chapter VII permits use of force only for self-defense or when organized under the authority of the Security Council to “maintain or restore international peace and security.”11 While humanitarian reasons had been given to bolster military interventions in an earlier era as well (Belgium in the Congo in 1960, United States in the Dominican Republic in 1965), those actions primarily relied upon the established justification of self-defense. Calling in the Troops 53 In the post–Cold War era, those who advocated for military intervention on the basis of humanitarian grounds often stated their case in terms of human rights. Many liberals as well as conservatives—especially, but not only, in the United States—adopted this approach, representing a shift for both groups. Conservatives began to turn to human rights, even women’s human rights, discourse to justify military intervention, and liberals began to use military discourse and rhetoric to show their commitment to human rights.12 For many “humanrights hawks,” as some liberals would later call themselves,13 treaty-based regime mechanisms, UN reports and rapporteurs, Human Rights Council investigations and condemnations, and even the international criminal tribunals being advocated at the time all seemed to pale in comparison to the ultimate enforcement regime—military intervention premised on humanitarian reasons. With regard to the former Yugoslavia, both state and non-state actors who argued for military intervention generally articulated their pleas not only in humanitarian or human rights terms but by specifically invoking genocide. Genocide, they contended, constituted a legitimate basis—if not a demand—for military intervention. Indeed, the question of whether what was happening in the former Yugoslavia could be labeled genocidal was key to U.S. decisions about the role it would play in promoting military intervention there. Samantha Power—who would become U.S. ambassador to the UN in the Obama administration, and who has advocated for a number of military interventions over the past two decades—has detailed the debate in the early 1990s surrounding the “g-word,” noting that opponents of intervention were careful not to discuss the conflict in terms of genocide.14 Prior to voting for the General Assembly resolution mentioned above, according to Power, “the Bush administration assiduously avoided using the word. ‘Genocide’ was shunned because a genocide finding would create a moral imperative.”15 As a result, Power explained, officials opposing intervention spoke in terms of ethnic cleansing: “[National Security Advisor Brent] Scowcroft believes genocide would have demanded a U.S. response, but ethnic cleansing, which is the label he uses for what occurred in Bosnia, did not.”16 Scowcroft justified his choice of terms by saying that “there is something of a national interest in preventing genocide because the United States needs to appear to be upholding international law.”17 Given this reluctance, the U.S. vote in favor of the General Assembly resolution naming ethnic cleansing as a form of genocide seemed to signal a shift for the Bush administration. But it came one month before the end of Bush’s term, and it was matched by ambiguous statements by members of his administration. 54 Chapter 2 Power points, for example, to a statement made by Patricia Diaz Dennis, the Assistant Secretary of State for Human Rights and Humanitarian Affairs during the final five months of the administration, in which—in Power’s words—she “equivocated unintelligibly.” The statement read in part: In Bosnia, our report describes widespread systematic atrocities, including the rapes and killings of civilian victims to the extent that it probably borders on genocide. We haven’t yet decided whether or not it’s a legal matter. The conduct in Bosnia is genocide, but clearly the abuses that have occurred there over the last year are such that they, as I said, border on that particular term.18 Even if equivocal, the statement confirms Scowcroft’s understanding of the consequences of a (legal) genocide finding, and it demonstrates how reports of rape can be used to support claims of genocide—a point to which I will return. The Clinton administration proved similarly reluctant to call the conflict in Bosnia “genocidal.” John Shattuck, then Assistant Secretary of State for Democracy, Human Rights, and Labor, has since explained that he was unable to get clearance from the State Department to use the term “genocide” to refer to events in Bosnia or Rwanda because of the “reluctance of U.S. policymakers to confront the responsibility of countries that had ratified the Genocide Convention ‘to prevent and punish’ crimes determined to constitute genocide.”19 Both Shattuck and Power refer to a 1994 State Department memorandum that cautioned against even investigating possible Genocide Convention violations, given the department’s reading of the obligations of the United States as a signatory to the convention: “Be careful. Legal at State was worried about this yesterday—genocide finding could commit the U.S. government to actually ‘do something.’”20 Those within the Clinton administration who did argue openly that genocide was taking place in the former Yugoslavia did so precisely with the hope of stimulating a military response. These officials included many human rights hawks, whose pressure for military intervention was especially intense prior to the establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY). Even though they would soon turn their efforts toward strengthening the ICTY, they aimed to keep the possibility of military intervention alive. As Shattuck puts it, “The United States would never be able to play more than a limited role in Bosnia so long as the deployment of U.S. ground forces continued to be ruled out.”21 While international criminal law became the principal agreed-upon way for the Security Council to respond to Bosnia, at least until the three-week-long Calling in the Troops 55 Operation Deliberate Force in 1995, and the preferred response in many other places, military intervention and advocacy for it based on human rights violations have not disappeared. UN member states and officials continue to debate about proper responses to particular cases of conflict, as well as about the parameters of the Responsibility to Protect (R2P), an attempt to set forth guidelines for when states can or should intervene individually or collectively in states that have failed to protect their own citizens.22 The UN’s own failures to prevent the Rwandan genocide as well as ongoing debates about whether the Security Council should have authorized more military intervention in the Balkans, the latter of which came to a head in 1999 when NATO intervened in Kosovo without such authorization, provided much of the impetus for R2P. The principal document outlining R2P in 2001 reflects that history, with genocide and “large scale ‘ethnic cleansing’” constituting the two accepted bases for military intervention.23 As we will see, rape and sexual violence are often central to such claims. II. Feminist Debates over the Meaning of Rape in the Yugoslavian Conflict In an award-winning New York Times column from March 1993, Anna Quindlen called for the United States to consider intervening militarily in Bosnia in light of what she called “gynocide.” That term appeared in the title of the piece, and functioned as an answer to a question she posed amidst details of some of the rapes of Bosnian Muslim women: “Is a particularly sophisticated and brutal form of genocide going on in the former Yugoslavia, which relies on the psychosexual destruction of those who would bear the next generation of Bosnian Muslims, so hated by the warring Serbs?”24 She went on to write, “We women once liked to think that if we ran the world, there might be less emphasis on brute strength. But pacifism suddenly seems a pallid ideal beside these stories. And the timidity of American policy seems ill-suited to this brutality.”25 By naming the rapes genocidal, invoking that genocide to suggest the need for U.S. military intervention, and rejecting a nonviolent response, Quindlen aligned herself with one side of a debate among feminists about how to understand and respond to the rapes that were occurring during conflict in the former Yugoslavia. This debate consumed significant attention and, as I have already suggested, bitterly divided feminists—not only over the meaning of rape, but also over whether and how to demand military intervention in the conflict. Feminists who labeled as genocidal the rapes by Serbian men of Bosnian Muslim—and early on, Croatian—women, took what I call the “genocidal-rape 56 Chapter 2 position.” Especially in their treatment of Bosnian Muslim women, they engaged in some of the very types of representation that many Third World feminists had critiqued in the debates considered in Chapter One. In particular, they treated Bosnian Muslim women as passive victims of oppression, not only by Serbian men but by Bosnian Muslim men as well. In doing so, they relied upon biological and cultural essentialisms. Feminists who opposed them took what I call the “rape-on-all-sides” position, claiming that the genocide formulation failed to address rapes perpetrated by and committed against those on other sides of the conflict. Some also opposed the deployment of the formulation to call for military intervention. The rape-on-all-sides position, however, did little to challenge either the treatment of Bosnian Muslim women as overwhelmingly victimized or the ethnic assumptions behind that treatment. These assumptions deserve our careful attention not only for their role in the former Yugoslavia, but also for the ways in which they eventually become part of the common sense about sexual violence in conflict. A. Genocidal Rape versus Rape on All Sides Catharine MacKinnon’s primary entry into the discussion of human rights and humanitarian law came during the early days of conflict in the former Yugoslavia.26 MacKinnon recounts that she was approached in 1992 by “Bosnian and Croatian survivors of Serbian genocidal sexual atrocities,” who asked her to “represent them in seeking what they called ‘international justice.’”27 According to Natalie Nenadic, she, Asja Armanda, and the organization Kareta (of which Armanda was a founding member) enlisted MacKinnon with the aim of addressing what they had theorized as “femicide,” a concept that “contains genocide, and in addition something more.”28 Part of that “something more” included mass rape and other sexual atrocities, as well as the production of “film footage of genocidal sexual atrocities—the pornography of genocide.”29 Although some argued that the reports of pornography were exaggerated or at least unproven,30 they were important for MacKinnon, who used them as a reason for her involvement and made them a key part of her analysis of the situation.31 That MacKinnon, along with Andrea Dworkin, took the pornography seriously was important for Nenadic, who wrote that MacKinnon “is the first major theorist of modern feminism who understood that Femicide is happening in Bosnia-Hercegovina and Croatia and has been theoretically accountable.”32 Inside and outside of the United States, MacKinnon soon became one of the most vocal proponents of the position that the rapes perpetrated by Serbs Calling in the Troops 57 in the Balkans were “genocidal.”33 She did so in part by serving as counsel in a U.S. civil lawsuit against Radovan Karadžić.34 She also supported the development of the ICTY. Both avenues were meant to respond to what she considered a “legal abdication” by states. In addition to the legal abdication, she contended that there was a “military one,” echoing the position that a finding of genocide was endowed with both legal and military consequences. By not intervening “to stop the genocide on the ground,” she argued, “the international community was largely denying that the conflagration was genocide at all.” This denial, in turn, “was driven by a desire to avoid the consequence of admitting that it was genocide: mandatory intervention.” In short, for MacKinnon, “Serbian aggression in the region was not being called a genocide in law or in fact not because it wasn’t, but because no one wanted to have to face them to stop it.”35 To make an argument for intervention based on genocidal rape, MacKinnon articulated an international legal understanding of rape that would distinguish the wartime rapes committed by Serbs from other wartime rapes and even from “everyday” rapes outside of conflict and post-conflict situations. Her insistence on those distinctions played a central role in the ensuing heated debate among feminists. The controversy concerned not only the meaning and harm of rape more broadly, but also its use in shaping sides in the conflict and its consequences for intervention. For ease of discussion, I call MacKinnon’s position the genocidal-rape position, but it is the fact that it holds rapes perpetrated by only one side of the conflict as genocidal that often distinguishes it from other positions. MacKinnon rhetorically asked: “If all men do this all the time, especially in war, how can one pick a side in this one? And since all men do this all the time, war or no war, why do anything special about this now? This war becomes just a form of business as usual.” Her response: “But genocide is not business as usual—not even for men.”36 This reliance on ethnicity to differentiate between the harm of everyday rape (in or out of war) and genocidal rape, or between rapes committed by different groups in war, was arguably in tension with MacKinnon’s own structural-bias position that saw sex as the organizing structure of (gender) oppression. It also seemed to go against her general tendency to challenge these types of demarcations. In the 1980s, for instance, she argued that the legal distinction between everyday heterosexual intercourse and rape was a product of male dominance and experience, and was therefore inherently suspect.37 Although she has never disavowed her arguments about genocidal rape in the former Yugoslavia, much 58 Chapter 2 of her work has turned back to a near-exclusive focus on gender oppression, even in discussions of rape and other sexual violence against women. Indeed, she has since argued that sexual subordination can be thought of as genocidal, even “outside war and genocide,” because it destroys women as a “people.” She even suggests the genocide might already have been successful, with women “so destroyed . . . as never to have been thought of as a ‘people’ at all. Women are thus created as a destroyed group in part through sexual abuse.”38 Those feminists taking the rape-on-all-sides position vehemently disagreed with MacKinnon. Rhonda Copelon, for example, argued that “to emphasize as unparalleled [which many had done] the horror of genocidal rape is factually dubious and risks rendering rape invisible once again.”39 For Copelon, “women are targets not simply because they ‘belong to’ the enemy. . . . They are targets because they too are the enemy . . . because rape embodies male domination and female subordination.”40 Susan Brownmiller agreed: “Balkan women, whatever their ethnic and religious background, and in whatever fighting zone they happen to find themselves, have been thrust against their will into another identity. They are victims of rape in war.”41 In fact, this dispute among feminists was not so much about whether rape had been used as an instrument of genocide as about whether a focus on genocidal rape—attached to one side in the conflict—functioned to downplay the extent to which all women raped during war, and even outside of war, were victims. Copelon, for example, never argued that were rape to be found to have been used as an instrument of genocide, it should not be specially prosecuted as such. In fact, in suggestions that she would later make to the ICTY through a widely circulated memorandum, Copelon left open the possibility that rape could be prosecuted as an act of genocide, even though her primary aim was to see the recognition of widespread rape as a crime against humanity based on gender.42 And, as we see in Chapter Four, she played an important role in the first international legal case to find acts of rape to be genocidal. At one level, the deepening association between rape and genocide in mainstream discourse benefited both feminist positions, as it helped build the common-sense notion that rape is the worst crime committed during conflict. If rape was genocidal, it could be used to call for military intervention. But even for those who did not want military intervention, the association helped secure a place for rape at the very top of the list of harms. It suggested that what was happening exceeded “normal” oppression. It was a crisis situation, requiring an extraordinary response. Calling in the Troops 59 At another level, particularly within the former Yugoslavia, whether one spoke primarily of genocidal rape by Serbs or of rape on all sides established one’s stance in relation to a fraught political divide. According to Jelena Batinić, some feminist groups, which she calls the “patriotic” or “nationalist” branches, prioritized their national affiliations over women’s solidarity. Other groups, which she calls “nonnationalist” or “antinationalist,” argued for women’s solidarity across nationalities.43 Obrad Kesić describes how the division manifested itself at two international meetings in Zagreb early in the war.44 At one of those meetings, organizers and the press attacked Croatian feminists for contending that those who called for attention to rape on all sides should be condemned for “aiding the Serbian aggressors because they failed to single out ‘Croatian’ and ‘Muslim’ women as the victims.”45 At the second meeting, which was on women’s solidarity, Kareta and other groups that Batinić identifies as patriotic criticized the meeting for its perceived neutrality. According to Kesić, “they came to the congress with the hope of passing a resolution that would condemn Serbian aggression and specifically name Muslim and Croatian women as the principal victims.”46 These debates put Serbian feminists in a difficult position, especially those who were anti-war, extremely critical of the Serbian government, and even felt responsibility for harm being done in their name. One of the most outspoken groups of Serbian feminists was the anti-militarist group Women in Black. From its founding in October 1991, the group identified the Serbian government as the aggressor, saying that “the Serbian regime and its repressive structures (Federal Army and paramilitary formation) are responsible for all three wars in Slovenia, Croatia and Bosnia-Herzegovina.”47 Refusing the patriotic position and even intentionally taking on the role of a “traitor” to their nation,48 they stressed the importance of women’s solidarity across national lines and expressed “sad[ness] that some of our sisters from Croatia . . . do not want to communicate with us anymore.”49 That said, Women in Black opposed the genocidal-rape position, contending succinctly that distinguishing among perpetrators, but more importantly among victims, was problematic and ran counter to women’s interests: “We refuse the politics of instrumentalization of victims. A victim is a victim, and to her the number of other victims does not decrease her own suffering and pain.”50 They held silent protests that demonstrated this concern for harms suffered on all sides of the war, dressing in black in mourning “for the death of all victims of war” as well as for refugees and victims of rape.51 In their written protests, they “demanded the return of all recruits and reserve troopers from war-affected 60 Chapter 2 areas” and voiced their support for “the men who refused to participate in all military formations . . . above all in the aggressor army . . . as well as in the armies of the aggressed countries.”52 In her prologue to Mass Rape, a 1994 collection of essays containing versions of many of the pieces I discuss in this chapter, feminist filmmaker Helke Sander wrote a fictional letter to Lysistrata, in which she complained about the lack of solidarity among women (not only feminists) in the former Yugoslavia. Lysistrata is the character who, according to Aristophanes’ eponymous comedy, ended the Peloponnesian War by persuading women on both sides to deny their own men sex as long as they were at war. Sander contrasted the solidarity in the ancient Greek play with the lack of solidarity among women in the former Yugoslavia: “You women of Athens and Sparta, kin to hostile groups of men, spoke with one another.” In the former Yugoslavia, although women “are not the ideologues of nationalism, . . . unlike you they scarcely speak to one another anymore, and instead play the role of their husbands’ cheerleaders. It was not always like that.”53 Sander went on to explain that in the beginning, there was strong resistance from women in both Croatia and Serbia but that the “propaganda machinery” succeeded: “Earlier, women had the right political instinct, but they were inexperienced and easy to manipulate.”54 By denying, on the one hand, that the Croatian and Serbian women were nationalist ideologues, even claiming they had the “right political instinct,” and insisting, on the other hand, that the instinct gave way to manipulation, Sander at once acknowledged and negated the women’s political agency. Her claim that women took on nationalist views merely as their husbands’ cheerleaders is hard to reconcile with a 1994 survey that found that Serbian women were more nationalist than Serbian men.55 Had she attempted to recognize women as promoters of nationalism on their own volition, Sander would have better understood the dynamics of the war, including the elusiveness of feminist, let alone female, solidarity. Some of the disagreement among feminists manifested itself in other debates, as many feminists seemed to understand that contending that one side of the conflict was engaged in genocide or even ethnic cleansing might constitute soliciting military intervention. Kareta and other patriotic groups, including one in Bosnia, published a 1993 open letter in the U.S. feminist periodical off our backs, appealing to American feminists to understand that rapes by Serbs constituted part of “a Serbian policy of genocide against non-Serbs.” For them, non-Serbian women “are not only tortured by rape as are all women, but are Calling in the Troops 61 being raped . . . on the basis of their sex and ethnicity both.” Importantly, they insisted, “this is not happening to all women.”56 The appeal to label the rapes genocidal often went hand in hand with a call for intervention. Journalist Alexandra Stiglmayer noted at the time, “Bosnian and Croatian feminists contend that the mass rapes of their countrywomen are an attempt at genocide, unique in the history of rapes, and many of them demand military intervention to rescue the women.”57 Whether or not patriotic groups in Bosnia and Croatia explicitly called for military intervention, their arguments about genocidal rape as well as their debates with other feminists certainly provided fodder for those who did. MacKinnon, for example, condemned those feminists who she said refused to take sides in the war, often as part of a “blanket critique of ‘nationalism,’” as being involved in a “cover-up” that functioned “to exonerate the rapists and to deflect intervention.”58 Elsewhere, she asserted that certain Croatian feminist groups “act as the collaborators [with Serb forces] by trying to hide what it is all about.”59 She also had a well-known exchange with a Serbian feminist at the 1993 UN World Conference on Human Rights in Vienna: MacKinnon is reported to have responded to a question posed by Nadežda Ćetković with, “If you are in opposition to the regime in Serbia, why aren’t you already dead?”60 In her genocidal-rape arguments, MacKinnon invoked the Holocaust. If genocide is the clearest and most commonly agreed-upon justification for military intervention, the Holocaust provides for many the clearest and most commonly agreed-upon example of genocide. Using this association, MacKinnon asserted: “These rapes are to everyday rape what the Holocaust was to everyday anti-Semitism. Without everyday anti-Semitism a Holocaust is impossible, but anyone who has lived through a pogrom knows the difference.”61 Beverly Allen also referenced the Holocaust in her criticism of the failure of Western Europe and the United States “to take decisive military action”62 as “a clear sign of the crisis, if not the end, of moral and ethical systems upon which Western democratic institutions have been based.”63 In her appeal, Allen favorably quoted a Sarajevan who likened the “sending of humanitarian aid to Sarajevo with no military intervention” to “sending Spam to Auschwitz.”64 Anna Quindlen, whose call for intervention began this chapter, was somewhat ambivalent about equating “gynocide” in the former Yugoslavia, as she labeled it, with the Holocaust, noting that “comparisons are odious, and comparisons with the Holocaust impossible.”65 At the same time, she followed that very sentence with: “But we should not want to contemplate yet another occasion 62 Chapter 2 on which a vulnerable people were exterminated and we Americans read the handwriting on the wall as though we were illiterate.”66 Those who opposed military intervention often expressed concern about the ways in which rapes by Serbs (whether or not seen as genocidal) were being used to call for intervention. Jerome Shestack, chair of the International League for Human Rights, a U.S.-based human rights group that had been involved in a UN investigation of war crimes, including rape, noted at the time that “there is a danger that the issue of rape will be used as a propaganda tool by the Croatians to draw the U.S. into this war.”67 In paraphrasing his argument and contextualizing it in disagreements about how many rapes had occurred and by which sides to the conflict, the Philadelphia Inquirer stated that, for Shestack, “to argue about who is most culpable . . . is to miss the point and invite military intervention.”68 Although the Security Council used its Chapter VII powers to authorize a number of interventions in the former Yugoslavia, it did so without ever definitively stating that genocide had occurred. Its major intervention was the establishment of an international criminal tribunal, rather than the authorization of the kind of military force that many advocates had called for. As Chapter Three demonstrates, even though the ICTY never convicted anyone of rape as a constitutive act of genocide, many of the genocidal-rape arguments made their way into the common sense about rape in conflict, both inside and outside of Bosnia. B. Genocidal Rape and Ethnic Essentialism Whether or not they deployed an analogy to the Holocaust or called for military intervention, feminists who took the genocidal-rape position manifested various understandings of the term “genocide,” with the result that multiple ideas took hold then about how rape could be genocidal. I look at some of those understandings here with an eye toward the implicit conceptions of genetic and cultural difference operant in discourse about Bosnian Muslims and Serbs, especially in the insistence that they are distinct, pure, and mutually exclusive groups. I also consider the conceptions about Bosnian Muslim communities, particularly their anticipated shaming and ostracization of rape victims and of any children conceived through those rapes. Together, these views provided some of the cornerstones for the emerging international common sense about sexual violence in conflict, even as they managed to elude Third World feminist critiques. To begin to disentangle the various grounds on which rapes by Serbs were characterized as genocidal, we need to review the generally accepted legal definition of genocide, found in Article II of the 1948 Genocide Convention. The Calling in the Troops 63 definition has two parts. The first requires the intent to destroy “in whole or in part, a national, ethnical, racial or religious group.” Note that gender is not a protected category under the definition, a matter that a number of feminists have criticized.69 The second part of the definition specifies the acts that—when committed with such intent—are genocidal. Those acts are: “(a) Killing members of the group; (b) Causing serious bodily or mental harm to members of the group; (c) Deliberately inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical destruction in whole or in part; (d) Imposing measures intended to prevent births within the group; (e) Forcibly transferring children of the group to another group.”70 Although many taking the genocidal-rape position did not explicitly refer to the convention, their arguments nevertheless were connected at some level to this definition. Because the ICTY and all other international criminal tribunals later incorporated the Genocide Convention’s definition into their statutes, these various articulations of the relationship between rape and genocide—even if not always precisely tailored to fit the convention’s definition—became important for the legal arguments made in international criminal law and for the resulting jurisprudence. Feminists made a number of different types of arguments about how rape might constitute an act of genocide, but two are most relevant for my discussion here because of the ways in which they portrayed the biological and cultural effects of rape.71 The first claims that the intended reproductive consequences of rape make it genocidal, while the second finds the genocidal intent of rape in beliefs that the act of rape will destroy communities. With regard to the first type of argument, Charli Carpenter notes that “evidence of a systematic policy of forced impregnation punctuated and supported” many attempts to classify rape as genocide.72 Some contended that forced impregnation constituted an act of genocide by “intending to prevent births within a group” under Article II(d) of the Genocide Convention. Those who relied on this ground contended that when a Muslim woman was forced to carry a child (or fetus) that resulted from a rape by a Serb, her womb was “occupied” by the enemy, making her “incapable of conceiving and bearing a child of her own ethnicity.”73 They often pointed to reports that women were detained after they became pregnant until a time by which it was too late for them to get abortions.74 As Carpenter explains in a critical discussion of this and related arguments, including some that invoked Article II(e) of the Genocide Convention to claim that the impregnations constituted forcible transfers of children from 64 Chapter 2 one group to another, the child was considered to be “explicitly not Muslim; she is not her mother’s own child.”75 This idea about the occupation of the womb, of course, assumes that the mother would, in the absence of the rape, otherwise be bearing a child—and that the father of that child would be Muslim, a point I return to below. Others who asserted that genocide had been committed through forced impregnation maintained that the rapes were intended not simply to occupy a womb, but to produce Serbian children. Those children, by populating otherwise Muslim territory, would effectively take it over. Early in the conflict, MacKinnon imputed this intent to Serbs with regard to Croatian as well as Muslim women, saying the women were raped in order “to help make a Serbian state by making Serbian babies.”76 She explained that “because it is ethnic rape, the children are regarded as clean and purified: their fathers’ babies, Serbian babies. . . . The idea seems to be to create a fifth column within Croatian and Muslim society, children (all sons?) who will rise up and join their fathers.”77 For MacKinnon, Serbian ideology compelled the conclusion that children born of rapes by Serbs would be (pure) Serbian. For others, Islamic law, by being patrilineal, made it so that the children would be considered Serbian by Bosnian Muslims themselves.78 For the latter group, the genocidal consequences of the rape often grew out of the presumed reaction of Muslim communities to those children. For all the discussion of forced impregnation, relatively few pregnancies are estimated to have resulted from the rapes, and even fewer to have resulted in births.79 Nevertheless, the pregnancies or claims of attempted pregnancies constituted an important part of the genocidal-rape argument, providing insight into problematic assumptions—sometimes genetic—about ethnic and religious identity that many advocates helped perpetuate. At first glance, it might seem that if children resulted from the rapes, there would be more, not fewer, offspring of Bosnian Muslims. But those who grounded their genocidal-rape argument in forced impregnation assumed that any resulting children would necessarily be Serbian. In doing so, they turned a blind eye to the history of Bosnia that demonstrates an abundance of “mixed marriages” before the war.80 While some advocates referred at times to the offspring or potential offspring as “mixed,” they attributed the same genocidal intent and consequences to the rapes—only with less explanation—as those who considered that the children were Serbian.81 Further, feminists arguing that the rapes were genocidal based on the ethnicity of the offspring generally failed to acknowledge Calling in the Troops 65 or take seriously evidence that during and after the war some religious leaders encouraged Bosnian Muslim women to raise as Muslim even those children who were conceived through rapes by Serbs. For instance, Imam Ševko Omerbašić, a Bosnian and a high-ranking Islamic authority in Croatia and Slovenia, insisted that the Islamic community would work to change men’s attitudes, noting, “Our women and girls . . . have experienced violence, and our community has to accept them as if nothing has happened.”82 Note that these feminists’ logic about genocide does not require that the sex that resulted in impregnation was coercive. If a Serbian sperm implanted in a Muslim egg were inevitably to create a Serbian child, lack of consent would not be necessary to the outcome. Yet, wittingly or not, feminists were beginning with this argument to participate in the development of evidentiary standards for rape that forgo reliance on factual consent, arguably affecting consensual interethnic sex as well. As we will see in subsequent chapters, international criminal law now essentially infers lack of consent for charges of rape and sexual violence between combatants and civilians on different sides of a conflict. The second type of genocidal-rape argument that I focus on here did not depend upon either intended or actual reproductive consequences of rape. Rather, mapping directly onto parts of the common sense that we have seen articulated elsewhere, these arguments assumed that rapes of Bosnian Muslim women were intended to destroy the Bosnian Muslim group “in whole or in part” through the socially corrosive operation of shame. That is, they believed the rapes would cause the communities to ostracize or stigmatize rape victims, which would harm the women and tear their communities apart. Adrien Wing and Sylke Merchán specifically tied this argument to Article II(c) of the Genocide Convention, stating, “Rape on a mass scale imposes a condition on a group that helps lead to their physical and spiritual destruction.”83 Importantly, in this argument Bosnian Muslim women and their communities were thought to be uniquely harmed because they were Muslim. One writer at the time stated, “The significant stigma of rape under Muslim and Islamic law served to ‘break up families, ostracize victims, and in some cases, leads to the murder of victims by their family or communities. In many Muslim communities, rape victims are perceived as undesirable, soiled, and unfit for marriage.’”84 Kelly Askin, who later became a legal advisor to judges on the ICTY and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) from 2000 to 2002, made a similar argument about the particular harm of rape to Muslim women, although she referenced Islamic culture more than Islamic law.85 She relied upon Wing 66 Chapter 2 and Merchán to say that consequences of rape “may be ‘particularly severe in traditional, patriarchal societies, where the rape victim is often perceived as soiled and unmarriageable, thus becoming a target of social ostracism.’”86 She went on to attribute the particular severity of the consequences, again following Wing and Merchán, to the chastity that is seen as “essential to maintain family honor. Stealing the virginity of a Muslim woman, even if by rape, causes the survivor to be considered unworthy of a man, casting shame and disgrace on the entire family.”87 This line of argument, similar to that critiqued by Third World feminists in other contexts and defied in this case by the reaction of at least some Muslim religious leaders in Bosnia, contended that Bosnian Muslim women needed to be saved from their cultures and their men. Furthermore, this reasoning suggested that Bosnian Muslims played a role in their own genocide through their presumed “backward” beliefs and practices concerning rape. Wing and Merchán cited a variety of secondary sources, some broadly about Islamic law and Muslim culture and some about particular contexts, though more about Palestine than Bosnia. At one point, they noted that the Muslim community in Bosnia has a “somewhat more liberal attitude” about intermarriage than would be suggested by its prohibition in Islamic law, but they did not use that to question any of their other claims about Islamic law or culture, or their arguments that the rapes were genocidal.88 Similarly, Askin included in a footnote that “some of the Muslims in the Yugoslav territory had become less fundamentalist . . . over the years.” Remarkably, she then wrote “nevertheless” and, to support her broader position, offered one story of a young Balkan Muslim woman who, during World War II, said she preferred death to rape.89 By casting Muslim culture—and Islamic law—as rigid and immutable, those who made genocidal-rape claims relied upon an assumption about what Žarkov has identified as the “greater-than-standard shame” of “raped Muslim women.” She characterizes this assumption as “a recreation of an Orientalist myth of a conservative Muslim community that is cruel to its women, even with evidence to the contrary.”90 Žarkov favorably discusses the work of political scientist Cheryl Benard, who “wrote that while working with raped Muslim women she ‘found no evidence to support the idea that Bosnian victims of rape or families reacted differently from other European victims and families’ and found most Bosnian ‘families have been highly supportive.’”91 In their dependence upon this “greater than shame” narrative, many taking the genocidal-rape position once again failed Calling in the Troops 67 to make room for the possibility that communities might respond differently from the ways suggested by the stereotypes about them and their cultures. C. Shared Assumption: The Force of Shame At the same time that feminists disagreed bitterly about whether rapes in Bosnia were properly characterized as genocidal, they also agreed on many of the assumptions about shame and stigmatization that we have just seen. In fact, these assumptions were pervasive, perhaps already a part of the common sense for feminists and non-feminists alike. Many of the ideas of shame and stigma that supported the genocidal-rape arguments were also used to make the sometimes less controversial claim about ethnic cleansing, in official as well as advocacy and scholarly discourses. The UN Special Rapporteur assigned to report on the former Yugoslavia in 1993, for instance, wrote in his discussion of rape as a method of achieving ethnic cleansing that “rape has been used not only as an attack on the individual victim, but is intended to humiliate, shame, degrade and terrify the entire ethnic group.”92 At a less technical level, journalists and humanitarian workers brought to their encounters with Bosnian Muslim women many of these same stereotypes. In articulations of the connection between rape and shame, “shame” functioned as both a noun and a verb. Raped women, their families, and their communities were all treated as having been shamed and also as continuing to bear their shame. As journalists and humanitarian workers began to seek out Bosnian Muslim rape victims, they took for granted that the women would be carrying shame. Those assumptions had significant consequences, leaving Bosnian Muslim women who had been raped little room to assume any identity other than, or in addition to, being a “raped woman.”93 Further, the association of Bosnian Muslim women with rape was so strong that it left the women little room to claim that they had not been raped. Sometimes the journalists even refused to believe denials from the women themselves. In a discussion of Croatian press depictions at the time of Bosnian Muslim (as opposed to Croatian) rape victims, Žarkov explains that nearly all the articles discussed “a specific effect [rape] had on the victim: the feeling of shame.” Through media interviews with Croatian medical and psychiatric professionals, she says, “readers invariably learned that Muslim women were deeply ashamed of their experiences, that they ‘hide behind anonymity’ and ‘do not easily admit that they were raped.’”94 For Žarkov, the focus on “the mute and humiliated 68 Chapter 2 Muslim women, and on the Croat experts who provided aid” functioned to establish “the difference between all Croats and Muslims,”95 exposing Muslim women “while rendering them invisible, making them public while describing them [as] hidden, naming them anonymously.”96 This portrayal of Bosnian Muslim women was not unique to the Croatian press. In 2009, medica mondiale, a German-based women’s rights and relief NGO that began in 1993 to respond to rapes in Bosnia, issued a report surveying the media coverage from the early 1990s, including that by Roy Gutman, the U.S. journalist who won a Pulitzer prize for his early coverage of the war in Bosnia. The report concluded that “Muslim women, who had survived rapes, were thus pigeonholed as particularly coy and therefore often described as extremely silent.”97 Significantly, the report went on to present an extended argument that “the idea that the Muslim society in Bosnia-Herzegovina is particularly prone to stigmatisation is utterly wrong.”98 Yet journalists, aid workers, and legal advocates often used assumptions about shame and stigmatization to explain some of the difficulties they encountered in finding rape victims who would speak with them.99 One such journalist, Slavenka Drakulić, expressed the frustration many experienced in attempting to find victims who would acknowledge having been raped. “This silence is driving everyone crazy: reporters, feminist activists, UN officials,” she said, describing how they went into “small and crowded rooms in this or another camp in Croatia, hoping to get closer to the real picture, to hear eyewitness testimony. But in vain.” Drakulić asked, “Why won’t they talk? Don’t they know it is good for them?”100 Sometimes journalists and feminist activists refused to believe women’s explicit denials that they had been raped. Drakulić’s description of her interview of a young girl, Mersiha, typifies the dynamic: I asked Mersiha, But what about you? She looked at her mother, sitting there and listening, as if asking her for permission to say more. “No, it did not happen to me,” she said, but I doubted her. Maybe, if I came on another day, she would decide to tell me her true story. That is how it works; only patience and empathy can break the wall of self-protection.101 If female victims of rape have long encountered the difficulty of being believed, an odd reversal took place here. In Drakulić’s speculation about Mersiha’s “true story,” she refused to believe the girl who denied that she had been raped. As silence itself became a testament to the trauma of rape, it became nearly impossible for a Bosnian Muslim woman to be identified as anything other than Calling in the Troops 69 a “raped woman.” Many attributed the silence to shame. Seada Vranić, in her introduction to a book of testimonies of Bosnian rape victims, reiterated that “all of those who investigated the war rapes in Bosnia have noted that the silence of the victims was the biggest, and often invisible, obstacle to discovering the truth.” Describing that silence as her “adversary,” she explained: “Very often I felt as if I were standing in front of a wall, yet it was human beings, not bricks, that were in front of me. Human beings who were unhappy, shamed, humiliated and lost.”102 Vranić’s use of shame and humiliation (which are often treated as synonyms103) to explain women’s silence is particularly vivid, but hardly unique.104 As we will see later in this chapter, the dynamic re-emerged in the context of Libya, where many read lack of testimony as an index of widespread rape. For all of the interpretation of silence, in fact many Bosnian Muslim women did attest to being raped. As the medica mondiale report noted, “No journalist would have been able to write a single word about war rapes, if Bosnian women had not spoken about these crimes directly in front of their cameras. They talked about these crimes with openness and anger, not shame.”105 Yet once Bosnian Muslims told of being raped, many feminist activists, journalists, and health care workers treated them as hopelessly traumatized and incapable of choosing—in any meaningful sense—to engage in political or military action. When Bosnian Muslims attempted to seek revenge (by joining the army or even expressing a vengeful desire), some feminists considered them extraordinary. Stiglmayer, for example, quoted a woman who explained her reasons for wanting to join the army after being raped: “I think the main reason I put on a uniform is to get revenge . . . we have to get even somehow, not in the same way, no ’cause then we’d be no better than they are, but somehow.”106 For Stiglmayer, both this woman and a teenage girl who also joined the army after being raped were exceptions by which to underscore the rule: “Most of the rape victims are broken, not thinking about revenge, for the horror of their rape and expulsion has also taken away whatever power of resistance they might have had.”107 She even suggested that most rape victims were so powerless that they did not have anything to do with their own children.108 Thus they were powerless to fight back or to support those who depended on them. They were “broken.” For others, the desire for revenge, when it occurred, was pathological. Psychiatrist Vera Folnegović-Šmalc, for example, who worked with twenty-nine rape victims in a clinic in Zagreb, explained: “Suicidal thoughts are evident above all in women who have become pregnant as the result of rape. After an induced abortion, the symptoms change, and depression is replaced by aggression and the 70 Chapter 2 wish for revenge.”109 This type of account allows very little chance of meaningful agency for women who have been raped. Instead, it sees them as plagued by one or another of the illnesses that wartime rapes purportedly inflict upon women. Note that what Folnegović-Šmalc sees in both cases are symptoms—terminology that assumes a disorder.110 The shared feminist assumption about the force of shame, including the silence it dictates, has had incredible staying power as an important element of the common sense. Indeed, we see it in every subsequent chapter of this book, articulated by activists, lawyers, judges, and UN and state representatives. III. The Military Stakes of Finding Rape: The Case of Libya Advocates for military intervention have continued to invoke rape as a justification. In the early 2000s, for example, many who argued for military intervention in Darfur emphasized allegations of mass rape. In doing so, they promoted and relied upon a public association of the conflict in Darfur with rape as well as genocide. The genocide connection, whether stated or implied, made for a more forceful argument, given that the 2001 document outlining R2P offered genocide and largescale ethnic cleansing as justifications for military intervention.111 The UN Security Council ultimately refused either to declare a genocide in Darfur or to authorize military intervention,112 although it referred the case to the ICC, which eventually issued an arrest warrant for Omar Hassan Ahmad al Bashir for, among other things, rape as genocide.113 And while many feminists and human rights hawks soon turned to international criminal law as a primary means of responding to widespread human rights violations, some persisted in their advocacy for military intervention, with accusations of rape, even in the absence of claims of genocide, continuing to play a central role. Such accusations were key to the Security Council–sanctioned military intervention in Libya, and to U.S. participation in it. In 2011, the UN Security Council once again found itself contemplating the appropriate response to widespread violations of human rights, this time in the Libyan Arab Jamahiriya. Sporadic protests against Mohammar Gaddafi’s regime had been under way in Libya for more than a year, but had surged to the attention of the UN and international media in January and February. In those months, clashes between anti-Gaddafi protesters and government security forces led to harsh reprisals and imprisonment of opposition leaders in what would soon develop into full-fledged civil war. Reports of the government’s repression of the civilian population soon began to talk of rape, including rumors that Calling in the Troops 71 Gaddafi’s troops were being issued Viagra, a brand-name drug used to induce erections in men. These rumors once again gave sexual violence a significant place in debates about military intervention, with pro-intervention voices employing some of the arguments about the harm of rape that were developed in the context of the former Yugoslavia. Following particularly explosive events in Benghazi and elsewhere, on February 26, 2011, the UN Security Council passed Resolution 1970, condemning human rights and humanitarian law violations by the Libyan government. Invoking Libya’s responsibility to protect its population, the Security Council first turned to international criminal law, referring the situation to the prosecutor of the ICC.114 But by March 17, the Security Council followed its call for international criminal investigation with Resolution 1973, which condemned “gross and systematic violation of human rights.”115 Again using the language of R2P, it reiterated “the responsibility of the Libyan authorities to protect the Libyan population,” but this time it authorized member states to “take all necessary measures to protect civilians,” effectively sanctioning the use of force in Libya.116 Specifically, Resolution 1973 set up a no-fly zone and authorized air strikes to enforce it.117 Despite the increase in calls for R2P over the preceding decade, the Libyan intervention became the first UN-authorized use of force in the territory of an unwilling state on explicitly stated humanitarian grounds. Though the violence in Libya was rarely labeled genocidal, the ghost of the Rwandan genocide of 1994—and the failure of the United States to intervene— haunted a debate within the Obama administration about how to respond to the unfolding crisis in Libya. A number of high-level officials discouraged a military response, warning that even a no-fly zone would require significant military involvement and could have costly long-term economic and strategic consequences.118 They ultimately lost to the proponents of military intervention. One of the strongest of those proponents was Samantha Power, who was at that point a senior aide at the National Security Council and who, we should recall, had criticized U.S. foreign policy for its failures to intervene militarily in Bosnia and Rwanda. The other was Susan Rice, then U.S. ambassador to the UN, who had been an advisor to President Clinton on Africa during the Rwandan genocide.119 Rice was widely reported to have said: “I swore to myself that if I ever faced such a crisis again, I would come down on the side of dramatic action, going down in flames if that was required.”120 Secretary of State Hillary Clinton joined forces with Power and Rice, announcing the day after Resolution 1973 passed that the United States was willing 72 Chapter 2 to support (if not lead) military action against Libya.121 Promptly thereafter, President Obama authorized the U.S. Navy and Air Force to fire into Libya, in accordance with the Security Council’s resolution.122 On March 21, he invoked the War Powers Resolution to notify Congress of his actions, which meant that— were he to act in strict accordance with that law—the authorization would expire sixty days after the notice, on May 19, 2011.123 Several commentators observed that the divide in the administration over intervention had largely broken down along lines of gender.124 Maureen Dowd began her column in the New York Times on the topic: “They are called the Amazon Warriors, the Lady Hawks, the Valkyries. There is something positively mythological about a group of strong women swooping down to shake the president out of his delicate sensibilities and show him the way to war.” She continued: “Everyone is fascinated with the gender flip: the reluctant men—the generals, the secretary of defense, top male White House national security advisers—outmuscled by the fierce women around President Barack Obama urging him to man up against crazy Gadhafi.” The flip was about more than gender, though, as evidenced in Dowd’s additional observation: “How odd to see the diplomats as hawks and the military as doves.”125 Curiously, but perhaps revealing the ghost of Rwanda, the New York Times titled Dowd’s column “Fearful of Next Genocide: Women Lead U.S. to Libya,” though there was no mention of genocide in the piece and little in the general discourse about Libya. Indeed, for all the earlier debates about whether to label certain conduct genocidal—with either the hope or the fear that doing so would lead to intervention—the Libya case suggested that the Obama administration placed less emphasis on the “genocide” label than had previous administrations. And although women in the administration, including self-avowed feminists, promoted military intervention, they did not make sexual violence central to their justification. But as the Libya intervention unfolded, the Obama administration faced a range of criticisms, on the one hand targeting its limited objectives—decidedly not to oust Colonel Mohammar Gaddafi from power—and on the other alleging that it had exceeded its mandate and should have sought congressional reauthorization to continue its intervention.126 Within these criticisms, sexual violence became a part of the story in ways both familiar and novel. On March 26, 2011, Eman al-Obeidi, a recent Libyan law graduate, stormed into a hotel restaurant in Tripoli to tell foreign reporters that she had been abducted at a checkpoint and gang-raped by government troops. Security guards at the hotel immediately dragged her away, despite attempts by the journalists to stop them. The ordeal became an international story, about both the lack of freedom Calling in the Troops 73 of expression in Libya and the extent to which rapes by government troops, and perhaps even rebel troops, were occurring.127 A few days after the event, columnist Nicholas Kristof used al-Obeidi’s story to respond to some critics of the intervention who argued that “we don’t have an exit plan, that [Obama] hasn’t articulated a grand strategy, that our objectives are fuzzy, [and] that Islamists could gain strength.” While acknowledging the legitimacy of some of the criticisms, Kristof nevertheless lauded the intervention for the rapes he presumed it prevented: “If we had not intervened in Libya, Qaddafi forces would have reached Benghazi and there might have been thousands of Eman al-Obeidys.”128 By the end of April, some diplomats and the press began to pay attention to war crimes being committed by rebel forces in Libya—the same forces the intervention was meant to aid. As with Bosnia, supporters of intervention felt compelled to distinguish rapes committed by different sides of the conflict. Indeed, The Guardian reported that, in response to some who suggested in a closed UN Security Council meeting that there was a moral equivalence between those crimes committed by Gaddafi forces and those perpetrated by rebels, Ambassador Rice claimed that Colonel Gaddafi was “supplying his troops with Viagra to encourage mass rape.”129 That claim had surfaced a month earlier in a report by Al Jazeera that “several doctors [said] they have found Viagra tablets and condoms in the pockets of dead pro-Gaddafi fighters, alleging that they were using rape as a weapon of war.”130 The accusation was also repeated by the Daily Mail.131 For Ambassador Rice, claims of Viagra use and “mass rape” as tools in the war functioned similarly to the way arguments of genocidal rape had functioned for advocates of military intervention in Bosnia: they signaled that something extraordinarily bad was happening, and that it was being carried out exclusively by one side of the conflict. Rumors of the use of Viagra by Gaddafi forces spread throughout the month of May. Libyan opposition forces apparently caught on to the significance of mass rape allegations, as Al Jazeera reported on May 3, 2011 that “opposition fighters say they have found Viagra pills in tanks and cars captured from the Gaddafi forces.”132 ICC Chief Prosecutor Luis Moreno-Ocampo also repeated the allegations, vowing in an interview with CNN that the ICC would investigate claims of systematic rape: “There’s some information with Viagra. So, it’s like a machete . . . Viagra is a tool of massive rape.”133 It is worth noting that at the time, and until Moreno-Ocampo’s departure from the ICC in 2012, Catharine MacKinnon served as his special advisor on gender. I do not think it is coincidental that these discussions of Viagra and mass rape would regain intensity in June 2011, when the future of the U.S. role in the 74 Chapter 2 intervention in Libya was becoming increasingly uncertain. Recall that President Obama’s invocation of the War Powers Resolution implied to many lawmakers that Congress would need to either authorize funding or declare war in order to continue the intervention in Libya for more than sixty days—that is, beyond May 19. But when that date came and went, the Obama administration argued that in fact it was not required to seek authorization, nor had it even initially been required to inform Congress of the activities in which it was engaged.134 On June 3, the U.S. House of Representatives passed by a wide margin (268–145) a resolution rebuking President Obama for failing to seek and receive congressional approval for U.S. involvement in Libya.135 In response, Obama submitted a formal report to the House explaining why U.S. military operations in Libya were consistent with the War Powers Resolution and congressional approval was unnecessary.136 As this dispute heated up, so too did the debate among humanitarian experts over claims about Viagra distribution and mass rape in Libya. These claims returned to center stage at the UN when, on June 1, the Human Rights Council received the report of the International Commission of Inquiry established to investigate alleged violations of international human rights law in Libya. This commission, chaired by Cherif Bassiouni, had been created by the Human Rights Council in February 2011 to investigate potential violations of international human rights and humanitarian law and, given Resolution 1970’s referral of the Libyan case to the ICC, “consider events in light of international criminal law.”137 The commission considered as “speculative” the repeated claims that members of Gaddafi’s special forces “were found with condoms and Viagra pills, leading those recounting these occurrences to suggest that troops were given instructions to engage in rape.”138 Nonetheless, it mentioned several reports of rape by government soldiers, including of Eman al-Obeidi, the only victim of rape with whom the commission spoke, as well as by armed opposition forces and civilians.139 While concluding that the number of reported cases was small, the report also recognized that victims would be reluctant to provide information because of “the trauma, shame and stigma linked to reports of sexual assault” and the harsh criminal sanctions (flogging) in Libya for sexual relations outside marriage.140 The message of the report became further muddled when, a week after its release, Moreno-Ocampo again spoke at the UN about rape in Libya. Though it was unclear what role (if any) the report played in the decision, he announced that the ICC would likely add rape to the list of war crimes against Gaddafi. He claimed that evidence of Viagra use was mounting, and that “we had doubts at Calling in the Troops 75 the beginning, but now we are more convinced. Apparently, [Gaddafi] decided to punish, using rape.”141 Moreno-Ocampo’s statement led to a strong response from Bassiouni, and became a source of some tension within the UN. Bassiouni countered MorenoOcampo’s claims by saying that references to Viagra and institutionalized rape resulted from “mass hysteria.” He noted that he heard similar claims from government officials about the rebels. His explanation was that “when the information spread out, the society felt so vulnerable . . . it has created a mass hysteria.”142 Amnesty International researcher Donatella Rovera’s findings seemed to support Bassiouni. After three months in Libya, she had not met a single woman who claimed to have been raped. “Normally the situation is the reverse—you don’t get many people to focus on it in society, but you can get the victims to talk,” Rovera said. “Here everyone’s talking about it, but despite our best efforts, we’ve not been able to meet a single victim.”143 However, the UN Secretary-General’s Special Representative on Sexual Violence in Conflict, Margot Wallström, supported Moreno-Ocampo. She asserted that there were “consistent reports [of rape] from people, from organizations, from UN entities and others on the ground” and that “this is part of the arsenal, the weaponry that Gaddafi’s troops use.”144 She also disparaged Bassiouni for the use of the term “mass hysteria,” saying that “for too long, it was not considered proper to mention rape and sexual violence. That’s why it’s so important to take it seriously.”145 As the U.S. House of Representatives considered further steps regarding the Obama administration’s involvement in Libya, Secretary Clinton joined MorenoOcampo and Wallström. Though she did not mention Viagra, Clinton referred to the ICC’s “appalling evidence that rape in Libya is widespread and systematically employed.”146 If this affirmation ended with a call for criminal law “to bring perpetrators to justice,”147 it was clearly also useful as justification for the ongoing, and highly contentious, U.S. intervention. Before June came to a close, the House considered and defeated two bills. One would have would have authorized the intervention, while the other would have prevented any further funding for U.S. military operations in Libya. In rejecting both, the House essentially left the administration free to continue as it wished.148 Over time, the stories of Viagra in Libya dissipated, as no one was ever able to prove the claims. In February 2012, when the Women’s Media Center issued its conflict profile on Libya, “Women under Siege: Libya,” it noted that the Viagra claims were unsubstantiated.149 And when the International Commission of Inquiry reported again to the Human Rights Council in March 2012, it further dispelled the claims, noting that “one witness who searched and identified over two hundred bodies stated he had not found any Viagra or condoms on any dead 76 Chapter 2 [Gaddafi] soldiers.”150 Furthermore, neither the commission nor Human Rights Watch found any more evidence of systematic rape than had Amnesty International.151 By its second report, the commission had met with twenty additional victims of sexual violence, both men and women, most of whom indicated that sexual violence had been used as a means of torture while they were in detention.152 The commission concluded that “the prevailing culture of silence, the lack of reliable statistics, the evident use of torture to extract confessions, and the political sensitivity of the issue combine to make this issue the most difficult one for the Commission to investigate.”153 Notwithstanding the lack of evidence of widespread sexual violence, a consensus seemed to have emerged, in line with the sentiments expressed in the commission’s first report, that shame, stigma, trauma, and criminal penalties combined to keep women from speaking out about sexual violence they experienced. Indeed, much of the discourse about shame and stigma, and about how rape affects the honor of entire communities, is similar to that from the early 1990s regarding Bosnian Muslims. But, since many women in Bosnia did talk, something about Libya had to be different. One Human Rights Watch researcher provided a possible explanation, saying that while ”research on rape is often challenging due to the shame and taboo,” in Libya it is especially tough “because of the conservative nature of the society and the hyperpoliticized environment we are operating in.”154 If the situation was hyperpoliticized in Libya, though, it became so at least partly because rape allegations were so central to calls for continued military intervention. What Bassiouni described as “mass hysteria” (and what others might term “sex panic”) had in fact become part of the harm. As the second report of the commission explained, “The reports of rapes and widespread fear had the consequence, if not purpose, of terrorizing a community and forcing many to flee their homes with their children.”155 Or, as the Women’s Media Center put it, “while evidence of systematic rape remains scarce, it is clear that there were numerous incidents of rape, and it is equally clear that the threat of rape was used to instill fear in entire communities.”156 Threats, of course, have to be credible to have such an effect. In this case, it could be argued that the statements of MorenoOcampo and others about Viagra and mass rape helped provide that credibility. The lack of available witness testimony, combined with the assumption of shame, has had repercussions for international criminal law as well. As we will see in Chapter Four, prosecutors at the ICTR proposed alternatives to witness testimony due to the difficulty of coaxing rape victims to testify, which they attribute to shame. Moreno-Ocampo pursued some of these ideas when he Calling in the Troops 77 announced to the UN Security Council in November 2011 that his office had “adopted a strategy which seeks to limit the exposure of victims,” given that, in Libya, rape “can trigger retaliation and honor based violence.”157 In the ensuing months, he clarified that he would seek evidence, not from the victims themselves but from “the testimony of doctors who received hundreds of victims, hospital records, video footage and confessions of soldiers in the army who can explain what happened.”158 He supported this approach to prosecution with reference to respect for “local traditions.”159 Given the taboo nature of the topic in Libya, Moreno-Ocampo stated, “we are building a rape investigation without any victim of rape, so we do not present names or faces of victims of rape.”160 At the end of the day, the Libya case became stalled,161 and there was no opportunity to test Moreno-Ocampo’s approach. If the ICC were at some point to succeed in achieving rape convictions without victim testimony, however, it would do so at a significant cost—not only with respect to due process for the accused, but by reinforcing the idea that rape is inevitable in conflict and that its ensuing shame and stigma must be accepted as natural and necessary. IV. The Continuation of Crisis Governance Feminists who labeled rapes by Serbs in Bosnia as genocidal both capitalized on emerging trends in the justification of humanitarian military intervention and furthered the use of claims of sexual violence to call for intervention, including in the absence of genocide. Even prior to the Libya intervention, MacKinnon had continued to make the case that military intervention was a crucial means of protecting women from violence. In 2006, in a piece called “Women’s September 11th,” she contrasted what she considered the international community’s willingness to adopt “potent” measures in response to terrorism with its failure to support a similar response to violence against women.162 Proposing that the treatment of women “be injected into all levels of discussion of humanitarian intervention,163 she suggested that the UN Security Council consider responding with military force to certain systematic forms of violence against women.164 As long as the United States and the “international community” were rethinking justifications for humanitarian intervention and were willing to respond to actions by private actors against private actors in the context of terrorism, she contended, they should rethink when and how to intervene to protect women from multiple forms of violence. Her principal concern about calling in the troops to protect women seemed to be about ensuring that the troops did not further abuse women, leading her to suggest that “maybe all the blue helmets on such missions should be women.”165 78 Chapter 2 I believe that MacKinnon overstated the extent to which most international law scholars, practitioners, and institutional actors were—at that time—willing to “legally justify resort to force” to respond to terrorism.166 Most had opposed the second invasion of Iraq. And, as we have seen, nearly all agree that forceful humanitarian intervention is reserved for crisis situations. States and international organizations are called to intervene, or are shamed for not intervening, when a situation is urgent, large numbers of people have already died or been raped, or “tomorrow we will be killed.”167 Within this crisis dynamic, however, human rights advocates have power. They make choices about what to bring to the public’s attention and how to do it. As Kenneth Cmiel put it, “When the larger public becomes interested in a brutality somewhere in the world, it is usually because some image has successfully conjured up the icon ‘human rights.’” For Cmiel, this interest and sympathy have not “depended upon a ‘thick’ understanding of those cultures” affected, but “upon reliable and concrete information about infractions making its way to key media and political elites, convincing them that the horrors are really taking place.”168 Human rights nongovernmental and intergovernmental organizations (both feminist and non-feminist) play an important role in providing such “reliable and concrete” information. In doing so, they exercise significant power in producing public sympathy for particular causes. In their rush to ensure adequate responses to sexual violence in conflict— including but not only through military intervention—the feminist humanitarians we have studied here seized upon that power. As they did so, however, they backgrounded or suppressed commitments to more nuanced conceptions of ethnicity, culture, sexuality, and women’s agency. The decline of these critical feminist theories and perspectives and the ascendance of the problematic common sense with which this book is concerned are not only damaging to women—including victims of rape—in the contexts in question. Through reifications of ethnicity and reinforcement of the perceived shameful harm of rape, these feminists have supported, if not provided, justificatory scripts for military interventions, especially where a cultural “other” is identified to fit the scripts. Even as calls for intervention began in the 1990s to lead to the creation of criminal tribunals or referrals to the ICC, instead of or alongside uses of force, these reifications and displacements continued to have effects. The next three chapters demonstrate that the common sense that was forged in making a case for military intervention in Bosnia traveled into international criminal law and into the UN’s Women, Peace and Security agenda. In that latter site, as we see in Calling in the Troops 79 Chapter Five, sexual violence by terrorists and extremist groups has been identified as constituting a new crisis. Broad UN Security Council support for counterterrorism measures to respond to that crisis suggests that MacKinnon’s appeal to treat sexual violence against women as “potently” as terrorism might have been heeded. CHAP TE R THR E E Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia T H E E A R LY 19 9 0 S W E R E R I F E with debates about how to name and respond to conflict in the former Yugoslavia. As Chapter Two demonstrated, the UN Security Council became a major site of contestation over those issues. Unable to reach the necessary agreement to authorize large-scale military intervention, especially in what some considered an internal conflict, the Security Council took a different tack, eventually favoring international criminal law as its mode of intervention. In late 1992, partly for “the purpose of appeasing world public opinion,”1 the Security Council established the Commission of Experts to investigate humanitarian law violations committed in the region.2 Continuing with the reluctance that we saw earlier regarding the use of the “g” word, the commission’s January 1993 report found that “ethnic cleansing,” which it put in quotation marks, had been perpetrated through a variety of means, including “rape and sexual assault.”3 Although the report did not include a finding of genocide, it noted that, in addition to constituting crimes against humanity, “such acts could also fall within the meaning of the Genocide Convention.”4 It called for the Security Council “or another competent organ” to establish an international criminal tribunal.5 On May 25, 1993, the UN Security Council made the unprecedented move of deploying its powers under Chapter VII of the UN Charter, not to authorize military intervention but to establish the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) as its response to what it named a continuing “threat to international peace and security.”6 The ad hoc tribunal, to be based in The Hague, would prosecute those responsible for “serious violations of international humanitarian law” in the former Yugoslavia, from 1991 until a date 80 Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 81 to be determined by the Security Council upon the “restoration of peace.”7 The resolution establishing the tribunal did not mention genocide, but it referenced mass killings and “ethnic cleansing” (again in quotation marks), as well as “organized and systematic detention and rape of women.”8 As the ICTY developed—through its statute, rules of evidence and procedure, and jurisprudence—it granted considerable attention to the treatment of rape and other forms of sexual violence. Feminists, particularly the structural-bias feminists who occupied much of the discussion in Chapter Two, were involved at nearly every stage, often putting aside their differences. As such, they had significant influence on both substantive and procedural aspects of the development of international criminal law. As one commentator observed almost a decade after the establishment of the ICTY, “From the start, most observers considered the [ICTY] a sop to human rights and feminist activists who wanted intervention. . . . Almost no one expected it to succeed. And yet to some extent, at least for women, it did.”9 The ICTY’s treatment of sexual violence, of course, resulted from more than the work of feminist advocates. It coincided with growing general support— including that of human rights advocates—for international criminal law that could be enforced through tribunals and courts.10 The conflict in the former Yugoslavia provided feminists and non-feminists alike with the opportunity to establish an international criminal tribunal that many had longed for, as well as to consider the treatment of rape in international criminal law. As Theodor Meron, who later became ICTY president, noted in 1993, “Indescribable abuse of thousands of women in the territory of former Yugoslavia . . . shock[ed] the international community into rethinking the prohibition of rape as a crime under the laws of war.”11 The tribunal’s impact on international criminal law has been significant, confirming Meron’s prediction in 1993 that “the tribunal’s charter, like that of Nuremberg, is likely quickly to become a fundamental normative instrument of the general law of war.”12 Indeed, the creation of the ICTY marked the beginning of an era of international judicial interventions in both conflict and post-conflict situations. It was followed in short succession by the ad hoc International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR), which is the subject of Chapter Four, and—over the next two decades—by various types of international criminal tribunals concerning conflicts in East Timor, Sierra Leone, Cambodia, Lebanon, and Kosovo. In 1998, the Rome Statute, establishing the International Criminal Court (ICC), was opened for ratification. It went into effect in 2002, institutionalizing ongoing 82 Chapter 3 general criminal liability for war crimes, crimes against humanity, and genocide. International criminal law has, in turn, evolved in important ways through the statutes, rules, and jurisprudence of these bodies. I focus on the ICTY in this chapter and the ICTR in the next. Although the tribunals officially closed, in 2017 and 2015, respectively, with only a small number of appeals remaining in a different forum, they have produced the largest body of case law to date on international criminal law in general, and on sexual violence in conflict in particular.13 They continue to serve as a model for subsequent international criminal tribunals. Through their engagement with the ICTY and ICTR, feminists embraced international criminal law as a new vehicle for attacking rape and other forms of sexual violence. In the process, important elements of the common sense forged in earlier articulations of the harm of rape began to solidify. Particularly vivid in the early years of the ICTY, charges of rape as acts of genocide and convictions of rape as crimes against humanity and war crimes reinforced the assumption that rape and sexual violence are the worst crimes that can be committed during wartime. Further—like much of the feminist advocacy leading to it—the ICTY tended to see women primarily as victims in war. Indeed, through both its rules of evidence and its jurisprudence, the tribunal presumed that civilian women were incapable of consenting to—let alone desiring—sex during conflict with a combatant from the other side of a drawn ethnic line. In addition to denying sexual agency, that position reinforced ahistorical conceptions of ethnicity in the region, largely cementing the abandonment of the Third World feminist critiques of essentialized ethnic identity, at least in this context. The turn to criminal law added new aspects to the common sense as well. First, the criminalization focus, by design, conceived of the perpetrators as individual monsters. Indeed, one of the aims of criminalization was to decrease ethnic conflict and nationalist identity by showing that individuals—not entire ethnic groups—were responsible for the harm.14 Even though some argue that the ICTY fell far short of achieving that aim, it brought claims against some non-Serb perpetrators presumably with that purpose in mind.15 Second, while those monsters were, with only one exception, men, the victims included men and boys. That coverage was partly facilitated by a broadening of rape into a category of sexual violence, which meant that, at some level, sexual violence became unmoored from violence against women and even gender-based violence. That unmooring arguably went against the very aims of the sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism. Yet, paradoxically, those same Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 83 feminists made the separation possible through their heightened attention to sexual harm. I. Feminist Engagement with the ICTY Statute and Rules In 1992, the Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women began to strategize about how to ensure international criminal accountability for the perpetrators of rapes being committed in the former Yugoslavia, encouraging the UN to establish a war crimes tribunal.16 Once the ICTY was established, some of the coalition members and other feminists began to engage with it in a variety of ways, ultimately securing broad coverage of sexual violence crimes. They achieved success despite a statute that was less explicit in naming those crimes than they might have hoped. The ICTY statute makes no reference to the term “sexual violence.” It mentions “rape” only once, but the context is significant. Rape appears in a list of prohibited acts that, when widespread or systematic and directed against a civilian population, could constitute a crime against humanity.17 The other acts listed are murder, extermination, enslavement, deportation, imprisonment, torture, persecution on political, racial, and religious grounds, and “other inhumane acts.”18 This definition of crimes against humanity mirrors the one that the Allied powers used after World War II to prosecute Germans not otherwise tried by the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg.19 Many consider the definition to constitute customary international law—or international law derived from certain state practices rather than from treaties or other sources—thereby justifying its inclusion in the ICTY statute.20 Indeed, to preclude the claim that the statute created ex post facto law, or new law that it applied retroactively, the ICTY drafters included only crimes that (they contended) already existed under customary international law. Thus, the tribunal could assert that perpetrators had been on notice as to the illegality of the acts they committed.21 A number of feminists at the time criticized the ICTY statute for its failure to list rape as a war crime.22 Yet the absence of that explicit reference did not in fact preclude its prosecution as a war crime.23 Ironically, silence on this point may have even given feminists room to maneuver, making way for the prosecution of a category of crimes that would be referred to in later statutes as “sexual violence.” Indeed, several years after the tribunal’s establishment, Rhonda Copelon called the omission of the term “rape” from the statute “fortuitous” because it “made it easier to argue for the mainstreaming of sexual violence crimes, else they would be excluded altogether.”24 84 Chapter 3 In the end, the Office of the Prosecutor (OTP) brought indictments of rape and sexual violence as war crimes, crimes against humanity, and genocide. The charges often reflected creative interpretation of the statute, as well as various understandings of the acts charged and of their harm. Those interpretations affected how the cases were prosecuted and were therefore often manifested in the jurisprudence. Given the statute’s omission of rape in its list of war crimes, for instance, the OTP brought indictments for rape and sexual violence as war crimes under “torture,” “outrages upon personal dignity,” and “humiliating and degrading treatment.” Although none of these crimes was listed as a war crime either, they—but not rape—appear in common Article 3 of the four 1949 Geneva Conventions.25 Through early, controversial decisions, the tribunal expanded the list of war crimes by reading all of common Article 3 into the statute as customary international law.26 The tribunal later read the war crimes provision of the statute as implicitly including rape, making it possible for future indictments to charge it directly.27 Since the definition of genocide in the statute followed the Genocide Convention definition verbatim, it did not list rape as an act of genocide. The OTP brought charges for rape or sexual violence under the definition as acts “causing serious bodily or mental harm” or “deliberately inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical destruction.”28 Because the ICTY did not convict anyone of genocide for acts of rape or sexual violence, it offered little theorizing on how the acts might constitute genocide.29 The ICTR drew the connection in its jurisprudence, as I consider in detail in Chapter Four. Even though the ICTY statute listed rape as a crime against humanity, the OTP did not limit its interpretation of rape to the ordinarily accepted legal definitions of the term. It sometimes charged other acts of sexual violence under that statutory provision, even describing those acts in indictments as “rape which includes other forms of sexual assault.”30 Indictments often also included charges of rape and sexual violence as crimes against humanity under the prohibitions on “torture,” “enslavement,” “other inhumane acts,” and “persecution on political, racial, and religious grounds.”31 This use of the statute to cover a wide range of sexual violence charges can be attributed in part to feminist strategy, if not strategies. From the early days of the ICTY, feminists lobbied the chief prosecutor, Richard Goldstone, to use the tribunal to prosecute rapes committed as part of the conflict. Goldstone later recalled: “From my very first week in office, . . . I began to be besieged with Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 85 petitions and letters, mainly from women’s groups, but also from human rights groups generally. . . . Letters and petitions expressing concern and begging for attention, adequate attention, to be given to gender related crime, especially systematic rape as a war crime. Certainly if any campaign worked, this one worked in my case.”32 Once again recalling the effect of these letters, Goldstone said in an interview in 2015: “I didn’t need any arm-twisting, but it certainly encouraged me to put this right at the top of the agenda.”33 Goldstone responded to those letters, as well as to his “amaze[ment] at the gender bias that emerged in our international office,” by naming a Legal Advisor for Gender Related Crimes.34 Patricia Viseur Sellers served in that position from 1994 to 2007, where she formulated the prosecution’s approach to rape and sexual violence in both the ICTY and the ICTR. The ICTY’s rules of evidence and procedure played an important role in these prosecutions. Indeed, according to Fionnuala Ní Aoláin, the substantive legal recognition of sexual offenses would have achieved little without the implementation of “radical” procedural mechanisms.35 She notes that the rules “are more ‘victim friendly’ than most parallel domestic criminal codes,” which she partly attributes to substantial nongovernmental lobbying.36 According to former ICTY Judge Gabrielle Kirk McDonald, many of the rules stemmed from proposals by women’s groups and were contentious among the judges, though they nevertheless approved them by consensus.37 The most significant feminist rule victory for my purposes is Rule 96. Not only did the rule ensure that a sexual assault victim’s testimony would not need to be corroborated and that evidence of the victim’s past sexual conduct would be precluded, but it also limited the extent to which consent could be presented as a defense to sexual assault.38 The consent provision was the most innovative and far-reaching aspect of the rule, as I discuss more fully below. Many also see Rule 34 as a feminist victory. That rule established the Victims and Witnesses Unit to provide victims and witnesses with counseling and support, “in particular in cases of rape and sexual assault.”39 It also instructed that “due consideration shall be given, in the appointment of staff, to the employment of qualified women.”40 These provisions and procedural innovations indicated a serious commitment on the part of the ICTY to prosecute rape and sexual violence. That commitment was borne out in the tribunal’s practice. Of 161 individuals indicted by the tribunal, 93, or 58 percent, faced charges for rape or sexual violence or had evidence of such violence presented against them at trial. Forty-four percent of those 93 individuals were convicted.41 Even though many of the accused avoided 86 Chapter 3 trial by pleading guilty, a significant body of jurisprudence on rape and sexual violence emerged from the ICTY’s Trial and Appeals Chambers. II. The Mediation of Feminist Disagreements By the time the tribunal began its work, many of the disagreements among women’s human rights advocates seen in earlier chapters had begun to dissipate. Indeed, for a variety of the reasons demonstrated in Chapter One, the criminalization of sexual violence in conflict, particularly in the former Yugoslavia, became an issue on which internationally engaged feminists largely agreed. At the same time, sustained attention to the issue furthered the interests and participation of the sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminists. Third World, anti-war, and sex-positive feminists might have acquiesced in the turns to both sexual violence in conflict and criminal law, but their perspectives had little effect on how the criminalization process moved forward. As the disagreements between structural-bias and other feminist approaches quieted down, a debate raged within structural-bias feminism, as detailed in Chapter Two. In that debate, both the genocidal-rape and rape-on-all-sides positions basically agreed that male sexual domination and female sexual subordination posed the greatest threat to women, in everyday life as well as in conflict. But they vehemently disagreed about whether rapes by Serbs should be treated differently—as genocidal—from other rapes committed during the conflict. Some who argued that the rapes were genocidal also argued for military intervention. Even the feminists engaged in this debate largely put aside their disagreements in order to pursue the criminalization of sexual violence in conflict. Yet the issues over which they initially struggled did not totally disappear, perhaps because their disagreements reflected deeper tensions about how the law should treat different sides of the conflict. The tribunal’s work, at least initially, appeared to mediate the feminist debate. Military intervention might have required taking sides in a conflict, but international criminal law—as conceived by the ICTY—allowed for prosecutions of individuals from all sides. Early on, ICTY prosecutors brought charges of rape and sexual violence against individuals who were parties to each side of the conflict. The first three judgments handing down rape convictions reflected that approach.42 In the first case of the three decided, Čelebići, the tribunal convicted one Bosnian Muslim and one Croat of torture (as a grave breach and a war crime) for rapes of Serbian women committed at the Čelebići prison camp.43 Though this case turned out to be the only one in which a Bosnian Muslim was convicted Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 87 for acts of rape or sexual violence as well as the only one in which such acts were committed against Serbian victims, it was symbolically important for demonstrating that the statute applied to all sides.44 The ICTY’s second rape conviction, Furundžija, reinforced this view. There, the tribunal found a Croat guilty of war crimes against a Bosnian Muslim woman—for torture and outrages upon personal dignity including rape.45 It was not until the third case, Kunarac, that the ICTY convicted Serbian men of the rape of Bosnian Muslim women. The OTP successfully designed the case to highlight the systematic detention and rape of Bosnian Muslim women by Serbian men in the Foča region, where Bosnia borders Serbia. The judgment was pathbreaking in a number of aspects. First, it convicted all three of the accused of the war crime of rape. As mentioned above, it did so by reading the statute’s provision on war crimes to include rape.46 Second, it convicted all three of rape as a crime against humanity.47 Third, it convicted two of the accused, Dragoljub Kunarac and Radomir Kovač, of enslavement, based on findings that they had detained girls and women and, in addition to raping them, forced them to cook, clean, do household chores, or obey other orders.48 Responses to the enslavement convictions demonstrate how the debate among feminists on the term “sexual slavery,” which we saw in Chapter One, had subsided. Even one disagreement about the interpretation of Kunarac indicates just how uncontroversial the use of the term had become. While Kelly Askin criticized the judgment for not explicitly finding the accused guilty of sexual slavery,49 other feminists lauded the judgment, reading its finding of enslavement as recognition of the crime of sexual slavery. The timing of the decision assisted in the latter interpretation given that, when Kunarac was handed down in 1996, many feminists were successfully advocating for the inclusion of sexual slavery as a crime against humanity and as a war crime in the Rome Statute. According to Valerie Oosterveld, who served on the Canadian delegation to the ICC negotiations, Kunarac was “precedent-setting” for the ICC statute due to its “consideration of the crime of enslavement for sexual purposes.”50 The finding of rape as a crime against humanity in Kunarac set the stage for the doctrinal mediation of the debate over genocidal rape. Although Askin criticized the OTP for not charging the accused in the case with genocide,51 the judgment in fact relied upon, reproduced, and even reinforced many of the characterizations of genocidal rape put forth by those taking the genocidalrape position. In particular, it stated that ethnic cleansing (which, recall, many equated with genocide) had occurred in Foča, found rape and enslavement 88 Chapter 3 of Bosnian Muslim women to be systematic (which was required for the crimeagainst-humanity convictions), and included references to the intent of at least individual Serbs to cause their rape victims to bear Serbian children.52 As these three cases show, both sides of the debate about rape as genocide gained something in the tribunal’s early work: the ICTY prosecuted and convicted rape and sexual violence on all sides, even while more harshly condemning the systematic commission of those crimes by Serbs. Feminists on both sides of the debate had already seen that they had a common interest in creating rules of evidence and procedure that would facilitate prosecution, not only of rape but of an expanded list of sexual violence crimes including, in addition to sexual slavery, enforced prostitution and enforced pregnancy. They eventually ushered this extended list into the Rome Statute.53 Perhaps because feminists were so focused on this new agenda, no significant disagreements or critiques emerged when Kunarac became the norm, in terms both of the frequency of indictments and convictions of Serbs (versus other groups) and of the treatment of rapes by Serbs as particularly harmful. In total, the OTP brought 75 percent of the indictments for rape or sexual violence against Serbs.54 Even though the ICTY never achieved a genocide conviction based on such acts, the OTP charged 11 of the 67 Serbs accused of acts of rape or sexual violence with genocide for those acts,55 and it charged only Serbs with genocide. Additionally, the OTP charged all but one of those Serbs with crimes against humanity for rape or sexual violence. In contrast, it charged no Bosnian Muslim with rape or sexual violence as a crime against humanity. And, although it charged 11 of the 17 Croats indicted for rape or sexual violence with crimes against humanity for those acts, more than half of those 11 were part of a single case.56 The tribunal’s emphasis on Serbian perpetrators’ ethnic bias against Bosnian Muslims that we saw in Kunarac became further entrenched in subsequent prosecutions for crimes against humanity. Although rape is included in the statute as a crime against humanity, and the OTP charged the accused in Kunarac under that provision, at one point the OTP began routinely to bring charges of rape under a different crime-against-humanity category, “persecutions on political, racial and religious grounds.”57 Indeed, for cases resolving after 2001, all but five of the accused Serbs charged for acts of rape or sexual violence as a crime against humanity were charged with persecution for those acts.58 Although the OTP also charged rape as a crime against humanity in many of these cases, resulting convictions were generally only for persecution, which the tribunal decided subsumed the rape charges since persecution requires a higher level of intent.59 Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 89 This trend toward convictions for acts of rape and sexual violence as persecution—and often not as rape—is somewhat ironic, given that rape is explicitly included in the statute only as a crime against humanity. Yet, especially aided by the tribunal’s understanding that “persecution as a crime against humanity is an offense belonging to the same genus as genocide,”60 the convictions for persecution served at least two aims of those taking the genocidal-rape position. First, the requirement of discrimination, including discriminatory intent, in the crime of persecution bolstered the idea that women were raped primarily because of their ethnicity.61 Since most of the persecution cases were brought against Serbs, rapes by Serbs were further distinguished from other rapes during the conflict. Indeed, in at least one case, Brđanin, the very fact that the rapes were committed by members of the Bosnian Serb police and army against Bosnian Muslim women made them “intrinsically discriminatory.”62 Although persecution requires that the accused “must consciously intend to discriminate,” the Chamber, following earlier case law, noted that intent can be inferred from context as long as “circumstances surrounding the commission of the alleged acts substantiate the existence of such intent.”63 It then found that rapes and sexual assaults of both Bosnian Muslim and Bosnian Croat women were “carried out with the intent to discriminate,” largely based on “the circumstances surrounding” the acts, again resting much of the analysis on the fact that the perpetrators were Bosnian Serb soldiers or police officers and the victims were not Serbs.64 The Chamber did add with regard to the rapes that “the direct perpetrators made abundant use of pejorative language.”65 It even pointed to language similar to that often employed in the genocidal-rape argument: “One of them made no secret that he wanted a Bosnian Muslim woman to ‘give birth to a little Serb.’”66 Second, finding that acts of rape constituted persecution indicated that, even if short of genocide, the acts were particularly egregious. Persecution provided a way to push rape further up the hierarchy of harms. That other acts of sexual violence were also charged as persecution extended the sense of egregiousness to those crimes as well. As explained by a group of former staff members of the OTP, the crime of persecution offered “an important vehicle for recognizing the seriousness of sexual violence other than rape.”67 That recognition came only second to “reconceptualizing sexual violence as an underlying act of genocide,” which the authors claim as their “biggest breakthrough in terms of communicating more accurately its violent and serious nature.”68 They claim that breakthrough, notwithstanding the absence of actual convictions of rape or sexual violence as an act of genocide. 90 Chapter 3 By elevating the seriousness of rape relative to other crimes, the use of persecution to charge rape could have served both sides of the debate over rape as genocide—had the statute not limited persecution to political, racial, and religious grounds. Indeed, some feminists who argued for attention to rapes on all sides, including Rhonda Copelon, had advocated early on for ICTY prosecutors and judges to understand persecution also to include prohibited acts committed on the basis of gender.69 They lost that battle at the ICTY (long before Brđanin), but they took their efforts to the drafting of the Rome Statute, where they once again achieved a victory: crimes against humanity in the Rome Statute include “persecution . . . on political, racial, national, ethnic, cultural, religious, gender . . . or other grounds.”70 Even after that win in the Rome Statute, the ICTY continued, at the urging of prosecutors, to emphasize the ethnic over gender harm of rapes by Serbs, with few if any criticisms by these or any other feminists. III. Solidifying the Common Sense: Jurisprudence on Rape and Sexual Violence As the tribunal’s jurisprudence continued to develop, both sides of the debate about rape as genocide saw incorporation of their shared view that rape and (now) sexual violence were among the greatest wartime crimes, even though the tribunal often relied upon the honor rationale that most structural-bias feminists had attempted to move away from. At the same time, the prominent role of ethnicity in the ICTY’s prosecutions, which seemed to serve the interests of the genocidal-rape camp, paved the way for the tribunal’s reinforcement of ethnic essentialism and the naturalness of ethnic conflict. A. The Worst Harm The ICTY’s jurisprudence supported the view that rape is a fate worse than death. It did so in a variety of ways, both doctrinal and rhetorical, primarily in its treatment of rape and sexual violence as torture and as outrages upon personal dignity. As we saw above, the OTP brought many of the charges involving rape and sexual violence as both war crimes and crimes against humanity under the statutory provisions on torture. The ICTY held that torture requires an intentional act for a prohibited purpose that causes “severe pain or suffering, whether physical or mental.”71 The Appeals Chamber in Kunarac ruled that Foča rape victims were not required to show that they had suffered severely: “Some acts establish per se the suffering of those upon whom they were inflicted. Rape is obviously such an Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 91 act.” Consequently, “severe pain or suffering, as required by the definition of the crime of torture, can . . . be said to be established once rape has been proved.”72 Later decisions affirmed this approach. In Brđanin, the Trial Chamber explained that “some acts, like rape, appear by definition to meet the severity threshold” of torture. In its explanation, it noted the purposes for which rape (“like torture”) is used, including the “destruction of a person.”73 The Trial Chambers in Kvočka and Simić arguably went further, stating that the mere “threat of rape or other forms of sexual violence” in the context of detention “undoubtedly caused severe pain and suffering,” thereby constituting torture.74 In the above examples, the presumption of severe pain and suffering constituted a doctrinal move that alleviated the need for the prosecutor to demonstrate harm through testimony by or about victims. Those cases might have suggested that rape is the ultimate harm, but they did not say it. Other decisions, however, repeated the common sense that rape is a fate worse than death. In Stakić, for example, the tribunal stated: “For a woman, rape is by far the ultimate offense, sometimes even worse than death because it brings shame on her.”75 Stakić made explicit the connection that many assume between shame and the unique harm of rape, and that was even at the heart of much of the discourse leading up to the establishment of the ICTY. Recall from Chapter Two that the UN Special Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights described in 1993 the role of rape in the conflict, stating: “Rape is an abuse of power and control in which the rapist seeks to humiliate, shame, degrade and terrify the victim.”76 The description was likely not incidental, given that common Article 3 of the four 1949 Geneva Conventions lists “humiliating and degrading treatment” as an example of “outrages upon personal dignity.” Feminists later worked hard, in their advocacy around the drafting of the ICC statute, to see rape and other sexual violence crimes moved out of the category of “outrages upon personal dignity,” where, when included, they had been housed alongside “humiliating and degrading treatment.”77 As I discuss more fully in Chapter Four, they did so to avoid the historical connection between sexual offenses and dignity and honor. But prosecutors at the ICTY took advantage of the tribunal’s reading of the statute to include “outrages upon personal dignity, in particular humiliating and degrading treatment,” as they pursued multiple avenues to achieve convictions not only for rape but also for a broader category of sexual violence. They did so, in part with the acquiescence of structural-bias and other feminists, even though shame, often discussed as humiliation, obviously proved key to many convictions. In the process, issues of honor often returned. 92 Chapter 3 In Furundžija, for example, the Trial Chamber found that the “severe physical and mental pain, along with public humiliation” caused by the rape and sexual assault constituted outrages upon the victim’s personal dignity. It also added, urged by the prosecutor, that it was an attack upon her “sexual integrity.”78 Especially given the historical connection between chastity and sexual integrity, this coupling of dignity and sexual integrity suggests yet another way in which the harm of rape and sexual violence has continued to be understood as connected to honor. In Češić, the tribunal seemed to go out of its way to read rape as necessarily humiliating. There, the accused had pleaded guilty to rape as a crime against humanity and the war crime of humiliating and degrading treatment for forcing two Bosnian Muslim brothers to perform fellatio on each other in front of guards at the Luka detention camp.79 At the sentencing stage, the Trial Chamber insisted that a salient distinction between the crime of humiliating and degrading treatment and the crime of rape is that the former emphasizes humiliation, while the latter stresses “the physical and moral integrity of the victim.”80 Note the tribunal’s use of “moral,” as opposed to “sexual” integrity here. Perhaps because the victims were men, the concept of chastity did not quite fit. In any event, the tribunal articulated this distinction only to make it clear that it had not collapsed the two crimes when it found “exacerbated humiliation” to be an aggravating circumstance for the rape charge. At the same time, it stated, “it is uncontested that rape is an inherently humiliating offense.”81 The chamber based its finding of exacerbated humiliation on the facts that the victims were brothers and that guards stood by to see the assault.82 Humiliation played an important role in the tribunal’s understanding of torture as well. The Čelebići decision offers some insight into the nature of the pain and suffering of rape that per se meets the torture definition. Noting the need to look not only at the physical but also the social and psychological consequences of rape, it quoted an Inter-American Commission on Human Rights judgment describing the effects on a rape victim in one of its cases to include “a fear of public ostracism; feelings of humiliation; fear of how her husband would react; a feeling that family integrity was at stake and an apprehension that her children might feel humiliated if they knew what had happened to their mother.”83 Thus, both as a feared result and as a cause of pain, the social ostracism associated with rape moved it per se into the category of torture.84 If humiliation, or shame, is central to the harm of rape, one of the justifications continually given for criminal prosecution of rape, which we see in nearly Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 93 every chapter of this book, is that it will shift the shame from the victim to the perpetrator. The ICTY signaled this possibility in the Nikolić case sentencing phase. There, the Trial Chamber considered the accused’s “final statement [in the hearing] that he genuinely feels shame and disgrace” as a “factor to be of some importance for mitigating the sentence.”85 In doing so, it arguably suggested that the public shaming of the accused could somewhat ameliorate the gravity of the offense, including its effects on a victim who had testified to feeling “miserable, degraded [and] humiliated as a woman and as a mother.”86 Assumptions about the inevitable consequences of rape for a victim’s life extended beyond the jurisprudence. They also affected the operation of the ICTY, because shame came to be seen as an obstacle to prosecution. Indeed, some feminists attributed the relatively small number of female witnesses (including victims) testifying before the tribunal to “intense shame and embarrassment,” “ostracism in their local communities,”87 and “stigma and taboo.”88 These concerns were amplified in relationship to the ICTR, as we see in Chapter Four. However ingrained it may be today, this common sense around rape as a fate worse than death was contestable at some moments, even in the context of the former Yugoslavia. As Gillian Mezey, a participant in a 1992 investigation into the rapes by what was then the European Community, explained, “For virtually all victims the sexual assault represents one aspect, but not necessarily the most significant, amongst other forms of degrading and humiliating treatment.” In addition to witnessing “the torture or death of family members” and having “their family dispersed to whereabouts that are unknown,” women have “been shot at, mortared, experienced extreme physical privations, seen their homes burned and their communities destroyed, with little prospect of being able to return in the future or seeing an end to the hostility and aggression.”89 This type of observation was short-lived, however, and received little traction. These harms to women, some of which would be difficult to trace to individual monsters who could be brought before a war crimes tribunal, did not demand the same type of attention as sexual violence did. Even Mezey, despite this observation, ultimately concentrated on the rapes, the motivations behind them, their normalization during wartime, and their ongoing effects.90 The insistence upon rape as the worst harm not only deflected attention from other issues that women (and men) faced in the conflict; it also served to deny some ways in which women might have suffered less because they were women. In Omarska, for example, women were raped, but the lives of most were spared. Men, on the other hand, were killed. Women were actually the first prisoners 94 Chapter 3 to be released from Omarska so that Serbs could deny that they were detaining women there.91 During the massacre at Srebrenica, Serbian forces separated out and took into custody boys and men from the ages of twelve through seventyseven, while buses transported approximately twenty-three thousand women and children to safety.92 The dynamic was, of course, not unique to Bosnia. Fionnuala Ní Aoláin has argued with regard to the Holocaust that “gender difference does not always imply greater victimization, and . . . some research has indicated that gender differences functioned to protect women in contradistinction to men in similar positions during the Holocaust.”93 The point here is not that women do not suffer from sexual or other forms of violence in conflict. Rather, even if only because of problematic paternalistic assumptions, women are often protected—as women—from certain types of harm. Ironically, then, treating women as innocent, victimized, and marginalized from political and military centers of power might be the best way to save their lives. B. Sexual Agency and Ethnic Difference The ICTY’s jurisprudence, particularly as it developed in the context of crimes against humanity, arguably criminalized any sexual activity between Serbian male combatants and Bosnian Muslim female civilians during the conflict. It did so by limiting consent as a defense to rape and sexual assault charges in conflict zones. Its doctrine betrayed a belief in ethnic hatred so overwhelming and insurmountable that it made consensual sex in these circumstances virtually impossible. In doing so, it largely relied upon the focus on ethnicity that the genocidal-rape feminists brought to the table. The jurisprudence resulted from the interpretation of Rule 96, which, as mentioned earlier, is the ICTY’s rule of evidence for sexual assault cases. The rule was amended several times, according to Viseur Sellers, “ostensibly due to a male-generated outcry because [in the first draft] consent appeared to be eliminated, not qualified, as a defence to wartime rape.”94 Later versions made it clear that, in some instances, evidence of consent would be admissible.95 Though early cases differed on the application of the rule and on the proof needed to establish the elements of the crime of rape, the Appeals Chamber in Kunarac provided an authoritative ruling on the matter: while the prosecutor technically had the burden of proving that the sexual acts were non-consensual, a determination of “coercive circumstances” could fulfill that burden. The Appeals Chamber used the fact that women were detained in what it described as “de facto military headquarters, detention centres and apartments maintained as soldiers’ residences” Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 95 to conclude that this “amount[ed] to circumstances that were so coercive as to negate any possibility of consent,”96 therefore alleviating the prosecution of the need to prove lack of consent for each of the rapes.97 This holding was particularly important because two of the accused had argued that some of the women they were charged with raping and enslaving had “freedom of movement inside and outside” the apartments to which they had been brought.98 Indeed, one of the women apparently admitted that she and another woman had keys to the apartment.99 The Appeals Chamber essentially accepted the Trial Chamber’s findings that the women were not actually permitted to move freely,100 or that escape was impossible given the “circumstances . . . in which Serb soldiers had exclusive control over the municipality of Foča and its inhabitants.”101 Yet we know from the Trial Chamber’s decision that one of the victims with keys had escaped, albeit with the help of a Serbian soldier whom she eventually married.102 Because the soldier she married was not on trial, the tribunal did not need to address directly whether the relationship was consensual, but its consent doctrine would seem to negate such a possibility. The presumed lack of consent in Kunarac was very much connected to the identities of the accused as Serbian and the victims as Bosnian Muslim. In response to Kunarac’s claim that one of the women he was accused of raping had consented to intercourse with him, the Appeals Chamber found that the “special circumstances and the ethnic selection of victims” supported the findings by the Trial Chamber of both lack of consent and discriminatory intent.103 The ethnic component of the rape thus combined with the finding of coercive circumstances to overshadow and minimize any possible evidence of consent. The relevance of ethnicity to the consent analysis was apparent in subsequent decisions by the ICTY. In Kvočka, a persecution case involving rape and sexual violence at the Omarska camp, the tribunal professed its own inability to conceive of wartime detention (and perhaps conflict itself) absent rape or other forms of sexual violence. The Appeals Chamber stated that “it would be unrealistic and contrary to all rational logic to expect that none of the women [all non-Serbs] held in Omarska, placed in circumstances rendering them especially vulnerable, would be subjected to rape or other forms of sexual violence.”104 It went on to say that the inevitability of rape and sexual violence is “particularly true in light of the clear intent . . . to subject the targeted [ethnic] group to persecution through such means as violence and humiliation.”105 The Kunarac decision could be read to extend well beyond the circumstances of detention in Foča—to apply to any sexual encounters between civilians and 96 Chapter 3 combatants on different sides of the conflict. Indeed, the Kunarac Appeals Chamber painted its ruling with broad strokes, stating that “the circumstances giving rise to the instant appeal and that prevail in most cases charged as either war crimes or crimes against humanity will be almost universally coercive. That is to say, true consent will not be possible.”106 Recall from the torture discussion that Kunarac also created an irrebuttable presumption that rape constituted severe pain and suffering. Read alongside that presumption, the consent rule leads to the conclusion that nearly all sex in Foča between Serbian (male) combatants and Bosnian Muslim (female) civilians also constituted torture. Although the Appeals Chamber suggested that consent would be impossible during wartime in nearly any jurisdiction (inside or outside of the former Yugoslavia), its judgment extended its reach, as a doctrinal matter, beyond Foča. Kunarac interpreted “armed conflict” to include “the whole territory of the warring states or, in the case of internal armed conflicts, the whole territory under the control of a party to the conflict, whether or not actual combat takes place there.”107 That broad reading came in response to arguments by the accused that though there was armed conflict in Foča, it was not occurring in the two other regions where the crimes were alleged to have taken place. The tribunal made clear: “A violation of the laws or customs of war may therefore occur at a time when and in a place where no fighting is actually taking place.”108 Among the types of evidence that would come into play to determine whether a particular act was related to the armed conflict were the status of the perpetrator as combatant and victim as non-combatant, and “the fact that the victim is a member of the opposing party.”109 This reading of “armed conflict” continued to be accepted in later cases.110 Taken together, the ICTY’s rules of evidence and jurisprudence on consent suggested the near impossibility of consensual sexual relations between combatants and civilians of warring ethnic groups, even where no fighting was taking place.111 As such, the ICTY largely denied the sexual agency of civilians (generally women), by making them legally incapable of consenting to sex with a combatant of a different ethnic group. It also denied the sexual agency of combatants (nearly always men), by considering their similar sexual conduct to be per se rape. This approach reinforced some of the essentialized notions of identity that were often relied upon by feminists in their arguments that rape constituted genocide. The ICTY, however, not only essentialized certain identities but also Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 97 conceived of the differences among them as insurmountable—responsible for perpetual hatred and conflict, and preclusive of genuine affection or desired sex. The jurisprudence therefore bought into an understanding of antagonisms in the Balkans as “age-old,” “tribal,” and “natural.”112 Yet, prior to the war, interpersonal relationships among various religious and ethnic groups were common in Bosnia and Herzegovina. People often married, entered sworn kinships, and celebrated festivities that crossed the ostensible religious and ethnic lines.113 Notwithstanding the divisive and often elusive concepts of nacija and nacionalnost (roughly translated as “nation” and “ethnicity”114), many contend that the Yugoslav socialist experiment of “brotherhood and unity” (bratstvo i jedinstvo) had been successful in Bosnia, adding a layer of “feeling Yugoslav” (jugoslavenstvo) to an already widespread sense of “Bosnianness” (bosanstvo).115 The heterogeneity of Bosnian religious practices helped facilitate these complex identities, especially since the powers of official religious institutions had been significantly curtailed under the socialist system.116 The ICTY opinions that discussed the history of ethnicity and religion in the region generally did so rather cursorily and with little attention to the contingency and construction of ethnic and religious identity in Bosnia. While decisions tended to see the period just before the war as one of relatively peaceful coexistence of different groups,117 they often treated or explained away that apparent peace as a mask for deep, underlying, and—for the most part—real ethnic/religious differences. The Trial Chamber’s decision in Tadić, for example, noted that many of the witnesses before the tribunal spoke “of good intercommunal relations, of friendships across ethnic and coincident religious divides, of intermarriages and of generally harmonious relations.” Yet, it continued, “it is only subsequent events that may suggest that beneath that apparent harmony always lay buried bitter discord, which skilful propaganda readily brought to the surface, with terrible results.”118 For the Trial Chamber in Kvočka, that “bitter discord” might have had at its core a constructed idea of ethnicity, but one that nevertheless manifested itself in “nationalist tendencies.” The chamber explained: “Following the Second World War, Marshal Tito and his communist regime took extensive measures to suppress and control all nationalistic tendencies, but in spite of the government’s efforts, the Yugoslav population remained very conscious of its so-called ethnic identity.”119 In each of these cases, then, the tribunal saw the ethnic divides as deeply entrenched. That sense of great difference and animosity made consensual sex 98 Chapter 3 unthinkable, particularly—but not only—between dominant Serbian male soldiers and subordinate Bosnian Muslim female civilians. To the extent that anything like consensual relationships might previously have seemed to exist, all bets were off during war, as the war was read to render anew old, underlying, but perhaps hidden divisions. The overwhelming sense of essentialized and ethnicized victimization of Bosnian Muslim women obscured other, competing narratives that emerged over time. Some Bosnian Muslim women and girls, for instance, reported that Serbian soldiers did not rape them, but told them to say they had been raped so that it would appear that the soldiers had obeyed orders.120 Others testified that Serbian soldiers helped them escape. And, as we already saw, at least one of the Foča rape victims married a Serb soldier. Of course, a presumption of coercion did not mean that every combatant known to be engaged sexually with a civilian from another ethnicity would be charged. Prosecutorial discretion, as always, meant that certain cases were chosen for prosecution over others. Viseur Sellers readily acknowledged when she was a prosecutor that such consensual relations occurred during the conflict, but she nevertheless supported Rule 96 and the broad judicial interpretation it was eventually given. Prosecutorial discretion, she contended, would prevent prosecution of Serbian soldiers in such instances.121 Even if we trusted Viseur Sellers’s use of prosecutorial discretion (I did), that trust might not be warranted for all prosecutors. Indeed, Darryl Robinson warns against “sanguine reliance on prosecutorial discretion” to respond to international criminal law’s often “overbroad doctrines,” by quoting legal philosopher Douglas Husak: “Discretion is not a reliable substitute for getting the rule right in the first place.”122 IV. Adding to the Common Sense: Male Victims For the most part, structural-bias feminists on both sides of the debate over genocidal rape emphasized sexual harm as that which the ICTY should address, largely setting aside concern for other forms of gender-based violence in conflict. They were also principally focused on male-on-female rape and sexual violence. Indeed, they practically never mentioned female perpetrators and rarely discussed male victims of sexual violence. Both omissions fit with the structuralbias perspective on male dominance and female subordination. For instance, MacKinnon, even with her insistence that “in this war the fact of Serbian aggression is beyond question,” made clear her belief that “the fact of male aggression against women is beyond question, both here and in everyday life.”123 Calling in the Judges: The Former Yugoslavia 99 Like most structural-bias feminists, the OTP rarely concerned itself with female perpetrators. Indeed, it brought charges against only one woman, Biljana Plavšić, who had been president of the Republika Srpska during the conflict. And it did so in 2000, relatively late in the day.124 Although the OTP charged Plavšić with counts of genocide and crimes against humanity that included acts of rape and sexual violence, it dropped those charges in exchange for her pleading guilty to one count of persecution.125 In contrast to its treatment of female perpetrators and to the approach of many structural-bias feminists, the OTP from the beginning brought charges for sexual violence committed against men. It did so as part of a deliberate strategy. Viseur Sellers recalls, for example, that the OTP successfully requested a 1995 amendment to Rule 96 that replaced the pronoun “she” with “the victim.”126 And in the case against Furundžija, the OTP “forwarded a gender-neutral definition of rape, inclusive of male rape, in its pleadings.”127 It did so, even though the only victim of rape in the case was a woman. In the end, a significant number of men were in fact convicted of sexual violence against men.128 Valerie Oosterveld criticized both the ICTY and the ICTR for their failure to charge many of the acts of sexual violence against men as rape, as opposed to other crimes.129 That, however, might also have been a part of the OTP’s strategy—to create a separate, broad category of acts of sexual violence that could be charged in a variety of ways. That the acts were not charged as rape did not, for the OTP, make them not serious. To the contrary, recall that those who had worked in the ICTY’s OTP indicated that one of their major breakthroughs was in seeing acts of sexual violence other than rape taken seriously, by successfully charging them as persecution, the crime against humanity that most approximates genocide. Structural-bias feminists also shared this aim of the criminalization of a broader category of acts of sexual violence. Upon closer examination, then, the similar treatment of sexual violence against men and women (if not as rape) could be compatible with their approach, especially if it were to treat sexual assault against men as reproducing the sexual domination and subordination dynamics of male-on-female (sexual) violence. Indeed, MacKinnon later articulated such a theory, including through an amicus brief in the United States on behalf of a man who alleged that he had been sexually assaulted by other men at his workplace. There, she contended that men suffer even greater harm from sexual assault than women are capable of suffering, because men “are stripped of their social status as men” and are “feminized.” For MacKinnon, “this cannot be done to a woman.”130 100 Chapter 3 Without the emphasis on sexual domination and subordination, however, treating cases of sexual violence against men and women together could serve to eliminate the sexual subordination analysis altogether, so that sexual violence would resemble any other war crime or crime against humanity that can be committed against men and women alike. That approach seems consistent with the work of the OTP. And it is largely the approach taken by UN Action Against Sexual Violence in Conflict in the treatment of what it has come to refer to as “conflict-related sexual violence,” as detailed in Chapter Five.131 Female victims might still capture the imagination, as demonstrated by the visual representations in the video discussed in the Introduction. But, thanks in part to the ICTY, the institutional and jurisprudential discourse is largely in line with the video’s spoken claim that “rape and sexual violence are used against women, girls, men and boys.”132 Even if, or perhaps because, male sexual dominance and female sexual subordination largely dropped out of the picture in the ICTY’s jurisprudence, the structural-bias feminists who focused on sexual subordination left a significant legacy. Despite their internal disagreements over the treatment of rape as genocide, they used the ICTY to bring attention to a broad range of acts of sexual violence (including “sexual slavery”) as some of the most egregious crimes in conflict. They did so at some cost, however. By foregrounding sexual harm, they deflected attention from other forms of violence, including gender-based violence, moving further away from the original motivation of many early women’s human rights advocates and scholars. In addition, the vehicle used to recognize the serious nature of sexual violence—crimes against humanity—functioned both to reinforce ethnic difference and to deny women’s sexual agency. As we see in Chapter Four, the doctrinal recognition and treatment of genocidal rape in the ICTR mirrored these consequences. CHAP TE R FO U R Calling in the Judges: Rwanda O N T H E E V E O F T H E R WA N DA G E N O C I D E and just over eighteen months after the establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY), the Security Council once again used its powers under Chapter VII of the UN Charter, this time to establish the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR). The tribunal’s mandate was to try crimes of genocide and “other serious violations of international humanitarian law” committed in Rwanda and by Rwandans in neighboring territories in 1994.1 Like the ICTY, the ICTR proved to be an important forum for the development of international criminal jurisprudence on rape and sexual violence and, as such, an important ground for feminist engagement and critique. In contrast to the ICTY, which never found rape to be a constitutive act of genocide, the ICTR handed down a number of convictions for rape as genocide. Through its jurisprudence in those cases, it made significant contributions to the formation and concretization of the common-sense narratives about shame and stigma that we have seen thus far. Most importantly, in concluding that rape and sexual violence were acts of genocide, intended to destroy an ethnic group in whole or in part, it embedded in its jurisprudence the notion that rape destroys individuals and tears communities apart, in large part due to shame. The assumption that rape victims are shamed into silence, which we saw so vividly in Chapter Two, also played a significant role in the ICTR. Prosecutors consistently cited shame as an obstacle to prosecution as they devised a number of means to attempt to mediate it. This chapter considers how these two functions of shame—one that doctrinally links rape and genocide and another that makes it hard to elicit testimony to prove rape—operated side by side. 101 102 Chapter 4 Unlike the ICTY, the ICTR was not instituted to intervene in an ongoing conflict, but to respond to genocide after it occurred. The newly installed, Tutsi-led Rwandan government initially requested the creation of a tribunal in September 1994 and even participated in the drafting of the resolution founding the ICTR. Nevertheless, it eventually cast the sole vote against the resolution for a variety of reasons, including that the ICTR would be housed in Tanzania, rather than Rwanda, and that it would not allow for capital punishment.2 The Security Council resolutions that set up the ICTR and the ICTY differed in important respects, indicating the principal concerns that motivated them. While only the ICTR resolution named “genocide,” only the ICTY resolution mentioned rape. Though rape had been reported by numerous intergovernmental organizations leading up to the establishment of the ICTY, it was not discussed in the reports of either the UN Special Rapporteur to Rwanda or the Commission of Experts that was formed to advise the Security Council on Rwanda.3 The failure of the text of the resolution to mention rape did not, however, prevent its inclusion in the ICTR statute. The statute followed that of the ICTY by listing rape as a possible crime against humanity.4 It also added a reference to rape through its inclusion of an article on serious violations of common Article 3 and Additional Protocol II of the Geneva Conventions.5 That article was not in the ICTY statute, though the tribunal essentially incorporated it through its jurisprudence on war crimes.The article listed rape under its examples of “outrages upon personal dignity,” which were “humiliating and degrading treatment, rape, enforced prostitution and any form of indecent assault.”6 If this addition made up for the omission of the identification of rape as a war crime or grave breach in the ICTY statute, it also defined rape in terms of dignity and associated it with humiliation, two moves that many feminists were actively trying to avoid.7 Indeed, around the same time the statute was drafted, feminists were beginning to engage actively in the drafting of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC), aiming in part, as Janet Halley puts it, to “delink” honor and dignity from sexual offenses. Halley explains that feminists succeeded in getting the Rome Statute to list “outrages upon personal dignity, in particular humiliating or degrading treatment” separately from rape and other listed forms of sexual violence.8 Yet, even as feminist advocates were seeking these changes in the ICC statute, they also engaged in prosecution and litigation strategies before both the ICTY and the ICTR that perpetuated the linkage.9 The linkage Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 103 extended beyond the framing and interpretation of war crimes; the jurisprudence on crimes against humanity and genocide was also highly reliant on interpretations of rape as humiliating, or shameful.10 The feminist debates over genocidal rape that we saw with regard to the former Yugoslavia did not surface in the context of Rwanda for a variety of reasons. In contrast to their treatment of the conflict in the former Yugoslavia, feminist and mainstream advocates and institutions largely agreed from the start that Hutus had engaged in genocide against the Tutsi group in Rwanda. Additionally, if controversially, only Hutus were tried by the ICTR.11 Nearly all of the indictments against them included charges of genocide. Once the Office of the Prosecutor (OTP) began to investigate and charge instances of rape, many indictments of genocide included acts of rape. In 1998, the ICTR handed down its first judgment, convicting Jean-Paul Akayesu, the Hutu bourgmestre (mayor) of Taba commune, of genocide and crimes against humanity for acts that included rapes of Tutsi women held in the commune.12 Many have considered the Akayesu decision pathbreaking for a number of reasons. Not only was it the first conviction for genocide by any international tribunal, but it was also the first rape conviction by one of the ad hoc tribunals, predating all of the ICTY cases examined in Chapter Three.13 Most importantly for many feminists, it was the first international criminal judgment to pronounce that acts of rape constituted genocide. It did so even without finding that Akayesu himself committed rape.14 Patricia Viseur Sellers, former prosecutor and Legal Advisor for Gender Related Crimes at the ICTY and ICTR, approvingly deemed the decision’s treatment of sex-based crimes in Akayesu “stunning.”15 Nevertheless, many, including Viseur Sellers, contended that the ICTR did not live up to Akayesu’s early promise. Some complained that, especially given what later came to light about the pervasiveness of rape and sexual violence during the Rwandan genocide, the tribunal convicted relatively few people for those acts. Indeed, although charges of rape or sexual violence were included in the indictments of more than half (52 of 93) of the individuals charged, only 36 were eventually tried on those charges. And only one-third of those 36 were finally convicted of such crimes.16 Of the 12 convicted, 6 were found guilty of rape or sexual violence both as genocide and as a crime against humanity, while the remaining 6 were convicted of rape or sexual violence as a crime against humanity, but not genocide. Five of the 12 were also found guilty of rape or sexual violence as war crimes.17 104 Chapter 4 Although a number of feminists have criticized the tribunal for its low conviction rate, few have scrutinized the jurisprudence in those cases that did result in convictions. Here, I assess and challenge much of that judicial reasoning on some of the same grounds that I critiqued the genocidal-rape position and its effect on ICTY jurisprudence in previous chapters. I am particularly concerned about the ICTR’s reliance upon and perpetuation of problematic assumptions about shame—or humiliation—and stigma, especially in its judgments finding rapes to be constitutive of genocide. After considering those decisions, I look at how similar assumptions are operant in prosecutorial attempts to manage perceived shame. I. The Doctrinal Function of Shame In contrast to the former Yugoslavia, a number of international legal responses to the Rwandan genocide accepted relatively early on that rape could constitute an act of genocide. They did so by attributing to the Hutus the intent to use rape to humiliate and shame the Tutsis as an ethnic group, in ways that would lead to the group’s destruction. This argument had seeds in reports issued after the ICTR’s establishment, and it took root in Akayesu and subsequent ICTR case law. It is partly because of this tight connection between genocide and intended shame, I contend, that the conception of rape as a violation of dignity and honor has had such staying power, notwithstanding its explicit disavowal by many feminists. Perhaps the first official call for the ICTR to consider trying individuals for acts of rape as genocide came from the Commission of Experts, in its final report that was released one month after the Security Council resolution establishing the ICTR. While its preliminary report had omitted discussion of rape, this one stated, “Disturbing reports have been filed with [us] that document the abduction and rape of women and girls in Rwanda during the period of armed conflict in Rwanda.”18 It relied upon an African Rights report that it had apparently not consulted earlier, which had devoted 40 (of 742) pages to “rape and abductions of women and girls.”19 Importantly, the African Rights report asserted that “rape is an instrument of genocide.”20 It based that conclusion in part on the claim that rape “destroys the fundamental fabric of interpersonal relations that constitutes a community. It shatters the sense of security and identity of the victim, and isolates her from her family and community.”21 The Commission of Experts’ final report contained significant analysis of the international legal criminalization of rape, borrowing in part from work done in the context of the former Yugoslavia. It endorsed the findings of the Special Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 105 Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights in the former Yugoslavia, which had linked ethnic cleansing and the shame of rape by stating, “Rape has been used not only as an attack on the individual victim, but is intended to humiliate, shame, degrade and terrify the entire ethnic group.”22 The Commission of Experts then turned directly to the possibility of genocidal rape: “There are clear cases where rape, which undoubtedly constitutes ‘serious bodily or mental harm,’ is perpetrated . . . as a systematic policy.” Quoting the Genocide Convention, the sentence continued, “alongside or as part of a larger policy that is ‘committed with intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnic[al], racial or religious group, as such.’”23 It therefore called upon the prosecutor to “explore fully the relation between the policy of systematic rape . . . as a crime against humanity on the one hand, and . . . as a crime of genocide on the other.”24 Akayesu provided the opportunity to pursue that relationship. In doing so, it put into legal doctrine on genocide some of the common-sense beliefs about communal shame. A. The ICTR Charges against Akayesu The case against Akayesu did not begin with the aim of procuring a conviction for rape as an act of genocide. In fact, the OTP included neither rape nor any other act of sexual violence in the original indictment against him. Such charges were absent notwithstanding the seeds planted by the report of the Commission of Experts and general pressure from the Coalition on Women’s Human Rights in Conflict Situations, an organization composed of more than forty Rwandan and international women’s human rights groups set up specifically to ensure the investigation of sexual violence crimes in Rwanda.25 Rape charges became a part of the case against Akayesu only after the trial began.26 In short, in January 1997, eighteen days into the trial, a witness testified during direct examination that when the Hutu Interahamwe (a paramilitary organization) came to kill her father, they raped her six-year-old daughter. She also stated that ICTR investigators had not asked her about rape. In response to questions from the bench, she further testified that she had heard of, though not witnessed, other incidents of rape, specifically of young girls in the bureau communal (central public building) of Taba commune.27 In March 1997, a second witness testified that she herself had been raped at the commune and that Akayesu had encouraged the Hutu Interahamwe, which the prosecution contended was under his command, to rape their Tutsi women prisoners.28 At that point, the presiding judge, Navanethem (“Navi”) Pillay 106 Chapter 4 (who later became UN High Commissioner for Human Rights), stayed the proceedings pending further investigation, which she ordered the prosecutor to conduct.29 The Coalition on Women’s Human Rights in Conflict Situations submitted an amicus curiae (friend-of-the-court) brief to the tribunal. According to Rhonda Copelon, three organizations took the lead in drafting the brief: the International Women’s Human Rights Clinic, directed by Copelon; the Center for Constitutional Rights, with whom Copelon had worked on a U.S. civil lawsuit against Radovan Karadžić (though representing different plaintiffs than Catharine MacKinnon did30); and the Working Group on Engendering the Rwanda Tribunal.31 Given the group’s focus on women’s human rights, the brief naturally relied upon parts of the Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, discussed in detail in Chapter One. It urged the Trial Chamber to invite the prosecutor to amend the indictment, supplement its investigation, and examine why existing indictments had failed to include charges of rape or sexual violence.32 Citing trial testimony, the prosecution’s reference to sexual assault in its opening statement, and numerous reports documenting rape and sexual violence in Rwanda, the brief argued that the prosecution’s failure to charge Akayesu with acts of rape or sexual violence raised “questions about the commitment of the Tribunal to the elimination of gender-based violence as well as the protection and advancement of the human rights of women.”33 Approximately five weeks after the trial was stayed, the prosecution made a motion to amend the indictment, which the Trial Chamber granted. The amended indictment added two charges of crimes against humanity—one for rape and another for other inhumane acts. It also added a charge of “outrages upon personal dignity, in particular rape, degrading and humiliating treatment and indecent assault.”34 The prosecution did not amend the genocide counts, apparently because it considered the definition of genocide to cover the new evidence of rape and other forms of sexual violence.35 The amendment of the indictment turned out to be a rare occurrence. Indeed, subsequent cases in the ICTR as well as in the ICTY and ICC have demonstrated that judges, and sometimes prosecutors, have been reluctant to amend indictments under similar circumstances.36 But in this case, the tribunal seemed to have been influenced at least partly by the prosecution’s argument that the previous insufficiency of evidence linking the accused to rape was attributable not only to “insensitivity in the investigation of sexual violence,” but to “the shame that accompanies acts of sexual violence as well.”37 As we see below, this suggestion Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 107 that shame prevents victims from testifying would continue to be offered as an obstacle to the successful prosecution of rape and sexual violence. B. The ICTR’s Reasoning in Akayesu If shame provided something of an alibi for the prosecution’s failure to include charges of rape and sexual violence in the original indictment against Akayesu, it played an even more significant role in his genocide conviction. In addition to finding him guilty of genocide, the tribunal also found him guilty of direct and public incitement to commit genocide and multiple counts of crimes against humanity. The latter included those counts from the amended indictment for rape and other inhumane acts.38 The judgment concluded that Akayesu had knowledge of acts of rape and sexual violence in or near the bureau communal, and that he did not attempt to prevent them.39 Moreover, in some instances, he ordered, instigated, or encouraged the sexual violence.40 Although Akayesu is notable for its finding that rape and sexual violence constituted a crime against humanity under the ICTR statute, it is best known for its holding that acts of rape constituted genocide. I dwell here on that part of the judgment, in particular on the link the Trial Chamber drew between rape and genocide. It was there that the shame and stigma of rape became doctrinally necessary to the genocide finding. I consider only the trial decision, not the appellate decision, because Akayesu did not challenge on appeal the legal conclusion regarding the link between rape and genocide.41 To understand the tribunal’s ruling, we need to revisit the definition of genocide, which is found in Article 2(2) of the ICTR statute and which, like other international criminal statutes, incorporates the definition from the Genocide Convention. Under that definition, genocide requires “intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a national, ethnical, racial or religious group,” and requires that one of the following acts be done with that intent: “a) Killing members of the group; b) Causing serious bodily or mental harm to members of the group; c) Deliberately inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical destruction in whole or in part; d) Imposing measures intended to prevent births within the group; e) Forcibly transferring children of the group to another group.”42 Chapter Two discussed the ways in which some feminists used this definition to argue that rape constituted genocide in the former Yugoslavia. They were opposed by other feminists, including Copelon, who believed that an emphasis on genocidal rape took away needed attention to rapes on all sides. Yet the amicus 108 Chapter 4 brief that Copelon coauthored as part of the Coalition on Women’s Human Rights in Conflict Situations made arguments that rapes of Tutsi women by Hutu men during the relevant time period were genocidal. She was able to do so in part because, as already noted, the ICTR focused nearly exclusively on crimes committed by Hutus against Tutsis. That said, the brief ’s argument that rape constituted genocide said surprisingly little about the nexus between rape and genocide. Indeed, only one paragraph addressed the issue head-on. Referencing Article 2(2)(a)-(d) of the statute, it stated, “Rape and other forms of sexual violence, including killing pregnant women, also constitute genocide where the requirements of Article 2 are met.” It then applied the statement to Rwanda, contending that “rape and sexual violence were an integral part of the genocidal campaign, inspired by hatred of Tutsi women, designed to result in death or to destroy a woman from a physical, mental or social perspective and her capacity to participate in the reproduction and production of the community.”43 That paragraph, perhaps in its vagueness, reflected both sides of the debate among feminists with regard to the former Yugoslavia. While it seemed to focus on the intent to use rape to kill or destroy “a woman” (rather than the group), it also added the possibility that the Hutus meant to harm the group by diminishing individual women’s “capacity to participate in the reproduction and production of the community.” This reference to reproduction, together with the mention of the killing of pregnant women, implicitly invoked Article 2(2)(d) of the statute, regarding the imposition of measures intended to prevent births. But it stayed away from a claim about the womb being occupied by another ethnicity, a claim on which some had based their genocidal rape arguments in the former Yugoslavia.44 The brief suggested further ambivalence about the genocide-rape nexus in its conclusion. It called for the prosecutor to amend the indictment to include charges of crimes against humanity and grave breaches.45 It was less directive with regard to genocide, asking the prosecutor to “consider charging Akayesu with rape as an act of genocide pursuant to . . . the Statute,” quoting the final report of the Commission of Experts for support.46 The brief avoided mention of humiliation or shame, perhaps suggesting the advocates’ unease with that language. But it was unable to escape the concept totally. By using the final report of the Commission of Experts to urge the prosecutor to consider charges of rape as genocide, the brief relied, if implicitly, on language that named the intent of rape to “humiliate, shame, degrade and terrify” Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 109 both the victim and “the entire ethnic group.”47 Further, other members of the coalition had been attempting to influence the ICTR with that very language. Human Rights Watch, for example, had issued a report the previous year calling for the ICTR to investigate rape and sexual violence crimes. The report, titled Shattered Lives and written by feminist Binaifer Nowrojee, made shame, stigmatization, and even loss of honor central to its analysis of rape as a weapon of war: The humiliation, pain and terror inflicted by the rapist is meant to degrade not just the individual woman but also to strip the humanity from the larger group of which she is a part. The rape of one person is translated into an assault upon the community through the emphasis placed in every culture on women’s sexual virtue: the shame of the rape humiliates the family and all those associated with the survivor.48 Although Nowrojee also noted that the harm done to individual women is “often obscured or even compounded by the perceived harm to the community,” she did so to support her claim that “in Rwanda, as elsewhere in the world, rape and other gender-based violations carry a severe social stigma.”49 Women’s injuries “are aggravated by a sense of isolation and ostracization.”50 Perhaps aware of the risk of putting the blame on the Tutsis for the ostracism of their own community members, she insisted that the harm is universal. Universal or particular, it is characterized by loss of honor and shame. When the Trial Chamber eventually considered the questions of whether and how rape and sexual violence might constitute genocide, it largely followed the lead of the Commission of Experts. That is, the Trial Chamber’s judgment in Akayesu readily accepted that rape and sexual violence “constitute genocide in the same way as any other act as long as they were committed with the specific intent to destroy, in whole or in part, a particular group, targeted as such.”51 It found that “the rape of Tutsi women was systematic,” demonstrating the group focus.52 It also concluded that rape “was perpetrated against all Tutsi women and solely against them.”53 Of course, it defies reason to suggest that every Tutsi woman was raped, so the meaning of the claim is unclear. Perhaps the Trial Chamber meant to suggest that all Tutsi women were targeted and therefore raped in some sense. The Trial Chamber’s statement that rape was perpetrated solely against the Tutsis was, again, less controversial than parallel claims in the context of the former Yugoslavia would have been. But it was nevertheless complicated by later cases where, in the context of crime against humanity charges, evidence revealed that Hutu women had been raped as well. Since in those cases 110 Chapter 4 they had been raped by Hutu men, the tribunal avoided the complication by finding that they were raped either due to mistaken identity or because of their affiliation with Tutsi men.54 Akayesu applied the Genocide Convention with a focus on Articles 2(2)(b), “causing serious bodily or mental harm to members of the group,” and 2(2)(c), inflicting “conditions of life calculated to bring about its physical destruction in whole or in part.” With regard to 2(2)(b), the judgment stated that “rape and sexual violence certainly constitute infliction of serious bodily and mental harm on the victims and are even . . . one of the worst ways of inflict[ing] harm on the victim as he or she suffers both.”55 In terms of 2(2)(c), the Trial Chamber found that “sexual violence was an integral part of the process of destruction, specifically targeting Tutsi women and specifically contributing to their destruction and to the destruction of the Tutsi group as a whole.”56 As is required by the statute, the Trial Chamber further found that Akayesu engaged in those acts “with the specific intent to destroy the Tutsi group, as such.”57 For both Article 2(2)(c) and the specific intent requirement under the statute, the Trial Chamber needed to explain how rape and sexual violence were intended to destroy the group. The Trial Chamber never explicitly considered the question under specific intent, but its Article 2(2)(c) analysis, which centered around shame, discussed as humiliation, is instructive. The judgment cited specific instances of acts by the Interahamwe against Tutsi women, which it stated were intended to humiliate them. Indeed, part of the psychological harm that the Trial Chamber attributed to some women who were raped came from their subjection to the “worst public humiliation.”58 The humiliation to individual women, however, would not suffice for the statute’s requirements. Ultimately, a finding of humiliation experienced by the entire community led the Trial Chamber to conclude that sexual violence was “a step in the process of destruction of the Tutsi group—destruction of the spirit, the will to live, and of life itself.”59 C. Feminist Reasoning and Akayesu Many feminists, including some who were skeptical of a concentration on, or even the naming of, genocidal rape in the former Yugoslavia supported the decision in Akayesu. Copelon, for example, considered both the amendment of the indictment and the judgment as feminist victories and positive examples of NGO advocacy. She noted that it was ironic, given the initial struggle to have rape and sexual violence recognized, that the evidence associated with those acts ended up carrying much of the evidentiary burden for proving genocide.60 Further, she Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 111 contended that “by emphasizing the suffering imposed on the women as well as its role as a tool of their destruction and the destruction of the group, the Trial Chamber took a significant step in recognizing women both as subjects in themselves and as part of their ethnicity.”61 Copelon’s praise for the recognition of both the gender and the ethnic harm followed at some level the amicus brief ’s attempt to straddle the two. But Copelon read into the judgment a hierarchy of the harms by arguing that, for the Trial Chamber, “rape and sexual violence are understood as instruments of genocide based primarily on the physical and psychological harm to the woman, and secondarily on the potential impact of this on the targeted community.”62 In doing so, she missed the extent to which genocidal intent requires the focus on the ethnic community. As much as she might have wanted rape of women classified as genocidal because it aimed at destroying women qua women, the tribunal in fact carved out no doctrinal space for such recognition. I do concur with Copelon, however, on one aspect of her interpretation of the decision. Although some feminists read Akayesu to find genocide based on Article 2(2)(d), relating to “measures intended to prevent births within the group,” Copelon disagreed. Indeed, she commended the tribunal for not resting its decision on that provision. The chamber did generally recognize that rape can, “in patriarchal societies,” amount to genocide under Article 2(2)(d) when perpetrated with the intent to “have [the victim] give birth to a child who will consequently not belong to its mother’s group,”63 but it did not ultimately connect the provision to Rwanda, nor cite it as a basis for the conviction. For Copelon, “it is significant that Akayesu did not, as some had contended, emphasize the reproductive consequences as the hallmark of rape as a genocidal measure” because “to emphasize the reproductive impact on the community would threaten once again to reduce women to being simply the vehicles of the continuity of the targeted population.”64 Just a year after the judgment, Hilary Charlesworth, who shared Copelon’s aim of highlighting the harm to women, read the decision quite differently from Copelon. Offering one of the few feminist critiques of the judgment’s reasoning, Charlesworth disagreed with the emphasis on ethnic harm but also saw the tribunal as having little choice: The emphasis on the harm to the Tutsi people as a whole is, of course, required by the international definition of genocide, and the Akayesu decision on this point simply illustrates the inability of the law to properly name what is at stake: rape is wrong, not because it is a crime of violence against women and a manifestation 112 Chapter 4 of male dominance, but because it is an assault on a community defined only by its racial, religious, national or ethnic composition. In this account, the violation of a woman’s body is secondary to the humiliation of the group.65 Charlesworth argued that “this understanding of rape perpetuates a view of women as cultural objects or bodies on which and through which war can be waged.”66 Charlesworth’s interpretation of both the doctrine and the view it perpetuates has been borne out, as evidenced by the persistence of the commonsense view that rape “tears communities apart.” In that same article, Charlesworth criticized the ways in which the protection of men’s and women’s honor has long been used to justify the criminalization of wartime rape.67 Most feminists have concurred, as seen in the changes made to the ICC statute considered at the start of this chapter. Notwithstanding these concerns, feminist engagement with the ICTR helped to facilitate a ruling that, through its assumptions about individual and communal shame, perpetuated many of the same social constructs that supported the concept of honor. As a result, the ICTR’s judgment essentially placed the blame for the genocide (or at least for the role of rape and sexual violence in it) on the very group that was the target of it. Although the arguments made about genocidal rape in Rwanda relied less on stereotypes of Tutsis than similar (if legally unsuccessful) arguments about Bosnia did on stereotypes of Muslims, they still required group humiliation that would account for, in Nowrojee’s words, the “ostracization and isolation” of the women who had been raped. D. The Legacy of Akayesu in Subsequent ICTR Jurisprudence The Akayesu ruling might not have led to the large number of convictions or even indictments for rape as genocide that some feminists who originally lauded it had expected, but it nevertheless had effects. We can see Akayesu’s legacy in a number of cases that directly or indirectly followed the judgment’s assumptions about the harm of rape and sexual violence as well as its linkage of rape to genocide. Doris Buss and Linda Bianchi have both demonstrated that, despite the relatively small number of convictions, the tribunal nevertheless provided accounts of widespread rape and sexual violence. Indeed, Buss “(re) reads” the record to show how the tribunal often went out of its way to discuss such violence, even when it was not included in the charges before it, and Bianchi provides additional examples.68 While for the most part, Buss and Bianchi see this documentation of widespread rape and sexual violence in the case law as positive,69 I point to problematic ways that Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 113 the tribunal documented that violence. My biggest concerns arise from the tribunal’s continued reliance on the reasoning in Akayesu. Some decisions of the tribunal simply restated Akayesu’s conclusion that rape or sexual violence can constitute an act of genocide.70 Others used Akayesu’s reasoning to reiterate the centrality of humiliation and shame to the harm. Musema, a case in which the accused’s conviction for genocide included a count of rape, provides an example of the latter.71 Like most other ICTR convictions of rape as an act of genocide, the Trial Chamber found that rape and other forms of sexual violence caused “serious bodily and mental harm” under Article 2(2)(b) of the statute.72 In terms of intent, it found that women were targets, and that rape and sexual violence contributed to “their destruction and therefore that of the Tutsi group as such.”73 The judgment made explicit the common sense about harm that we have seen assumed elsewhere, saying that a victim “who was left for dead by those who raped her, had indeed been killed in a way.” It also quoted another witness’s testimony “that ‘what they did to her is worse than death.’”74 If rape was a fate worse than death for the victim herself, humiliation was key to the destruction of the group. Indeed, the chamber used the finding that rape and other forms of sexual violence were “accompanied by humiliating utterances” as proof of genocidal intent, pointing in particular to the accused’s statement that “the pride of the Tutsis will end today.” For the chamber, such utterances “clearly indicated that the intention underlying each specific act was to destroy the Tutsi group as a whole.”75 Similarly, in Karemera, two of the accused were convicted of genocide involving rape and sexual violence and of rape as a crime against humanity. In its discussion of the acts of genocide, the Trial Chamber reasoned: “Many of these women were subjected to severe humiliation and physical injuries. As a consequence, these crimes did not only cause serious bodily and mental harm to the women themselves, but also, by extension, to their families and communities.”76 The chamber went on to note that “many Tutsi women were killed after they were subjected to rapes and sexual assaults.”77 Their murder, however, was not required for the genocide conviction. Rather, sexual violence combined with the subsequent humiliation—to the individual women as well as to their communities—to constitute genocide. The ICTR began to associate genocide with rape and sexual violence to such an extent that, in some instances, rape and sexual violence became stand-ins for genocidal intent. That is, the tribunal sometimes used evidence of rape and sexual violence to demonstrate general genocidal intent, even in cases in which rape 114 Chapter 4 or sexual violence had not been charged (properly) as genocide. For example, in Nyiramasuhuko (the only international criminal case in which a woman was convicted of genocide, which I discuss further in the Epilogue), the Trial Chamber found the indictment of rape as genocide to be defective.78 It nevertheless found Nyiramasuhuko guilty of conspiracy to commit genocide and of rape as a crime against humanity. Inferring genocidal intent for the non-rape charges, the Trial Chamber stated: “Nyiramasuhuko ordered Interahamwe to rape refugees. This evidences Nyiramasuhuko’s intent to destroy, in whole or in part, the Tutsi group.”79 In other cases, the tribunal derived genocidal intent from evidence not related to sexual violence and then applied that intent to counts of rape and sexual violence. Such analysis avoided the need to find genocidal intent for the sexual acts. Instead, it saw any sexual violence it interpreted as falling under 2(2)(a)-(e) as having genocidal intent. In Gacumbitsi, for example, the Trial Chamber first found genocidal intent based on “the scale of the massacres and the fact that Tutsis were targeted, including in the incitement by the Accused.”80 Then it turned to Article 2(2)(a) and (b) of the statute for the requisite acts. As for the rapes, the chamber found that “these rapes caused serious physical harm to members of the Tutsi ethnic group,” and went on simply to conclude that “Sylvestre Gacumbitsi incurs responsibility for the crime of genocide by instigating the rape of Tutsi women and girls.”81 A wrinkle emerged in Gacumbitsi, however: one of the rape victims was a Hutu woman. The tribunal’s treatment of that wrinkle further demonstrated its prioritization of the harm to the ethnic group over the harm to women, and even suggested that the tribunal saw the main harm to an ethnic group as falling to its male members. Because the victim was married to a Tutsi man, the Trial Chamber reasoned that “through the woman, it was her husband, a Tutsi civilian, who was the target. Thus, the rape was part of the widespread attacks against Tutsi civilians.”82 This reasoning related only to a crime against humanity charge because, as Buss points out, the ICTR considered only Tutsi women as genocide victims.83 Nevertheless, this notion of harm to the ethnic group resonates with the one in the genocide analysis as well: Tutsi men (as a stand-in for the group) were harmed by the sexual violence against women in their communities or families. Only one sexual violence case before the ICTR veered away from the inferences of genocidal intent found in Akayesu and its progeny. That case, Rukundo, also brought to the fore assumptions about the harm of sexual assault (short of rape) and about the role of shame. In 2010, the Appeals Chamber reversed Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 115 Rukundo’s genocide conviction based on sexual assault. According to the Appeals Chamber, the prosecutor had not provided sufficient evidence that the assault was committed for genocidal—rather than opportunistic—reasons. The appeals judgment attracted strong dissent and criticism from feminist scholars, including one who labeled it a “regressive decision.”84 The case involved Emmanuel Rukundo, who was a priest. A Tutsi woman he knew sought him out and asked him to hide her. He refused, saying that she and her family must be killed because of the affiliation of one of her family members with the Rwandan Patriotic Front. He nevertheless let her into his room, after which he locked the door and sexually assaulted her.85 The Trial Chamber based its conviction for genocide on a finding that the assault constituted the infliction of serious mental harm, referencing Article 2(2)(b) of the statute and quoting Akayesu’s conclusion that rape and sexual violence is “one of the worst ways of inflicting harm on the victim.”86 It also followed other decisions to say that “‘serious harm’ need not entail permanent or irremediable harm.”87 A dissent in the Trial Chamber challenged the judgment’s implicit assumption that sexual assault inevitably results in the level of serious mental harm required for a genocide conviction. It also criticized the majority for presuming that such mental harm was the only reasonable conclusion to be drawn from the existence of the circumstances—an ongoing genocide against the Tutsi and the victim’s being a Tutsi woman who had testified that, in the dissenting judge’s words, the “shame of the incident prevented her from telling anyone.”88 When the Appeals Chamber reversed, it did not follow the dissent but found instead “that [the accused’s] act could reasonably be construed as an opportunistic crime that was not accompanied by the specific intent to commit genocide.”89 The chamber went on to say that its conclusion “does not alter the highly degrading and non-consensual nature of the act committed,” but that, although the assault occurred during a genocide, it “was not necessarily a part of the genocide itself.”90 As the various opinions in the Rukundo case reveal, shame can play a paradoxical role in the analysis of genocide. On one hand, the community is presumed to be shamed, which helps explain why the public nature of rapes and sexual violence is often mentioned. On the other, shame is often seen to lead to a victim’s silence. Yet, if the sexual assault is not public and the victim is presumed to be too ashamed to tell anyone about it, it is difficult to see how the assault harms the group, making it challenging to argue that it was committed with the intent of destroying the group. Advocates and judges (as in the Trial Chamber’s judgment in Rukundo) have skirted this issue in a variety of ways we have 116 Chapter 4 seen here, primarily by assuming, rather than making a finding of fact about, communal and sometimes individual shame. The presumption of individual shame is also often proffered by prosecutors as an obstacle to obtaining sexual violence convictions, an issue to which I now turn. II. Shame as Prosecutorial Alibi If many feminists have been loath to challenge the reasoning of the ICTR in its convictions for rape and sexual violence, they have not, as already suggested, hesitated to criticize the relatively low rates of indictments and convictions for those crimes. Critics have attributed the rates to a number of causes, many of which put the blame squarely on the OTP. Among the institutional problems identified are scarce resources,91 inadequate training and investigations,92 faulty drafting of indictments,93 inconsistencies in prosecutorial strategy and charging practices with respect to crimes involving rape and sexual violence,94 and failure to appeal acquittals in a timely manner.95 While those within the OTP who were also disappointed by the indictment and conviction rates often ascribed these institutional problems to a lack of resources or to “general lack of understanding” and “experience” concerning the investigation and prosecution of sexual violence,96 outside critics have asserted that these issues merely compounded an overriding lack of political will in the OTP itself.97 These criticisms are not totally distinct from another concern voiced by some feminists and policy-makers, but especially by the ICTR’s own internal analyses of rape and sexual violence prosecutions at the tribunal: the reluctance of victims to testify about their experiences of sexual violence seriously hindered effective investigation, trial testimony, and, ultimately, conviction.98 As we have seen elsewhere, including in Chapter Two’s discussion of the ICC investigation in Libya, prosecutors and investigators, as well as some policy-makers and feminist advocates, often contended that shame and the possibility of being marked by stigma inhibited the ability or willingness of victims to speak about sexual violence. As Nowrojee put it in Human Rights Watch’s Shattered Lives, “Rwandan women who have been raped or who suffered sexual abuse generally do not dare reveal their experiences publicly, fearing that they will be rejected by their family and wider community and that they will never be able to reintegrate or to marry.”99 The ICTR regularly invoked this concern to explain the difficulty of obtaining testimony. Recall, for example, that when amending the Akayesu indictment after the trial had begun, the Trial Chamber endorsed the prosecutor’s rationale that there had been insufficient evidence to include sexual violence in the original Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 117 indictment due in part to “the shame that accompanies acts of sexual violence.”100 Several years later, ICTR prosecutor Alex Obote-Odora attributed the difficulty of investigating sex-based crimes, or even of gaining an accurate count of the number of victims, to the infliction of “physical and psychological wounds, which women can conceal, avoiding further emotional anguish, ostracization, and retaliation from perpetrators who may live nearby.”101 His description invoked the stigma associated with rape, suggesting the incentive for women who have been raped either to “pass” or to “cover,” in Erving Goffman’s terms.102 This invocation of stigma was meant to limit the responsibility of ICTR investigators for their failures to prosecute rape; if the women would not talk to them, investigators could not do their job. While many feminist advocates were critical of the claims of investigators and prosecutors that women would not talk about sexual violence, they rarely challenged the assumptions of shame and stigma that lay behind such claims. Rather, they tended to treat the issue as a technocratic problem and to focus on proposing ways to manage shame.103 They sought methods for coaxing sexual violence victims to tell their stories to investigators and testify at trial. Their suggestions included improved training for investigators and witnesses, the addition of more female investigators, and better translation work.104 The idea was that under the right circumstances women could be encouraged to talk. As Shattered Lives explained (based on Human Rights Watch’s experience of having had victims tell their stories), “If interviews are conducted in conditions of safety and privacy, and if Rwandan women believe that telling their testimony will help bring about justice, they will talk.”105 Although the report took this position to counter ICTR staff members’ “mistaken assertion” that “they do not need to devote scarce resources to investigating rape because Rwandan women will not come forward to talk,”106 it nevertheless reinforced the common-sense assumptions, contending that “in Rwanda, as throughout the world, there is profound shame and stigma associated with rape.”107 The OTP responded to criticisms and suggestions for obtaining victim and witness testimony with a series of “best practices” manuals, beginning in 2008. The manuals were recommended by the Committee for Review of the Prosecution of Sexual Violence, established in 2007 and chaired by Linda Bianchi. The final manual, published in 2014, aims to draw from lessons learned at the ICTR by outlining a number of “protective measures” that should be implemented more broadly to encourage testimony on rape and sexual violence in conflict. Its “guiding principle” is “to avoid, to the maximum extent possible, re-traumatizing the 118 Chapter 4 victims,” though some trauma “is inevitable.”108 It explicitly relies on the analysis of stigmatization and its effects set out in Shattered Lives, and states that “victims in sexual violence cases are often subjected to public scrutiny of their sexual past, shamed with the stigma of being ‘dishonored,’ and even ostracized by their own families and communities.”109 It therefore calls for protective measures to avoid revealing the identity of victims so as to “secure [their] willingness to cooperate with the investigation and prosecution.”110 The 2014 manual proposes a variety of methods for managing shame to encourage witnesses to talk. Its proposals range from those addressing the need to use relatively well-accepted interview techniques in general111 to those focused on how better to take into account issues of gender and culture.112 With regard to gender, the manual calls for gender parity, especially in leadership positions on investigation and prosecution teams, contending that “victims and witnesses often prefer to deal with investigators and prosecutors of the same gender, age, and ethnicity as them.”113 It does not, however, make the same call for parity with regard to ethnicity, though it suggests that having local staff might be helpful in understanding cultural norms.114 Relatedly, many of its recommendations seek to raise sensitivity among investigators, prosecutors, and other team members to the shameful effects of sexual violence within the culture where the investigation is taking place.115 It encourages investigators and translators, for example, to learn the euphemisms for sexual violence within given cultures, since “in some societies, it is taboo to talk openly about sexual intercourse.”116 Of course, shame and stigmatization cannot always be managed, particularly at the trial stage. Indeed, many commentators assume that rape and sexual violence victims, if they agree to testify, will be further traumatized by doing so, either because of the adversarial characteristics of the system itself or due to the responses of their families and communities. Elsie Effange-Mbella, former Gender Advisor to the ICTR Office of the Registrar, for example, contended that judicial proceedings regarding rape and sexual assault “often have a devastating and long lasting impact on the victim and witness.” Indeed, “the elements of stigmatization by the family and community, including fear of reprisals upon testifying, are almost permanently present.”117 The 2014 manual reflects this concern, telling prosecutors not to “opt for expedience,” but to discuss with witnesses the possibility of “being ostracized or stigmatized by family and community members” so that they might “make an informed decision” about whether to testify.118 Concerns about the difficulty of soliciting testimony and also the harmful impact it might have on victims have led to attempts to find alternatives to Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 119 victim testimony. As Bianchi explained in 2008, “Due to the extreme sensitivity of eliciting and obtaining this type of evidence [of sexual violence], and the detrimental impact and re-traumatization [that] providing such evidence often has on a victim, thought should be had as to alternative methods by which to bring evidence of sexual violence into the courtroom.”119 The best practices manuals have taken up that thought. The 2014 manual, for example, includes a section titled “Alternative Means to Oral Testimony.” In line with Moreno-Ocampo’s strategy on Libya that we saw in Chapter Two, it begins by instructing prosecutors that evidence can come from various sources, particularly in instances in which victims “are unable or unwilling to appear.”120 Some of those sources include expert witnesses, such as medical professionals.121 The manual also encourages prosecutors, when jurisdictions allow it, to consider using written statements by victims rather than oral testimony. That said, it recognizes that statements about the direct role of the accused in sexual violence would likely never be permitted since those victims would need to be available for cross-examination.122 When the prosecution needs victims to testify, which it often does given that victims are among the most relevant witnesses, the manual aims to ensure that they will not be required to testify as to lack of consent. Like the ICTY, the ICTR retained, through its jurisprudence, lack of consent as an element of rape. And (again like the ICTY) it allowed non-consent to be inferred in a variety of circumstances, such as during armed conflict, meaning that a witness would not need to testify or be questioned about consent.123 The manual endorses this conclusion, suggesting, as one alternative to oral testimony, evidence of “general circumstances prevailing at the time of conflict.” It further encourages the elimination of the element of non-consent altogether in “conflict and postconflict environments.”124 Feminists, especially feminist prosecutors, have paid significant attention to the impact of shame and stigmatization on individual victims of sexual violence. They have worked both to prevent that impact from becoming an obstacle to prosecution and to avoid re-traumatizing victims or introducing stigma that might result from making the sexual violence public. But these same feminists have paid much less attention to whether or how sexual violence might be made less shameful. And they have not considered seriously that sexual violence might not be shameful and stigmatizing for some, even (or especially) in those cultures that have been the subject of international criminal legal interventions around sexual violence. The ICTR essentially foreclosed such consideration through doctrinal reliance on communal shame and stigmatization. 120 Chapter 4 III. The Redistribution of Shame Notwithstanding the proposed alternatives to victim testimony, the reality is that such testimony significantly enhances the likelihood of a conviction. It is therefore the preferred approach of prosecutors, even if it risks that victims who testify will be further harmed in the trial process. Prosecutors and feminist advocates have often justified that risk by claiming that a successful conviction will be healing or at least ameliorate the shame and stigmatization of victims. For Nowrojee, for example, “the importance of holding perpetrators responsible for their actions cannot be underestimated as an aspect of healing the victims of, and witnesses to, major atrocity.”125 Even the 2014 manual concurs, at least with regard to the sentencing stage. Indeed, it recommends that the adjudication and sentencing stages be separated (which was not the case in the ICTR) because “allowing victims to be heard at sentencing promotes the healing process and recovery, and helps restore their personal dignity and respect.”126 Obote-Odora took the argument further, joining those who see international criminal mechanisms as a way to shift the shame and stigma from victim to perpetrator. After observing in the context of the ICTR that “the victims of these atrocious crimes feel ignored and invisible,” and calling upon the need to ensure that perpetrators were “severely punished,” he stated: “The perpetrator should bear the shame and stigma that society now attributes to the victim.”127 Participating in a case at the ICTR would thus offer to rape victims the possibility for the burden of shame and stigma that they carry to shift, upon conviction, to the masterminds of the genocide. Indeed, this might be one of the reasons that the manual sees shame and stigma as no longer posing a threat to victims testifying at the sentencing stage: at that point, the shame should already have shifted to the perpetrator. This emphasis on shaming arguably has roots in human rights advocacy, in that it mirrors at some level the “naming and shaming” process practiced and commended by human rights NGOs for several decades. According to Kenneth Roth, director of Human Rights Watch, “The core of our methodology is our ability to investigate, expose, and shame. We are at our most effective when we can hold governmental (or, in some cases, nongovernmental) conduct up to a disapproving public.”128 Of course, many advocates saw naming and shaming, as it was originally devised, as a weak enforcement tool, but the best that the human rights movement could do with the law it had. That was before the human rights movement began to help develop and rely upon criminal enforcement Calling in the Judges: Rwanda 121 mechanisms. That said, today’s naming and shaming differs significantly from that of old. While early naming and shaming was aimed at states, criminal law targets individuals, even individual monsters, as we have seen in the common sense.129 The new naming and shaming differs from the old in another way as well, in that it is partly justified by the claim that it relieves shame. It is as if each act contains a finite amount of shame, which must be borne fully by one or another person. However unfounded, that claim at least suggests that the shame of rape need not forever adhere to victims. But at the same time, it reinforces the idea that shame is an inevitable response to rape to begin with. It also of course works on the assumption that those who are criminally convicted of rape will actually feel shamed, and that the shame will be productive and normatively justified. The proponents of shame-shifting make no attempt to respond to the many criticisms that have been voiced of shaming (generally in the context of noncarceral alternative sentencing), which include not only that individual shaming is indecent and illiberal but counterproductive. Some argue, for example, that “shame can be a destructive emotion because it can lead one to attack others, attack self, avoid, or withdraw” and even “promote crime.”130 Perhaps there are other ways to attack shame and stigmatization associated with rape and other forms of sexual violence. But perhaps there are also ways to attack the assumption that all rape victims and their communities inevitably experience the affects and effects attributed to them. In the Epilogue, I will prompt us to imagine rape victims who are not completely destroyed by shame or do not, in any event, rely on criminal prosecution (or shaming, by whatever means) as their only or even best hope for restoration. By encouraging advocates, prosecutors, and judges to question their assumptions about the necessarily destructive effects of rape, my aim in part is to reduce the real and perceived efficacy of rape as a tool of war. In my mind, were targeted communities not to shame or stigmatize victims of sexual violence, or were victims of sexual violence otherwise not to feel completely destroyed by it, that would be a significant gain. I reach that conclusion even knowing that reducing the harm of rape and sexual violence would reduce the extent to which they could be treated as acts of genocide. But sexual violence in conflict should not need to be genocidal for either it or the conflicts in which it occurs to engender attention. CHAP TE R FIVE Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security AT T H E T U R N O F T H E T W E N T Y- F I R S T C E N T U R Y, the Women’s International League for Peace and Freedom (WILPF) joined with a number of other NGOs to establish the NGO Working Group on Women, Peace and Security (NGO Working Group).1 The NGO Working Group aimed to engage directly with the UN Security Council to ensure that the council would take women and women’s efforts at peacebuilding into account in all of its work. By focusing on peace, the group also hoped to derail the centrality of women’s victimization to feminist and mainstream thinking about gender and conflict. Felicity Hill and Maha Muna, both actively involved in the network, explained: “The strategy was to shift the focus from women as victims (without losing this aspect of conflict) to women as effective actors in peace and peacebuilding.”2 In 2000, shortly after its founding, the NGO Working Group achieved a landmark success, the unanimous passage of UN Security Council Resolution 1325.3 That resolution primarily called for measures to increase women’s participation in peacebuilding. While Resolution 1325 is mostly known for its attention to women in peacebuilding, it also called for measures to protect women and girls in conflict, including protecting them from sexual violence. Resolution 1325 became the first of a number of resolutions generally considered to be a part of the UN Security Council’s Women, Peace and Security agenda (WPS agenda). These Security Council resolutions differ significantly in kind from the ones considered in Chapters Two through Four. They were not passed under Chapter VII of the UN Charter, and therefore did not, at least on their own, authorize use of force, the creation of courts, or other coercive measures. Despite statements to 122 Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 123 the contrary, especially by those feminists who pursued the passage of Resolution 1325, these resolutions are not legally binding upon states in the way that Chapter VII resolutions are.4 That does not mean the resolutions could not be written in a way to be binding or that they do not reinforce binding obligations of states.5 Nor does it mean that they are not significant. They have in fact garnered a great deal of attention from local and global feminist groups and from UN institutional actors. And they have been important sites of contestation, including among feminists. Three of the original members of the NGO Working Group—WILPF, the Hague Appeal for Peace, and International Alert—were peace-centered organizations. Despite their deliberate aim to move away from a focus on women’s victimization in order to enhance their roles in peacebuilding, they, and what became the WPS agenda, were soon gripped by the issue of sexual violence in conflict. The grip of sexual violence is evidenced in many of the Security Council resolutions subsequent to Resolution 1325 and in related institutional developments at the UN. In 2007, for example, thirteen different UN entities came together to create UN Action Against Sexual Violence in Conflict (UN Action), to combine “efforts across the UN system with the goal of ending sexual violence during and in the aftermath of armed conflict.”6 In 2008, UN Action successfully lobbied for Resolution 1820, which focused on sexual violence in conflict. A subsequent resolution in 2009 established the Office of the Special Representative to the Secretary-General on Sexual Violence in Conflict (Special Representative on SVIC), tasked with leading UN Action efforts.7 As the Security Council has focused its attention on sexual violence over the years, primarily but not solely through the WPS agenda, it has both reflected and contributed to nearly every part of the common sense that we have examined throughout the book. Indeed, the 2014 Global Summit on Sexual Violence in Conflict discussed in the Introduction was closely connected with the WPS agenda. As I mentioned there, Zainab Bangura served as the Special Representative on SVIC from 2012 through mid-2017. She was the keynote speaker at the 2014 Global Summit, and she worked with Angelina Jolie and William Hague in their advocacy before the G8 and the Security Council. Almost all of the WPS resolutions, as well as the NGO and intergovernmental statements that accompany the production and release of them, treat sexual violence as one of the worst injuries that can occur during armed conflict. And, in line with what we have seen elsewhere, they tend to attribute much of that harm to the shame inflicted on individuals and communities. They cast perpetrators as 124 Chapter 5 individuals (and sometimes groups) who can and should be named, shamed, and prosecuted—domestically or internationally. Although some of the resolutions I consider call for counterterrorism measures, targeted sanctions, or even arguably military intervention, most of the resolutions make criminal prosecution and punishment the primary means for responding to sexual violence. They endow criminal law with the power, as seen elsewhere, both to redistribute shame from victim to perpetrator and to deter future conflicts. While much of the work of the WPS agenda suggests that women and girls are the central targets of sexual violence, its official discourse has become more inclusive of men and boys over time. The discourse increasingly uses genderneutral language, which is read as implicitly including men and boys, as well as explicit references to men and boys, alongside women and girls (who are sometimes flagged as being particularly at risk). This move away from a sole focus on women and girls (or sometimes on children) has gone along with a broader move away from the category of gender-based violence to one specifically focused on sexual injury. While these shifts are in line with the largely unstated prosecutorial strategy of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) discussed in Chapter Three, UN Action has been particularly explicit about the need to make its terminology reflect them. At least initially, the Security Council resolutions on WPS and the debates leading up to them provided an opportunity for the re-emergence of the women’s peace movement. Although the women’s peace movement has been around at least since the interwar period (indeed, WILPF was founded in 1915), it has gained and lost traction over the years.8 The Cold War had revived some of the efforts of the movement, as many women’s peace activists encouraged women to connect across the “Iron Curtain”—and other battle lines—to pressure their states to disarm and otherwise find peaceful solutions.9 But the end of the Cold War relieved the immediacy of that work, even as new conflicts emerged. When human rights became the primary avenue for feminist interventions in the new conflicts, their focus on ending the abuse of women in war, rather than on ending war itself, sidelined or transformed the women’s peace advocates and their aims. Feminist calls for military and criminal intervention, ostensibly to protect women, left little room for women’s peace advocates who opposed the use of force and promoted women as the solution to, not the victims of, conflict. Although women’s peace activism resurfaced with the NGO Working Group, and initially seemed to succeed with Resolution 1325, it did not in the end “shift the focus from women as victims,” as Hill and Muna had explained the strategy. Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 125 Indeed, Hill and Muna’s parenthetical commitment to not “losing this aspect of conflict” prevailed. As victimization narrowed to sexual violence, women’s peace activists failed to counter the common-sense representations of the harms of sexual violence. To the contrary, they reproduced them, as they included them even in the resolutions that they promoted on women’s participation in peacebuilding. Further, they arguably added to the power (which we saw in Chapter Two) of sexual violence to compel military intervention, now largely under the rubric of counterterrorism. If women’s peace advocates aimed to achieve peace and an enhanced role for women in waging it, the WPS agenda has turned those efforts on their head by sparking three developments: the emergence of a common-sense view that ending sexual violence is key to building peace, an increase in calls for militarized responses such as peacekeeping forces and counterterrorism measures, and an insistence on the need for women’s participation in those responses. Before I trace the ways in which the resolutions and discourse surrounding them reflect, concretize, and add to the common sense, even as they allow for some re-emergence of anti-war feminism, let me provide additional context for Resolution 1325 and subsequent resolutions. Most of the scholarly and policy work in this area considers only the resolutions explicitly under the WPS agenda. But to get a sense of the extent to which the issue of sexual violence in conflict has permeated Security Council resolutions and related discourse, I consider the WPS agenda alongside other Security Council activity over the past two decades. I. Overview: Human Security, the WPS Agenda, and Beyond While the NGO Working Group played a dominant role in the drafting and passage of Resolution 1325, the resolution’s emergence was also linked to another process at the Security Council. In 1998, a group of states, prompted by Canada and Norway, joined together to form the Human Security Network, with the goal of considering specific security issues, such as land mines or children in armed conflict, particularly in the context of human rights and international humanitarian law.10 They consulted with NGOs in some of their efforts, through a procedural mechanism that was later used by the NGO Working Group on WPS.11 Between August 1999 and August 2000, the Security Council passed four resolutions on human security, two on the protection of civilians in armed conflict and two on the protection of children.12 All four resolutions referred to the status of women or girls as particularly vulnerable subjects in conflict.13 The two on children cited specific concerns about sexual abuse, exploitation, and violence.14 126 Chapter 5 At least a portion of Resolution 1325—that part considering women and girls to be victims of conflict—fit well with this larger human security agenda.15 Resolution 1325 offered additional detail on the ways in which women and girls were victims of conflict, calling for those engaged in armed conflict to protect them “from gender-based violence, particularly rape and other forms of sexual abuse,”16 thereby spotlighting sexual crimes. While it also addressed other issues, like the needs for greater participation of women in peacebuilding processes and for “a gender perspective” in peacekeeping operations,17 the civilian-protection context in which Resolution 1325 was introduced offers a possible explanation for why the victimization aspect of it has had more staying power than the provisions on peacebuilding and peacekeeping. Just as the WPS agenda has both broadened and deepened over time, so too has the human security agenda. The Security Council has produced more than twenty-five resolutions that deal generally with the treatment in armed conflict of civilians, children, or women—three distinct, if overlapping categories for the resolutions. (See Table 5.1 for a partial list.) These resolutions largely embody international humanitarian law and increasingly seek to apply the rules not only to state and non-state actors, but to the UN in its peacekeeping operations. Nearly all passed unanimously and, while some states abstained on some resolutions, none voted against any of them.18 As with Security Council resolutions in general, these resolutions contain much repetition and name resolutions on the same themes that precede them. Each new resolution becomes more specific than those preceding it about its understanding of the harm that needs attention and the various enforcement mechanisms that should be used to address that harm. From 2001 through 2007, the Security Council passed no WPS resolutions, but it passed four resolutions on the protection of children and two on the protection of civilians in armed conflict. All but one referenced sexual violence, and they considered women (together with children) as a group at risk of sexual violence and exploitation.19 Almost immediately after its creation, UN Action turned its attention to the Security Council, helping to pass Resolution 1820.20 This resolution connected sexual violence to peace in a way that would eventually morph into another part of the common sense seen in the Introduction, in the refrain that “sexual violence makes wars last longer.” When used as a “tactic of war,” according to Resolution 1820, sexual violence “can significantly exacerbate situations of armed conflict and may impede the restoration of international peace and security.”21 Further, responding effectively to sexual violence “can significantly contribute Table 5.1. UN Security Council WPS resolutions in the human security context, 1999–2019 Resolution Date Focus 1261 8/25/99 Children 1265 9/17/99 Civilians 1296 4/19/00 Civilians 1314 1325 1379 1460 8/11/00 10/31/00 11/20/01 1/30/03 Children WPS Peacebuilding Children Children 1539 4/22/04 Children 1612 7/26/05 Children 1674 4/28/06 Civilians 1820 6/19/08 WPS Sexual Violence 1882 1888 8/4/09 9/30/09 Children WPS Sexual Violence 1889 10/5/09 WPS Peacebuilding 1894 11/11/09 Civilians 1960 12/16/10 WPS Sexual Violence 1998 7/12/11 Children 2068 2106 9/19/12 6/24/13 Children WPS Sexual Violence 2122 10/18/13 WPS Peacebuilding 2143 3/7/14 Children 2175 2225 2242 2427 2467 8/29/14 6/18/15 10/13/15 7/9/18 4/23/19 Civilians Children WPS Peacebuilding and Sexual Violence Children WPS Sexual Violence The categories in this table (children, civilians, WPS) are based on the identifiers used by the UN Security Council in its online resolution database. UN Security Council, “Resolutions,” https://www.un.org/securitycouncil/content/resolutions. The table further distinguishes those WPS resolutions mostly focusing on sexual violence from those mostly concerned with women and peacebuilding. It excludes country-specific resolutions and, with one exception in those predating Resolution 1325, includes only resolutions that mention rape, sexual violence, or sexual exploitation. 128 Chapter 5 to the maintenance of international peace and security.”22 Resolution 1820 also furthered institutional attention to sexual violence in conflict, in part by calling on the Secretary-General to submit a report to the Security Council on the implementation of the resolution within one year.23 Some members of the NGO Working Group had initially been wary that this attention to sexual violence would displace what they saw as Resolution 1325’s emphasis on women as important constituents for peacebuilding.24 The group eventually supported the resolution, however, because it comported with their “bottom-line requirements”: it included the monitoring and reporting just mentioned, and it called for the involvement of local women’s groups in the design and implementation of any policies meant to protect them.25 The initial concerns, however, reappeared soon after the passage of 1820,26 and the NGO Working Group began to promote and support a number of additional resolutions calling for increased participation of women in peacebuilding. WPS resolutions started to appear in a leapfrogging pattern. That is, resolutions concentrating on women as (sexual) victims of conflict were succeeded by resolutions that emphasized women’s centrality to peace processes, which were in turn followed by resolutions that centered around women as victims of sexual violence. In 2009, the Security Council passed four resolutions that, together, represent this pattern: one on the protection of civilians (Resolution 1894); one on the protection of children (Resolution 1882); one primarily on women as victims of war, highlighting sexual violence (Resolution 1888); and one calling for greater inclusion of women in peacebuilding processes (Resolution 1889). Regardless of their emphasis, each of the resolutions named sexual violence as a harm, whether to civilians, children, or women. Despite this apparently evenhanded treatment of women as peacebuilders, on the one hand, and as victims of sexual violence, on the other, the apparatus regarding the latter grew. Resolution 1888, in addition to establishing the Special Representative on SVIC, made the Secretary-General’s reporting requirement under 1820 an annual obligation.27 It also mandated that the reports include information on parties “credibly suspected of committing patterns of rape or other forms of sexual violence.”28 In 2010, the Security Council passed Resolution 1960, which extended the reporting requirement to those who were credibly suspected of any acts of sexual violence, not simply patterns of it. It also required the Secretary-General to publish detailed information on suspected perpetrators in an annex to each report.29 In 2013, the Security Council followed up with Resolution 2106, to respond to “the slow implementation” of 1960.30 Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 129 Those who aimed to increase women’s participation in peace processes did not fully cede the terrain to sexual violence, however, continuing to push for additional resolutions with the peacebuilding emphasis. They teamed up with the UN Entity for Gender Equality and the Empowerment of Women (UN Women), which had been created in 2010, in part to “increase women’s leadership and participation,” including “in peace and security and humanitarian response.”31 Only four months after Resolution 2106 passed, they achieved the passage of Resolution 2122. One commentator at the time noted that the “focus on peace processes in the new resolution is seen by some as a way of rebalancing the emphasis on violence in conflict [seen in Resolution 2106] to the important role women can play in conflict resolution.”32 The Security Council debate on the resolution evidenced this intent to counterbalance the attention given to sexual violence. UN Women Executive Director Phumzile Mlambo-Ngcuka spoke at the beginning of the debate and emphasized the need for sustained focus on women’s empowerment and gender equality measures.33 The representative of Portugal contrasted the relatively close attention paid by the Security Council to sexual violence with the tendency “to consider transitional justice as the second-to-last concern of peace agreements, the last being the participation of women in peace agreements.”34 Statements by several other representatives echoed this sentiment.35 Notably, no representative of UN Action spoke in the debate. If the WPS agenda seemed to be taking a turn toward peacebuilding, the broader focus on sexual violence did not disappear. Indeed, as did the other WPS resolutions on peacebuilding, Resolution 2122 included provisions on sexual violence.36 Further, in 2014 and 2015, the Security Council passed four additional resolutions on human security, two on civilians and two on children. Three of the four mentioned sexual violence among the harms to be addressed during armed conflict.37 In 2015, on the occasion of the fifteenth anniversary of Resolution 1325, UN Women published a global study that the Secretary-General had commissioned in accordance with Resolution 2122.38 In many ways the report pushed back on what had become the agenda of UN Action and the Special Representative on SVIC. In addition to emphasizing women’s participation in decision-making at a variety of levels, it also called attention to women’s rights to education, health, land, and assets. With regard to sexual violence, it reported that while women in several conflict or post-conflict regions recognized the need to address sexual violence, “more often the conversation would turn to reparations, livelihoods and economic empowerment.”39 130 Chapter 5 Later that year, the Security Council passed Resolution 2242. UN Women lauded the resolution, saying it “makes clear the substantive links between women’s participation and sustainable peace and security,” and noting that it had been informed by its global study.40 But UN Women took little note of the fact that the resolution also paid a significant amount of attention to sexual violence.41 The resolution did so, as I discuss in more detail later, primarily in the context of terrorism. As such, it identified sexual violence as a “tactic of terrorism,”42 and also called for the participation and leadership of women’s organizations in devising strategies to counter terrorism and violent extremism.43 In 2016 and 2017, the Security Council passed three additional resolutions centrally concerned with sexual violence. (See Table 5.2.) In 2016, it passed Resolution 2272, under the label “peacekeeping.” The resolution concentrated nearly exclusively on “sexual exploitation and abuse” by UN peacekeeping forces and authorized the Secretary-General to exclude or repatriate troops from states that failed to investigate and prosecute allegations of sexual abuse adequately.44 Two subsequent resolutions concerned trafficking, with a focus on terrorist groups that engage in it. Both resolutions deployed the term “sexual slavery.”45 Although, as we have seen in previous chapters, that term had made its way into the 1993 Vienna Declaration and the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC), this was its first significant appearance in Security Council resolutions.46 Its inclusion was uncontroversial, in part because much of the discussion on the resolution centered on reports that ISIS had rounded up several thousand Yazidi women and forced them into slavery, including sexual slavery. One such young woman, Nadia Murad, who escaped from ISIS and later won the Nobel Peace Prize—and whose memoir I discuss in detail in the Epilogue—was one of two Yazidi women to speak to the Security Council on Resolution 2331, the first of the trafficking resolutions. Evidence of the success of her advocacy appeared in the debate on that resolution, when nearly every speaker referenced or thanked her for her testimony,47 and in the resolution itself, which specifically condemned “all acts of trafficking, particularly the sale or trade in persons undertaken by the ‘Islamic State of Iraq and the Levant,’ . . . including of Yazidis and other persons belonging to religious and ethnic minorities.”48 The Security Council did not classify these trafficking resolutions as part of its WPS agenda, but placed them among its resolutions on the “maintenance of international peace and security.” As such, they sit alongside many other resolutions on counterterrorism, with national, not human, security as their Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 131 Table 5.2. Other relevant UN Security Council resolutions on sexual violence, 2016–2017 Resolution Date Focus 2272 3/11/16 Peacekeeping (Sexual Exploitation) 2331 12/20/16 Peace and Security (Trafficking) 2388 11/21/17 Peace and Security (Trafficking) These resolutions on sexual exploitation and assault by peacekeepers and on trafficking are not listed by the Security Council under any of the categories in Table 5.1. They are addressed in the Secretary-General’s reports on conflict-related sexual violence. concern.49 I return to the security dimensions of these and other resolutions at the end of the chapter. In April 2019, Germany held the presidency of the Security Council and put forward a new resolution on sexual violence in conflict under the WPS agenda. Unlike other WPS resolutions, this one was not urged or even backed by women’s groups. In fact, ten German-based women’s civil society organizations issued a statement that, while acknowledging concern for victims of sexual violence in conflict and even repeating much of the common-sense understanding of that violence, stated that their government was “treading on dangerous ground” in pursuing the passage of another WPS resolution. Rather than opposing particular aspects of the resolution, they warned that any proposed resolution would likely be watered down in the contemporary political climate. Referencing Russia, China, and the United States, they argued, “Given the further hardening of anti-democratic and decidedly misogynistic stances in the UN Security Council, we believe there is a danger of a weak resolution text ultimately being negotiated and adopted.”50 In fact, the fears expressed in the statement proved to be well founded. Resolution 2467 passed unanimously, with abstentions by China and Russia, but with important omissions from Germany’s original draft. Those omissions were largely secured by threats of veto by China, Russia, and the United States, though not 132 Chapter 5 always on the same issues. In a move that was widely condemned, the United States successfully used the threat of its veto to omit expression of support for, or even reference to, the “sexual and reproductive health” of survivors, even though the proposed language was mostly repeating earlier resolutions. While many critics of the United States denounced what they viewed as disregard for the health of survivors, many also criticized the reported motivation of the United States to avoid language that might endorse access to abortion for rape victims.51 The civil society organizations that opposed Germany’s promotion of Resolution 2467, even in its initial form, had other, perhaps more significant, concerns as well. They suggested that Germany should, among other things, use its leadership in the Security Council “to shift the focus to conflict-prevention and peacebuilding measures,” attend to “structural inequalities,” “systematically take into account the continuum of gender-based violence,” ensure greater involvement of directly affected communities, and increase the control of arms exports and the arms trade.52 Remarkably, the final resolution contains language that is responsive to nearly all of these concerns, albeit mostly in preambular paragraphs, leading even some critics to see “reasons for optimism.”53 Having surveyed this two-decade trajectory, I now turn to a close reading of the resolutions and related discourse for their characterization of the nature and victims of sexual violence, as well as of the relationship between sexual violence and gender-based violence. II. Naming the Victims and Types of Violence The Security Council resolutions I review above, alongside their attendant discourses and institutional activities, demonstrate tensions around two significant questions. First, what type of violence toward civilians in conflict should the Security Council target? And, second, who are the victims of that violence? These two questions, and the UN’s responses to them, are intertwined. Over time, the resolutions have moved from addressing sexual violence in conflict as one of many forms of gender-based violence to approaching it as the central form. And the centering of sexual violence has coincided with at least a rhetorical broadening of the category of victims, from women and girls to boys and men as well. I begin with the second question. A. Victims: Gender Specificity versus Gender Neutrality The human security resolutions that predate Resolution 1325 expressed concern about children, women, or sometimes “women and children.”54 Resolution 1325 Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 133 moved away from the use of the term “children,” making it clear that women and girls were its subjects.55 Between Resolution 1325 in 2000 and the next WPS resolution, Resolution 1820 in 2008, most of the human security resolutions continued that approach, singling out girls—and sometimes women—as particularly vulnerable to sexual violence.56 Resolution 1820, with its thematic focus on sexual violence, generally followed suit. Almost immediately after it was passed, however, Resolution 1820 faced criticism. As already suggested, some women’s peace advocates argued that its representation of women as victims detracted from women’s empowerment, overshadowing any sense of women as agents of change in the peacebuilding process.57 More importantly for our purposes here, others contended that the resolution failed to take into account men as possible victims of sexual violence. Even though the resolution at times referenced sexual violence against “civilians,” one commentator maintained that the resolution’s “focus provides no space to think about the rape of men, nor to think about how forcing a man to rape a woman can be understood as a form of gender-based violence.”58 While the WPS resolutions on women and peacebuilding continued to refer to sexual violence victims mostly as women and girls, those that concentrated on sexual violence, as well as the human security resolutions, began to expand concern about sexual violence to all children (not only girls) and arguably to all civilians (men as well as women). The start of the shift can be seen in gender-neutral references to children in three of the four 2009 resolutions.59 Ironically, this meant a short return to the coupling of “women and children” that has long been critiqued by feminists for casting women in infantilizing and dependent terms. In 2010, Resolution 1960 extended the gender neutrality to adults. The move was relatively seamless, especially since the Secretary-General had already begun to interpret Resolution 1820 in gender-neutral terms in his reports, in part referencing the case law of the ICTY.60 Resolution 1960, with the exception of a part of the preamble,61 addressed sexual violence in conflict with no mention of the gender of its victims. Some applauded this gender neutrality for its implicit recognition that men could be victims of sexual violence in conflict.62 In 2013, when the Security Council considered Resolution 2106, a followup resolution to 1960, the UN Secretary-General as well as a number of states, including Botswana, Canada, Jordan, Korea, Liechtenstein, Namibia, and Pakistan, acknowledged that men and boys can also be targets of sexual violence.63 The preamble to 2106 made explicit what some had read into 1960; it included a specific reference to men and boys as possible victims of sexual violence. 134 Chapter 5 Subsequent resolutions that have devoted significant attention to sexual violence—WPS Resolutions 2242 and 2467, along with those on peacekeeping and trafficking—have also contained gender-specific language, including language about men and boys. Resolution 2331 on trafficking, for example, notes the vulnerability of boys and names men as potential victims of sexual violence, in accord with concerns raised by a number of states in the debate on the resolution.64 In proposing Resolution 2467, the German government made it clear that the inclusion of men and boys was a priority. Its draft resolution included a specific operative paragraph, which remained unchanged in the final resolution that was passed, on responses to male victims of sexual violence. In language that has been widely praised, including by activists for male victims of sexual violence, the paragraph urges member states to “challenge cultural assumptions about male invulnerability” to sexual violence.65 This increased explicit attention to men and boys would at one level seem to have the same impact as gender-neutral language, the decentering of harm to women and girls. Instead, with the specificity often comes a hierarchy. The preamble to Resolution 2106, for example, “notes with concern that sexual violence in armed conflict and post-conflict situations disproportionately affects women and girls.” Resolution 2467 includes similar language in a number of places, including at the beginning of the operative paragraph on men and boys.66 B. From “Gender-Based Violence” to “Conflict-Related Sexual Violence” The move of the resolutions toward the inclusion of men and boys as potential victims of sexual violence was accompanied by a change in the types of violence that the resolutions aimed to address. Early human security resolutions expressed concern about the special vulnerability of women and children, but they did not limit their attention to sexual violence.67 Resolution 1325, even as it moved to focus on women and girls, suggested a broader concern than sexual or even “gender-based” violence. Specifically, it called on actors in armed conflict to protect women and girls from “gender-based violence, particularly rape and other forms of sexual abuse, and all other forms of violence.”68 Since Resolution 1325, subsequent resolutions have narrowed the type of violence to be addressed. Each WPS resolution and nearly every resolution on children or civilians mentions the need to protect that group from sexual violence (sometimes connoted by, and sometimes alongside, the terms “rape,” “sexual exploitation,” “sexual assault,” and “sexual abuse”). References to sexual Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 135 violence are frequent. When resolutions occasionally reference “gender-based violence,” they almost always put it in the compound “sexual and gender-based violence.” In those instances, “gender-based violence” is never defined or used in a way that suggests that it includes violence other than sexual violence, for either males or females. I have attempted to treat the categories of victims and the types of violence to be addressed as conceptually distinct, but UN Action has sometimes conflated the two issues in its arguments not only for expanding the scope of victims to include men and boys but also for moving away from the term “gender-based violence.” In her briefing to the Security Council on Resolution 1960 in 2010, for example, Margot Wallström, who was at the time the Special Representative on SVIC—and therefore the chair of UN Action—asserted that “sexual violence as a tactic or consequence of war could not be captured under existing categories.” Calling for use of the term “conflict-related sexual violence,” she further explained what she believed was missing in existing categories: “Cases against men and boys did not fall under ‘violence against women’ . . . and ‘gender-based violence’ did not reflect sexual violence as a method of ethnic cleansing or a tactic of terror.”69 Wallström’s view was in line with the UN Secretary-General’s report on the implementation of Resolutions 1820 and 1888, which had been released three weeks earlier. That report also used the term “conflict-related sexual violence” and expressed concern about field report uses of the “broader rubric of genderbased violence,” noting that “gender is a critical but insufficient explanatory tool.”70 Resolution 1960 reflected the success of UN Action’s strategy. In addition to responding to some of the criticisms of 1820’s specification of women as the main targets of sexual violence, it also included a reference to “conflict-related sexual violence.”71 UN Action soon read the resolution as recognition by the Security Council that conflict-related sexual violence is a “self-standing issue of concern.”72 In 2011, UN Action issued a summary of its “Analytical and Conceptual Framing of Conflict-Related Sexual Violence,” a document put together to determine the criteria by which parties suspected of committing patterns of sexual violence would be listed under Resolution 1960. “To foster greater specificity and disaggregation of incidents,” UN Action contended, “conflict-related sexual violence should no longer be treated as synonymous or interchangeable with” a number of terms, including “gender-based violence” and “violence against women.”73 For the listing purpose of Resolution 1960, UN Action’s framing included the 136 Chapter 5 same list of crimes that structural-bias feminists successfully fought to get into the Rome Statute of the ICC: “rape, sexual slavery, forced prostitution, forced pregnancy, enforced sterilization, or any other form of sexual violence of comparable gravity,” and—leaving no doubt about the potential set of victims—added “against women, men, girls or boys.”74 Here again we see the two issues, of the type of harm and the victim subjects, combined. UN Action’s framing is now represented in UN Secretary-General reports that, since Resolution 1960, have been titled “Conflict-Related Sexual Violence” and include explicit discussion of sexual violence against men and boys.75 “Sexual violence” has therefore largely displaced “gender-based violence” as the descriptor of the principal harm to women and girls in armed conflict. At the same time, the category of victims has broadened to include men and boys as potential victims. This displacement has not totally escaped criticism, though the criticism has come largely from those who promote women’s role in peacekeeping rather than, as one might have expected, from structural-bias feminists. In response to UN Action’s shift in language, for instance, a 2011 WILPF conference report reiterated the need for sexual violence in conflict to “be understood as a component of a broader category of gender-based violence.” Among other concerns, it warned that if the topic is “approached too narrowly, donor agents run the risk of attacking the symptom while failing to thoroughly address discriminating gender relations as one of the underlying problems.”76 The conference report referenced “sexual and gender-based violence” throughout, presumably as a way to keep the latter term in play. This type of pushback has received some limited traction. It has manifested primarily in the inclusion of language about “sexual and gender-based violence” in WPS resolutions.77 It has also manifested in an institutional separation of sexual violence in conflict from other aspects of the WPS agenda. The UN Secretary-General, for example, issues annual reports on “conflict-related sexual violence,” in addition to reports on “women and peace and security.” These latter reports have often defined sexual violence as a part of gender-based violence, leading to different representations of some of the same conduct in different types of reports.78 III. The Shame of Sexual Violence in Conflict Nearly all of the resolutions and many of the institutional practices under the WPS agenda perpetuate an important element of the common sense seen in other chapters: sexual violence in conflict causes overwhelming, even annihilating, Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 137 harm to the victim’s personhood while also tearing communities apart. As such, even those resolutions and practices that call for women’s increased participation in peacebuilding generally portray victims of sexual violence as incapable of political, sexual, military, or even economic citizenship. Perhaps Resolution 1820 most directly states the relationship it sees between shame and sexual violence in conflict when it describes sexual violence as “a tactic of war to humiliate, dominate, instill fear in, disperse and/or forcibly relocate civilian members of a community or ethnic group.”79 This description mirrors the reasoning of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) in Akayesu, where the tribunal found acts of rape to be genocidal, in part because of the humiliation brought by the rapes and the resulting “physical and psychological destruction of Tutsi women, their families and their communities.”80 Although some resolutions note the need to spur religious and traditional leaders to discourage stigmatization of victims,81 UN Action has tended to take for granted that shamed communities will stigmatize their members who have been raped. A video produced in 2007 by UN Action to build support for Resolution 1820 provides one of the most vivid representations of this perception.82 It was part of a campaign called Stop Rape Now, organized around a Web-based advocacy strategy on the theme “Get Cross: No Security without Women’s Security.” Although it was launched in 2007, as of October 2019 the campaign remained the central feature of a website, stoprapenow.org, which has served as the principal site for UN Action for many years.83 (See Figure 5.1.) In the video, no victims or survivors speak.84 Indeed, it is as if they are unable to speak; they can only be spoken for. The video opens with a helicopter flying over desert terrain, as an anonymous narrator lists numbers of women raped in Rwanda, Sierra Leone, and Bosnia and Herzegovina. The image shifts to fires moving quickly across the distance of a seemingly different desert terrain, evoking a scorched-earth strategy. The narrator recites the number of women raped during a six-month period in a “single province of the Democratic Republic of the Congo.” The image shifts again—this time to the hand of a black, presumably African, woman. The hand covers her eyes. She rubs her temples as the narrator announces that “every day, hundreds of women are raped in Darfur.” The narration continues: “These are not the random acts of individual soldiers. They are military tactics used to shame and demoralize women, tear communities apart, and control populations.” At this point, the video shows an image of two black girls, one covering her face and the other apparently distraught, with her hand over her head. As the language turns to 138 Chapter 5 Figure 5.1. StopRapeNow.org front page (as of October 2019). the destruction of communities, the image is replaced with one of a group of young black boys sitting outside what appears to be a hut of a rural village somewhere in Africa. The message is not nuanced: boys and girls are divided by the shame of rape. The last three clips of the video continue to vocalize and display much of what has become the common sense about sexual violence in conflict. Brown, apparently Muslim, bodies, replace black bodies. The narrator’s statement that “many women and girls suffer torture and mutilation in front of their families” accompanies an image of a presumed mother and young daughter, both looking distraught. A young girl in a hijab peeks out of and then retreats into a doorway along with the words “Others are impregnated to shift the balance of territories.” With the final description of the harm of rape—“All face the physical, emotional and social consequences of rape”—a black child appears, partially hidden behind a column. Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 139 The video portrays shame and stigma as an inherent part of rape and sexual violence, at least in the parts of the world it surveys. These representations combine with UN discourse on sexual violence in conflict to suggest once again (as with Bosnia and Herzegovina in Chapter Two and Rwanda in Chapter Four) that certain communities participate in their own destruction by shaming and stigmatizing those members who have experienced sexual violence. For instance, a 2009 Secretary-General report stated: “In many countries around the world, sexual violence continues to be deeply entrenched in inequalities and discrimination against women, and patriarchal structures. In addition, violence against women committed in the name of culture or tradition persists.”85 The result is “double victimization” for those women affected: “first for having been sexually violated and second for having to bear the fear, shame and stigma that surrounds sexual violence.”86 That theme continued in Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon’s remarks congratulating the Security Council for its passage of Resolution 1960 (and also alluding to its expanded category of victims). Attributing much of the harm of sexual violence to shaming by the victim’s community members, he stated: “Victims are shamed and marginalized. Their husbands reject them. Men and boys who are sexually attacked often suffer isolation and discrimination. Just when these individuals need support from their communities, it falls away.”87 He connected his claim that sexual violence “shatters lives, devastates countries and destroys hope” to its economic impact on girls, women, and therefore the entire community: “Victims who might have contributed to development are shunned. Girls who might have grown into great leaders cannot even attend school.”88 At the same time that UN discourse on sexual violence in conflict pins much of the shame suffered by victims on their communities, it also often emphasizes that sexual violence targets the community, not necessarily the victim. As such, this discourse defies the original aim of many feminists to spotlight the harm to women, not to their communities. The Secretary-General’s April 2017 report on conflict-related sexual violence offers a poignant example. Although largely about terrorism, the report does not distinguish between the aims of terrorism- and conflict-related sexual violence. “The rape of a wife or daughter is intended to punish her absent husband, father or relative,” according to the report.89 “Shame and stigma are integral to the logic of sexual violence being employed as a tactic of war or terrorism” because “aggressors understand that this type of crime can turn victims into outcasts, thus unravelling the family and kinship ties that hold communities together.”90 140 Chapter 5 As the WPS agenda has developed, it has—as planned—given greater attention to women’s roles in peacebuilding. But the imagined women who might participate in such activities bear little resemblance to the women depicted as victims or potential victims of sexual violence in conflict. Even though women’s peace advocates have criticized the amount of attention paid to sexual violence, they generally have not questioned or pushed back against the common-sense representations of the harm of sexual violence to women and their communities. A 2011 letter by the Global Network of Women Peacebuilders, whose mission is “to empower women and amplify their voices to build sustainable and inclusive peace,”91 provides a telling example. Worried that the passage of Resolution 1960 signaled another move away from the commitments of Resolution 1325, the organization wrote, “We are concerned that women’s right to full participation in all matters of peace and security is being overlooked as women are increasingly being seen and treated mostly as passive victims of violence and abuse.” The group criticized the drafters of Resolution 1960 for failing to see “that if women were recognized as participants in decision making they would be less vulnerable to attack.” Further, the letter argued that if governments “worked harder to prevent wars” and regulated “small arms,” there would be less sexual violence. In short, “we cannot pluck rape out of war for our attention and let the war go on. . . . Rape will be reduced when violence is reduced and when women are taken more seriously and treated equally in all decisions on the fate of humanity.”92 By promoting the reduction of armed conflict (with women’s participation) and the empowerment of girls and women before they are raped, the letter at least partly challenges the dominant approach of taming the ways wars are fought rather than attempting to prevent the wars to begin with. The letter does not, however, challenge the common-sense representations of the harm of rape once it occurs. Far from it—the letter demonstrates once again the grip of the narrative about sexual violence as shameful and stigmatizing: “Rape is the worst crime that women or men can endure and survive. The trauma lasts a lifetime and has ripple consequences of ostracism from family and community as well as physical damage.”93 IV. The Carceral Turn: Calling in the Judges Since the passage of Resolution 1325, all WPS resolutions, including those that primarily focus on women as peacebuilders, have manifested the turn to criminal law that we have seen throughout the book. They have done so largely through anti-impunity discourse, articulating the common-sense view that criminal Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 141 prosecution of individual offenders is a potent means to deter sexual violence and—in some instances—secure peace. As expressed in a 2015 UN SecretaryGeneral report, “The importance of delivering individual justice and addressing impunity is underscored in all Security Council resolutions on women and peace and security.”94 Resolution 1325, borrowing in part from language in earlier human security resolutions, set the stage for this view by emphasizing “the responsibility of all States to put an end to impunity and to prosecute those responsible for genocide, crimes against humanity, and war crimes including those relating to sexual and other violence against women and girls.”95 It also opposed the exclusion of those crimes from amnesty provisions, “where feasible.”96 As the WPS resolutions progressed, their focus on impunity intensified. By the time of Resolution 2106, the anti-impunity focus had become so central that the UN titled the Security Council debate on the resolution “Addressing Impunity: Effective Justice for Crimes of Sexual Violence in Conflict.”97 Much of the resolution concerned the need to combat impunity, noting that the battle against it “has been strengthened through the work of the ICC, ad hoc and mixed tribunals, as well as specialized chambers in national tribunals.”98 It called on states to investigate and prosecute those responsible for sexual violence in conflict committed in their jurisdiction.99 All subsequent WPS resolutions—Resolutions 2122, 2242, and 2467—also directly called upon member states to investigate and prosecute perpetrators of sexual violence.100 Resolution 2467 demonstrates the continued primacy of a carceral response to sexual violence, with most speakers during the debate discussing the need to fight impunity by increasing prosecutions.101 The resolution goes further than others before it by calling upon states to remove “procedural impediments” to the successful prosecution of sexual violence, such as the “discrediting of victims’ testimony . . . within judicial and other proceedings.”102 Feminist international lawyers Christine Chinkin and Madeleine Rees read this language to call for the prohibition of the cross-examination of those who testify to being victims of sexual violence. For them, “This is exactly what is needed for justice to be made accessible.”103 Somewhat surprisingly, they do not mention the caveat in the same paragraph of the resolution that all actions taken by states in this regard should be “consistent with fair trial guarantees under international law.” Although the prohibition of the cross-examination of an accuser would almost certainly extend beyond what is permitted in international law, the resolution’s very inclusion of it demonstrates yet another attempt to push the procedural and 142 Chapter 5 evidentiary boundaries of criminal law in order to facilitate the prosecution of sexual violence victims. Resolution 2467 also calls upon states to provide “a survivor-centered approach” to sexual violence in conflict and its aftermath.104 While such an approach might seem to require a shift in attention away from criminal prosecution, the proponents of the resolution instead linked the two, by assuming both that victims want prosecutions and that they want to testify in court against perpetrators. Indeed, some of the resolution’s proposed procedural reforms are meant to elicit such testimony. Germany’s representative to the Security Council explained Germany’s rationale in the debate: “Only when we help victims to achieve justice, when we hear their voices and let them testify, are we giving survivors the chance to stop being victims.”105 Of course, for some victims, the right to testify against their perpetrators is important. When Nadia Murad’s attorney, Amal Clooney, spoke during the debate on Resolution 2467, she called the resolution “the Council’s Nuremberg moment, its chance to stand on the right side of history.” Murad, she claimed, “would trade her Nobel Peace Prize in a heartbeat for the chance to get what she really wants—the chance to face, in a court of law, those who murdered her mother and her brothers and those who brutally and repeatedly raped her.”106 As we will see in the Epilogue, this claim is consistent with Murad’s own statements, at the UN and in other forums. Resolution 2467, like Resolution 2106 before it, justifies its attempts to facilitate more prosecutions and convictions by appealing to their deterrent effects, claiming that “the consistent and rigorous prosecution of sexual violence crimes is central to deterrence and prevention.”107 This rationale is reflected in the WPS agenda more broadly, which has embraced deterrence as a principal justification for privileging criminal punishment. As in the video discussed in the Introduction, the discourse surrounding the resolutions has stressed that successful prosecution of individual, often monstrous, offenders is the most promising means of prevention available. Deputy Secretary-General Amina J. Mohammed stated at a 2017 Security Council WPS debate on the theme “sexual violence in conflict as a tactic of war and terrorism”: “We have a solemn responsibility to convert a centuries-old culture of impunity into a culture of accountability and deterrence. . . . All our words and laws and resolutions will mean nothing if violations go unpunished in practice.”108 Note how the discussion of culture emerges again here, but now the threatening culture is that of impunity. It can only be challenged by the creation of a culture of deterrence, which necessarily calls upon criminal Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 143 law. Pramila Patten, Special Representative on SVIC since 2017, has used similar language, telling the Security Council that she would make “converting cultures of impunity into cultures of deterrence through consistent and effective prosecution” the first pillar of the strategy for her tenure in office.109 This common-sense assumption that criminal punishment will deter sexual violence in conflict is often stated but rarely justified. Many agree that sexual violence in conflict has, if anything, increased over time, despite the enormous amount of funds and attention that NGOs, other advocates, and national and international institutions have put toward responding to it.110 Wallström, speaking to the Security Council in 2017 as Sweden’s Minister of Foreign Affairs, referenced Resolution 1325 to say: “Today, that resolution and seven more have existed for 17 years, and we are unfortunately still far from eradicating this horrendous practice. It saddens me, but it also strengthens my resolve.”111 Statements like these have become common at Security Council discussions of sexual violence in conflict.112 One way in which many insist simultaneously that criminal punishment is a deterrent and that current efforts to decrease sexual violence have failed is simply to assert that insufficient numbers of perpetrators have been prosecuted. In late 2018, for example, William Hague defended his and Angelina Jolie’s Preventing Sexual Violence Initiative and the tens of millions of dollars they had spent on it since its launch in 2014. At the same time that he insisted they had made “enormous progress,” he acknowledged the difficulty in measuring success, given the scale of the problem. Tellingly, he suggested prosecutions as the measure of success, something he and Jolie presumably have little control over: “We’ve made a tremendous start, but it’s only a start because as things stand, no member of ISIL or Boko Haram or the armed forces of Burma has been brought to trial for crimes of sexual violence.”113 Even as those involved in the WPS agenda often speak on behalf of the needs and desires of victims, the agenda’s promotion of criminal punishment in fact goes against some of its own research. Indeed, the UN Women’s global study reported that “it was clear that women in conflict-affected settings favour interventions that are focused less on perpetrators or potential perpetrators and more on empowering women and girls and putting them at the front line of service delivery.”114 That observation, however, seems to have had little impact on the prioritization of criminal punishment in the treatment of sexual violence. The embrace of criminal punishment includes a rejection of the possibility of amnesties for conflict-related sexual violence offenses, even if granted in 144 Chapter 5 exchange for peace agreements. The qualifying language in Resolution 1325, that amnesties should be excluded “where feasible,”115 soon disappeared from resolutions and Secretary-General reports. Resolutions 1820, 2106, and 2467, for example, all call for “the exclusion of sexual violence crimes from amnesty” provisions that result from peace processes.116 Over time, that exclusion has become understood as a UN “principle.” Secretary-General reports on sexual violence in conflict have consistently opposed amnesties for sexual violence, paying little attention to what effect the exclusion might have on peace processes. One report, for instance, called for greater efforts to “ensure that amnesties and immunities exclude those who commit or commission sexual violence.”117 Another referred to “the principle of no amnesty for sexual violence crimes.”118 A third declared that, in accordance with Resolution 1820, “peace agreements that include amnesty provisions for crimes of conflict-related sexual violence should be deemed invalid by the international community.”119 The call to exclude amnesties for acts of sexual violence in peace agreements is part of a larger resistance to amnesties for certain serious international crimes or human rights violations. One Secretary-General report explained, for example, that “any amnesty ordinance reached at the end of a conflict must, as a matter of consistent United Nations policy, exclude international crimes and gross breaches of human rights.”120 That same paragraph in the report read sexual violence crimes into those two categories.121 While some scholars have argued that even amnesties for international crimes and gross human rights violations are—and should be—legally permitted in peace agreements, few have questioned the exclusion of sexual violence crimes. Even women’s peace advocates have not challenged it, despite the fact that it could in principle prevent or disrupt a peace accord. This possibility is not merely hypothetical. One Security-General report criticized Colombia’s 2012 “Legal Framework for Peace” for the impact it would have on the ability to prosecute sexual violence crimes. The report asserted that the peace process “could lead to de facto amnesties benefiting alleged perpetrators of human rights violations.”122 Around the same time, Amnesty International also decried the possibility of amnesty for sexual violence crimes in the Colombian peace process. To stave off concerns that prohibiting amnesty might undercut a peace deal, the organization invoked what has become a common refrain: “There can be no lasting and stable peace” with such amnesty.123 With this refrain, Amnesty International endorsed another aspect of the common sense Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 145 set forth in the Introduction. As Angelina Jolie put it with regard to the G8 Declaration’s opposition to amnesty for sexual violence offenses, “There is no choice between peace and justice: peace requires justice.” Or perhaps, more accurately, lasting peace requires criminal justice.124 The pressure on Colombia was successful. While the 2016 final peace accord did include an amnesty provision for some crimes, a Secretary-General report praised the agreement’s identification of “sexual violence as a grave violation that cannot be amnestied.”125 In addition to promoting criminalization based on arguments about both its deterrence function and its contributions to lasting peace, the WPS agenda has reinforced another common-sense idea we have seen in the previous two chapters: criminal law facilitates the redistribution of shame by shifting it from victims to perpetrators. Perhaps Resolution 1960’s requirement that the Secretary-General reports include an appended list of parties credibly suspected of patterns of sexual violence most clearly demonstrates this notion.126 Even before the passage of Resolution 1960, Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon had called a similar list required by certain resolutions on children a “list of shame.”127 And when Wallström, as Special Representative on SVIC, issued a report in response to the listing requirement in Resolution 1960, she stated that through “naming and shaming,” the report “became an instrument which, in the hands of political leaders, could help track and address sexual violence.” Suggesting that the report would alleviate harm to the victim by shifting the shame and stigma to its proper locus, she claimed that the report and others like it are “historical records,” telling a history that “had been suppressed chiefly because the victim rather than the attacker was most often shamed and stigmatized.”128 Of course, whether through naming and shaming or through the encouragement of criminal prosecution, the UN cannot possibly ensure the prosecution of all perpetrators (despite its oft-stated aspirations). It has, therefore, not limited shaming to formal criminal punishment mechanisms. In a WPS debate before the Security Council in 2017, Adama Dieng, who was then Acting Special Representative on SVIC, cited the “need to re-direct the stigma of sexual violence from the victim to the perpetrator.” That redirection, he explained, would come from justice being done, and being seen to be done, “not only in the courtroom but also in the community.”129 When she was Special Representative on SVIC, Zainab Bangura was particularly committed to shifting the shame. In a 2013 Security Council debate, she blamed impunity, in the context of Bosnia, for the ongoing shame victims 146 Chapter 5 experience: “While the perpetrators have enjoyed the fruits of peace and have been free to rebuild their lives, their victims continue to work in the shadows and in shame, unable to lay the past to rest and to move forward.” Furthermore, she argued that by concentrating on impunity, the Security Council would assist in the redistribution of stigma in a broader set of conflicts, to “begin to re-direct stigma and the consequences of sexual violence from the survivors to the perpetrators.”130 In a meeting at the U.S. Institute for Peace that same year, Bangura suggested how sites other than the courtroom, like communities themselves, might be engaged in the redistribution of shame. Indeed, she shocked a number of audience members when she indicated that one of UN Action’s goals was for men who have raped to internalize shame—even to the extent that they might commit suicide. In response to critiques of naming and shaming (by Gina Heathcote and myself, who were also at the meeting), Bangura explained UN Action’s intention to “put the spotlight on the perpetrators, so they feel ostracized in their own community, they are isolated, and they are the one[s] who are stigmatized.” Continuing, she said, “We need to get people to want to say, ‘I want to look forward to the day when somebody is identified as a rapist, he will commit suicide.’” Aware of her provocation, she followed up with: “I’m sorry. I don’t believe in the death sentence, but let him take his own action.”131 When the Security Council began to concern itself with sexual violence committed by terrorist groups, and to call for greater female participation in counterterrorism efforts, it also began to rely upon the very traditional leaders it once blamed for stigmatizing victims, not simply to decrease shame but to displace it from the victims onto the perpetrators. Thus, the 2016 UN Secretary-General’s report—echoing Resolution 2242’s emphasis on combating terrorism—called for community leaders to participate in shifting the blame. For the report, “engagement with traditional and religious leaders, who can help to shift the shame and stigma of sexual violence from the victims to the perpetrators, is vital to ensuring that extremists do not win the underlying battle of ideas.”132 The 2018 Report continued the theme by calling for “concerted engagement with religious and traditional leaders” in order “to shift harmful social norms around honour, shame and victim-blaming.”133 Resolution 2467 embodies some of these ideas, as it was the first WPS resolution to discuss the possibility of shame-shifting. Even with its focus on criminalization, it emphasizes communities as the site for such efforts, recognizing the need to support “community mobilization campaigns to help shift the stigma of Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 147 sexual violence from the victims to the perpetrators.”134 This approach suggests a potential recognition of some limits of criminal law, although the resolution also calls upon traditional and religious leaders to “address impunity.”135 V. Counterterrorism: Calling in the Troops In her 2006 piece “Women’s September 11th,” Catharine MacKinnon called on the “international order” to treat violence against women with the gravity it had accorded to terrorism—as “so serious that there is no choice but to stop it.”136 At the time, that largely meant armed intervention—the type that the United States and its allies had engaged in against Afghanistan and Iraq. As I said in Chapter Two, I think MacKinnon overstated in 2006 the enthusiasm of the “international order” for Security Council–authorized armed intervention, which had waned in large part because of wariness about the legality and desirability of the U.S.-led invasion of Iraq.137 It turned out, however, that she was more spot-on than I expected about the extent of international commitment to a variety of counterterrorism measures. In her plea for serious international responses to violence against women, MacKinnon saw counterterrorism as a useful analogue: “The post–September 11th paradigm shift, permitting potent response to massive nonstate violence against civilians in some instances, exemplifies, if not a model for emulation, a supple adaptation to a parallel challenge.”138 She therefore may have gotten more than she hoped for in the Security Council resolutions from 2016 and 2017. Those resolutions depict sexual violence not as a parallel challenge to terrorism, but as part of the same threat. Indeed, Resolution 2242 specifically calls for “greater integration by Member States and the United Nations of their agendas on women, peace and security, counter-terrorism and countering-violent extremism which can be conducive to terrorism.”139 Resolution 2242, the subsequent resolutions on trafficking, and the Security Council debates around them suggest that criminal law might have run out when it comes to certain lawless groups. Indeed, Security Council debates and meetings that bear on these resolutions contain statements similar to those we have already seen about the failure of the fight against impunity to decrease sexual violence. If one response to that failure is to fight harder with criminal law, another is to add new weapons to the arsenal. In a 2016 meeting of the Security Council, Bangura spoke of the need for “new tools” to combat the “new and previously unforeseen threats” by extremist and terrorist groups, groups that she claimed are “beyond the reach of judicial deterrence.”140 148 Chapter 5 In a similar vein, as a member of the Security Council in 2017, Sweden called upon the Security Council and member states to “use all of the Council’s tools to combat sexual violence.”141 Other states used comparable language in the same meeting.142 Sweden’s “all tools” language was likely influenced by the “feminist foreign policy” self-consciously and publicly enacted by Sweden’s Minister of Foreign Affairs, Margot Wallström.143 Five years earlier, as the Special Representative on SVIC, Wallström had stated that the Security Council had “promised to use all the instruments available to them to fight this scourge,” a development that she found “very, very promising.”144 Shortly thereafter, Resolution 2106 expressed the UN’s commitment to use “all means at its disposal . . . to address sexual violence in conflict.”145 Despite the mention of “all” tools, those who advocate for them mostly emphasize the need for targeted sanctions against non-state armed groups and individuals who are credibly suspected of sexual violence. Indeed, in October 2018, a number of Security Council members hosted an informal meeting on the theme “Moving from a Culture of Impunity to a Culture of Deterrence: The Use of Sanctions in Addressing Sexual Violence in Conflict,” reiterating with its title that criminal law might not be a sufficient deterrent.146 Although WPS resolutions have, at least since Resolution 1820, expressed the need to ensure that state-specific sanctions committees consider rape and sexual violence as a basis for sanctions,147 the meeting aimed to consider “ways to better use” them. It also pursued the possibility of creating “sexual violence as a single designation criterion” in countries that do not already have sanctions regimes in place.148 Those who propose increased use of targeted sanctions to combat sexual violence argue that the sanctions will serve a number of purposes, which are strikingly similar to some of the stated aims of criminal law. According to a 2018 report by the Georgetown Institute for Women, Peace and Security that called for greater use of targeted sanctions to respond to sexual violence, such sanctions are meant to “constrain individuals and entities from engaging in certain conduct, to change behavior that is contrary to international law and norms, to deter other actors, to signal support for international norms by naming and shaming perpetrators, and to cut financial resources used to fuel conflict.”149 Yet sanctions are often called upon to apply to individuals who are merely “credibly suspected.” As Gina Heathcote put it in response to Resolution 1960’s indication that the Security Council sanctions committees should consider using the lists of credibly suspected individuals in the Secretary-General reports, “The idea that those credibly suspected of sexual violence in armed conflict can be named and Calling in the Security Council for Women, Peace, and Security 149 therefore shamed presents a curious development that appears to assume some form of criminal process yet, at the same time, rejects existing legal structures and human rights provisions on the rights of the accused.”150 Even though targeted sanctions, in general, have been subject to significant criticism for their failure to provide adequate due process, such criticisms are largely absent from the discussions of the use of sanctions for sexual violence.151 Neither the framework document for the informal Security Council meeting nor the report of the Georgetown Institute, for example, includes any consideration of due process, even though both focus on accountability. Perhaps more controversially, others suggest that “all tools” include at least the potential for use of force. Christine Chinkin points to Resolution 2242’s call for the integration of WPS with the Security Council’s agenda on preventing and countering violent extremism. The latter programs, she notes, “often involve military actions and are implemented in conjunction with the armed forces.”152 Chinkin sees this introduction of militarization into the WPS agenda as antithetical to the aims of Resolution 1325 and the agenda more broadly, pointing to the UN Women’s 2015 global study, which insisted that “attempts to ‘securitize’ issues and to use women as instruments in military strategy must be consistently discouraged.”153 Some argue that the invocation of the possible use of force in Resolution 2242 did not constitute a dramatic break from previous resolutions or Security Council activity in relationship to rape and sexual violence.154 Indeed, anti-war and anti-imperial feminists have long been wary of the attachment of women’s peace advocates to the Security Council, arguing that the WPS agenda, far from leading to a focus on peace, in fact opened the door to the use of force to combat sexual violence. Gina Heathcote and Dianne Otto date this opening to Resolution 1820, with its language that, as Heathcote notes, is most commonly found in resolutions justifying the lawful use of force under Chapter VII of the UN Charter. Heathcote points in particular to the resolution’s expression of the “readiness” of the Security Council, “where necessary,” to take steps to address widespread or systematic sexual violence in situations on its agenda.155 Vasuki Nesiah argues that the door to the use of force opened even earlier, when the Security Council’s post–September 11 counterterrorism strategy began to develop alongside the WPS agenda.156 Otto notes that the Security Council resolution that arguably granted post hoc legitimacy to the 2003 military intervention in Iraq in fact referenced Resolution 1325.157 That linkage lends support to Nesiah’s claim. 150 Chapter 5 The militarized counterterrorism response to sexual violence brings us squarely back to Chapter Two and the resort to calling in the troops. While women’s peace advocates might insist that recourse to use of force is incompatible with Resolution 1325, something has happened on their watch. Unlike their acquiescence in dominant representations of sexual violence victims and their support for calling in the judges, they express an allegiance to peace and an opposition to calling in the troops. Yet the Security Council, with the guidance of many powerful feminists, has increased its attachment to the use of force to protect women. For Otto, this outcome is partly the price of engaging with the Security Council.158 For Nesiah, it comes with the territory of international conflict.159 Again, it would be too simple to say that women’s peace advocates or their aims have simply been co-opted, especially by non-feminists. Feminists—including those originally behind Resolution 1325 and what they see as its progeny— wanted to participate in the mainstream action, whatever that action might be. Fionnuala Ní Aoláin, for example, while cautioning that counterterrorism measures will harm women, nevertheless promotes “making sex, sexuality, gender and harm relevant in all wars, conflicts and substantive military engagements.”160 The only way to do that is to get involved with the Security Council’s anti-terrorism efforts, which explains why some women’s peace advocates worked toward the adoption of Resolution 2242. As one of the civil society representatives of the NGO Working Group, Iraqi Yanar Mohammed, explained during the debate on that resolution, “Research demonstrates that women’s meaningful participation improves peacebuilding and sustains efforts to counter extremism.”161 Women’s peace advocates have indeed succeeded in obtaining recognition for the need to bring women to the table. But they have done little to change what is being served at that table. E P ILO GU E Beyond Social Death What does it mean—rape? When I said the word for the first time aloud . . . it sent shivers down my spine. Now I can think and write it with an untrembling hand, say it out loud to get used to hearing it said. It sounds like the absolute worst, the end of everything—but it’s not. A Woman in Berlin, 19451 Generally it bothers me when someone says raped women. . . . Raped women—that hurts a person, to be marked as a raped woman, as if you had no other characteristic, as if that were your sole identity. Judge Nusreta Sivac, 19962 I want to talk about everything—the murder of my brothers, the disappearance of my mother, the brainwashing of the boys—not just the rape. Nadia Murad, 20173 I N T H I S B O O K , I H AV E A R G U E D that the grip of sexual violence in conflict has narrowed and distorted the lens through which feminists understand, represent, and address issues of gender, sex, ethnicity, and armed conflict. Through power they often deny, many feminists—including women’s rights advocates and women’s peace advocates—have facilitated, if not deployed, stereotyped images of victims and their communities to support militarized or criminalized responses to sexual violence in conflict. Those responses have had distributive effects. Not only have they failed to make a significant dent in incidences of sexual violence in conflict, but they have displaced attention to imperialism, economic distribution, and—relatedly—the causes of the very armed conflicts in which they aim to intervene. Also, somewhat ironically, they have sidelined attention to a great deal of gender inequality. Further, whether or not military interventions and 151 152 Epilogue counterterrorism measures have women at the helm or are done in the name of protecting women, they have had devastating effects on uncountable lives, mostly in the global South, and have perpetuated both political and economic global inequality. A recurring theme throughout the book has been that feminist successes in bringing international institutional attention to sexual violence—whether through military intervention, criminal law, or the Security Council’s Women, Peace and Security agenda (WPS agenda)—have cemented and even amplified some of the very imaginaries about rape and sexual violence that nearly all feminists originally hoped to dispel. Perhaps the most dominant theme throughout has been that feminists, however unwittingly, have participated in the continuation of the common-sense view that rape is a fate worse than death. Relatedly, their efforts have led to what Doris Buss identifies, in the context of Rwanda, as the “hypervisibility” of wartime rape, which elides not only other issues but also other aspects of victims’ lives.4 As Nusreta Sivac, a former Bosnian judge who was detained and raped in the Omarska camp, puts it in the epigraph above, being a “raped woman” becomes one’s “sole identity.” I have intentionally concentrated my critique in the book on the prevailing emphasis on and common sense about rape and sexual violence found in institutional and advocacy discourse. That is, I have avoided making claims about the actual subjective experiences of victims, other than to suggest that the experiences are almost certainly more diverse and complex than the prevailing narratives account for. In this Epilogue, I take a different approach. I return to key elements of my critique, but in doing so I bring in some literary accounts of women’s experiences in conflict to complicate the common-sense narratives we have seen thus far about women’s political, military, and sexual roles in war. Most importantly, I use the accounts to counter the assumptions about the inevitability of shame and stigma, both individual and communal, with the hope of offering possibilities for reimagining and maybe even lessening the harm of rape. In this endeavor, I am partially guided by Lauren Berlant’s question: “If one determines that an event or a relation is shameful, must it produce shame in the subjects it impacts?”5 The narratives I most rely on here come from three different literary sources that represent women in armed conflict. The first, Ernest Hemingway’s 1940 novel For Whom the Bell Tolls, follows a band of Republican fighters behind enemy lines for three days during the Spanish Civil War. Two women involved in the band, one who is sometimes the commander, play central roles in this Beyond Social Death 153 fictional work. The second source, A Woman in Berlin: Eight Weeks in the Conquered City, is the diary of a German woman that was written in 1945 during the fall of Berlin to Soviet forces. It was first published anonymously in the 1950s and then republished in 2003 (in German, 2005 in English) after the death of the person who many claim was its author.6 The third source is Nadia Murad’s The Last Girl: My Story of Captivity and My Fight against the Islamic State, published in 2017. It is the memoir of the Yazidi 2018 Nobel Peace Prize recipient about her childhood, the occupation of her village by ISIS, and her experiences during and subsequent to her captivity by ISIS. I contend that each of these narratives—novel, diary, and memoir—offers a more nuanced perspective on women’s experiences in wartime, including their experiences of and responses to sexual violence, than those we have seen elsewhere in the book. Each work contributes a different set of experiences and reflections, as well as historical, political, and geographical specificity. The accounts produced by Hemingway in 1940 and the anonymous diarist in 1945 predate every institution and movement (save the interwar women’s peace movement) that I have considered in the book. They are useful to explore in part for that reason. Murad’s memoir is on the other end of the spectrum. Not only is it contemporary, but Murad is steeped in the discourse that I have covered in this book. She has spoken to the UN Security Council, even playing a significant role in the UN debates on Resolution 2331 on human trafficking and Resolution 2467 on sexual violence (both discussed in Chapter Five); she serves as the first UN Goodwill Ambassador for the Dignity of Survivors of Human Trafficking; and she has been attempting—with the representation of Amal Clooney—to convince the International Criminal Court (ICC) that it should investigate and prosecute ISIS militants, including her captors. Although Murad’s post-ISIS life has largely been shaped by engagement with and perpetuation of much of the common-sense narrative, her autobiography pushes against it in some crucial ways. Some readers might find my choice of Hemingway surprising, even disturbing, given that he was often accused of sexism—some would say misogyny—in both his life and his writing. Some might also be concerned that, by contrast with the other two books I consider here, For Whom the Bell Tolls was produced as a piece of fiction, even if it was partially based on Hemingway’s own experiences covering the Spanish Civil War as a journalist.7 As to the first concern, I am convinced that Hemingway allows us to broaden the range of our imagination about women’s roles in and perspectives on war, in ways that I describe below and that I hope will at least partially sway those who are wary of the effort.8 As 154 Epilogue to the second issue, I read all three of the books as literary, in the sense that, as Janet Halley puts it in the context of her own reading of A Woman in Berlin, each book “structures our language for understanding the relationship between rape and other kinds of violence in war.”9 At the same time, I do not presume that literary narratives (whether written as fiction or as autobiography) are necessarily more (or less) powerful or accurate than legal, advocacy, policy, or journalistic narratives. As with the literary accounts, all of the authors and speakers we have encountered throughout the book engage in the production of narrative. They all make choices, if often unconsciously, about what to include and exclude in their stories, and their imaginations are all guided by assumptions. My goal throughout the book has been to identify and demonstrate the pervasiveness and power of many of those assumptions and to show that in a number of instances what might have begun as short-term legal or political strategy or compromise has hardened into a dangerous common sense. The literary accounts provide a view into perspectives that were generally not part of the broader legal and political narrative, but that I believe could be. Through the analysis of these books, then, I hope to encourage those who work on or interact with the issue of sexual violence in conflict to embrace more nuanced accounts of women’s political and sexual lives in war as well as of the wars themselves, and to discourage them from assuming that suppression of the nuances is necessary to the achievement of their aims. I also want to encourage them to reconsider some of those very aims, particularly the extent to which they call for or rely upon an increase in military intervention, criminal prosecutions, and counterterrorism measures. Not only do I question those ends, but I am concerned about the ways in which they have been pursued with the help of reductive accounts of the experiences of women in conflict and of the harm of sexual violence. Thus far in this book, we have seen a wide array of female actors. We have seen women’s human rights advocates, women’s peace activists, lawyers, judges, diplomats, UN officials, and a variety of feminist theorists. Notwithstanding their own powerful roles, these actors have largely focused on—and imagined—a much narrower range of female subjects in the context of armed conflict: victims of sexual violence and sometimes of a broader category of gender-based violence, potential peacemakers, and members of families and communities. Less often, we have seen references to women as combatants, perpetrators, or individuals who are responsible for their own politics or sexual conduct. As I hope to demonstrate Beyond Social Death 155 in these final pages, these facets of women’s experience and activity are not and should not be read as necessarily distinct, and they should not be suppressed in and by accounts of women’s sexual victimization. I. Women at War To the extent that the texts and discourses considered in this book thus far regard women as militarily or politically engaged in war, they tend to imagine them engaged in work that is limited and instrumental. Some of the UN Security Council resolutions, for example, call for more women in the areas of peacekeeping and counterterrorism, but most often only with the purpose of responding to sexual violence. Other resolutions emphasize that women and women’s organizations should play an important part in peacebuilding, but they do not generally recognize that women might also play a role in disturbing the peace. Much of this international institutional approach to women’s participation in conflict can be attributed to feminist advocacy. That advocacy has tended to see women either as pacifying agents or as victims, a dichotomy particularly heightened in the Security Council’s WPS agenda. Even when women are part of what is considered to be the aggressing group, their political agency is often denied. Recall from Chapter Two, for example, Helke Sander’s fictional letter to Lysistrata in which she described Serbian and Croatian women as having good political instincts that gave way to the “propaganda machinery” and their nationalist husbands’ ideology. In Chapter Two, we also saw some reference to Bosnian Muslim women serving as combatants, but their military participation was presented both as exceptional and as a way to seek revenge for their sexual harm. In one effort to expand the narrative about women’s motivations and roles in the Balkan conflict, UK journalist Lesley Abdela published a story in 1994 in the women’s magazine Cosmopolitan. Titled “Bosnia: Women Are Fighting Back,” the story covered women who served in the Bosnian Army as combatants as well as in more traditional roles such as nurses. Far from pathologizing the former, Abdela portrays their quotidian combat life. She describes one female soldier, for example, who—shortly after returning Serb fire—says, “I love the dangerous situation.” She also depicts women who were fighting in other ways, including through activism with women on other sides of the conflict. Telling these stories was meant to fill a gap in coverage, according to the editorial introduction to the article: “As the war limps on in the former Yugoslavia, women, if they’re mentioned at all, are portrayed as pathetic victims of 156 Epilogue war. To redress the balance, Cosmo sent Political Editor, Lesley Abdela, to an embattled Bosnian enclave and to the Croatian capital, Zagreb, to meet some of the courageous women who are caught in the crossfire.”10 Although the article demonstrated women’s agency in a variety of ways, the magazine’s own introduction to the piece shows the difficulty of escaping the notion that women are “caught” in the conflict. Notwithstanding the presumption of most international institutional discourse and social commentary that men are the primary actors in war, the stories Abdela tells are not in fact that rare; most wars feature significant participation by women, including as combatants. During the Spanish Civil War, thousands of women served as fighters early on. According to historian Lisa Lines, “Due to the advances in women’s rights introduced by the progressive Second Republic, many women from all political backgrounds did not consider their gender to be an issue when they volunteered for combat positions in the militias.”11 Further, one of the leading Spanish communists of the time was Dolores Ibárruri Gómez, known as La Pasionaria (“The Passion Flower”). She delivered what became a well-known rallying cry for the Republic during a radio address in July 1936: “It is better to die on your feet than to live on your knees: ¡No Pasarán!”12 Although women played various roles during the Spanish Civil War, they were largely removed from front-line combat roles less than a year into the conflict. Historians still disagree over when or how that decision was made, but although the media had initially paid a great deal of attention to female combatants, “the fact that the decision had been made was never reported or discussed,” according to Lines. Rather, “fewer and fewer references to the militiawomen were made, until by July 1937 they had all but disappeared.”13 Given this disappearance, it is both remarkable and useful that when Hemingway wrote For Whom the Bell Tolls in 1940, he made Pilar a main character and the commander of her small band of fighters during the time period covered by the novel. The narrative offers an account of her daily life that, while it might seem sexist, also seems consistent with the historical record.14 Pilar, for instance, in addition to being the commander, has a broader range of jobs than most of the men in the novel. She cooks, fans the fire, and tends the horses. Milicianas, Lines’s 2012 book, which she claims is the first comprehensive study on militiawomen, provides a similar description: “The vast majority of milicianas . . . participated in combat on equal terms with their male counterparts. This was the case despite the fact that they also . . . were often expected to undertake tasks traditionally considered ‘women’s work.’”15 Beyond Social Death 157 Of course, I do not claim—nor did Hemingway—that the novel is true, accurate, or real. But there were women during the war serving in the same positions as his female characters in the novel, and they were making good and bad wartime decisions. The institutional and advocacy discourses rarely allow us to imagine those decisions, particularly the bad ones. Yet, not only have women served as combatants in many wars, like Pilar, they have often participated in atrocities. In a scene in the novel that Hemingway went out of his way to report was fictional, Pilar tells a particularly graphic story of a Republican victory earlier in the war and the shockingly brutal and cruel executions of the fascists that followed.16 Pilar’s lover, Pablo, was commander at the time and directed the executions, but most of the village participated. As Pilar tells the story, it was important for all of the village to be involved so as to take responsibility for the victory and for the violence that ensued: “Certainly if the fascists were to be executed by the people, it was better for all the people to have a part in it, and I wished to share the guilt as much as any, just as I hoped to share in the benefits when the town would be ours.”17 Describing her response to one particularly humiliating murder, Pilar says, “I felt a feeling of shame and distaste, and . . . I wished that I might disassociate myself altogether from the lines, and I walked away, across the square, and sat down on a bench under one of the big trees that gave shade there.”18 After speaking with two men from the village who had also walked away, Pilar volunteered to go speak with Pablo. It would seem that her role was to tame her man and that, at least in this scenario, she had the power to do so. In the end, however, Pilar never even attempted to stop Pablo. Instead of pleading with him to end the massacre, she fought with a drunken man for a good position to witness it. When the drunkard pushed her aside, she hit him in the groin. While he yelled, “This, woman, you have no right to do,” she watched a mob—at the orchestration of Pablo—beat and chop a priest to death.19 Pilar says she slept with Pablo that night but, at his request, they did not make love. He believed it would have been in “bad taste after the killing of so many people.”20 He then slept “like a baby,”21 while she stayed awake all night “full of shame and a sense of wrongdoing.”22 In her retelling of this story, Pilar never denies her involvement, her politics, her loyalty, or her shame. She says “much” happened. “And all of it ugly. Even that which was glorious.”23 Pilar’s story is not about sexual violence. But it is violent, and it involves a woman who had the power, even if she was not yet the commander, to help convince the villagers to participate in atrocities, and who thought she might 158 Epilogue have the power to stop the violence but did not try. It involves a woman who wanted to witness the horrors as they occurred and used physical force when necessary to get a good view. Nadia Murad’s memoir discusses women who are even more directly involved in atrocities, both inside and outside the ISIS military apparatus. And they direct those atrocities at women, making it clear that they sense no solidarity with women across enemy lines. During her captivity, Murad encountered the mother of a man who was guarding her. She was the first non-Yazidi woman that Murad had engaged with since being captured, and Murad hoped the woman would sympathize with her. “She was a mother, after all, and I thought that might mean more to her than being Sunni and me being Yazidi.”24 When the woman, rather than showing sympathy, showed “only glee in finding out that because I had been forced to convert to Islam, there was one fewer Yazidi in Iraq,” Murad claims, “I hated her, not just because she had let Mosul be taken over by ISIS, but because she had let it be taken over by men.” While Murad could understand that men joined the jihadists to get “money, power, and sex,” she could not understand why women would do it.25 Speaking from the other side of captivity, Murad writes, “I now know that female terrorists are nothing new. Across the world and throughout history, women have joined terrorist organizations, sometimes taking starring roles, and yet their actions continue to astonish outsiders.” Part of the astonishment comes because “people assume that women are too docile, particularly in the Middle East, to be violent. But there are many women in ISIS,” Murad continues, some “who are even crueler than men.”26 Murad’s attempt to portray these women as unexceptional pushes against the common-sense view that only in rare, perhaps pathological, circumstances do women engage in combat, and even much less frequently do they commit atrocities, including against women. If the common-sense narrative largely elides images of women as participants in atrocities, it even more comprehensively omits the possibility of women as perpetrators of sexual violence. Despite evidence that women participated on all sides of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina, that large numbers of women were involved in the Rwandan genocide, and that women participated directly and indirectly in perpetrating sexual violence in both conflicts, the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) only rarely scrutinized the actions of women. Indeed, each of the tribunals convicted one—and only one—woman. Both were Beyond Social Death 159 charged with genocide and crimes against humanity, including acts of sexual violence attributed to them.27 In the ICTY, the former president of the Republika Srpska, Biljana Plavšić, pleaded guilty to one count of the crime against humanity of persecution, which did not include acts of rape or sexual violence, as part of a plea agreement in which the tribunal dropped the remaining charges.28 The ICTR tried Pauline Nyiramasuhuko, Rwandan Minister for Family, Welfare and the Advancement of Women, and convicted her of, among other things, inciting Hutu men to rape Tutsi women. Nyiramasuhuko’s case garnered a great deal of attention, in large part because her conduct was seen as exceptional. The fact that she was a woman and the minister in charge of women’s affairs made her conduct especially inexcusable to many. Whether or not she felt shame, others did so on her behalf. One minister of Rwanda, Angelina Muganza, described her reaction to hearing accusations against Nyiramasuhuko: “She makes me ashamed to be a woman.”29 In fact, Nyiramasuhuko was far from alone. Women’s participation in the Rwandan genocide had been an open secret for some time. A 1998 African Union report stated the importance of understanding that “women were not only victims of violence during the genocide. Many became its perpetrators— against men, but also against other women.”30 Even then this discovery was not a new one. The report explained that the “phenomenon was sufficiently widespread that African Rights . . . published a study in 1995 . . . specifically on the participation of women in the genocide.”31 Women imprisoned other women, directed that women be raped in front of them, and used implements to rape other women.32 They also exposed Tutsis in hiding, stole and looted, and killed Tutsis, including children.33 Despite significant documentation, many—including many feminists—have been slow to take seriously the claim that “ordinary” women engage in, and are responsible for, atrocities. Thus, after photographs of female U.S. soldiers as perpetrators in the Abu Ghraib prison in Iraq were broadly disseminated, longtime feminist Barbara Ehrenreich wrote: “A certain kind of feminism, or perhaps I should say a certain kind of feminist naivete, died in Abu Ghraib. It was a feminism that saw men as the perpetual perpetrators, women as the perpetual victims and male sexual violence against women as the root of all injustice.”34 She went on to connect the Abu Ghraib incidents to the growing international attention among feminists to rape in war, adding her own self-critique: “Rape has repeatedly been an instrument of war and, to some feminists, it was beginning to look as if war was an extension of rape. There seemed to be at least some 160 Epilogue evidence that male sexual sadism was connected to our species’ tragic propensity for violence. That was before we had seen female sexual sadism in action.” Ehrenreich described her discovery succinctly: “What we have learned from Abu Ghraib, once and for all, is that a uterus is not a substitute for a conscience.”35 Ehrenreich acknowledged that the view that women would somehow be exempt from acting as perpetrators of war crimes was “naive,” but it is not clear why it took Abu Ghraib to undermine her belief that every woman (or at least any who have a uterus) would have a conscience. She seemed particularly affected by what she considered to be the sexual nature of the crimes. By further labeling them “sexual sadism,” she isolated and pathologized the perpetrators, contrasting them with feminist (if not female) innocence (naivete). Like men—whose status as “perpetual perpetrators,” sexual sadists, or persons lacking in conscience she did not question—women could now be monsters. And, if monsters, they presumably could not experience the “shame and distaste” that Pilar described as her response to part of the massacre in which she participated. II. Women and Sex at War By concentrating excessively on sexual violence, the institutional and advocacy discourses covered in this book make little room for any non-violent sex, let alone sexually positive experiences. Due to assumptions that are often embedded in legal rules and judgments, they largely fail to attend to, and even function to exclude, the possibility of desired sexual relations between individuals on opposing sides of a conflict. Like all narratives, legal narratives produced through trials are necessarily limited. Judges make decisions about the admissibility of evidence based on its relevance and the extent to which it is likely to be prejudicial. Lawyers choose what evidence to put forth and challenge with that in mind. Through rules of evidence and jurisprudence that allowed the fact of conflict to constitute inherently coercive circumstances, thereby satisfying the prosecutor’s technical requirement to prove lack of consent, the ICTY and the ICTR all but foreclosed the possibility of a consent defense to charges of rape and sexual violence. Although some feminists would have preferred simply to remove non-consent as an element of rape, they essentially achieved that result through the jurisprudence (and later, arguably, through the ICC’s elements of crime). In earlier chapters, I argued that the legal assumption of the improbability, if not impossibility, of consensual relations between civilians and combatants on opposing sides of a conflict matched a sense of social impossibility that Beyond Social Death 161 presumed that, as a result of ethnic hatred, individuals on opposing sides would never have any mutual desire to engage in sexual relations with one another. In Chapter Three, I provided part of a socio-historical account of multi-ethnic relationships in Bosnia that defied that impossibility. I also pointed to the one ICTY case I could find that acknowledged a consensual relationship between a Serb combatant and a Bosnian Muslim civilian who married each other. In addition to imagining consensual sex between male combatants and female civilians, once we acknowledge that women participate in military operations—as combatants or civilians—it is not a leap to think that they too engage in sexual conduct, even in wartime. It should also not be a leap to think that much of that conduct would be desired, perhaps even pursued by the women themselves, even after experiences of sexual violence. But again, even these stories are difficult to find in the common-sense discourse. In For Whom the Bell Tolls, both Pilar and Maria, the other main female character in the story, play significant roles in the military operations around which the book centers. And both lead lives in which sexuality and conflict are intertwined. Pilar is intensely sexual, and she openly discusses sex and her previous sexual relationships. Maria, who is much younger, came to accompany the band of fighters after its members blew up a fascist train on which she was being transported. Her father had been a Republican mayor of a village, and he and her mother were killed by the fascists. These same fascists captured Maria, shaved her head, ridiculed her, drew letters on her forehead identifying her as a communist, and took turns raping her. These acts, especially the rapes, haunt Maria and her relationships throughout the novel. But the sexual violence is not the endpoint of either her life, including her sexual life, or the novel. She participates in a mutual seduction with the novel’s protagonist, Robert Jordan, an American professor who is volunteering in the war and whose dangerous mission the band has joined. In part through her relationship with him, she demonstrates that she is not destined to be forever marked solely or even primarily by the rape. Indeed, at one point she tells Robert Jordan, “And now, I am happy that I did not die. I am so happy that I did not die.”36 If some of the discourses I have considered in the book have occasionally recognized aspects of female sexual agency, they have nevertheless reinforced sexual hierarchies, as discussed in Chapter One.37 Take, for example, the unstated monolithic and heteronormative vision of female sexuality that permeates the discourse, precluding the possibility that women might love, partner with, and have sex with one another. Here too, For Whom the Bell Tolls offers a corrective. 162 Epilogue Erotic attraction and sexual tension link Pilar and Maria, and Hemingway portrays a complex relationship between the two women. Pilar both asserts and denies her sexual feelings for Maria. At one point when they are together with Robert Jordan, Pilar tells him, “You can have her in a little while, Inglés.”38 She then turns to Maria: “‘He can have thee,’ Pilar said and ran her finger around the lobe of the girl’s ear. ‘But I am very jealous.’”39 After claiming there is always “something” between women “that there should not be,” she reasserts her heterosexual identity: “Listen, guapa [beautiful], I love thee and he can have thee, I am no tortillera [lesbian] but a woman made for men.”40 Maria responds that she loves Pilar too, and when Pilar insists that the “silliness [about their feelings for each other] is over,” Maria insists on the significance of the encounter, responding: “It was not silly.”41 III. The Force of Shame Revisited Every chapter of this book has confronted the assumptions about shame and stigma that permeate the common-sense understanding of sexual violence as a fate worse than death. Those assumptions have rarely been challenged—in part, I have argued, because of the significant role they play in the judicial reasoning that finds rape to be an act of genocide and sometimes a crime against humanity. The reliance on stigma and shame, even to achieve these jurisprudential results, has significant costs. It disincentivizes attempting to decrease stigma and shame, other than by claiming that criminal law will displace shame onto perpetrators. And, just as importantly, it fails to recognize and value the instances in which rape does not trigger overwhelming shame or stigma in either individuals or communities. Perhaps that failure partly stems, as Miriam Ticktin suggests, from Northern feminist projections about what constitutes a proper response to rape.42 All three of my sources provide important counterpoints to dominant narratives about shame, by offering portraits of women who, though they have experienced wartime sexual violence, have not been forever destroyed by it. They, and sometimes their communities, have resisted the potential threat of shame in a variety of ways. Though often due to problematic assumptions about sexual purity or the need to prove one’s innocence, fighting back can be one way in which rape victims can not only exercise some form of resistance, but perhaps even fend off shame. Ironically, the near absence of the consent defense to sexual violence charges in international criminal law keeps the trials from providing a venue for those who have been raped to argue, as Maria does to Robert Jordan in For Whom the Beyond Social Death 163 Bell Tolls, that they have “fought” their attackers. When Maria first tells Robert Jordan of the assault, she says: “Where things were done to me I fought until I could not see.”43 After the two of them decide to marry, she insists that he know for his “own pride” that “never did I submit to any one. Always I fought and always it took two of them or more to do me the harm.”44 As just described, Maria’s response sounds fairly traditional, centered around preserving her sexual integrity. Yet Maria construes the sexual and other violence she experienced and her response to it in military terms—as part of the battle. She makes it clear that her fighting was not only for her (or her future husband’s) sexual honor but also for her political and military honor. She recounts that when her father was shot, he said, “Viva la República.”45 When her mother was shot, she said, “Viva my husband who was the Mayor of this village.”46 And Maria says, “I hoped they would shoot me too and I was going to say ‘Viva la República y vivan mis padres [my parents].’”47 Unlike her mother, Maria would make her political loyalties known. Many civilians play important roles in war. Particularly when they are on the front lines, the military/civilian distinction is often blurred, as it was for Maria when the fascists captured her village. Her fight was both personal and political, and not only in the sense that the personal is political; her fight against those who raped her was also for her a fight for the Republic. In this sense, even if she was understood as a civilian, she fought in the civil war. Sometimes civilians on the front lines have an even more intense experience of the war than soldiers do, especially those soldiers with posts removed from the conflict. A Woman in Berlin demonstrates how the very struggle for survival in war can challenge two dichotomies that advocacy, legal, and institutional discourses have taken for granted: rape versus consensual sex, and civilian versus combatant. It also shows that shame is not an inevitable result of rape. The diary spans eight weeks during and immediately following the Battle of Berlin.48 It records multiple rapes of the diarist and others by Russian soldiers during the period, as well as many other challenges that German residents faced during the city’s occupation. The diary also demonstrates that the diarist exercised a surprising amount of composure and agency during the ordeal. After she has been raped several times, for example, she writes: “I have to find a single wolf to keep away the pack. An officer, as high-ranking as possible, a commandant, a general, whatever I can manage.” Referring to the fact that she speaks some Russian, she asks: “After all, what are my brains for, my little knowledge of the enemy’s language.”49 In fact, 164 Epilogue she successfully acts on that instinct. She also makes a number of other calculated decisions to agree to and even seek out sexual acts for food and money. In reflecting on a resulting experience at one point, she states, “By no means could it be said that the major is raping me.”50 In surveying what she receives from the exchange with him, she admits that she likes him but also wonders whether “I should now call myself a whore, since I am essentially living off my body, trading it for something to eat.”51 Perhaps it is the diarist’s very composure and sense of agency, including her writing about the experiences as they happened, that led to the reception of the book when it was published in Germany in 1959.52 According to Hans Magnus Enzensberger, “The book was met with either hostility or silence. One of the few critics who reviewed it complained about the author’s ‘shameless immorality.’”53 The diarist, it seems, would not have been surprised by that critic’s reaction, given that she identifies a similar response in the diary itself. At the very end of the diary, her boyfriend, Gerd, returns from the war. He listens to her and some of the other women’s accounts of the occupation and, demonstrating the author’s “literary capacity,” according to Halley, even reads part of her diary.54 He responds harshly. After hearing one of the women poke fun at a German who raped her, he calls the diarist and the other women in the building “shameless bitches.”55 He sees them, according to Halley, as having been disloyal: “If her rapes had been ‘the absolute worst,’ her national solidarity with the defeated German soldiers would have remained intact and Gerd would not have been repelled. If instead she and the other women took some of the rapes lightly, even in jest, as one among many harms of war, they became ‘shameless,’ ‘disgusting,’ and . . . nationally disloyal.”56 In her recounting of her experiences, however, the diarist makes clear her sense of having fought on the front even if, unlike Maria, she did not fight back when she was sexually assaulted and she did not participate in a military operation. Writing after Hitler’s defeat, when the male German soldiers are about to start returning to Berlin, the diarist contrasts the experiences of many of those troops “in cities like Paris or Oslo, which were farther from the front than Berlin,” or even “in places where there was absolute peace,” with the “constant bombardment” she and others have faced in Berlin. The bombardment to which she refers is not only, or even necessarily, sexual violence, but the general violence that civilians experience in a war zone—the lack of secure housing, food, and water supplies, and the reality of ongoing military attacks. Even those men who had come from the front, she notes, had “always looked neat and well fed, unlike most of us today.”57 Beyond Social Death 165 When I began to read The Last Girl, Nadia Murad’s account of the rapes, beatings, and forced conversion she faced during her approximately three months in captivity in 2014, I assumed it would leave little room for imagining even a remnant of the agency that the diarist claimed for herself.58 “Every second with ISIS,” Murad states at one point, “was part of a slow, painful death—of the body and the soul.”59 Much of her account supports that perspective. Throughout the book, she recounts numerous incidents during her time with ISIS when she wished she had died or been killed. Yet in a number of ways, the book shares remarkable similarities with the diary, notwithstanding that more than seventy years and nearly 2,500 miles separate them. Murad recounts a moment early on after her capture when she and some other young women made a pact to commit suicide: “Killing ourselves seemed more honorable than submitting to the militants, our only way of fighting back.”60 But then, after considering how little a death would matter to the militants and thinking about her mother’s view that nothing could justify suicide, she says: “Quickly, we reversed our pact. We wouldn’t kill ourselves; we would help one another as much as we could and take the first opportunity to escape.”61 Murad concentrated on escape nearly constantly at the beginning of her captivity. After one failed attempt with horrific consequences, she eventually succeeded. Like the diarist in A Woman in Berlin, Murad often writes matter-of-factly about her daily life in captivity. Unlike Maria in For Whom the Bell Tolls, Murad makes a point of not having fought back within her daily existence as a sabiyya (an ancient word for slavery used by ISIS). “I have never admitted this to anyone,” she says halfway through the book, “but I did not fight back when . . . anyone . . . came to rape me. I just closed my eyes and wished for it to be over.” She claims she was not as brave as “other girls [who] punched and bit their attackers.”62 Note Murad’s subtitle: “My Story of Captivity, and My Fight against the Islamic State.” The comma seems carefully positioned to indicate that she sees her fight in her UN and advocacy work, not in her response to captivity. Notwithstanding her revelation about not resisting the rapes, Murad’s story in captivity is very much one of resistance. When she and other unmarried women from her village were loaded onto a bus to be taken to Mosul, one of the ISIS guards groped a number of them, including Murad. It was her first experience of assault, and she screamed and complained to another ISIS militant, believing that he would help. Her complaint backfired, though, as ISIS militants later punished her by burning her with cigarettes for causing a scene. Soon thereafter, she made the pact to escape. 166 Epilogue When the young women were taken to a slave market—where ISIS militants would choose their sabaya (the plural form of sabiyya)—she made a decision, not to find a wolf to protect her, as had the diarist, but to find the least threatening man to choose her. She had been selected by a particularly large and brutal man, whom she describes as looking “like a monster,” and whom in fact she had attempted to fight off.63 When she failed in her physical resistance, she took a different tack. As the transaction was being finalized, she was looking at the floor and she “saw a pair of men’s sandals and ankles that were skinny, almost womanly, and before I could think about what I was doing, I flung myself toward those feet.”64 She convinced that man—who turned out to be a judge—to take her instead. She expresses amazement that she thought it possible that the decision would save her, but the episode nevertheless demonstrates a moment of decision and action, rather than passivity and surrender. Murad leaves no doubt about the extent of the damage that ISIS militants caused her. But even though she sometimes wished she had been killed, her narrative is strikingly short on internalized shame. That said, she acknowledges that she did sometimes worry about how her community might respond to her. At one point, she recalls that “the rape was the worst part” because “it stripped us of our humanity and made thinking about the future—returning to Yazidi society, marrying, having children, being happy—impossible.”65 ISIS shared these beliefs about the effects of the loss of virginity, as well as of the conversion to Islam (the latter of which Murad notes was “the cruelest”66): “They used our worst fears—that our community and religious leaders wouldn’t welcome us back—against us.”67 Later, the man who eventually helped her flee to Kurdistan expressed concern about how her family members might treat her when they learned what had happened. She confesses that she was uncertain: “Yazidis are conservative, sex before marriage is not allowed. . . . A situation like this would test any community, no matter how loving and no matter how strong.”68 “We shouldn’t have underestimated our religious leaders,” Murad says after her escape, upon learning that, far from ostracizing or stigmatizing her, Yazidi religious leaders had announced that former sabaya “would be welcomed back to society and not judged for what had happened to us.” She explains: “We were not to be considered Muslim because the religion had been forced upon us, and because we had been raped, we were victims, not ruined women.”69 Murad is clear that the religious acceptance she received could not be sufficient to “make us feel completely normal again,” but that, nevertheless, “I have never loved my community more than in that moment of compassion.”70 Beyond Social Death 167 Murad does not question the concept of being a “ruined woman,” its contrast with being a victim, or how that dichotomy might situate someone like the diarist, who was not so clearly held in conditions of what nearly all agree in Murad’s instance are accurately identified as “sexual slavery.”71 But her story at once confirms the fear of stigmatization and defies its inevitability. It presents a different traditional religious response than she and many others had anticipated. One might attempt to distinguish the response of the Yazidis from those of Muslims, but recall Chapter Two’s discussion of an imam who made a similar pronouncement in Bosnia.72 From my description of Murad’s book thus far, it might seem as though she centers her account around sexual abuse. In fact, like both Maria and the diarist, Murad’s rapes and even her captivity are only one part of a complicated story, of a type to which we are often not exposed in the laser-like focus on sexual violence in conflict. After confessing that she did not fight the rapes, Murad expresses exasperation that it sometimes feels that “all that anyone is interested in when it comes to the genocide is the sexual abuse of Yazidi girls, and they want a story of a fight. I want to talk about everything—the murder of my brothers, the disappearance of my mother, the brainwashing of the boys—not just the rape.”73 Throughout the discussion of her time in captivity, she tells of constantly searching for news about whether any of the men from her village had survived and about what happened to the women and children who were not sent off to be sabaya. In one of the final chapters of the book, Murad returns to the death metaphor: “Even the people whom ISIS hadn’t managed to kill had lost their lives—an entire generation of lost Yazidis like my brothers and me, walking around in the world with nothing in our hearts but the memory of our family.”74 We come to see here that her “slow, painful death” is one she shares with her surviving brothers, not because of loss of honor, but because of loss of the lives of so many members of her family and community. If Murad and the diarist push back against the common-sense narrative in many ways, they also concur with a view, which we have seen throughout the book, that many women who have been raped might well be reluctant to speak of the rapes. During the Russian occupation of Berlin, the diarist speaks a great deal with other women who have had similar experiences, noting how “this mass rape is something we are overcoming collectively. . . . All the women help each other by speaking about it, airing their pain, allowing others to air theirs and spit out what they’ve suffered.”75 After the war, however, she presumes that (civilian) women’s battles will be treated differently from those of (male) soldiers. 168 Epilogue Contrasting how she imagines the former will be censored, whether by others or by the women themselves, with what she knows of German soldiers she has met through the years on their leave, she discusses how the men had “loved to tell their stories, which always involved exploits that showed them in a good light. We, on the other hand, will have to keep politely mum; each one of us will have to act as if she in particular was spared.”76 Like the diarist, Murad obviously tells her own story, though she does so in a memoir clearly intended for publication. She also understands and respects that other women will not respond in the same way: “It was their tragedy and their right not to tell anyone.”77 If the diarist and Murad call attention to women who will not speak about their experiences, they go beyond the common-sense narrative that offers shame as the principal explanation. That is, they suggest that there are reasons to be silent about many things that happen in war. The diarist suggests that women’s stories will not be heard as stories of combat. But she also demonstrates, through the example of her boyfriend’s return, how the stories could be used against the women, including as evidence of disloyalty. Murad also expresses the dangers of speaking. When the Kurdish media publicly aired an interview that she gave shortly after fleeing to Kurdistan about some of what had happened to her (though denying the rape), Murad says she learned quickly that her story, which she “still thought of as a personal tragedy, could be someone else’s political tool.” Looking back on it, she says, “I would have to be careful what I said, because words mean different things to different people, and your story can easily become a weapon to be turned on you.”78 IV. The Context of War Foregrounded The Last Girl is about more than oppression, at least by ISIS. In fact, it offers yet another type of narrative that, if present at all, is generally backgrounded in much international discourse on sexual violence in conflict. The type of narrative is political context, including one that sheds light on what might motivate those identified as the oppressors. It is missing from the Security Council’s resolutions on trafficking that discuss the Islamic State, even though Murad spoke at the debate on the first such resolution and was often cited by proponents of the resolutions. The first four chapters of the memoir set the stage for the eventual ISIS occupation of Kocho, Murad’s village in the disputed region of Sinjar. Murad briefly describes what it was like to grow up under a regime of sanctions that affected “ordinary Iraqis, not the political elite and certainly not Saddam himself.”79 And Beyond Social Death 169 she considers who in the region benefited (Kurds) and who lost (Sunni Muslims) from the U.S. invasion of Iraq. The Yazidis, she tells us, “welcomed the Americans but were less certain than Kurds about what our lives would be like after Saddam.” Although life had been incredibly hard in terms of education and economic opportunities, she notes that “at the same time, with the Baathists in power, we in Kocho had been able to practice our religion, farm our land, and start our families . . . [and] had close ties with Sunni Arab families.”80 Of course, those ties eventually disintegrated, and she calls out both the Iraqi Kurds and the Americans for their strategic use of the Yazidis. She also points to the effect of U.S. occupation on the daily lives of “ordinary Sunnis,” and in turn—she suggests—on the growth of ISIS.81 When she discusses the role of women in ISIS, for example, she says that “like the men, they consider themselves victims of sectarian oppression and the American invasion.”82 Here, Murad adds to her narrative the role of geopolitical forces, including U.S. hegemony, in the emergence of the many harms she names. In her December 2016 speech to the Security Council at the debate on Resolution 2331, her testimony matched her commitment in the memoir to talk about more than the rapes. Thus, while she noted that “3,500 Yazidis” were then in captivity, she also emphasized that “more than 350,000 Yazidis, along with more than 1.5 million other refugees, continue to live under difficult conditions in the Kurdistan region of Iraq.”83 Her speech did not, however, reveal any of the anti-imperial impulses that appear in the book. The Security Council did not offer an appropriate forum for her to suggest that the United States or its allies might have been part of the problem. One place where the memoir and the Security Council speech do not diverge is in the proposed response to ISIS. In Chapter Five, we read Amal Clooney’s statement to the Security Council about Murad’s strong desire to confront her perpetrators in court. The final paragraphs of Murad’s book recount one of her own addresses to the UN, in which she expressed the same sentiment: “I told them that every Yazidi wants ISIS prosecuted for genocide, and that it was in their power to help protect vulnerable people all over the world. I told them that I wanted to look the men who raped me in the eye and see them brought to justice. More than anything else, I said, I want to be the last girl in the world with a story like mine.”84 While Murad also calls for a safe zone in Iraq for religious minorities, the teaching of Yazidism in Iraqi schools, and support for women and girls who have escaped ISIS to rejoin society, her quest for criminal accountability for 170 Epilogue ISIS defines her fight against ISIS referenced in the book’s subtitle. When she fantasizes about accountability in the book, the tone is usually retributive, though the closing line here imparts a deterrent spin. Given Murad’s rich understanding of the history of the conflict, the reliance on criminal law seems somewhat shortsighted. It demonstrates that international criminal law continues to have a good hold on the field of emancipatory responses to rape, as well as to the other harms she names. Her claim that every Yazidi shares her preferences fits with the discourse perpetuated by the ICC itself. According to Sara Kendall and Sarah Nouwen, the ICC speaks on behalf of an abstracted idea of “The Victims.”85 Because victims are treated as one abstracted figure thought to desire prosecution, any Yazidis who might not share that aim are invisible to the system. As Kendall and Nouwen put it, they “cannot impeach the representative.”86 V. The Redistribution of Shame Reconsidered Murad is not alone in placing her faith in criminal law. Again, her narrative fits with the common-sense idea that criminal law is the best way to respond to, and possibly even deter, violations of the laws of war. Although advocates for increased criminalization generally assume—rather than argue for—the efficacy of the approach, we have seen it justified, particularly in the context of sexual violence, as a means to shift the shame from victim to perpetrator. When this justification has emerged in the book, I have responded by contending that such a response problematically feeds the assumption that being raped is inherently shameful, precluding a closer examination of whether, under what circumstances, and for whom sexual violence is shameful to begin with. I have also been dubious about how shaming one person would take the shame away from another. And I have questioned why, if shame is so problematic, we would so readily impose it on others. I do not want to argue, however, that shame can never serve a positive function. Both A Woman in Berlin and For Whom the Bell Tolls provide expressions of shame that suggest its productive, even agency-generating, potential. They call attention to how both men and women often engage in shameful military acts, and how—even as civilians—they might make political alliances or take political positions that they will later rue. The diarist in A Woman in Berlin criticizes Hitler throughout, and suggests that many German civilians almost welcomed the fall of Berlin. Yet the diarist attempts to make sense of her participation in and political agency during the war. Many German soldiers and even leaders in the Third Reich began to understand Beyond Social Death 171 in the aftermath of the war that, when one is on the losing side, it sometimes pays to be a victim. The diarist is attuned to this dynamic, and does not hide her own ambivalence about the role that civilians and soldiers alike played in the rise and acts of the Third Reich: “Everyone is now turning their backs on Adolf, no one was ever a supporter. What about me? Was I for . . . or against? What’s clear is that I was there, that I breathed what was in the air, and it affected all of us, even if we didn’t want it to.”87 This passage reflects a significant capacity for individual and collective responsibility, especially in the midst of a daily fight for survival. Like Pilar’s story of her participation in the atrocities, it forces the reader to question the line between perpetrator and victim, particularly in relationship to the larger aims of any given side to a conflict. The diarist discusses her possible complicity in a fascist regime, while not denying her own suffering. Pilar admits being plagued by the atrocities she participated in—“full of shame and a sense of wrongdoing”—notwithstanding that she was battling fascism. These narratives also make it clear that men are not the only possible purveyors of ideology or genuine political conviction. Such recognition is an essential part of any effective response to conflict, including to its structural causes. VI. Conclusion In this epilogue, I have brought counter-narratives from literary sources to bear on the common-sense understanding of sex and gender in war and its aftermath. I have focused most closely on the common-sense view that rape constitutes the worst harm in war due to the shame it brings to both individuals and communities. Shame might thrive on silence, but it also thrives on narratives that make certain acts or experiences shameful. All three of the literary works I have discussed push back on such narratives. I have turned to these literary sources, in large part because of the dearth of critiques of the shame narrative within the legal and political spaces studied in the book. Chapter Five shows that even critiques of the hyper-attention to sexual violence have generally stopped short of disrupting the “worst-harm,” shame, and stigmatization narratives that have driven the machinery to respond to, or act in the name of, sexual violence in conflict. As with other parts of the common sense, the concretization of this view was not inevitable. Indeed, one of the major aims of nearly all feminists when they began to approach sexual violence in conflict was to move consideration of it away from the honor discourse that had driven the earlier prohibition of rape in wartime. 172 Epilogue I contend that feminists have facilitated the perpetuation of the fate-worsethan-death discourse, at least in part because of its efficacy. To mobilize troops, judges, and counterterrorism measures, sexual violence has to be portrayed as fully destructive. I have sought in this epilogue to challenge that portrayal, and I have tried throughout the book to question these very mobilizations that rely on it. To resist both the common-sense view and the deployments of force it justifies, we need to extricate ourselves from the grip of sexual violence. Notes Introduction 1. See Douglas, The Memory of Judgment; Koskenniemi, “Between Impunity and Show Trials”; Mamdani, “Beyond Nuremberg”; Meister, After Evil. 2. For a comparison of international law–based challenges to U.S. atrocities committed during the Vietnam War and those committed during the war on terror, the former based on jus ad bellum (contesting the legality of U.S. involvement in the war itself) and the latter on jus in bello (contesting human rights violations committed during the war), see Moyn, “From Antiwar Politics to Antitorture Politics.” Of course, at the same time that human rights advocates were turning their attention to condemning human rights and humanitarian law violations during war, as we see in Chapter Two, some were using those violations to call for military intervention. For David Kennedy, both approaches are part of the modern law of force that “now permits humanitarians, military professionals, and statesmen to speak about decisions to go to war and the conduct of war in the same—humanitarian—terms.” Kennedy, The Dark Sides of Virtue, 267. 3. G8, “Declaration on Preventing Sexual Violence in Conflict,” Apr. 11, 2013, Foreign and Commonwealth Office, https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads /attachment_data/file/185008/G8_PSVI_Declaration_-_FINAL.pdf. 4. All quotations from the press conference can be found at Foreign and Commonwealth Office, “News Story: G8 Declaration on Preventing Sexual Violence in Conflict,” Apr. 11, 2013, https://www.gov.uk/government/news/g8-declaration-on -preventing-sexual-violence-in-conflict. 5. UN Security Council, Resolution 2106, preambular para. 3. For a summary of the proceedings and of the roles that each of the trio played, see UN News Center, “Security Council Strengthens Efforts to End Impunity for Conflict-Related Sexual Violence,” June 24, 2013, https://news.un.org/en/story/2013/06/443072. This resolution is discussed in detail in Chapter Five. 6. The declaration remained open for signature, and 156 states had signed it as of July 2016. For the declaration, see UN General Assembly, Letter Dated 26 November 2013 from the Permanent Representative of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and 173 174 Notes to Introduction Northern Ireland to the United Nations Addressed to the Secretary-General, Appendix: Declaration of Commitment to End Sexual Violence in Conflict, UN Doc. A/68/633, Dec. 3, 2013. For the number of signatories as of 2016, see UN Secretary-General, Status of the Protocols Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 1949 and Relating to the Protection of Victims of Armed Conflicts: Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc. A/71/183, July 22, 2016, 43. 7. Foreign and Commonwealth Office, “Don’t believe the thumbnail, this video is the stuff of nightmares,” June 2, 2014, https://youtu.be/1QFUD2Q6D8k. 8. The designer of the video, London-based marketing agency Don’t Panic, uses this opening scene in its online magazine as the thumbnail of the video. Don’t Panic magazine, “Don’t Believe the Thumbnail, This Video Is the Stuff of Nightmares,” June 3, 2014, http:// dontpaniconline.com/magazine/radar/dont-believe-the-thumbnail-this-video-is-the -stuff-of-nightmares. The UK government announced the video with a different thumbnail, which shows a monster baring his teeth (taken from the 0:34 mark of the video). Foreign and Commonwealth Office, “Animation Launched for Summit to End Sexual Violence in Conflict,” June 4, 2014, https://www.gov.uk/government/news/animation -launched-for-summit-to-end-sexual-violence-in-conflict. 9. For discussion of some of the history of this treatment of rape, see Kinsella, The Image before the Weapon, 73–74, 216n99. 10. There are many debates as to when the first prosecution of rape as a war crime occurred, ranging from 1385 (Richard II) and 1474 (Peter von Hagenbach) to 1863 (under the Lieber Code) and 1946 (in the Tokyo Tribunals). For all but the 1474 date, see Meron, “Rape as a Crime under International Humanitarian Law,” 425–26. Crystal Feimster tells of more than 450 prosecutions for sexual crimes, including against Black women, under the Lieber Code. Feimster, “Rape and Justice in the Civil War.” For more on the treatment of rape and other crimes against women under the Lieber Code, including, importantly, the code’s nonapplication to Native American women (and children) during the Sand Creek Massacre, see Kinsella, The Image before the Weapon, 84, 89–96, 98–101. A trove of documents from the UN War Crimes Commission, made available by the Wiener Library for the Study of the Holocaust and Genocide in 2017, offers evidence of war crimes prosecutions of rape and forced prostitution in the 1940s, in places ranging from Greece and Poland to the Philippines. Owen Bowcott, “Opening of UN Files on Holocaust Will ‘Rewrite Chapters of History,’” The Guardian, Apr. 17, 2017, https://www.theguardian.com/law/2017/apr/18/opening-un-holocaust-files-archive -war-crimes-commission. 11. Geneva IV, art. 27. 12. Additional Protocol II, art. 4(2)(e). Further, Additional Protocol I includes an article titled “The Protection of Women,” stating that they “shall be the object of special respect,” adding that they “shall be protected in particular against rape, forced prostitution and any other form of indecent assault.” Additional Protocol I, art. 76(1). 13. Foreign and Commonwealth Office, “Foreign Secretary’s Remarks at the Opening of the Global Summit Fringe,” June 10, 2014, https://www.gov.uk/government/news/foreign -secretarys-remarks-at-the-opening-of-the-global-summit-fringe--2. (Hague delivered Notes to Introduction 175 remarks at the opening of the Global Summit.) Rhonda Copelon, one of the feminists involved in early international criminalization efforts, viewed the International Criminal Court as holding this potential. Copelon, “Rape and Gender Violence.” Claims about the shame-shifting benefit for victims fit with a larger pattern of using victims—or an abstracted figure of “The Victims,” as Sara Kendall and Sarah Nouwen put it—to justify the existence of international criminal law. Kendall and Nouwen, “Representational Practices at the International Criminal Court.” 14. Secretary of State Hillary Clinton, “Remarks on the Adoption of a UN Security Council Resolution to Combat Sexual Violence in Armed Conflict,” Sept. 30, 2009, https://2009–2017.state.gov/secretary/20092013clinton/rm/2009a/09/130041.htm. 15. Kinsella, The Image before the Weapon. 16. For critical discussions of these depictions of women perpetrators as aberrational, see Drumbl, “She Makes Me Ashamed to Be a Woman”; Sjoberg, Women as Wartime Rapists; Sjoberg and Gentry, Mothers, Monsters, Whores. 17. For one example, see Mohanty, “Under Western Eyes.” For detailed discussion of Third World feminist critiques specifically in the context of human rights, some of which make similar arguments, see Chapter One, Section II(C). 18. Catharine MacKinnon has made both assimilative and worse-harm arguments. As to the assimilative argument, she contends that “women’s experience is the template” for understanding sexual violence against men so that when men are sexually abused, they are “ignored as women are.” MacKinnon, “On Torture,” 21. Elsewhere, however, she argues that men lose their masculinity when sexually attacked, thereby suffering a harm that women cannot experience. For further discussion of MacKinnon’s and others’ positions on male victims of sexual violence, see Chapter Three, p. 99. 19. Sandesh Sivakumaran, for example, notes that “male rape is often considered to be ‘a slur on [the] virility or manhood’ of the victim” and discusses how homophobia both exacerbates the stigma and contributes to the underreporting of sexual violence against men. Sivakumaran, “Male/Male Rape,” 1289, 1279, respectively. He cites MacKinnon favorably to this end. Ibid., 1282. 20. Hannah Arendt famously coined this term in the context of the trial of Adolf Eichmann, a Nazi bureaucrat who, in Arendt’s (controversial) diagnosis, was remarkable in his ordinariness (evidenced in part by his facility, even dependence, on cliché). See Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem. 21. Judith Gardam was one of the few feminists considering international humanitarian law during that period and, notably, her focus was not on rape and sexual violence. See, for example, Gardam, “A Feminist Analysis.” See also Gardam, NonCombatant Immunity. Yougindra Khushalani published a book in 1982 that made a doctrinal argument that rape had long violated international humanitarian law, though relying in large part on the dignity and honor language that feminists would later attempt to move away from. See Khushalani, Dignity and Honour of Women. 22. For an early example, see Meron, “On the Inadequate Reach of Humanitarian and Human Rights Law.” Writing in 1983 to encourage a new human rights instru- 176 Notes to Introduction ment that could be applied to internal strife falling short of armed conflict, Meron noted that “humanitarian law and human rights law have not been tightly woven into each other.” Ibid., 602–3. At the same time, he also insisted that “there exists a very large measure of convergence and parallelism” between their norms “in matters such as the prohibition of torture and cruel, inhuman, or degrading treatment or punishment, arbitrary arrest, and detention, discrimination on grounds of race, sex, language, or religion, and the norm of due process.” Ibid., 593. A few years later, in 1987, the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights declined to apply international humanitarian law in a case before it. Only in 1998 did the commission and the InterAmerican Court of Human Rights begin to use international humanitarian law to interpret the American Convention on Human Rights. Lixinski, “Treaty Interpretation,” 591–94. Although human rights advocates and courts might have been relatively slow to appreciate the utility of international humanitarian law to their work, the UN had considered the application of human rights law to wartime in the late 1960s—even before the onset of the contemporary human rights movement and only shortly after the covenants on human rights opened for signature. In 1967, for example, the Security Council passed Resolution 237 in response to the Six-Day War, indicating to Israel that “essential and inalienable human rights should be respected even during the vicissitudes of war.” UN Security Council, Resolution 237, preambular para. 2. For mention of this resolution in a larger examination of human rights during times of armed conflict, see UN Secretary-General, Respect for Human Rights in Armed Conflicts, UN Doc. A/7720, Nov. 20, 1969, para. 31. 23. See, for example, Bernstein, “The Sexual Politics of the ‘New Abolitionism.’” 24. See Engle, “Anti-Impunity and the Turn to Criminal Law.” 25. See Halley, Kotiswasan, Rebouché, and Shamir, Governance Feminism: An Introduction; and their edited volume, Governance Feminism: Notes from the Field. 26. This argument that rape is not an inevitable part of war has become a trope, but its use here differs from the way it has been asserted by some academics in the field, which is to contest the idea that rape in war is natural by pointing to armed groups that have not used rape as a weapon of war. Elisabeth Wood’s work has been most influential in this regard. See especially Wood, “Rape during War Is Not Inevitable.” See also Cohen, “Explaining Rape during Civil War”; Hoover Green, “Repertoires of Violence against Non-Combatants.” For an example of work that they contest, see Brownmiller, Against Our Will, 32, saying, “War provides men with the perfect psychologic backdrop to give vent to their contempt for women.” 27. This lack of justification is not unique to sexual violence, and it is particularly pronounced in the context of international criminal law. For an analysis of the lack of justification offered by the promoters of the ICC, see Moyn, “Anti-Impunity as Deflection of Argument.” For an argument that international criminal law is “deeply retributive,” though generally defended on other grounds, see Woods, “Moral Judgments and International Crimes.” 28. Scott, The Politics of the Veil, 10. Notes to Chapter One 177 Chapter One An earlier version of this chapter was published as “Feminist Governance and International Law: From Liberal to Carceral Feminism,” in Governance Feminism: Notes from the Field, ed. Janet Halley, Prabha Kotiswaran, Rachel Rebouché, and Hila Shamir, 3–30 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2019). 1. UN World Conference on Human Rights, Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action [hereinafter Vienna Declaration], para. 38. 2. UN World Conference on Human Rights, Report of the World Conference on Human Rights, 47–49. 3. I borrow the phrase “carceral feminism” from Elizabeth Bernstein. See Bernstein, “The Sexual Politics of the ‘New Abolitionism.’” See also Bernstein, “Militarized Humanitarianism Meets Carceral Feminism,” and Bernstein, “Carceral Politics as Gender Justice?” 4. UN Security Council, Resolution 798, preambular para. 2. 5. Ibid., para. 2. 6. Ibid., preambular para. 3. 7. Amnesty International, Bosnia-Herzegovina, 6–7; UN Commission on Human Rights, Situation of Human Rights in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1993/50, Feb. 10, 1993, paras. 82–85; European Council Investigative Mission into the Treatment of Muslim Women in the Former Yugoslavia, Report to European Council Foreign Ministers, para. 13. The European Council’s report, often called the Warburton Report, estimated the number of Muslim rape victims at 20,000, but noted that other estimates ranged from 10,000 to 60,000. Ibid., para. 14. For discussion of the discrepancies in estimates and a critique of the higher number, see von RagenfeldFelman, “The Victimization of Women.” 8. UN Commission on Human Rights, Situation of Human Rights in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia, para. 82. 9. UN Security Council, Resolution 827, preambular para. 3 and para. 2. 10. UN Charter, art. 27, para. 3. The stalemate with regard to Chapter VII did not, however, mean that international law and international institutions were in a hiatus during the Cold War. See Craven, Pahuja, and Simpson, “Reading and Unreading a Historiography of Hiatus.” 11. By dating the “takeoff ” of human rights to the 1970s, I essentially follow Samuel Moyn’s history of the origins of the contemporary human rights movement. Moyn, The Last Utopia. 12. For a perspective from the interwar years, see Woolf, The Three Guineas. For a contemporary historical analysis of the period, see Knop, “Of the Male Persuasion.” See also Fraser, “Becoming Human.” 13. See Fraser, “Becoming Human,” 857; Otto, “Disconcerting ‘Masculinities,’” 112–13. 14. See Rathgeber, “WID, WAD, GAD,” for an overview of the historical involvement of women in international development programs, as well as the three conceptual paradigms that emerged over time: “WID” (Women in Development), “WAD” (Women and Development), and “GAD” (Gender and Development). 178 Notes to Chapter One 15. For detailed discussion of the work of liberal inclusionists—whom I labeled doctrinalists and institutionalists—from the time period discussed here, see Engle, “International Human Rights and Feminism: When Discourses Meet,” 535–64. 16. The most systematic example of the structural-bias critique of international law in general, not just of human rights, is Charlesworth, Chinkin, and Wright, “Feminist Approaches to International Law.” 17. Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 494. 18. Thomas, “Conclusion,” 358. 19. As Hilary Charlesworth has put it, “Patriarchy and the devaluing of women, although manifestly different in different societies, are almost universal.” Charlesworth, “Human Rights as Men’s Rights,” 103. On that same page, however, she is careful to state that “certainly no monolithic ‘women’s point of view’ can be assumed.” 20. See, for example, Knop, “Re/Statements.” 21. See, for example, Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 488; Stark, “The ‘Other’ Half of the International Bill of Rights”; Sullivan, “The Public/Private Distinction,” 126–27. Hilary Charlesworth offered an even more extensive list of dichotomies: “objective/subjective, legal/political, logic/emotion, order/anarchy, mind/body, culture/nature, action/passivity, public/private, protector/protected, independence/dependence.” Charlesworth, “Feminist Methods in International Law,” 382. 22. Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 488. 23. This general approach to the public/private distinction was probably first articulated in the international context in 1986 by Noreen Burrows. See Burrows, “International Law and Human Rights.” 24. See, for example, Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 491; Eisler, “Human Rights,” 289–90. 25. For a detailed analysis of public/private discussions in the early 1990s, including the oscillation between these two positions by many, see Engle, “After the Collapse of the Public/Private Distinction.” See also Sullivan, “The Public/Private Distinction.” 26. MacKinnon, “On Torture,” 21. She noted that intimate violence against men would also not be seen as a human rights violation. 27. Ibid. 28. Ibid., 23. 29. Ibid. 30. For just a few examples, see Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 489; Cerna and Wallace, “Women and Culture,” 633; Eisler, “Human Rights”; Toubia, “Female Genital Mutilation.” For a critique of some of the assumptions about culture that are embodied in some feminists’ fixation on practices such as dowry deaths and female circumcision, as well as the implications of those assumptions for the treatment of entire countries (India) or even continents (Africa), see Kapur, “The Tragedy of Victimization Rhetoric,” 12–17. 31. Charlesworth, Chinkin, and Wright, “Feminist Approaches to International Law,” 621. Notes to Chapter One 179 32. For discussion of Third World feminist critics who did analyze international law for its treatment of Third World women in ways that parallel the doctrinal and structural-bias approaches, see Engle, “International Human Rights and Feminisms: When Discourses Keep Meeting,” 59–60. 33. For a contemporary reexamination of the NIEO and its lessons for global governance today, see the essays in Gilman, “Toward a History of the New International Economic Order.” 34. For an elaboration of this literature, as well as a description of what I mean by Third World feminism (as distinct from feminism in the Third World), see Engle, “International Human Rights and Feminisms: When Discourses Keep Meeting,” 60–66. 35. Ong, “Strategic Sisterhood or Sisters in Solidarity?,” 113. 36. See, for example, Gunning, “Arrogant Perception, World-Travelling and Multicultural Feminism”; Lewis, “Between Irua and ‘Female Genital Mutilation,’” 32. 37. Johnson and Obiora, “Panel Discussion,” 207. 38. Nesiah, “Toward a Feminist Internationality,” 197. 39. Kapur, “The Tragedy of Victimization Rhetoric,” 6. 40. Spivak, “Can the Subaltern Speak?,” 296. 41. Obiora, “Feminism, Globalization, and Culture,” 385. See also ibid., 370–71, agreeing with the “poignant objections raised against solipsistic researchers who zero in on clitoridectomy as the sole point of reference and definition for women’s oppression in Africa and the Middle East.” 42. Ibid., 363. 43. Ong, “Strategic Sisterhood or Sisters in Solidarity?,” 126. 44. UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, “World Conference on Human Rights, 14–25 June 1993, Vienna, Austria,” https://www.ohchr.org/en/aboutus /pages/viennawc.aspx. See also Boyle, “Stock-taking on Human Rights,” 79–80. 45. For some analyses of the positions taken by various sides in the debate in the years shortly after the Vienna Conference, see Bell, “The East Asian Challenge to Human Rights,” and Ghai, “Human Rights and Governance.” For a later discussion connecting that debate to other debates about culture in human rights, see Engle, “Culture and Human Rights.” 46. Bunch, “How Women’s Rights Became Recognized as Human Rights,” 30. 47. Keck and Sikkink, Activists beyond Borders, 186. 48. Bunch, “How Women’s Rights Became Recognized as Human Rights,” 30. 49. Ibid., 33–34. 50. Ibid., 29. 51. The conference was held on April 15 and 16, 1988, and consisted of an introduction by Henry Steiner, who was faculty director of the Human Rights Program and very supportive of the event, a keynote address by Arvonne Fraser, a panel titled “The Struggle for Women’s Rights: Perspectives from around the World” (with Marjori Agosín, Charlotte Bunch, Kekelwa Dall, Kumari Jayawardena, Annette Liu, and Alison Weatherfield), and a panel titled “Putting Women’s Issues on the International Human Rights Agenda: Can We? Should We?” (with Philip Alston, John Carey, Rebecca Cook, 180 Notes to Chapter One Felice Gaer, Aída González, Fran Hosken, and Michael Posner). The conference also included film and poetry, as well as the following working groups: Developed and Developing Countries: Perspectives on Women’s Rights; Non-Governmental Organizations: Thinking Globally, Acting Locally; Women’s Health: A Human Rights Issue; Lesbian Rights: A Strategy for Recognition; Women in Popular and Revolutionary Struggles: A Focus on Latin America; and Women and Violence: A Case Study of India’s Rape Laws. The student organizing committee was composed largely of individuals who continue to work on gender and human rights, including Stacy Brustin, Brenda Cossman, Suzanne Goldberg, and Ratna Kapur. 52. Bunch, “How Women’s Rights Became Recognized as Human Rights,” 33. 53. Ibid., 34. Language in brackets in a UN document is language on which the states have been unable to agree prior to the stage at which the document is being considered. 54. Bunch and Reilly, Demanding Accountability, 2. 55. Ibid. See also ibid., 104–6. 56. Vienna Declaration, para. 38. 57. Bunch and Reilly, Demanding Accountability, 8. 58. For discussion of, critique of, and reaction to this compromise in the context of the Vienna Declaration, see Engle, “Culture and Human Rights,” 320–24. 59. Vienna Declaration, para. 1. 60. Ibid., para. 5. 61. Ibid. 62. Secretary-General Boutros Boutros-Ghali later used the compromise to call in a different context for the “same dialectic of the universal and the particular, of identity and difference” that he had supported in Vienna. Boutros-Ghali, “Address by the Secretary-General of the United Nations at the Opening of the International Conference on Population and Development,” 5. 63. UN World Conference on Women, Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action, Annex II, ch. II, para. 9. 64. Obiora, “Feminism, Globalization, and Culture,” 389. 65. See, for example, Cerna, “Universality of Human Rights and Cultural Diversity,” 741–42; Orford, “Contesting Globalization,” 192; Posner, “Reflections on the Vienna Conference on Human Rights,” 317. 66. Otto, “Rethinking the ‘Universality’ of Human Rights Law,” 11. 67. See, for example, Brems, “Enemies or Allies?”; Cossman, “Turning the Gaze Back on Itself ”; Desai, “Hearing Afghan Women’s Voices”; Garay, “Women, Cultural Relativism, and International Human Rights”; Higgins, “Anti-Essentialism, Relativism, and Human Rights”; Hom, “Commentary: Re-Positioning Human Rights Discourse on ‘Asian’ Perspectives”; Oloka-Onyango and Tamale, “‘The Personal Is Political,’”; Romany, “Black Women and Gender Equality in a New South Africa”; Stacey, “Legal Discourse and the Feminist Political Economy”; Stark, “Bottom Line Feminist Theory.” For an earlier such article, see Kim, “Toward a Feminist Theory of Human Rights.” Notes to Chapter One 181 68. For one discussion of anti-imperialist feminist work and some of the debates in which it has and has not had particular traction, see Engle, Nesiah, and Otto, “Feminist Approaches to International Law.” 69. Bunch and Reilly, Demanding Accountability, 4–5. The 16 Days campaign is still in existence. 70. See ibid., 21–91. 71. See ibid., 63–73, 89–90. 72. See Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 488, discussed on page 24. 73. For discussion of Nairobi as having been central to the emergence of VAW as a theme, see Miller, “Sexuality, Violence against Women, and Human Rights”; Patton, “Women and Power”; Pietilä and Vickers, Making Women Matter. 74. UN World Conference on Women, Report of the World Conference to Review and Appraise the Achievements of the United Nations Decade for Women, para. 258. 75. Ibid. Jutta Joachim attributed its inclusion in the peace section to “linkage politics.” Joachim, “Shaping the Human Rights Agenda,” 147, citing Patton, “Women and Power.” 76. Joachim, “Shaping the Human Rights Agenda,” 147. 77. Fraser, She’s No Lady, 225. See also Keck and Sikkink, Activists beyond Borders, 170, noting that in general at the conference, “convergence around the issue of violence against women was the result of creating a category for discussion and action that linked concerns of women around the world.” 78. A statement on the Peace Tent by the organizers of the event described it as “the international feminist alternative to men’s conflict and war,” with the aim to “bring women’s peacemaking will and consciousness to the world, which so desperately needs it.” Peace Tent Statement, ca. 1985, https://law.utexas.edu/farenthold/document/peace-tent -statement/. See also Frances Tarlton Farenthold, “The Peace Tent: Its Origin, Its Impact, Its Future,” Oct. 10, 1985, https://law.utexas.edu/farenthold/document/the-peace -tent-its-origin-its-impact-its-future/. The program from the Peace Tent also suggested this emphasis. See Frances Tarlton Farenthold and Genevieve Vaughan, “Nairobi Notes,” ca. 1985, https://law.utexas.edu/farenthold/document/nairobi-notes/. These documents are physically located in the Frances Tarlton Farenthold Papers, 1913–2015, Dolph Briscoe Center for American History, The University of Texas at Austin, boxes 3U132a and 3U145a. 79. “Activist Origins of the 16 Days Campaign,” 16 Days Campaign, http://16dayscwgl.rutgers.edu/about/activist-origins-of-the-campaign. 80. Ibid. 81. Keck and Sikkink, Activists beyond Borders, 170–71. 82. Ibid., 171, quoting interview with Charlotte Bunch, New York City, Feb. 21, 1996. 83. Ibid. 84. Suchland, Economies of Violence, 51. 85. Ibid. 86. Ibid. 182 Notes to Chapter One 87. UN Division for the Advancement of Women, “Sexual Violence and Armed Conflict,” 8. 88. Ibid., 13. 89. Ibid., 13–14. 90. Vienna Declaration, para. 38. 91. Miller, “Sexuality, Violence against Women, and Human Rights,” 25. 92. Bunch and Reilly, Demanding Accountability, 34. 93. The full transcripts of the testimonies given can be found at Center for Women’s Global Leadership, Testimonies of the Global Tribunal on Violations of Women’s Human Rights, http://www.cwgl.rutgers.edu/docman/coalition-building -publications/294-testimoniesglobaltribunal-pdf/file. A look at these on war crimes demonstrates that testimony did cover other issues as well, such as the unique situation of women as peacemakers (from a Somalian woman, 29–30) and the importance of women’s solidarity (from a member of the Serbian anti-militarist group Women in Black, 39). Many of the testimonies and profiles of the speakers, of course, also demonstrate the active roles that women often play in politics. 94. Miller, “Sexuality, Violence against Women, and Human Rights,” 25, citing Center for Women’s Global Leadership, Rutgers University, Women’s Rights Are Human Rights: The Vienna Tribunal, video (1993). 95. Bunch and Reilly, Demanding Accountability, 47. 96. Miller, “Sexuality, Violence against Women, and Human Rights,” 19. 97. Indeed, some argued that the rapes received serious attention only “because the Western world identified with the victims they were hearing about. It was not possible to dismiss the stories as concerned with distant cultural traditions or genders unfamiliar to the Western world.” Skjelsbæk, “Sexual Violence in the Post-Yugoslav Wars,” 69. Regardless of the motive for attention, I would contend that Bosnia was in fact often treated as a site of the global South. 98. There was, however, occasional mention of such violence. See, for example, Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 497; Thomas and Beasley, “Domestic Violence as a Human Rights Issue,” 39–40. 99. Bunch, “Women’s Rights as Human Rights,” 490–91. 100. Ibid., 497. See also ibid., 489. 101. Barry, Female Sexual Slavery. On Barry’s coining the term, see Scoular, The Subject of Prostitution, 58. 102. Barry, Bunch, and Castley, eds., International Feminism. 103. Pheterson, “Not Repeating History,” 17–21. 104. For an extended and very helpful genealogy of the shift in Barry’s position on whether there exists a category of unforced prostitution (pointing to Barry’s publicly changing her mind in 1995 to say that no such category exists) and the legacy of debates over the issue in the drafting of the Rome Statute, see Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 91–92. 105. Barry, “The Opening Paper,” 22. In their introduction to the report on the Rotterdam workshop, Bunch and Castley quoted and followed Barry’s definition of female sexual slavery from her earlier work, as that which “is present in all situations where Notes to Chapter One 183 women or girls cannot change the immediate conditions of their existence; where, regardless of how they got into those conditions they cannot get out; and where they are subject to sexual violence and exploitation.” Bunch and Castley, introduction to Barry, Bunch, and Castley, International Feminism, 8–9, quoting Barry, Female Sexual Slavery. 106. Barry, “The Opening Paper,” 21. See also Bunch, “Network Strategies,” 49, offering a similar list. 107. International Committee for Prostitutes’ Rights, “World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights, Amsterdam, February 1985,” in Pheterson, A Vindication of the Rights of Whores, 40. 108. Ibid. 109. Bunch, “Network Strategies,” 49. That position was consistent with earlier writing by Bunch, in which she called for an expansion of the term “feminism” to “[respond] to the realities of all women, across race, sexuality, and national boundaries,” as a part of her manifesto for “non-aligned feminism.” Bunch, “Beyond Either/ Or,” 54. 110. Bunch and Castley, introduction to Barry, Bunch, and Castley, International Feminism, 10. 111. Ibid., 9. 112. Suchland, Economics of Violence, 48 (paraphrasing from an interview with Bunch; italics in the original). 113. Ibid. 114. This dynamic has manifested in other contexts as well. In particular, Miriam Ticktin describes an almost parallel move in what she called the medicalization and politicization of sexual violence by humanitarian and aid organizations in the early 2000s. She, too, points to how a politics of the body displaced one of redistribution. Ticktin, “The Gendered Human of Humanitarianism,” 255. 115. Copelon, “International Human Rights Dimensions of Intimate Violence,” 867. 116. Vienna Declaration, para. 38. 117. Pillay, “Opening Statement by Ms. Navi Pillay United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights at the 22nd Session of the Human Rights Council,” Feb. 25, 2013, https://newsarchive.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews .aspx?NewsID=13031&LangID=e. The third achievement she listed was “its swiftly realized recommendation to create . . . the Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights.” Ibid. 118. Ibid. 119. Tamar Lewin, “The Balkans Rapes: A Legal Test for the Outraged,” New York Times, Jan. 15, 1993, https://nyti.ms/2OpjEnH. 120. Other members of the coalition included Human Rights Watch’s Women’s Rights Project, Equality Now, Amnesty International, the Fund for a Feminist Majority, Women’s Action Coalition, the Center for Reproductive Policy and Law, and Ms. Foundation for Women. Ibid. 121. Mertus, “When Adding Women Matters,” 1300, quoting her telephone interview with Bunch, Feb. 2004. 184 Notes to Chapter One 122. Gruber, “The Feminist War on Crime,” 749–51. 123. See, for example, Bernstein, “Carceral Politics as Gender Justice?,” 239. 124. Gruber, “The Feminist War on Crime,” 794–96. 125. Martin, “Retribution Revisited,” 166. For consideration and critique of feminist criminal law reform strategies in the United States, see Gruber, “Rape, Feminism, and the War on Crime.” 126. Martin, “Retribution Revisited,” 156–57, 157n9. 127. Ibid., 168. 128. Joachim, Agenda Setting, the UN, and NGOs, 116–22. 129. Ibid., 119. 130. See Engle, “Anti-Impunity and the Turn to Criminal Law in Human Rights,” 1074–79. 131. Velásquez Rodríguez v. Honduras, Merits, Inter-American Court of Human Rights, Ser. C No. 4 (July 29, 1988). 132. Ibid., para. 174. 133. See, for example, Byrnes, “Women, Feminism, and International Human Rights Law,” 229; Etienne, “Addressing Gender-Based Violence in an International Context,” 157n97; Spahn, “Waiting for Credentials,” 1064n34. To this day, VelásquezRodríguez and its progeny are cited by those who argue for state responsibility for VAW. See, for example, UN General Assembly Human Rights Council, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Violence against Women, Its Causes and Consequences, Rashida Manjoo, UN Doc. A/HRC/23/49, May 14, 2013, para. 15. 134. Vienna Declaration, paras. 23, 60, 90, 92. The Special Declaration on Bosnia and Herzegovina also called for the speedy implementation of Security Council Resolution 808, establishing the ICTY. UN World Conference on Human Rights, Report of the World Conference on Human Rights, 49, para. 9. 135. Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 101–20. The statute, for example, names rape alongside “sexual slavery, enforced prostitution, forced pregnancy, enforced sterilization, or any other form of sexual violence of comparable gravity” as a crime against humanity. Rome Statute, art. 7(1)(g). It includes similar language in two other places, under the lists of war crimes in both international and non-international conflicts. Ibid., arts. 8(2)(b)(xii), 8(2)(e)(vi). 136. Halley elaborates: “The consensus that emerged as the feminists’ joint representation of their worldview, argument repertoire, and reform agenda was not, as one might expect, a median liberal feminist view that split the difference between conservative and leftist feminist ideologies. Instead, the manifest consensus view was an updated radical feminism, strongly committed to a structuralist understanding of male domination and female subordination. There was some tension on a few issues between structuralist and liberal-individualist feminists . . . but it was muted by the coalitional style adopted by feminists and compromised usually in the direction of structuralist rule choices.” Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 2–3. 137. Ibid., 6. 138. See, for example, UN Security Council, Resolution 1820; Resolution 1888; Resolution 1960; Resolution 2106. Notes to Chapters One and Two 185 139. Miller, “Sexuality, Violence against Women, and Human Rights,” 36–37. She uses Gayle Rubin’s notion of sexual hierarchies, which are “systems of legitimacy both tacit (shaming) and explicit (legal) that arise in various contexts (country, culture, whatever the unit of imagination) and that prioritize certain forms of reproductive, marital, and heterosexual activity above other sexual behaviors and identities.” Ibid., 36, citing Gayle Rubin, “Thinking Sex: Notes for a Radical Theory of the Polities of Sexuality,” in Pleasure and Danger: Exploring Female Sexuality, ed. C. S. Vance (Boston: Routledge, 1984), 267–319. One of the few other written expressions of this concern can be found in the discussion of an international gathering on gender and transitional justice held in the mid-2000s. Reflecting on some of the debates that emerged at the event, Vasuki Nesiah notes: “There were questions about whether the focus on sexual violence feeds into a regressive sex panic that is then used to regulate and further criminalize women’s sexuality—with particular consequences for women who were involved in sex work in conflict contexts. Did the preoccupation with sexual violence to the exclusion of other issues accompany, and even engender, a preoccupation with ‘legitimate’ and ‘illegitimate’ sex, policing the borders of the ‘decent’ and the ‘deviant,’ only to then reinscribe heteronormative models and approaches?” Nesiah, “Discussion Lines on Gender and Transitional Justice,” 806. 140. Here is one of the few places I disagree with Dianne Otto, who states (largely in disagreement with Janet Halley): “I argue that the institutional reception and management of feminist ideas works to divest them of their emancipatory content, and therefore prefer to depict the result as ‘cooption’ rather than ‘governance feminism,’ which implies the result is intentional.” Otto, “The Exile of Inclusion,” 13. I disagree in part because I do not believe that intentionality is required in governance feminism. But I also think that Halley and Otto are talking past each other in a way because they are discussing the impact of two very different forms of feminism—with Halley concentrating on the successes of structural-bias feminism and its role in international criminal law and Otto largely considering the women’s peace movement in relationship to the Women, Peace and Security agenda. Chapter Two 1. For a detailed analysis of media coverage of the rapes, and of the very different ways in which they were covered by the Croatian and Serbian press, see Žarkov, The Body of War, 216. 2. For an early collection of articles about rape in Bosnia, see Stiglmayer, Mass Rape. 3. The first such resolution was UN Security Council, Resolution 713. For discussion of two of the other resolutions, see Chapter One, Section I. 4. UNPROFOR was meant to facilitate the delivery of humanitarian aid and “ensure a peaceful political settlement.” UN Security Council, Resolution 743, preambular para. 8. 5. For sanctions, see UN Security Council, Resolution 757 and Resolution 787. For safe areas, see UN Security Council, Resolution 819 and Resolution 824. 6. Operation Deliberate Force was approved in July 1995 and carried out between August 30 and September 20, 1995. For a concise summary of the events leading up to it, including limited NATO strikes, see Hansen, Security as Practice, 116–23. 186 Notes to Chapter Two 7. See, for example, UN Security Council, Resolution 771, para. 2. 8. UN General Assembly, Resolution 47/121, preambular para. 9. 9. Ibid., para. 7(a). Articles 41 and 42, found in Chapter VII of the UN Charter, enumerate measures that the Security Council may take to “maintain or restore international peace and security.” Article 41 provides for economic sanctions, interruption of communications, and severance of diplomatic relations. The language of necessity arises in Article 42, which expressly provides for the use of military force that “may be necessary to maintain or restore international peace and security,” in the event that Article 41 measures are inadequate. Article 51 makes clear that, notwithstanding other provisions, the Security Council is authorized “to take at any time such action as it deems necessary in order to maintain or restore international peace and security.” 10. The resolution passed with 102 votes in favor, 57 abstentions, and 20 member states not voting. Of the ten non-permanent members that year, six voted yes: Austria, Cabo Verde, Ecuador, Hungary, Morocco, and Venezuela. Belgium, India, Japan, and Zimbabwe abstained. Voting Record for UN Doc. A/RES/47/121 (Dec. 18, 1992), available at https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/282898?ln=en. 11. UN Charter, arts. 42, 51. Humanitarian justifications also played a key role in calls for individual state actors or collective actors other than the UN (like NATO) to use military force. After NATO intervened in Kosovo without Security Council authorization, the Independent International Commission on Kosovo proposed to amend the UN Charter to allow for action by the Security Council or other “collective actors in international society” on humanitarian grounds. Independent International Commission on Kosovo, Kosovo Report, 187. Although the effort failed, the UN SecretaryGeneral later suggested that “genocide, ethnic cleansing and other such crimes against humanity” be considered as threats to international peace and security under the UN Charter. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General: In Larger Freedom: Towards Development, Security and Human Rights for All, UN Doc. A/59/2005, Mar. 21, 2005, para. 125. 12. Rieff, At the Point of a Gun. 13. Kenneth Roth, director of Human Rights Watch, and John Shattuck, former U.S. Assistant Secretary of State for Democracy, Human Rights, and Labor, have both used this term to describe themselves. See Roth, Tesón, and Arthur, “Ending Tyranny in Iraq,” 2; Shattuck and Myers, “Freedom on Fire” (interview). 14. On this “‘g-word’ controversy,” see Power, “A Problem from Hell,” 290. 15. Ibid., 288. 16. Ibid., reflecting on the Bush administration’s decision to describe the situation in Bosnia as “ethnic cleansing,” not as “genocide.” 17. Ibid., 289. 18. Ibid., 292, quoting Patricia Diaz Dennis, “Special State Department Briefing on Report to Congress on Human Rights Practices for 1992,” Jan. 19, 1993. 19. Shattuck, Freedom on Fire, 131. 20. Ibid., 343n43, quoting Power, “A Problem from Hell,” 359. Shattuck believed the memo mischaracterized the State Department’s objection as “based on ‘legal’ rather Notes to Chapter Two 187 than ‘policy’ issues,” but acknowledged that “it certainly reflects the bureaucracy’s nervousness over the issue.” Ibid. 21. Ibid., 139–40. That said, he also sets forth criteria for limiting instances of intervention (ibid., 295–96) and discusses the important role of criminal justice (ibid., 299–301). 22. Many of the arguments about intervention have taken place under the rubric of R2P, which remains controversial in terms of both its legal status and its definition. At its core, R2P specifies that states have a responsibility to protect their populations from mass crimes. If a state fails to offer that protection, other states individually or collectively (positions differ on whether UN Security Council approval should be necessary and whether, if not, the action nevertheless needs to be collective) have a responsibility to intervene in the internal affairs of the state to prevent or end the atrocities. In the early 2000s, many states and UN actors voiced widespread rhetorical support for R2P, including then UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan. Some states even went so far as to establish the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, led by the Canadian government and tasked with supporting the recognition of R2P as law. Despite these efforts, states remain hesitant to rely on it to prevent mass crimes and, where it has been used—such as in Libya—its emphasis on coercive or military measures has been a subject of great controversy. See UN Secretary-General, A Vital and Enduring Commitment: Implementing the Responsibility to Protect, UN Doc. A/69/981– S/2015/500, July 13, 2015, paras. 3–5, 8–9. See also UN Office on Genocide Prevention and the Responsibility to Protect, “About the Responsibility to Protect,” http://www .un.org/en/genocideprevention/about-responsibility-to-protect.html. 23. International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, The Responsibility to Protect, para. 4.19. 24. Anna Quindlen, “Public & Private; Gynocide,” New York Times, Mar. 10, 1993, A19. 25. Ibid. 26. Recall from Chapter One, p. 25, that in 1990 she had also written a short piece on torture, though most of the examples it discussed were from the United States and Canada. MacKinnon, “On Torture.” 27. MacKinnon, “Remedies for War Crimes at the National Level.” 28. Nenadic, “Femicide,” 456n1, 460. 29. Ibid., 459. 30. See, for example, Kesic, “A Response to Catharine MacKinnon’s Article,” 269. 31. See, for example, MacKinnon, “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights,” 189–90. See also MacKinnon, “Crimes of War, Crimes of Peace,” 146. Andrea Dworkin, MacKinnon’s collaborator in her opposition to pornography in the United States, also remarked upon the importance of pornography to the treatment of women in the former Yugoslavia, describing pornography as “war propaganda that trained an army of rapists who waited for permission to advance.” Andrea Dworkin, “The Real Pornography of a Brutal War against Women: Bosnia,” Los Angeles Times, Sept. 5, 1993, M2, M6, http://articles.latimes.com/1993–09–05/opinion /op-32107_1_serbian-military. 188 Notes to Chapter Two 32. Nenadic, “Femicide,” 462n16, also favorably citing Dworkin. 33. Early on, many who viewed rape as genocide, including MacKinnon, contended that rapes by Serbian men of both Croatian and Bosnian Muslim women constituted genocide, but later—as Croatia became an aggressor in the war—the focus shifted to the Serbian rape of Bosnian Muslims. According to Žarkov, the Croatian media also concentrated most heavily on the rape of Muslim, as opposed to Croatian, women. Žarkov, The Body of War, 129–42. 34. The civil lawsuit, Kadic v. Karadžić, was brought under two U.S. laws: the Alien Tort Statute and the Torture Victim Protection Act. Ironically, it was joined with a similar suit brought by claimants represented by Rhonda Copelon, who, while a major advocate of bringing accountability to perpetrators of rape in the former Yugoslavia, was opposed to treating the rapes as genocidal, at least on ethnic grounds. When the cases were joined “by judicial fiat,” according to MacKinnon, Copelon “strongly pressured me at counsel table to abandon [the genocide] claim in my argument. I refused.” MacKinnon, Butterfly Politics, 152. The case eventually ended with a default judgment against Karadžić in 2000, upon his stated intent not to continue to participate in further proceedings. Doe v. Karadžić, 2001 WL 986545 (S.D.N.Y. 2001). MacKinnon drew a causal connection between the decision and the eventual finding of rape as genocide in the ICTR: “Kadic has been a butterfly.” MacKinnon, Butterfly Politics, 140. 35. MacKinnon, “Remedies for War Crimes at the National Level.” 36. MacKinnon, “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights,” 186. 37. In MacKinnon, “Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State,” 647, for example, she argued: “Perhaps the wrong of rape has proven so difficult to articulate because the unquestionable starting point has been that rape is definable as distinct from intercourse, when for women it is difficult to distinguish them under conditions of male dominance.” Further, “If sex is normally something men do to women, the issue is less whether there was force and more whether consent is a meaningful concept.” Ibid., 650. Finally, “women are also violated every day by men who have no idea of the meaning of their acts to women. To them, it is sex. Therefore, to the law, it is sex.” Ibid., 652–53. In response, MacKinnon encouraged a legal definition of rape that would distinguish rape from everyday sex by focusing on the “meaning of the act from women’s point of view.” Ibid., 652. This task was of course made difficult by the fact that women themselves have a hard time distinguishing the two in a state of dominance. MacKinnon insisted that she did not equate all heterosexual sex with rape, and called the claims that she did so “a political libel.” MacKinnon, “Pornography Left and Right,” 144. 38. MacKinnon, “Genocide’s Sexuality,” 225–26. She draws the comparison back to genocide under the traditional definition, stating: “Thus men do to women (and some men) through sexual abuse outside of genocides what some men do in genocides when they sexually abuse women (and some men, especially sexually defined groups of men such as gay men) on the basis of their ethnicity, religion, nationality, or race.” Ibid. 39. Copelon, “Surfacing Gender,” 198. 40. Ibid., 207. 41. Brownmiller, “Making Female Bodies the Battlefield,” 180. Notes to Chapter Two 189 42. International Women’s Human Rights Clinic of CUNY Law School, “Gender Justice and the Constitution of the War Crimes Tribunal Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 808,” Appendix B in Green et al., “Affecting the Rules for the Prosecution of Rape and Other Gender-Based Violence before the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia,” 236–37. Elsewhere, Copelon decried “the complete failure of the United Nations and the international community in general to recognize that persecution based on gender must be recognized as its own category of crimes against humanity.” Copelon, “Surfacing Gender,” 206–8. 43. Batinić, “Feminism, Nationalism, and War,” 3–4. In the end, Batinić prefers the label “patriotic” because even those who prioritized their national identity over women’s solidarity across national lines “developed articulate critiques of nationalism in general, and of nationalism of their state’s enemy in particular.” Ibid., 20n12. Even though her article primarily focuses on debates within Croatia, she also discusses anti-nationalist groups in Bosnia and Serbia, and the solidarities they forged with non-nationalist groups in Croatia. She notes that she does not discuss Serbian patriotic women’s groups because, though they existed, they did not identify as feminist. Ibid., 10. 44. Kesić, “Women and Gender Imagery in Bosnia,” 187. 45. Ibid., 194–95. 46. Ibid., 195. 47. Hughes, Mladjenović, and Mršević, “Feminist Resistance in Serbia,” 517–18, quoting a Women in Black announcement from June 1992. 48. Stojanović, Zajović, and Urošević, Women for Peace, 45. 49. Batinić, “Feminism, Nationalism, and War,” 8, quoting a Women in Black announcement from 1992. 50. Ibid., quoting Women in Black, “Women in Black against War: A Letter to the Women’s Meeting in Amsterdam on the 8th of March 1993,” Women’s Magazine 40 (December 1993): 17–18. For an ethnographic account of Women in Black of Belgrade during the Yugoslav wars, see Athanasiou, Agonistic Mourning. For more on Women in Black and its later opposition to NATO’s bombing of Kosovo, see Scott, The Fantasy of Feminist History, 83–88, discussing in part the work of Jasmina Tešanović, Me and My Multicultural Street (Belgrade: Feministicka 94, 2001). 51. Hughes, Mladjenović, and Mršević, “Feminist Resistance in Serbia,” 517, quoting a Women in Black announcement from June 1992. 52. Stojanović, Zajović, and Urošević, Women for Peace, 96, quoting a Women in Black announcement from October 1991. 53. Sander, “Prologue,” xviii. 54. Ibid. 55. See Lilly and Irvine, “Negotiating Interests,” 139. 56. Batinić, “Feminism, Nationalism, and War,” 7, quoting a letter published in “Serbia’s War against Bosnia and Croatia,” off our backs 23 (1993), pull-out page 10. 57. Stiglmayer, “The Rapes in Bosnia-Herzegovina,” 162. Elsewhere, she criticized the “international community” for its lack of serious military response to Serbian aggression. Stiglmayer, “The War in the Former Yugoslavia,” 22–24. 190 Notes to Chapter Two 58. MacKinnon, “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights,” 186. 59. Kesic, “A Response to Catharine MacKinnon’s Article,” 275, quoting an interview MacKinnon gave to a Berlin newspaper, in Andrea Bohm, “To Create a Precedent,” Die Tageszeitung, Feb. 5, 1993, 23. 60. Batinić, “Feminism, Nationalism, and War,” 11, citing Jill Benderly, “Rape, Feminism, and Nationalism in the War in Yugoslav Successor States,” in Feminist Nationalism, ed. Lois West (New York: Routledge, 1997), 59–72. 61. MacKinnon, “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights,” 183. 62. Allen, Rape Warfare, 106. 63. Ibid., 135. 64. Ibid., 106. 65. Quindlen, “Public & Private: Gynocide,” A19. 66. Ibid. 67. Dianne Marder, “Bosnian War Puts Focus on Use of Rape as a Weapon. The Violence Has Precedent. The Attention Does Not,” Philadelphia Inquirer, Feb. 14, 1993. 68. Ibid. 69. See, for example, Askin, War Crimes against Women, 342–43. 70. Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, art. II. 71. Elsewhere, I provide a fuller account of the arguments made to connect rape and genocide, which include that rape is genocidal when it is used for ethnic cleansing, when it is deployed systematically, or when it is part of a genocidal war. Engle, “Feminism and Its (Dis)contents,” 788–94. 72. Carpenter, “Surfacing Children,” 434. 73. See, for example, Fisher, “Occupation of the Womb,” 93; Goldstein, Forced Impregnation as a War Crime under International Law, 24 (both quoted in Carpenter, “Surfacing Children,” 455). 74. Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 19. 75. Carpenter, “Surfacing Children,” 455. Carpenter also points out an incoherence in appealing to both Article II(d) and Article II(e): “But if the child is not a member of the group, . . . how could the child also be ‘forcibly transferred from the group to another’?” She argues that Wing and Merchán are inconsistent by “claiming first that the ‘resulting child will never be considered an ethnic Muslim, thereby preventing the birth of a Muslim child’ and then that ‘the event of the birth of such a non-Muslim child resulting from rape transfers that child from the Muslim population to the non-Muslim population.’” Ibid., 457, quoting Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 19. 76. MacKinnon, “Crimes of War, Crimes of Peace,” 146. 77. Ibid. 78. See, for example, Kalosieh, “Consent to Genocide?,” 132; Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 18. 79. Carpenter notes that “it is impossible to determine” how many babies were born as a result of wartime rapes in Bosnia during the conflict. On the basis of estimates of the number of Bosnian Muslim women who were raped (which she notes is “widely disputed”), the number of rapes likely to have led to pregnancies, and the percentage Notes to Chapter Two 191 of pregnancies in Bosnia that led to births, she extrapolates that there were “as many as 1,800 pregnancies and 504 births.” Carpenter, Forgetting Children Born of War, 22–23, 204n63. She claims that “the number is consistent with conservative estimates of 400– 600 given by doctors and aid workers in the field at the time and much lower than the wildly inflated estimates that prevailed during the war.” Ibid., 23. 80. For further discussion of ethnic formation and interethnic relations in Bosnia, see Chapter Three, p. 97. 81. See, for example, International Women’s Human Rights Clinic of CUNY Law School, “Gender Justice and the Constitution of the War Crimes Tribunal Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 808,” 237; Niarchos, “Women, War, and Rape,” 658; Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 20. 82. Laura Pitter and Alexandra Stiglmayer, “Will the World Remember? Can the Women Forget?,” Ms. 3, no. 5, Mar./Apr. 1993, 22, quoting from an interview with Imam Omerbašić. For a summary of many ways in which Muslim religious leaders supported Bosnian Muslim rape victims during the conflict, even if for nationalist reasons, and contrasting it with the lack of Serbian Orthodox support for Bosnian Serb victims of rape, see Simić, Silenced Victims of Wartime Sexual Violence, 66–68. 83. Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 18. Note that they added “and spiritual” to the definition, which was important to their additional argument that the rapes constituted what they termed a “spirit injury.” 84. Kalosieh, “Consent to Genocide?,” 132, quoting Jocelyn Campanaro, “Women, War, and International Law: The Historical Treatment of Gender-Based War Crimes,” Georgetown Law Journal 89, no. 8 (2001): 2557–92. 85. Askin made this claim in a section of her book on ethnic cleansing, but much of the discussion there is about genocidal rape. Askin, War Crimes against Women, 262– 87. Later in the book, she argued that “rape with the intent to destroy an ethnicity (by ethnic cleansing . . . ) is genocidal rape.” Ibid., 372. 86. Ibid., 267–68, quoting Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 5. 87. Askin, War Crimes against Women, 269. Additionally, for Wing and Merchán, “this ostracism will affect the perception that these women and children [born from rapes] have of themselves, most likely resulting in shame and lack of dignity.” Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 25. 88. Wing and Merchán, “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture,” 23. 89. Askin, War Crimes against Women, 269n889. 90. Žarkov, The Body of War, 148. 91. Ibid., discussing and citing Cheryl Benard, “Rape as Terror: The Case of Bosnia,” Terrorism and Political Violence 6, no. 1 (1994): 29–43, 43n19. 92. UN Commission on Human Rights, Report on the Situation of Human Rights in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia Submitted by Tadeusz Mazowiecki, Special Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1993/50, Feb. 10, 1993, para. 85. For discussion of these and other developments at the time that “suggest a change in the ways in which sexual violence in war came to be understood,” see Skjelsbæk, “Sexual Violence in the Post-Yugoslav Wars,” 68–69. 192 Notes to Chapter Two 93. This term and idea are taken from Judge Nusreta Sivac. For further elaboration, see the first epigraph in my Epilogue. 94. Žarkov, The Body of War, 129–30, quoting the Zagreb daily newspaper Vjesnik, Nov. 4, 1992, 9, and Dec. 29, 1992, 8. 95. Ibid., 132. 96. Ibid., 131. 97. Mischkowski and Mlinarevic, “ . . . And That It Does Not Happen to Anyone Anywhere in the World,” 6. 98. Ibid. Indeed, the report contended that representations of Bosnian Muslim communities as exceptionally stigmatizing were used to send a “subliminal message” that “Bosnian Muslim men and women cannot be a part of a civilised Europe, as they . . . mistreat ‘their’ women.” Ibid. 99. Arcel, “Deliberate Sexual Torture of Women in War,” 182–83. 100. Drakulić, “Mass Rape in Bosnia,” 270. 101. Ibid. 102. Vranić, introduction to Breaking the Wall of Silence, 29. 103. For a classic treatment of shame and humiliation as “one and the same affect,” see Tomkins, “Shame-Humiliation and Contempt-Disgust.” 104. See, for example, Drakulić, “Mass Rape in Bosnia,” 270, stating that the main concerns of victims are their fears of jeopardizing family members’ lives and their desire to forget the rapes and to avoid speaking “the ultimate humiliation and shame.” 105. Mischkowski and Mlinarevic, “ . . . And That It Does Not Happen to Anyone Anywhere in the World,” 6. 106. Stiglmayer, “The Rapes in Bosnia-Herzegovina,” 99. 107. Ibid. 108. Ibid., 131–37. 109. Folnegović-Šmalc, “Psychiatric Aspects of Rapes in the War against the Republics of Croatia and Bosnia-Herzegovina,” 177. 110. Libby Tata Arcel does identify one seemingly healthy response, in the case of Ajnusha, a twenty-five-year-old victim who, when asked if she felt shame or guilt because of what happened to her, answered: “The shame is theirs, not mine.” Still, for Arcel, Ajnusha was “one of the few women who had the ability to differentiate between herself as an object of violence and herself as a subject without any complicity in what happened.” Arcel, “Deliberate Sexual Torture of Women in War,” 181. 111. See p. 55 above, citing International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, The Responsibility to Protect, para. 4.19. 112. In September 2004, the UN Security Council invoked its Chapter VII powers to establish an International Commission of Inquiry on Darfur, which would, among other things, investigate whether genocide had taken place. UN Security Council, Resolution 1564. When the commission issued its report the following January, it stated that it had failed to uncover the intent required for a finding of genocide. Report of the International Commission of Inquiry on Darfur to the United Nations Secretary-General, Jan. 25, 2005, https://www.un.org/News/dh/sudan/com_inq_darfur.pdf, 4. Although it did Notes to Chapter Two 193 not authorize the military intervention that many had called for, in August 2006, the Security Council did expand the UN Mission in Sudan (UNMIS) to include deployment to Darfur, a decision that, after initial resistance, the Sudanese government eventually consented to. In July 2007, with sexual violence as one of its principal justifications, the Security Council authorized the expansion of the mission through the establishment of the African Union/UN Hybrid Peacekeeping Mission. UN Mission in Sudan, “UNMIS Background,” http://www.un.org/en/peacekeeping/missions/past/unmis/background .shtml. 113. For the referral, see UN Security Council, Resolution 1593. The ICC issued warrants for al Bashir’s arrest in 2009 and 2010. While the first warrant included only charges of crimes against humanity and war crimes, the second warrant charged him with genocide. Acts of rape were included in both warrants, with the latter describing acts of rape as constitutive of genocide. Warrant for Arrest for Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir, Case No. ICC-02/05-01/09 (ICC Pre-Trial Chamber, Mar. 4, 2009); Second Decision on the Prosecution’s Application for a Warrant of Arrest, Case No. ICC-02/ 05-01/09 (ICC Pre-Trial Chamber, July 12, 2010), paras. 29–30. Although al Bashir was deposed by a military coup in April 2019 and arrested and put on trial by the new regime, as of October 2019, he had not been turned over to the ICC. 114. UN Security Council, Resolution 1970, preambular para. 9 and paras. 4–8. 115. UN Security Council, Resolution 1973, preambular para. 5. 116. Ibid., preambular para. 4. 117. Ibid., paras. 6, 8. 118. See, for example, David E. Sanger and Thom Shanker, “Gates Warns of Risks of a No-Flight Zone,” New York Times, Mar. 2, 2011, https://archive.nytimes.com/www .nytimes.com/2011/03/03/world/africa/03military.html. 119. When the Washington Post first commented on the decision by the United States to support a no-fly zone, the reporters noted that “Obama’s decision to participate in military operations marks a victory for a faction of liberal interventionists within the administration, including [Susan] Rice, [Ben] Rhodes [deputy national security advisor for strategic communications,] and National Security Council senior directors Samantha Power and Gayle Smith. The announcement had been made by then Secretary of State Hillary Clinton.” Scott Wilson and Joby Warrick, “Obama’s Shift toward Military Action in Libya,” Washington Post, Mar. 18, 2011, A1, A11, available at https:// www.washingtonpost.com/politics/obamas-shift-toward-military-action-in-libya /2011/03/18/ABiClIs_story.html. 120. See, for example, Massimo Calabresi, “Susan Rice: A Voice for Intervention,” Time, Mar. 24, 2011, http://content.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171,2061224,00 .html. 121. Helene Cooper and Steven Lee Myers, “Obama Takes Hard Line with Libya after Shift by Clinton,” New York Times, Mar. 18, 2011, A1. For Clinton, the Arab League’s call for UN enforcement of a no-fly zone “changed the diplomatic landscape.” Elise Labott, “How Clinton Got behind the Military Coalition,” CNN, Mar. 20, 2011, http://www.cnn.com/2011/US/03/19/us.libya.action/index.html. 194 Notes to Chapter Two 122. Barack Obama, “Address to the Nation on the Intervention in Libya,” Washington, DC, Mar. 28, 2011, https://obamawhitehouse.archives.gov/the-press -office/2011/03/28/remarks-president-address-nation-libya. 123. Barack Obama, “Letter from the President regarding the commencement of operations in Libya,” Mar. 21, 2011, https://obamawhitehouse.archives.gov/the-press -office/2011/03/21/letter-president-regarding-commencement-operations-libya. According to the Department of Justice’s Office of Legal Counsel and State Department Legal Advisor Harold Koh, the president did not need congressional approval because national security interests (the maintenance of UN credibility and the preservation of regional stability) were at stake, and because the intervention did not rise to the threshold of a “war” for constitutional purposes. Vigeant, “Unforeseen Consequences,” 210. 124. Ryan Lizza, for example, wrote in the New Yorker of his interviews with current and former foreign policy advisors, who suggested that “the Administration’s policy debates sometimes broke down along gender lines. The realists who view foreign policy as a great chess game—and who want to focus on China and India—are usually men. The idealists, who talk about democracy and human rights, are often women.” Ryan Lizza, “The Consequentialist: How the Arab Spring Remade Obama’s Foreign Policy,” New Yorker, May 2, 2011, 50. That women might be more focused on human rights and democracy than on realpolitik, of course, is not inconsistent with their being hawks. 125. Maureen Dowd, “Fearful of Next Genocide, Women Lead U.S. to Libya,” Springfield News-Sun, Mar. 23, 2011, http://www.springfieldnewssun.com/news/lifestyles /philosophy/maureen-dowd-fearful-of-next-genocide-women-lead-1/nMqF6/. For some of the articles Dowd was likely referring to, see Jonathan Chait, “Obama’s Female Hawks,” New Republic, Mar. 20, 2011, http://www.newrepublic.com/blog/ jonathan-chait/85503/obamas-female-hawks; Jacob Heilbrunn, “America’s Foreign Policy Valkyries: Hillary Clinton, Samantha Power, and Susan Rice,” National Interest, Mar. 21, 2011, http://nationalinterest.org/blog/jacob-heilbrunn/americas-foreign -policy-valkyries-hillary-clinton-samantha-p-5047. 126. Dowd, for example, stated in the same column discussed above: “As compelling as the gender split is, it’s even more interesting to look at the parallels between Obama and W.,” noting that candidate Obama said about a possible strike on Iran, “The president does not have power under the Constitution to unilaterally authorize a military attack in a situation that does not involve stopping an actual or imminent threat to the nation.” Dowd, “Fearful of Next Genocide.” 127. Initially, the security guards at the hotel encouraged al-Obeidi to claim that rebel soldiers had raped her. For one account of al-Obeidi’s ongoing saga—from multiple arrests to life as a refugee, see Moni Basu, “A Symbol of Defiance in Ghadaffi’s Libya, Eman Al-Obeidi Just Wants to Be Left Alone,” CNN, Apr. 9, 2012, http://www.cnn.com /2012/04/08/us/colorado-libyan-rape-victim/. 128. Nicholas Kristof, “Is It Better to Save No One?,” New York Times, Apr. 2, 2011, WK12, https://www.nytimes.com/2011/04/03/opinion/03kristof.html. For Kristof and others, al-Obeidi provided a direct link by which to invoke fear of another Rwanda or Darfur: “But just because we allowed Rwandans or Darfuris to be massacred, does it re- Notes to Chapter Two 195 ally follow that to be consistent we should allow Libyans to be massacred as well? Isn’t it better to inconsistently save some lives than to consistently save none?” 129. Ewen MacAskill, “Gaddafi ‘Supplies Troops with Viagra to Encourage Mass Rape,’ Claims Diplomat,” The Guardian, Apr. 29, 2011. 130. “Rape Used ‘as a Weapon’ in Libya,” Al Jazeera, Mar. 28, 2011, http://www .aljazeera.com/video/africa/2011/03/201132845516144204.html. 131. “Fuelled ‘by Viagra,’ Gaddafi Troops Use Rape as a Weapon of War with Children as Young as Eight among the Victims,” Daily Mail, Apr. 25, 2011, http://www.dailymail .co.uk/news/article-1380364/Libya-Gaddafis-troops-rape-children-young-eight.html. 132. “Gaddafi Forces Accused of Rape: Many Women in Libya Say They Have Been Sexually Assaulted by Troops Loyal to the Libyan Leader,” Al Jazeera, May 3, 2011, http://www.aljazeera.com/video/africa/2011/05/20115381016787271.html. 133. “ICC to Investigate Reports of Viagra-Fueled Gang-Rapes in Libya,” CNN, May 17, 2011, http://edition.cnn.com/2011/WORLD/africa/05/17/libya.rapes.icc/index .html. 134. The Obama administration maintained that no authorization was needed because U.S. military involvement has remained below the level of “hostilities” since NATO took over the operation in early April. See U.S. Senate, 112th Cong., 1st sess., Hearing 112–89, Libya and War Powers: Hearing before the Committee on Foreign Relations, 7–17 (statement of Harold H. Koh). 135. U.S. House of Representatives, 112th Cong., 1st sess., H. Res. 292, “Declaring that the President Shall Not Deploy, Establish, or Maintain the Presence of Units and Members of the United States Armed Forces on the Ground in Libya, and for Other Purposes.” After approving Resolution 292, the House defeated (148–265) a second resolution that insisted upon withdrawal of troops (H. Con. Res. 51). 136. U.S. Department of State and Department of Defense, United States Activities in Libya, June 15, 2011, http://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2011/06/16/us/politics /20110616_POWERS_DOC.html. 137. The final report was published in January 2012. UN Human Rights Council, Report of the International Commission of Inquiry to Investigate All Alleged Violations of International Human Rights Law in the Libyan Arab Jamahiriya, UN Doc. A/HRC/17/44, Jan. 12, 2012, para. 4. 138. Ibid., para. 205. 139. Ibid., paras. 202, 204–8. 140. Ibid., para. 202. 141. Moreno-Ocampo, quoted in Ed Pilkington, Xan Rice, Chris Stephen, and Richard Norton-Taylor, “Gaddafi Faces New ICC Charges for Using Rape as Weapon in Conflict,” The Guardian, June 8, 2011, http://www.theguardian.com/world/2011/ jun/08/gaddafi-forces-libya-britain-nato. 142. “Libya Rape Claims ‘Hysteria’ - Investigator,” Herald Sun, June 10, 2011, http:// www.heraldsun.com.au/news/news-story/d77dd324155a3a7361f8401a3506bb23. 143. Rovera, quoted in Karen Leigh, “Rape in Libya: The Crime That Dare Not Speak Its Name,” Time, June 9, 2011, http://www.time.com/time/world/article/0,8599,2076775,00.html. 196 Notes to Chapter Two Liesl Gerntholtz, executive director of the Women’s Rights Division of Human Rights Watch, also stated in 2011 that the investigation conducted by Human Rights Watch had “not been able to find evidence” of mass rape. Patrick Cockburn, “Amnesty Questions Claim That Gaddafi Ordered Rape as Weapon of War,” The Independent, June 23, 2011, http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/africa/amnesty-questions -claim-that-gaddafi-ordered-rape-as-weapon-of-war-2302037.html. 144. Wallström, quoted in Stephanie Nebehay, “Rape Used as Weapon of War in Libya and Elsewhere: U.N.,” Reuters, June 10, 2011, http://www.reuters.com/article/us-un -rape-idUSTRE75945020110610. 145. Ibid. 146. Secretary of State Hillary Clinton, “Sexual Violence in Libya, the Middle East and North Africa,” press statement, Washington, DC, June 16, 2011, https://2009–2017 .state.gov/secretary/20092013clinton/rm/2011/06/166369.htm. 147. Ibid. 148. Jennifer Steinhauer, “House Spurns Obama on Libya, but Does Not Cut Funds,” New York Times, June 24, 2011, A1. Steinhauer reports that the resolution authorizing the intervention was defeated 295–123; the resolution preventing the financing of U.S. military operations was defeated 238–180. Ibid. 149. Wueger, “Women under Siege.” 150. UN Human Rights Council, Report of the International Commission of Inquiry on Libya (advance unedited version), Mar. 2, 2012, Annex I (full report), para. 518, available at https://reliefweb.int/sites/reliefweb.int/files/resources/A_HRC_19_68_en%20_1 _.pdf [hereinafter Full Report of Commission of Inquiry]. 151. Ibid., paras. 70, 536. Human Rights Watch stated that although “the full extent of sexual violence during the conflict remains unknown, due in part to the stigma surrounding rape in Libya and the dangers that survivors may face when they make crimes public,” it “could not confirm claims of mass or systematic rape by Gaddafi forces.” Human Rights Watch, “Libya: Transitional Government Should Support Victims,” Sept. 19, 2011, https://www.hrw.org/news/2011/09/19/libya-transitional-government -should-support-victims. 152. Full Report of Commission of Inquiry, para. 496. 153. Ibid., para. 535. 154. Leigh, “Rape in Libya,” quoting Sidney Kwiram. 155. Full Report of Commission of Inquiry, para. 522. 156. Wueger, “Women under Siege.” 157. Moreno-Ocampo, “Statement to the United Nations Security Council on the Situation in Libya, Pursuant to UNSCR 1970 (2011),” para. 14, available at http://www.iccnow .org/documents/StatementICCProsecutorLibyaReporttoUNSC021113.pdf. 158. International Justice Desk, “ICC Wants to Tackle Taboo Topic of Rape in Libya,” Apr. 23, 2012, http://www.rnw.nl/international-justice/article/icc-wants-tackle-taboo -topic-rape-libya. 159. Ibid. 160. Ibid. Notes to Chapters Two and Three 197 161. As of October 2019, the ICC has yet to secure custody of any individuals involved in the Libyan situation. ICC, “Situation in Libya,” https://www.icc-cpi.int/libya. 162. MacKinnon, “Women’s September 11th,” 273. 163. Ibid., 276. 164. Ibid. 165. Ibid. That said, she also noted that military intervention to protect women would require that “protectionism, well understood by women around the world, would have to be confronted” and that “resort to arms inflicts disproportionate casualties on women and children.” In response to the latter, she countered that “so does the present peace.” Ibid., 278. 166. See ibid., 273. If MacKinnon might have overstated then the extent to which the “international community” accepted terrorism as a justification for use of force, she might have understated the frequency with which humanitarian intervention has been used, at least ostensibly, to “protect” women. Gayatri Spivak and others have shown how colonialism was often defended as an attempt to save “brown women from brown men.” Spivak, “Can the Subaltern Speak?” Deborah Weissman reminds us that the United States has long justified military intervention—in Cuba, the Philippines, Hawaii—in large part to “protect” women. Weissman, “The Human Rights Dilemma,” 268–70. 167. Gourevitch, We Wish to Inform You That Tomorrow We Will Be Killed with Our Families, 42, referencing a letter sent by seven Tutsi pastors to a Hutu pastor seeking intervention on their behalf. 168. Cmiel, “The Emergence of Human Rights Politics in the United States,” 1250. Chapter Three 1. Bassiouni, foreword to Hazan, Justice in a Time of War, xii. See also Hazan, Justice in a Time of War, 16–19. 2. UN Security Council, Resolution 780, para. 2. 3. UN Secretary-General, Letter Dated 9 February 1993 from the Secretary-General Addressed to the President of the Security Council, Annex: Interim Report of the Commission of Experts Established Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 780 (1992), UN Doc. S/25274, paras. 55–57 [hereinafter Interim Report]. The report also noted, in the following section, that it would investigate allegations of “widespread and systematic rape and other forms of sexual violence.” Ibid., para. 58. For discussion of the significance of labeling the conflict “ethnic cleansing” as opposed to “genocide,” see Chapter Two, pp. 52–54. 4. Ibid., para. 56. The final report arguably went further, saying that a court would likely find that acts during one part of the conflict constituted genocide. UN SecretaryGeneral, Letter Dated 24 May 1994 from the Secretary-General to the President of the Security Council, Annex: Final Report of the Commission of Experts Established Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 780 (1992), UN Doc. S/1994/674, para. 182. 5. Interim Report, para. 74. A subsequent resolution in February 1993 decided to establish the tribunal and called on the UN Secretary-General to propose details for it within sixty days. UN Security Council, Resolution 808. 198 Notes to Chapter Three 6. UN Security Council, Resolution 827. As I note in Chapter Two, Chapter VII of the UN Charter provides for economic and other sanctions as well as the use of force to “maintain or restore international peace and security.” It does not mention a court or tribunal. This use of Chapter VII to establish the ICTY was unsuccessfully challenged by the first accused to be tried by the tribunal. Prosecutor v. Tadić, Case No. IT-94-1, Decision on the Defense Motion on Jurisdiction (ICTY Trial Chamber, Aug. 10, 1995). 7. UN Security Council, Resolution 827, para. 2. 8. Ibid., preambular para. 3. 9. Barkan, “As Old as War Itself,” 62. 10. See Chapter One, Section IV, for discussion of this trend, including growing support for a permanent international criminal court. Some human rights groups had already called for a criminal response. Helsinki Watch (by then a division of Human Rights Watch), for example, had been urging the United States to push for a tribunal for the former Yugoslavia since at least August 1992, while also advocating for a stronger regime of sanctions. Though Helsinki Watch stopped short of making a recommendation on the use of military force—stating that the question “[is] not our province”—it was unequivocal in its support for “a tribunal to investigate, prosecute, adjudicate and punish war crimes.” Helsinki Watch, War Crimes in Bosnia-Hercegovina, 190. 11. Meron, “Rape as a Crime under International Humanitarian Law,” 425. 12. Ibid., 428. 13. As a part of the completion strategy for both tribunals, the International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals (MICT) has assumed the remaining duties of the ICTY and the ICTR, including the last few trials and appeals. MICT, “About,” http://www .irmct.org/en/about. 14. For but a few articulations of this rationale, see Kritz, “Coming to Terms with Atrocities,” 128; Meron, “Answering for War Crimes,” 2–3, 6. See also Koskenniemi, “Between Impunity and Show Trials,” 13, discussing an ICTY prosecutor’s claim that, as Koskenniemi put it, “The (Serb) nation was not on trial, only an individual was.” 15. See Milanovic, “The Impact of the ICTY on the Former Yugoslavia,” using survey evidence to demonstrate that Serbs, Croats, and Bosnian Muslims all believe that the ICTY is biased against their ethnicity. 16. See Chapter One, pp. 44–45, for discussion of this group and its composition. 17. Statute of the ICTY, art. 5(g). The statute does not mention “widespread or systematic,” but the tribunal read the requirement into it based on its interpretation of customary international law. See, for example, Prosecutor v. Tadić, Case No. IT-94-1-A, Judgement (ICTY Appeals Chamber, July 15, 1999), para. 248 [hereinafter Tadić (Appeals Chamber)]. 18. Statute of the ICTY, arts. 5(a–f), 5(h–i). 19. The crimes against humanity definition can be found in Control Council Law No. 10, which was adopted as a charter for these war crimes trials pursuant to the Moscow Declaration and the London Agreement, two sets of international documents organizing the governance of Germany after World War II and declaring a commitment to prosecute members of the Nazi regime. Control Council Law No. 10: Punishment of Notes to Chapter Three 199 Persons Guilty of War Crimes, Crimes against Peace and against Humanity, 3 Official Gazette Control Council for Germany 50–55, Dec. 20, 1945. 20. Meron specifically refers to Control Council Law No. 10 as the basis for the treatment of rape as a crime against humanity in customary international law. Meron, “Rape as a Crime under International Humanitarian Law,” 426–28. But Ní Aoláin contends that “the lesser status of the Council Laws left unresolved the status of rape as a serious violation of the laws of war in its own right.” Ní Aoláin, “Radical Rules,” 891. 21. As a former president of the ICTY explained, “[The drafters] granted the Tribunal jurisdiction over a set of very broadly defined crimes, the specific content of which was to be found in customary international law.” Fausto Pocar, “Introductory Note to the Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia,” http://legal .un.org/avl/ha/icty/icty.html. 22. See, for example, Charlesworth and Chinkin, The Boundaries of International Law, 334, expressing concern that the absence of rape in the list of war crimes might create “the assumption that ‘lesser’ rapes may still be committed with impunity.” In 2016, two scholars referred to the same absence as a “deplorable gap.” Robinson and MacNeil, “The Tribunals and the Renaissance of International Criminal Law,” 201. 23. Askin, “A Decade of the Development of Gender Crimes in International Courts and Tribunals,” 16; Mertus, “When Adding Women Matters,” 1316; Robinson and MacNeil, “The Tribunals and the Renaissance of International Criminal Law,” 201–2. Recall from the Introduction that rape had long been treated by many as a war crime. 24. Copelon, “Gender Crimes as War Crimes,” 229. 25. Although “outrages upon personal dignity” and “humiliating and degrading treatment” are absent from the statute, torture was listed as a grave breach. Especially early on, charges of rape and sexual violence were in fact brought as grave breaches under the statute—as “torture or inhuman treatment” or as “wilfully causing great suffering or serious injury to body or health.” Statute of the ICTY, arts. 2(b), 2(c). However, because the statutory provision on grave breaches arguably applied only to international conflicts, and because of disagreement about whether the conflict or certain aspects of it were international, it did not clearly apply in all cases. 26. See Prosecutor v. Tadić, Case No. IT-94-1-AR72, Decision on the Defense Motion for Interlocutory Appeal on Jurisdiction (ICTY Appeals Chamber, Oct. 2, 1995), para. 134, concluding that “customary international law imposes criminal liability for serious violations of common Article 3.” Also see Prosecutor v. Mucić et al., Case No. IT-96-21-T (ICTY Trial Chamber, Nov. 16, 1998), para. 452 [hereinafter Čelebići (Trial Chamber)], stating that “there can be no doubt that torture is prohibited by both conventional and customary international law.” For one critique of Tadić, for “eroding the distinction between international and internal armed conflict” without providing convincing evidence of the state practice required for customary international law, see Anghie and Chimni, “Third World Approaches to International Law,” 93. 27. Prosecutor v. Kunarac et al., Case No. IT-96-23-T & IT-96-23/1-T (ICTY Trial Chamber, Feb. 22, 2001), paras. 406–8 [hereinafter Kunarac (Trial Chamber)]. 28. Statute of the ICTY, art. 4, paras. 2(b), 2(c). 200 Notes to Chapter Three 29. At least one decision did theorize the possibility, despite failing to convict on those grounds. In a procedural ruling in Karadžić, the Appeals Chamber referred to rape as a “quintessential” example of an underlying act of genocide. Prosecutor v. Karadžić, Case No. IT-95-5/18-AR98bis.1, Judgement (ICTY Appeals Chamber, July 11, 2013), para. 33. 30. Franke, “Putting Sex to Work,” 1174. Franke observes that the OTP initially charged sexual violence against women as rape, but sexual violence against men as “other inhumane acts.” 31. Statute of the ICTY, arts. 5(f), (c), (i), and (h), respectively. 32. Goldstone, “The United Nations War Crimes Tribunals,” 231. 33. Briand and Swigart, “Interview with Richard J. Goldstone,” 17. 34. Goldstone, “Prosecuting Rape as a War Crime,” 280. 35. Ní Aoláin, “Radical Rules.” 36. Ibid., 892. 37. Briand and Swigart, “Interview with Gabrielle Kirk McDonald,” 8–9. 38. ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, Rule 96. For a history of the rule, see Briand and Swigart, “Interview with Gabrielle Kirk McDonald,” 9–10. 39. ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, Rule 34(A)(ii). 40. Ibid., Rule 34(B). This provision, though viewed as a success, fell short of the NGO call for staff who attend to sexual violence victims to be primarily women. Ní Aoláin, “Radical Rules,” 894. 41. Of these 93 individuals, 6 were transferred to national courts. These percentages are based on records of indictment and case outcomes found in Vigneswaran, “Annex B: Charges and Outcomes in ICTY Cases Involving Sexual Violence.” The conviction numbers include any individual who received a sentence, whether through a conviction or a guilty plea during trial or on appeal, unless the conviction was overturned on appeal. Partly because the annex includes the cases that were transferred as well as all cases in which there was evidence at trial of sexual violence, whether or not an accused was indicted for it, the numbers differ from the ICTY’s own numbers. See Jarvis, “Overview,” 4, explaining that the annex includes those who “have faced charges relating to sexual violence crimes.” According to the ICTY, 78 individuals were charged, of whom 32 (or 41 percent) were convicted. ICTY, “Crimes of Sexual Violence: In Numbers,” http://www .icty.org/en/features/crimes-sexual-violence/in-numbers. 42. The three cases with rape convictions were not the first to include charges involving rape or sexual violence. In fact, Tadić, the first case tried by the tribunal, and its first conviction not involving a guilty plea, initially included charges of rape. Prosecutor v. Tadić, Case No. IT-94-1-T, Indictment (Amended) (ICTY Office of the Prosecutor, Dec. 14, 1995), paras. 4–6. The rape charges were eventually dropped, but Tadić was convicted of cruel treatment (a war crime), inhumane acts (crimes against humanity), and inhuman treatment and wilfully causing great suffering (grave breaches) for ordering one detainee to bite off the testicles of another. Prosecutor v. Tadić, Case No. IT-94-1-T, Opinion and Judgment (ICTY Trial Chamber, May 7, 1997), paras. 722–30 [hereinafter Tadić (Trial Chamber)]. Over time, Tadić began to Notes to Chapter Three 201 be referred to as a sexual violence case. The ICTY website, for example, lists it among the “landmark” cases on sexual violence, under the heading “Duško Tadić: First-Ever Trial for Sexual Violence against Men.” ICTY, “Landmark Cases,” http://www.icty.org /en/features/crimes-sexual-violence/landmark-cases. 43. Three men—two Muslims (Hazim Delić and Zejnil Delalić) and one Croat (Zdravko Mucić)—were tried for crimes of rape and other forms of sexual violence, but one of the Muslims, Delalić, was acquitted. 44. Two other Bosnian Muslims were charged with war crimes based on acts of sexual violence, but one died shortly after the charges were brought and the other was acquitted of sexual violence charges. Prosecutor v. Hadžihasanović et al., Case No. IT01-47, Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Mar. 15, 2006). 45. Prosecutor v. Furundžija, Case No. IT-95-17/1-T (ICTY Trial Chamber, Dec. 10, 1998), paras. 264–75 [hereinafter Furundžija (Trial Chamber)]. 46. Kunarac (Trial Chamber), paras. 406–8. 47. Ibid., paras. 883–86. 48. Ibid., paras. 728–29, 742, 745, 749–51, 883–86. All three defendants were also found guilty of a variety of war crimes, including rape (ibid., paras. 883–89). Kovač was found guilty of the war crime of outrages upon personal dignity, for forcing a girl and a young woman to dance naked on a table while he watched (ibid., paras. 9, 772–74, 782). All convictions were upheld on appeal. Prosecutor v. Kunarac, Case No. IT-96-23 & IT-96-23/1-A, Judgement (ICTY Appeals Chamber, Jun. 12, 2002), 125–27 [hereinafter Kunarac (Appeals Chamber)]. 49. Askin, “Prosecuting Wartime Rape and Other Gender-Related Crimes under International Law,” 340. 50. Oosterveld, “Sexual Slavery and the International Criminal Court,” 647. For more on the history of the Rome Statute’s treatment of sexual slavery, particularly in light of early feminist debates over the term, see Chapter One, p. 47. 51. Askin, “Prosecuting Wartime Rape and Other Gender-Related Crimes under International Law,” 340. 52. I have detailed the connection among a variety of the genocidal-rape arguments and the ICTY’s decision in Kunarac in Engle, “Feminism and Its (Dis)contents,” 798–803. 53. Rome Statute, arts. 7(1)(g), 8(2)(b)(xxii), 8(2)(e)(vi). Although, as we see throughout the book, feminists achieved many successes in terms of the ICC’s statute and rules, particularly with regard to sexual violence, some feminists have criticized the court’s operations for failing to follow through on those achievements. As Louise Chappell puts it in her introduction to a book on the topic, “The ICC’s implementation record in regard to gender justice has been partial and inconsistent.” Chappell, The Politics of Gender Justice at the International Criminal Court, 2. 54. Nearly 15.7 percent were brought against Croats, with 2.4 percent brought against Bosnian Muslims and 7.2 percent against Kosovars. These numbers are calculated based on the record of indictments in Vigneswaran, “Annex B: Charges and Outcomes in ICTY Cases Involving Sexual Violence,” but exclude those cases for which 202 Notes to Chapter Three Vigneswaran notes that “there was no explicit reference to sexual violence in the Indictment.” This pattern is roughly consistent with the distribution of indictments at the tribunal more generally, where 67.7 percent of those indicted were Serb, 20.5 percent Croat, 4.3 percent Bosnian Muslim, and 7.5 percent Kosovar. Ford, “Fairness and Politics at the ICTY,” 68–69. 55. Indeed, two of the earliest indictments of the tribunal, brought in 1995 against Radovan Karadžić and Ratko Mladić, included such charges. Prosecutor v. Karadžić and Mladić, Case No. IT-95-5-I, Initial Indictment, “Bosnia and Herzegovina” (ICTY Office of the Prosecutor, July 24, 1995), para. 19. Bosnian Muslim plaintiffs also brought civil claims in the United States against Karadžić for rape as genocide under the U.S. Alien Tort Claims Act and won default judgments. Kadic v. Karadžić, 70 F.3d 232, 242 (2d Cir. 1995). 56. Prosecutor v. Prlić, Case No. IT-04-74-T, Second Amended Indictment (ICTY Office of the Prosecutor, June 11, 2008). 57. Statute of the ICTY, art. 5(h). 58. The Tadić indictment, which had come much earlier, also included a charge of persecution that included sexual assaults. Tadić was eventually convicted of persecution, but because the prosecutor presented insufficient evidence of sexual assault, the conviction was not on the basis of the sexual assault. Tadić (Trial Chamber), paras. 38, 40, 427, 714–18. 59. Under the test set forth in Čelebići, it was permissible to enter cumulative convictions under different statutory provisions only if “each statutory provision involved has a materially distinct element not contained in the other. An element is materially distinct from another if it requires proof of a fact not required by the other.” Prosecutor v. Mucić et al., Case No. IT-96-21-A (ICTY Appeals Chamber, Feb. 20, 2001), para. 412. The tribunal also found, however, that convictions for acts charged as both crimes against humanity and war crimes were permissible. Prosecutor v. Kvočka et al., Case No. IT-98-30/1, Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Nov. 2, 2001), para. 219 [hereinafter Kvočka (Trial Chamber)]. 60. Prosecutor v. Kupreškić, Case No. IT-95-16-T, Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Jan. 14, 2000), para. 636. The chamber further explained that persecution and genocide are both “crimes perpetrated against persons that belong to a particular group and who are targeted because of such belonging.” 61. Although findings of discriminatory intent were instrumental in convictions of rape as a crime against humanity, the tribunal decided early on that while “crimes against humanity as a matter of fact usually are committed on discriminatory grounds,” the intent to discriminate on racial, religious, or political grounds is required only for persecution. Tadić (Appeals Chamber), paras. 297, 305. 62. Prosecutor v. Brđanin, Case No. IT-99-36-T, Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Sept. 1, 2004), para. 523 [hereinafter Brđanin (Trial Chamber)]. The Trial Chamber made this and a similar finding that rapes were “aimed at discriminating against the women because they were Muslim” part of its consideration of torture charges, and then referred back to them when deciding that the rapes constituted persecution. Ibid., paras. 518, 1010. Notes to Chapter Three 203 63. Ibid., paras. 996–97. 64. Ibid., paras. 1011, 1013. 65. Ibid., para. 1011. 66. Ibid. 67. Baig et al., “Contextualizing Sexual Violence,” 200. 68. Ibid., 201. 69. International Women’s Human Rights Clinic of CUNY Law School, “Gender Justice and the Constitution of the War Crimes Tribunal Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 808,” Appendix B in Green et al., “Affecting the Rules for the Prosecution of Rape and Other Gender-Based Violence,” 236–37. See also Green et al., “Affecting the Rules for the Prosecution of Rape and Other Gender-Based Violence,” 189, citing Copelon, “Surfacing Gender.” 70. Rome Statute, art. 7(1)(h) (emphasis added). That success was limited, however, by one of the few battles feminists lost; the statute defines gender narrowly, as meaning “the two sexes, male and female, within the context of society.” Rome Statute, art. 7(3). On the importance of the addition of gender to this list, see Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 108–9. Halley notes that this definition of gender is “the only statutory fly in the ointment” for the feminists’ success in adding gender to the bases of persecution. Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 109. 71. Kunarac (Appeals Chamber), para. 142. 72. Ibid., paras. 150–51. The Trial Chamber in Čelebići had arguably made a similar finding, noting that “it is difficult to envisage circumstances in which rape, by, or at the instigation of a public official, or with the consent or acquiescence of an official, could be considered as occurring for a purpose that does not, in some way, involve punishment, coercion, discrimination or intimidation. . . . This is inherent in situations of armed conflict.” Čelebići (Trial Chamber), para. 495. 73. Brđanin (Trial Chamber), para. 485. 74. Kvočka (Trial Chamber), para. 561. See also Prosecutor v. Simić, Tadić, and Zarić, Case No. IT-95-9/2-T, Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Oct. 17, 2003), para 772. 75. Prosecutor v. Stakić, Case No. IT-97-24-T, Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Jul. 31, 2003), para. 803 [hereinafter Stakić (Trial Chamber)]. The Brđanin Trial Chamber agreed with this statement. Brđanin (Trial Chamber), para. 1009. In Stakić, the Trial Chamber used the statement in part to explain why a victim could not have been expected to be a “calm and detached witness.” Stakić (Trial Chamber), para. 804. 76. UN Commission on Human Rights, Report on the Situation of Human Rights in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia Submitted by Tadeusz Mazowiecki: Special Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1993/50, Feb. 10, 1993, para. 85. 77. See Additional Protocol II, Part II, art. 4(e). 78. Furundžija (Trial Chamber), paras. 272, 279. The ICTY also handed down convictions for rape and sexual violence as outrages upon personal dignity as a war crime in Kunarac. Kunarac (Trial Chamber), para. 773. For discussion of outrages upon personal 204 Notes to Chapter Three dignity, which were generally used to charge sexual violence other than rape, see de Brouwer, Supranational Criminal Prosecution of Sexual Violence, 213–14. According to Anne-Marie de Brouwer, these cases make “clear that such conduct as rape, including forced fellatio, threats of sexual mutilation, forced public nudity and sexual exploitation, in particular the sale of women for purposes of sex, are all examples of conduct that amounts to ‘outrages upon personal dignity.’” Ibid., 214. 79. Prosecutor v. Češić, Case No. IT-95-10/1-S, Sentencing Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Mar. 11, 2004), paras. 14, 52. 80. Ibid., para. 53. 81. Ibid. 82. Ibid., paras. 35, 52, 53. 83. Čelebići (Trial Chamber), para. 486, citing Case 10.970, Inter-American Commission on Human Rights 186 (1996). 84. The tribunal later emphasized that psychological pain can constitute torture and noted that this suffering may be “exacerbated by social and cultural conditions,” in a seeming reference back to the Inter-American Commission decision. See ibid., paras. 494–95. 85. Prosecutor v. Dragan Nikolić, Case No. IT-94-2-S, Sentencing Judgment, Annex: Summary (ICTY Trial Chamber, Dec. 18, 2003), pg. X, para. 54. 86. Prosecutor v. Dragan Nikolić, Case No. IT-94-2-S, Sentencing Judgment (ICTY Trial Chamber, Dec. 18, 2003), para. 203. 87. Ginn, “Ensuring the Effective Prosecution of Sexually Violent Crimes in the Bosnian War Crimes Chamber,” 580–81. 88. Henry, “Witness to Rape,” 121. Both Henry and Ginn (see previous note) rely on a study by Wendy Lobwein showing that 18 percent of the witnesses who testified before the ICTY between 1996 and 2006 were women. Ginn, “Applying Lessons from the ICTY,” 579; Henry, “Witness to Rape,” 120. The data in that study, however, do not distinguish women testifying about sexual violence charges from women testifying about other crimes. Henry’s and Ginn’s analyses thus miss that some of these women testified about other crimes or as expert witnesses. See Lobwein, “Experiences of the Victims and Witnesses Section at the I.C.T.Y.,” 199. 89. Mezey, “Rape in War,” 585. 90. See generally ibid. 91. Ibid. 92. It is estimated that Serbian forces killed seven thousand men in the massacre. David Rohde, “In Bosnia, World Leaders Apologize for Massacre,” New York Times, July 12, 2005, A6. 93. Ní Aoláin, “Sex-Based Violence and the Holocaust,” 45. 94. Viseur Sellers, “Individual(s’) Liability for Collective Sexual Violence,” 160. For discussion of the original version and early amendment history of Rule 96, see Viseur Sellers and Okuizumi, “Intentional Prosecution of Sexual Assaults,” 52–53. 95. The second version added a clause (retained in the final version) describing criteria for admission of evidence of consent. See ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, Rule 96 (iii). Notes to Chapter Three 205 96. Kunarac (Appeals Chamber), para. 132. At one point, the Appeals Chamber analogized the situation of Bosnian Muslim women to that of prison inmates, favorably referencing U.S. laws that criminalize all sexual relationships between prison guards and inmates, making consent legally impossible. Ibid., para. 131. For a specific critique of this analogy and for the inference of lack of consent in Kunarac more generally, see Halley et al., “From the International to the Local in Feminist Legal Responses,” 380. 97. Kunarac (Appeals Chamber), paras. 129–33, upholding a similar ruling by the Trial Chamber. 98. Ibid., para. 108 (Kovac’s claim). 99. Ibid., para. 255 (Kunarac’s claim). 100. Ibid., para. 263. 101. Ibid., para. 255. 102. Kunarac (Trial Chamber), paras. 270, 271, 293. The prosecution, defense, and Trial Chamber all recognized that Witness 191, one of the Foča rape victims, married a Serbian soldier during the war. Prosecutor v. Kunarac, Case Nos. IT-96-23-T and IT-96-23/1-T, Transcript (ICTY Trial Chamber, Nov. 22, 2000), 6497 (defense closing argument); ibid., 6277 (Nov. 20, 2000) (prosecution closing argument). Witness 191 explained that this Serbian soldier had rescued her from her rapists and “didn’t see [her] just as a Muslim but as a human being.” Ibid., 6273–74 (Nov. 20, 2000) (prosecution closing argument, quoting Witness 191’s testimony). 103. Kunarac (Appeals Chamber), para. 218. 104. Kvočka (Trial Chamber), para. 327. 105. Ibid. 106. Kunarac (Appeals Chamber), para. 130. 107. Ibid., para. 57. 108. Ibid. 109. Ibid., para. 59. 110. See, for example, Kvočka (Trial Chamber), para. 125; Stakić (Trial Chamber), para. 569; Brđanin (Trial Chamber), para. 123. 111. Largely as a result of feminist advocacy, the ICC Rules of Procedure and Evidence reflect the approach to consent taken by the judgments of the ICTY as well as similar ones by the ICTR. According to Halley, the ICC Elements of Crimes go even further, arguably—and contradictorily—redefining the substantive crime of rape “to include a positive duty to obtain meaningful consent.” Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 119. In Bemba, the ICC continued with the contradiction, both by stating that “lack of consent is not a legal element of the crime of rape” and by requiring the prosecution to prove “force, threat of force, or coercive environment.” Prosecutor v. Bemba, Case No. ICC01/05-01/08-3343, Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute (ICC Trial Chamber, Mar. 21, 2016), paras. 105–6. Although Bemba’s conviction was ultimately reversed, neither the appeals judgment nor any of the separate or dissenting opinions challenged the treatment of consent in the case. 112. In describing a similar view by world leaders, to which she attributed their reluctance to intervene in the conflict, Seada Vranić explains, “They resorted to the fiction 206 Notes to Chapter Three of a civil war, reviving the old myth of the atavistic need of the people of Bosnia to ritually engage, over time, in mutual bloodlettings. But if they ignored the historical facts, it is strange indeed that they ignored a very recent fact—ethnically mixed marriages constitute almost a third of all marriages in Bosnia. That this would be true in an ‘ambience of centuries of ethnic hatred’ did not tell them anything.” Vranić, introduction to Breaking the Wall of Silence, 25. See also Sells, The Bridge Betrayed, 11. 113. Bringa, Being Muslim the Bosnian Way, 151, wrote shortly after the war that although it was difficult to document, “it has been suggested that 27 percent of all marriages in Bosnia-Herzegovina before the war were between people of different nacije.” For a nuanced and insightful ethnographic account of shared festivities in a Bosnian pastoral community before and after the war, see HadžiMuhamedović, Waiting for Elijah. 114. Although nacija and nacionalnost are loosely translatable as “nation” and “ethnicity,” in the Yugoslav socialist federal nomenclature, the former came to mean membership in a state “constitutive” group. 115. Thanks to Vanja Hamzić for helpful explanations of these terms and their usage. For his discussion of the impact of law—including international law—on “postwar imaginings of Bosnianness,” see Hamzić, “Ethnicity and International Law,” 492–93. For ethnographic accounts, see generally Burić, “Dwelling on the Ruins of Socialist Yugoslavia”; Jansen, Yearnings in the Meantime. 116. For Michael Sells, the prewar understanding of what it is to be Bosnian was to be “any resident of Bosnia-Herzegovina who seeks a nation based not on exclusive religious affiliation but on constitutional rule and respect for differing religions.” Sells, The Bridge Betrayed, 8. For discussion of the long history of Bosnian heterogeneous religious movements and practices—from an autochthonous church deemed “heretical” by both Rome and Constantinople to the cosmologically pluralist Bosnian Sufi circles—that produced an array of complex narratives that predated and often transgressed the nineteenth- and twentieth-century religious delineations, see Fine, The Bosnian Church, 8. 117. In Čelebići, for example, the Trial Chamber noted that “accounts demonstrate that, prior to the build-up to the conflict, these groups had generally friendly relations and extensive interaction, including substantial inter-marriage.” Čelebići (Trial Chamber), para. 99. See also Stakić (Trial Chamber), para. 24; Kvočka (Trial Chamber), para. 9; Tadić (Trial Chamber), para. 64. 118. Tadić (Trial Chamber), para. 64. 119. Kvočka (Trial Chamber), para. 9. 120. Gutman, A Witness to Genocide, 65. 121. Briand and Swigart, “Interview with Patricia Viseur Sellers,” conducted when she was the ICTY’s Legal Advisor for Gender Related Crimes. 122. Robinson, “The Identity Crisis of International Criminal Law,” 941, quoting Douglas Husak, Philosophy of Criminal Law (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1987), 138. 123. MacKinnon, “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights,” 183. 124. Indeed, into the late 1990s, Plavšić received a great deal of support from Notes to Chapters Three and Four 207 NATO countries, including the United States, partly because she was seen as the most likely leader to enforce the terms of the Dayton peace agreement. See Elizabeth Rubin, “The Enemy of Our Enemy,” New York Times, Sept. 14, 1997, https://www.nytimes .com/1997/09/14/magazine/the-enemy-of-our-enemy.html. 125. Plavšić was initially charged with two counts of genocide, five counts of crimes against humanity, and one count of violating the laws of war. Prosecutor v. Plavšić, Case No. IT-00-39 & 40/1-S, Sentencing Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Feb. 27, 2003), para. 5. 126. Viseur Sellers and Nwoye, “Conflict-Related Male Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Jurisprudence,” 213–14, discussing ICTY, Rules of Procedure and Evidence, Rule 96 (ii)(b). The change was made in Rev. 3 (May 3, 1995). 127. Ibid., 214. 128. Campbell, “The Gender of Transitional Justice,” 422, discussing cases as of 2007. For a 2018 discussion of 17 individuals convicted in 14 cases involving what Viseur Sellers and Nwoye label as “conflict-related male sexual violence,” see “ConflictRelated Male Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Jurisprudence.” 129. Oosterveld, “Sexual Violence Directed against Men and Boys in Armed Conflict or Mass Atrocity,” 110–12. 130. MacKinnon, “Oncale v. Sundowner Offshore Services, Inc.,” 19–20. For discussion of the brief, see Halley, Split Decisions, 54–57. In the early 2000s, MacKinnon specifically mentioned men as potential targets of sexual abuse in genocide, if parenthetically, and as part of an argument that foregrounded sexual abuse against women as a group. MacKinnon, “Genocide’s Sexuality,” 226, quoted in p. 188n38. 131. See Chapter Five, pp. 135–36. 132. Foreign and Commonwealth Office, “Don’t believe the thumbnail, this video is the stuff of nightmares,” June 2, 2014, https://youtu.be/1QFUD2Q6D8k. See p. 11. Chapter Four Many thanks to Annelies Lottman for working with me to develop some of the ideas in this chapter in Engle and Lottman, “The Force of Shame,” in Rethinking Rape Law: International and Comparative Perspectives, ed. Clare McGlynn and Vanessa E. Munro, 76–91. London: Routledge-Cavendish, 2010. 1. UN Security Council, Resolution 955, para. 1. 2. Only one country, China, abstained. The Rwandan government also voted against the resolution because of its temporal jurisdiction, its arrangement by which the ICTY and ICTR would share the same Appeals Chamber and Office of the Prosecutor, and its inclusion of violations of common Article 3 and Additional Protocol II of the Geneva Conventions. Cisse, “The International Tribunals for the Former Yugoslavia and Rwanda,” 108. 3. See UN Commission on Human Rights, Report on the Situation of Human Rights in Rwanda, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1995/7, June 28, 1994; UN Commission on Human Rights, Report on the Situation of Human Rights in Rwanda, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1995/70, Nov. 11, 1994; UN Commission on Human Rights, Report on the Situation of Human 208 Notes to Chapter Four Rights in Rwanda, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1995/71, Jan. 17, 1995; UN Security Council, Letter Dated 1 October 1994 from the Secretary-General Addressed to the President of the Security Council Established in Accordance with Security Council Resolution 935 (1994), Annex: Preliminary Report of the Independent Commission of Experts, UN Doc. S/1994/1125, Oct. 4, 1994. Though the preliminary report did recite Article 4 of Additional Protocol II and therefore included the word “rape,” there was no sense that it applied to the issue at hand. Ibid., para. 97. 4. Statute of the ICTR, art. 3(g). 5. This article served to provide an explicit basis for trying crimes committed in a non-international conflict, avoiding some debates that arose in the ICTY about whether the conflict was international and, if not, whether certain crimes were prohibited by the statute. 6. Statute of the ICTR, art. 4(e) (emphasis added). Recall from Chapter Three, pp. 84 and 199n26, that while the drafters of the ICTY statute did not explicitly include common Article 3, the tribunal found that serious violations of the provision constituted customary international law and therefore applied. 7. Although a number of accused were charged with the war crime of outrages upon personal dignity, I do not analyze the treatment of those charges. Rather, my focus in this chapter is the tribunal’s treatment of rape and sexual violence in its landmark finding that such acts can constitute genocide. 8. Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 102–3. See Rome Statute, arts. 8(2)(b)(xxi), 8(2)(b)(xxii). See also Copelon, “Gender Crimes as War Crimes,” 234. The same language as in the ICTR statute appears again in the statute for the 2002 Special Court for Sierra Leone, even though it was drafted after the Rome Statute. Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, art. 3(e). 9. For discussion of ICTY convictions under similar language that was read into the ICTY statute, see Chapter Three, pp. 91–92. 10. As in other chapters, I follow Silvan Tomkins’s classic treatment of shame and humiliation as “one and the same affect.” See Tomkins, “Shame-Humiliation and Contempt-Disgust.” 11. ICTR prosecutors attempted to pursue indictments against commanders of the Rwandan Patriotic Front, but their efforts were thwarted by the Rwandan government. Miller, “Anti-Impunity Politics in Post-Genocide Rwanda,” 166; Judi Rever, “What Remains Hidden in Rwanda: The Role of Tutsi Civilians in Killing Hutus,” Foreign Policy Journal, June 3, 2016, http://www.foreignpolicyjournal.com/2016/06/03/ what-remains-hidden-in-rwanda-the-role-of-tutsi-civilians-in-killing-hutus/. 12. Prosecutor v. Akayesu, Case No. ICTR-96-4-T, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, Sept. 2, 1998), paras. 686–97, 731–34 [hereinafter Akayesu (Trial Chamber)]. 13. As discussed in Chapter Three, however, the ICTY had, more than a year earlier, convicted Duško Tadić of war crimes, grave breaches, and a crime against humanity for sexual violence committed against men. See Chapter Three, p. 200n42. 14. The Trial Chamber found that Akayesu had aided and abetted acts of rape and sexual violence, and that his presence, attitude, and utterances constituted tacit encour- Notes to Chapter Four 209 agement of the sexual violence carried out by those under his command. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), paras. 706–7. The tribunal rejected the argument, however, that Akayesu was liable under the theory of command responsibility, finding that it had not clearly been charged in the indictment. Ibid., para. 691. 15. Viseur Sellers, “‘Tokyoisation’ of the ICTR’s Gender Jurisprudence,” 42. 16. While the ICTY indicted 78 individuals for crimes involving sexual violence out of 161 total defendants, resulting in an indictment rate similar to that of the ICTR, it convicted 32 individuals, or just over 40 percent. In contrast, the ICTR’s conviction rates are around 23 percent. ICTR, “Crimes of Sexual Violence in Numbers,” http://www.icty .org/en/features/crimes-sexual-violence/in-numbers. 17. The numbers in this paragraph can be confirmed by an annex in an ICTR manual on the prosecution of sexual violence. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, Annex B. Thanks to Maddy Dwertman and Kyle Shen for an earlier compilation upon which I also relied. 18. UN Security Council, Letter Dated 9 December 1994 from the SecretaryGeneral Addressed to the President of the Security Council, Annex: Final Report of the Commission of Experts Established Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 935 (1994), UN Doc. S/1994/1405, Dec. 9, 1994, para. 136 [hereinafter Final Report], citing African Rights, Rwanda: Death, Despair and Defiance. 19. African Rights, Rwanda: Death, Despair and Defiance, 410–49. I refer here to the September 1994 edition. A 1,201–page second edition was published in 1995, with relevant discussion on pp. 748–97. While the Final Report of The Commission of Experts mentions African Rights as one of the NGOs it consulted, the group was not mentioned in a similar list in the Preliminary Report. Contrast Final Report, para. 38, with para. 34 of the Preliminary Report (UN Security Council, Letter Dated 1 October 1994 from the Secretary-General Addressed to the President of the Security Council, Annex: Preliminary Report of the Independent Commission of Experts Established in Accordance with Security Council Resolution 935 (1994), UN Doc. S/1994/1125, Oct. 4, 1994). 20. African Rights, Rwanda: Death, Despair and Defiance, 410. 21. Ibid. It went on to state, “Tutsi women who are pregnant on account of rape will bear children who are the off-spring of the men who are responsible for terrible crimes against their community.” It did not explicitly connect either basis to the Genocide Convention. 22. Final Report, paras. 144, 145, quoting UN Security Council, The Situation of Human Rights in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia, Annex: Report on the Situation of Human Rights in the Territory of the Former Yugoslavia Submitted by Mr. Tadeusz Mazowiecki, Special Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights, UN Doc. S/25341, Feb. 26, 1993, para. 85. 23. Ibid., para. 145. 24. Ibid. 25. Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide,” 8–9, also recounts that in early August 1996, the coalition wrote a letter to the chief prosecutor at the time, Richard Goldstone, 210 Notes to Chapter Four encouraging him to investigate and include sexual violence crimes in the Rwandan prosecutions. Human Rights Watch also issued a report in 1996 after Akayesu’s indictment but before his trial that, among other things, documented the failure of prosecutorial staff to investigate rape seriously. Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 54–56. 26. A number of scholars have told the story of how rape became a part of the ICTR’s proceeding in Akayesu. For the most part I follow the account of Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide.” 27. Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide,” 199n10. 28. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 416. 29. Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide,” 200. Van Schaack notes that although many accounts of the trial credit Pillay with bringing the issue to the fore, the transcript shows that while each judge engaged in questioning, the lawyers for the prosecution and defense remained largely silent on the issue. 30. As I noted in Chapter Two, p. 188n34, both Copelon and MacKinnon represented plaintiffs in separate actions against Karadžić, which were eventually combined on appeal. 31. Copelon, “Gender Crimes as War Crimes,” 225. Recently graduated law school students in Canada organized the Working Group on Engendering the Rwanda Tribunal. For the full list of organizations that signed the brief, see Coalition on Women’s Human Rights in Conflict Situations, Amicus Brief Respecting Amendment of the Indictment and Supplementation of the Evidence to Ensure the Prosecution of Rape and Other Sexual Violence within the Competence of the Tribunal, 11–13 [hereinafter Amicus Brief]. 32. Amicus Brief, para. 38, citing UN World Conference on Human Rights, Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, paras. 18, 38. 33. Ibid., paras. 22–40. The brief argued that in addition to rape, other forms of sexual violence, such as genital mutilation and forced public nudity, constituted torture, cruel treatment, and an “outrage to the personal dignity of women,” in violation of the ICTR statute. Ibid., para. 39. 34. Prosecutor v. Akayesu, Case No. ICTR-96-4-I, Amended Indictment (ICTR Office of the Prosecutor, June 17, 1997), Count 15, cited in Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide,” 204–5. 35. Van Schaack references an e-mail message from Patricia Viseur Sellers indicating that amending the genocide counts was unnecessary because the definition of genocide covered the new evidence of sexual violence. Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide,” 205n28. 36. See, for example, Prosecutor v. Ntagerura, Bagambiki, and Imanishimwe, Case No. ICTR-99-46-T, Judgement and Sentence (ICTR Trial Chamber, Feb. 25, 2004); Prosecutor v. Lukić, Case No. IT-93-32/1-PT, Prosecutor’s Motion Seeking Leave to Amend Second Amended Complaint (ICTY Office of the Prosecutor, June 16, 2008); Prosecutor v. Lubanga Dyilo, Case No. ICC-01/04-01/06, Decision on Sentence pursuant to Article 76 of the Statute (ICC Trial Chamber, July 10, 2012), paras. 64–75. 37. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 417. Notes to Chapter Four 211 38. Ibid., section 8 (Verdict). 39. Ibid., para. 691. 40. Ibid., paras. 692–93. The Trial Chamber found Akayesu not guilty of the violations of common Article 3 and Additional Protocol II because it found that the prosecution had failed to establish that Akayesu had the requisite military capacity to connect his acts of sexual violence to armed conflict. Ibid., paras. 641–43. Although the ICTY had required that same nexus for crimes against humanity, the ICTR did not. Compare Statute of the ICTR, art. 3, with Statute of the ICTY, art. 5. Subsequent international and hybrid criminal statutes, including the ICC statute, have followed the ICTR statute on this point. See Rome Statute, art. 7; Law on the Establishment of the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia, art. 5; Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, art. 2; UN Transitional Administration in East Timor, Regulation No. 2000/15, On the Establishment of Panels with Exclusive Jurisdiction over Serious Criminal Offenses, section 5. 41. Prosecutor v. Akayesu, Case No. ICTR-96-4-A, Judgement (ICTR Appeals Chamber, June 1, 2001), Annex B. 42. Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, art. II. The same language is included in the Statute of the ICTR, art. 2(2). 43. Amicus Brief, para. 19. 44. See Chapter Two, pp. 63–64. 45. Amicus Brief, para. 42. 46. Ibid., para. 43, quoting Final Report, para. 145. The brief ’s call for consideration of genocide charges referenced only Article 2(2)(b), (c), and (d), leaving out 2(2)(a). 47. Ibid. The final report had endorsed the analysis of the parallel commission for the former Yugoslavia, which used that language. Final Report, paras. 144–46. 48. Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 2. The report was written on behalf of Human Rights Watch/Africa, the Human Rights Watch Women’s Rights Project, and the Fédération Internationale des ligues de Droit de l’Homme. 49. Ibid., 2–3. 50. Ibid., 3. 51. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 731. 52. Ibid., para. 732. 53. Ibid. 54. See Prosecutor v. Gacumbitsi, Case No. ICTR-2001-64-T, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, June 17, 2004), paras. 222, 228, finding that a Hutu woman was raped as a means of targeting her husband, a Tutsi man, as part of a widespread and systematic attack on Tutsi civilians; Prosecutor v. Muhimana, Case No. ICTR-95-1B-T, Judgement and Sentence (ICTR Trial Chamber, Apr. 28, 2005), paras. 284–92, finding that a Hutu woman was raped because she had been mistaken as Tutsi. For further discussion of this aspect of these cases, see Buss, “The Curious Visibility of Wartime Rape,” 14–15; Buss, “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 150. 55. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 731. 56. Ibid. 212 Notes to Chapter Four 57. Ibid., para. 734. 58. Ibid., para. 731. 59. Ibid., paras. 731–32. 60. Copelon, “Gender Crimes as War Crimes,” 227. 61. Ibid. 62. Ibid., 228. 63. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 507. 64. Copelon, “Gender Crimes as War Crimes,” 228. 65. Charlesworth, “Feminist Methods in International Law,” 387. 66. Ibid. 67. Ibid., 386–87. Charlesworth argued that international humanitarian law, at least before the onset of modern international criminal tribunals, “treats rape and sexual assault as an attack on (the warrior’s) honor or on the sanctity of motherhood,” using as examples Geneva IV (Article 27) and Additional Protocol I. For discussion of critiques of honor-based conceptions of rape by Charlesworth and others, see Halley, “Rape at Rome,” 57–58. 68. For Buss’s (re)reading, see “Learning Our Lessons?,” 68–72. See also Buss, “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 152–55. Bianchi follows Buss’s analysis and extends it to additional cases. 69. While both Bianchi and Buss read the ICTR’s record as documenting rape as widespread and genocidal, Buss also points to the limitations imposed by trial settings and how a focus on individual criminal responsibility elides broader questions of why certain individuals commit rape and why some women are at greater risk or more visible as victims than others. Buss, “Learning Our Lessons?,” 72. 70. See, for example, Prosecutor v. Kayishema and Ruzindana, Case No. ICTR-951-T, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, May 21, 1999), paras. 95, 108. 71. Prosecutor v. Musema, Case No. ICTR-96-13-T, Judgement and Sentence (ICTR Trial Chamber, Jan. 27, 2000), paras. 931–36 [hereinafter Musema (Trial Chamber)]. 72. Ibid., paras. 908, 933. Note that while the Statute of the ICTR, art. 2(2)(b) uses the language of “serious bodily or mental harm” (emphasis added), the Trial Chamber in Musema referred to “serious bodily and mental harm” (emphasis added), except when expressly quoting the statute. 73. Musema (Trial Chamber), para. 933. 74. Ibid. 75. Ibid. Musema was convicted of rape both as a crime against humanity and as genocide. His conviction for genocide was upheld on appeal, but, given new testimony, was no longer based on rape. The Appeals Chamber did not, however, challenge the reasoning of the Trial Chamber on the issue of whether and how rape and sexual violence might constitute genocide. Prosecutor v. Musema, Case No. ICTR-96-13-A, Judgement (ICTR Appeals Chamber, Nov. 16, 2001), paras. 165–71. 76. Prosecutor v. Karemera et al., Case No. ICTR-98–44–T, Judgement and Sentence (ICTR Trial Chamber, Feb. 2, 2012), para. 1667. 77. Ibid. Notes to Chapter Four 213 78. Prosecutor v. Nyiramasuhuko et al., Case No. ICTR-98-42-T, Judgement and Sentence, (ICTR Trial Chamber, June 24, 2011), paras. 5828–36. 79. Ibid., para. 5873. See also Prosecutor v. Niyitgeka, Case No. ICTR-96-14-T, Judgement and Sentence (ICTR Trial Chamber, May 16, 2003), para. 416. 80. Prosecutor v. Gacumbitsi, Case No. ICTR-2001-64-T, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, June 17, 2004), para. 258. 81. Ibid., para. 292. 82. Ibid., para. 222. 83. Buss, “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 155, 159. For her extended discussion of Gacumbitsi, see Buss, “The Curious Visibility of Wartime Rape,” 13–17. 84. Oosterveld, “Atrocity Crimes Litigation Year-in-Review,” 352. See also EboeOsuji, International Law and Sexual Violence in Armed Conflicts. 85. Prosecutor v. Rukundo, Case No. ICTR-2001-70-T, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, Feb. 27, 2009), para. 373. 86. Ibid., para. 386, quoting Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 731. 87. Ibid., citing Prosecutor v. Kamuhanda, Case No. ICTR-95-54A-T, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, Jan. 22, 2004), para. 634. 88. Prosecutor v. Rukundo, Case No. ICTR-2001-70-T, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Park (ICTR Trial Chamber, Feb. 27, 2009), para. 4. 89. Prosecutor v. Rukundo, Case No. 2001-70-A, Judgement (ICTR Appeals Chamber, Oct. 20, 2010), para. 236. 90. Ibid. 91. Davis, “The Politics of Prosecuting Rape as a War Crime,” 1225; Nowrojee, “Your Justice Is Too Slow,” 9. 92. Askin, “Gender Crimes Jurisprudence in the ICTR,” 108; Bianchi, “The Prosecution of Rape and Sexual Violence,” 130–33; Buss, “Learning Our Lessons?,” 64. 93. Buss, “Learning Our Lessons?,” 65–68; Buss, “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 152; Oosterveld, “Gender-Sensitive Justice and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda,” 127–28. 94. Nowrojee, “Your Justice Is Too Slow,” 7–8; Oosterveld, “Gender-Sensitive Justice and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda,” 125–28; Van Schaack, “Engendering Genocide,” 223. 95. Nowrojee, “Your Justice Is Too Slow,” 18–19. 96. See, for example, Bianchi, “The Investigation and Presentation of Evidence relating to Sexual Violence,” paras. 14–17; Bianchi, “The Prosecution of Rape and Sexual Violence,” 131. As I note later, Bianchi was the chair of an internal committee to consider how best to investigate and prosecute sexual violence. 97. See Buss, “Learning Our Lessons?,” 64; “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 152; Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 55–56; Nowrojee, “Your Justice Is Too Slow,” 9–12; Oosterveld, “Gender-Sensitive Justice and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda,” 125–28. 98. See, for example, Bianchi, “The Investigation and Presentation of Evidence relating to Sexual Violence,” paras. 19–20; Bianchi, “The Prosecution of Rape and Sexual 214 Notes to Chapter Four Violence,” 131–32; Buss, “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 152. For some internal analyses from the ICTR, see “The Challenges of Conducting Investigations of International Crimes,” ICTR Newsletter, Nov. 25, 2004, http://wwww.unictr.org/sites/unictr .org/files/news/newsletters/November2004.pdf, 7; Alex Obote-Odora, “Excerpt from ‘Rape and Sexual Violence in International Law: ICTR Contribution,’” ICTR Newsletter, Apr. 2005, http://unictr.irmct.org/sites/unictr.org/files/news/newsletters/april05.pdf, 7–8; “Sexual Assaults One Day Workshop for Investigations Division Takes Place in Kigali,” ICTR Newsletter, May 2005, http://unictr.irmct.org/sites/unictr.org/files/news /newsletters/may05.pdf, 6–7. 99. Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 3. 100. Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 417. 101. Obote-Odora, “Rape and Sexual Violence in International Law,” 140. 102. Goffman, Stigma, 91–104. 103. See, for example, Bianchi, “The Prosecution of Rape and Sexual Violence,” 132, noting in a discussion of investigation methodology that “in Rwandan society, sexual violence crimes carry strong stigmas and there is a powerful taboo against speaking about these crimes.” For another example, see “The Challenges of Conducting Investigations of International Crimes,” ICTR Newsletter, Nov. 25, 2004, http://wwww.unictr .org/sites/unictr.org/files/news/newsletters/November2004.pdf, 7, summarizing comments by Navanethem Pillay on the need for a “particular approach” to sexual violence crimes “since they are surrounded by feelings of shame and stigma on the part of the victims.” 104. Bianchi, “The Investigation and Presentation of Evidence relating to Sexual Violence,” paras. 19–22; Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 16. 105. Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 55. 106. Ibid. 107. Ibid., 17. For another example of feminist reinforcement of the shame of rape, see U.S. Senate, 110th Cong., 2nd sess., Hearing 110–581, Rape as a Weapon of War: Accountability for Sexual Violence in Conflict: Hearing before the Subcommittee on Human Rights and the Law of the Committee on the Judiciary, Apr. 1, 2008, Testimony of Dr. Kelly Dawn Askin, 43–56. Although Askin’s testimony was given in the context of intervention in Darfur, her claims were not limited to that country or region when she stated that “shame and stigma attached to sex crimes causes harm-plus.” Ibid., 53. 108. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, para. 132. 109. Ibid., para. 51. See also ibid., para. 52, paraphrasing and citing Nowrojee, Shattered Lives, 3. 110. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, para. 51. 111. See, for example, ibid., paras. 133–38, 141–45. 112. Ibid., paras. 115, 166. 113. Ibid., paras. 47–48. 114. Ibid., para. 49. 115. See, for example, ibid., paras. 39, 113–15. 116. Ibid., para. 37. See also ibid., paras. 46, 126, 173. Notes to Chapters Four and Five 215 117. Effange-Mbella, “On Support Measures to Victims and Witnesses Summoned to Appear before the Tribunal,” 10. 118. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, para. 180. 119. Bianchi, “The Investigation and Presentation of Evidence relating to Sexual Violence,” para. 24. 120. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, para. 183. In an earlier part, the manual reminds investigators of the same. Ibid., para. 132. 121. Ibid., paras. 183, 189. 122. Ibid., paras. 187–88. 123. See Akayesu (Trial Chamber), para. 688, finding that “coercion may be inherent in certain circumstances, such as armed conflict or the military presence of Interahamwe among refugee Tutsi women at the bureau communal.” For discussion of the ICTY’s treatment of consent, see Chapter Three, pp. 85, 94–97. 124. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, paras. 184–85. 125. Nowrojee, “Making the Invisible War Crime Visible,” 104. 126. ICTR, Prosecution of Sexual Violence, para. 229. 127. Obote-Odora, “Rape and Sexual Violence in International Law,” 157. 128. Roth, “Defending Economic, Social and Cultural Rights,” 67. 129. In Chapter Five, pp. 145, 148–49, we encounter yet another form of naming and shaming with UN Security Council resolutions naming individuals suspected, but not convicted, of sexual violence. 130. Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation, 79. In his self-proclaimed recantation of his call for alternative sentences based on shaming in the U.S. penal system, Dan Kahan provides an excellent summary of the critiques of shaming that have been articulated in a debate he provoked. See Kahan, “What’s Really Wrong with Shaming Sanctions,” 2077–81. Chapter Five 1. The other original NGO Working Group members were International Alert, Amnesty International, Women’s Commission for Refugee Women and Children, and The Hague Appeal for Peace. Cohn, Kinsella, and Gibbings, “Women, Peace and Security,” 140n1 (also listing the International Peace Research Association); Otto, “The Exile of Inclusion,” 12n4. As of 2019, the working group had eighteen members. See “Members,” http://www.womenpeacesecurity.org/about/members/. The group had organized informally in the late 1990s, with the aim of following up on the implementation of provisions on women and armed conflict found in the 1995 Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action, some of which had first been introduced at the 1993 Vienna Conference. Cohn, Kinsella, and Gibbings, “Women, Peace and Security” (interview with Felicity Hill and Maha Muna), 131. For further detail on the background and initial focus of the working group, see Shepherd, “Power and Authority in the Production of United Nations Security Council Resolution 1325,” 387–89. 2. Hill and Muna, interviewed in Cohn, Kinsella, and Gibbings, “Women, Peace and Security,” 132. See also Otto, “The Exile of Inclusion,” 16, citing Sheri Gibbings, 216 Notes to Chapter Five “Governing Women, Governing Security: Governmentality, Gender-Mainstreaming and Women’s Activism at the UN” (master’s thesis, York University, 2004), 52. 3. For one very thorough discussion of Resolution 1325 that situates it in the women’s peace movement and considers the representations of gender in the language of the resolution as well as in its implementation, see Otto, “A Sign of ‘Weakness’?” 4. Dianne Otto discusses the invocation of the resolutions as binding and the inaccuracy and function of the invocation (as well as her resistance to it), in “The Exile of Inclusion,” 11–12, 19, 25–26. 5. For arguments that many aspects of the WPS resolutions and the WPS agenda more broadly either represent or lead to binding legal obligations, see Chinkin and Rees, Commentary on Security Council Resolution 2467, 4–11. 6. UN Action, Strategic Framework, 2011–12, Jan. 2011, http://www.stoprapenow .org/uploads/images/features/pdf/UNASF_2011-12_final.pdf, 3. 7. UN Security Council, Resolution 1888, para. 4. 8. For various accounts, see generally Alonso, Peace as a Women’s Issue; Amos and Parmar, “Challenging Imperial Feminism”; Rupp, Worlds of Women; Wiltsher, Most Dangerous Women. 9. The UN World Conferences on Women were one place where some of that work happened. Recall the discussion in Chapter One, pp. 35, 181n78, of the Peace Tent at the Nairobi Conference in 1985. The Peace Tent statement read in part: “The Peace Tent is the international feminist alternative to men’s conflict and war. It is the place where finding peaceful solutions to conflict, both in personal lives and in the public arena, is the priority. . . . It is important that women whose countries are locked in conflict meet and communicate to expose the patriarchal barriers to peace.” “Peace Tent Statement,” ca. 1985, https://law.utexas.edu/farenthold/document/peace-tent-statement/. Some of the work celebrated or initiated at Nairobi continued through Women for a Meaningful Summit, which began as an ad hoc group of women’s organizations that formed to ensure the representation of women’s voices at the Reagan-Gorbachev Summit Meetings in Reykjavik, Iceland in 1986. For more information, see Frances Tarlton Farenthold, “Women’s Search for Peace,” ca. 1988, https://law.utexas.edu/farenthold/document /speech-womens-search-for-peace/, 11–12. 10. For an account of the founding of the Human Security Network and the development of its agenda, see Small, “Case Study,” 231–35. For discussion of its later decline, see Martin and Owen, “The Second Generation of Human Security,” 211. 11. In 1993, the UN Security Council began to allow non-members to present their views in what are called “Arria Formula Briefings,” first adopted by human rights and humanitarian NGOs in 1997. Paul, “NGOs and the Security Council.” 12. See Table 5.1. At least one of the resolutions was highly correlated with the NGO input described above. See Paul, “NGOs and the Security Council,” discussing the 2000 briefing “Protection of Civilians in Armed Conflict” by Care, Oxfam, and Médecins sans Frontières and the passage of Resolution 1296 on the same topic. 13. UN Security Council, Resolution 1261, para. 10; Resolution 1265, preambular para. 4; Resolution 1296, preambular para. 4 and paras. 9–10; Resolution 1314, para. 13. Notes to Chapter Five 217 14. UN Security Council, Resolution 1261, para. 10; Resolution 1314, para. 13. 15. Scholars and advocates have disagreed, however, about the precise linkage between the Human Security Network and the NGO Working Group. See Cohn, Kinsella, and Gibbings, “Women, Peace and Security,” 135–36. For two competing narratives on the production and situation of 1325, one from the perspective of the NGO Working Group and the other from that of the UN Security Council’s intergovernmental activity on human security, see Shepherd, “Power and Authority in the Production of United Nations Security Council Resolution 1325.” 16. UN Security Council, Resolution 1325, para. 10. 17. Ibid., paras. 4–5. 18. In negotiations around Resolution 1820, China, Russia, Indonesia, and Vietnam suggested that rape might not be a matter for the Security Council, but the resolution nevertheless passed 15–0. Ní Aoláin, Haynes, and Cahn, On the Frontlines, 16. 19. Table 5.1 lists the five resolutions that mentioned sexual violence during those years. All but Resolution 1612 (on children) made explicit reference to women. Resolution 1612 made tacit reference to women and children as subjects of sexual violence by referencing the Secretary-General’s zero-tolerance policy, which relies heavily on such language. UN Security Council, Resolution 1612, para. 11. 20. The work of UN Action is acknowledged in UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, preambular para. 11. 21. Ibid., para. 1. This statement reflected the views articulated by several states during the debate on the resolution. See, for example, those by the UK, stating, “The trauma and injuries caused by sexual violence are designed to cripple communities, trigger revenge attacks, and cause lasting bitterness,” thereby “feed[ing] the fires of conflicts,” and Costa Rica, remarking, “It is indisputable that sexual violence . . . exacerbates armed conflicts and becomes an enormous obstacle to their resolution and to the consolidation of peace.” UN Security Council, 5916th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.5916, June 19, 2008, 14, 23. States also expressed concern that sexual violence by peacekeepers would compromise peacekeeping missions and impede their mandates to assist in the emergence of sustainable peace. See, for example, statements by Liechtenstein and Australia. Ibid., 30 and 34. 22. UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 1. Later resolutions repeated the language of Resolution 1820 on this point as well as on the previous one (that sexual violence exacerbates conflict and impedes peace). UN Security Council, Resolution 1888, para. 1; Resolution 1960, para. 1; Resolution 2106, para. 1; and Resolution 2242, preambular para. 10. In Resolution 1325, in contrast, it is the protection of women and girls and of their “full participation in the peace process” that could make such a contribution. UN Security Council, Resolution 1325, preambular para. 10. 23. UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 15. 24. Achuthan and Black, “United Nations Security Council Resolution 1820,” 7. 25. Ibid. The provision can be found at UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 10. 26. See, for example, Cook, “Security Council Resolution 1820,” 127–28. 218 Notes to Chapter Five 27. UN Security Council, Resolution 1888, paras. 4, 27. 28. Ibid., para. 26(c). 29. UN Security Council, Resolution 1960, paras. 3, 18(c). 30. Resolution 2106 largely resulted from the advocacy of Hague, Jolie, and Bangura, as discussed in the Introduction. 31. Executive Board of the United Nations Entity for Gender Equality and the Empowerment of Women, Strategic Plan, 2011–2013, UN Doc. UNW/2011/9, May 16, 2011, 1–2. UN Women was created in 2010 by the UN General Assembly in Resolution 64/289. The new agency absorbed and unified mandates and functions from four preexisting agencies of the UN concerned with women, so as to enhance “system-wide coherence.” Its first “Strategic Plan” enumerated six main goals, primarily about gender equality and the need to increase women’s leadership, participation, and economic empowerment. Only one goal considers violence against women and girls, though it does not refer to sexual violence, and its focus is on survivor services. Ibid. 32. Liz Ford, “UN Passes New Resolution on Women’s Role in Peace Processes,” The Guardian, Oct. 21, 2013, http://www.theguardian.com/global-development/2013 /oct/21/un-resolution-2122–women-peace-processes. 33. UN Security Council, 7044th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7044, Oct. 18, 2013, 4–5. 34. Ibid., 68. 35. Brazil, for example, said that while sexual violence had been a focus of the council, “it is warranted that we also focus on the importance of furthering the equal rights of women and their right to equal participation in decision-making processes.” Ibid., 27. For additional examples, see the statements of representatives of the Czech Republic, Botswana, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Mexico, and Estonia. Ibid., 32, 35, 40, 48, 72. The president of the council, speaking in his national capacity as representative for Azerbaijan, also suggested the need for the Security Council to attend to a broader range of harms to women in conflict than sexual violence: “While genuine gains have been made . . . to secure justice and deal with conflict-related sexual violence, little has been said of the full range of violations and serious crimes experienced by women.” Ibid., 26. 36. UN Security Council, Resolution 2122, preambular para. 9 and paras. 2(a), 9. 37. UN Security Council, Resolution 2143, para. 9; Resolution 2175, para. 1; and Resolution 2225, preambular paras. 12, 15, and paras. 1, 16. 38. UN Women, Preventing Conflict, Transforming Justice, Securing the Peace; UN Security Council, Resolution 2122, para. 16. 39. UN Women, Preventing Conflict, Transforming Justice, Securing the Peace, 28. Others had reached similar conclusions for some time. See, for example, Physicians for Human Rights, “Nowhere to Turn,” 21, reporting that a majority of women interviewed in Darfuri refugee camps reported health and safety concerns other than sexual violence, particularly their need for more and better-quality food and their profound desire to return home to their farms in Darfur. 40. UN Women, “Statement on the Adoption of Security Council Resolution 2242 on Women, Peace and Security,” Oct. 14, 2015, http://www.unwomen.org/en/news/ stories/2015/10/ed-statement-unsc-resolution-1325. Notes to Chapter Five 219 41. UN Women noted only that the resolution called for more regular briefings by the Special Representative on SVIC. Ibid. For discussion of sexual violence in the resolution, see UN Security Council, Resolution 2242, preambular paras. 10, 14, and paras. 6, 9, 10, 14. 42. UN Security Council, Resolution 2242, preambular para. 14. 43. Ibid., paras. 11, 13. 44. UN Security Council, Resolution 2272, paras. 2, 3, 8. For many years, complaints had been lodged at the UN regarding sexual abuse and exploitation committed by its peacekeepers. Several Security Council resolutions condemned such abuses along the way and expressed support for the UN’s zero-tolerance policy with regard to sexual relations between peacekeepers and civilians in the areas in which they work. For examples of resolutions on children with such language—from 2005 and 2018, respectively—see UN Security Council, Resolution 1612, para. 11; Resolution 2427, para. 35. For similar language in a resolution on civilians, see UN Security Council, Resolution 1674, para. 20. For criticisms of the zero-tolerance policy from feminist perspectives, see, for example, Otto, “Making Sense of Zero Tolerance Policies,” and “The Sexual Tensions of UN Peace Support Operations”; Simić, Regulation of Sexual Conduct in UN Peacekeeping Operations. 45. UN Security Council, Resolution 2331, paras. 8, 9, 11; Resolution 2388, preambular para. 17 and para. 10. 46. See Chapter One, pp. 40–43, 47, and Chapter Three, p. 87, for some of the history of this term’s use. “Sexual slavery” had been referenced one other time, in a 2015 resolution on children, but only in a preambular paragraph. UN Security Council, Resolution 2225, preambular para. 13. 47. UN Security Council, 7847th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7847, Dec. 20, 2016. 48. UN Security Council, Resolution 2331, para. 11. The same paragraph also condemned Boko Haram, Al-Shabaab, and the Lord’s Resistance Army for “any such trafficking in persons and violations and other abuses committed,” without explicitly saying that they had engaged in trafficking. 49. Niamh Reilly also points out that Resolutions 2331 and 2272, which she calls “WPS-related resolutions” do not reference Resolution 1325 at all and that the only WPS resolution they cite is Resolution 2242, and for limited purposes. Reilly, “How Ending Impunity for Conflict-Related Sexual Violence Overwhelmed the UN Women, Peace, and Security Agenda,” 645–46. 50. Anica Heinlein, Jeannette Böhme, and Dr. Ines Kappert, “German Government Treading on Dangerous Ground in the UN Security Council: Planned New Resolution Threatens to Weaken the ‘Women, Peace and Security’ Agenda,” Gunda Werner Institute for Feminism and Gender Democracy, Berlin, Mar. 7, 2019, https://www.gwi-boell .de/sites/default/files/statement_1325_en.pdf, 1. The letter was co-signed by a group of ten German NGOs, including medica mondiale and UN Women. 51. For a summary of the negotiations, see Julian Borger, “US Threatens to Veto UN Resolution on Rape as Weapon of War, Officials Say,” The Guardian, Apr. 22, 2019, https://www.theguardian.com/world/2019/apr/22/us-un-resolution-rape-weapon -of-war-veto; “In Hindsight: Negotiations on Resolution 2467 on Sexual Violence in Con- 220 Notes to Chapter Five flict,” What’s in Blue, May 2, 2019, https://www.whatsinblue.org/2019/05/in-hindsight -negotiations-on-resolution-2467-on-sexual-violence-in-conflict.php. For a critique of the removal of the language on “sexual and reproductive health,” see Fionnuala Ní Aoláin, “Gutting the Substance of a Security Council Resolution on Sexual Violence,” Just Security, Apr. 24, 2019, https://www.justsecurity.org/63750/gutting-the-substance -of-a-security-council-resolution-on-sexual-violence/. 52. Heinlein, Böhme, and Kappert, “German Government Treading on Dangerous Ground in the UN Security Council,” 2. 53. Chinkin and Rees, Commentary on Security Council Resolution 2467, 1. 54. For a discussion of the ways in which the category “women and children” has long been a stand-in for the category “civilian,” see generally Kinsella, The Image before the Weapon. 55. It used “women and girls” just once, in the preamble. 56. See UN Security Council, Resolution 1314, para. 13; Resolution 1379, para. 11; Resolution 1460, para. 10; Resolution 1539, para. 10; and Resolution 1539, para. 1. 57. See, for example, Cook, “Security Council Resolution 1820,” 127–28; Heathcote, “Feminist Politics and the Use of Force,” 40–42; Otto, “The Exile of Inclusion,” 13; Otto, “Power and Danger,” 108. Otto also observes that the resolution perpetuated several myths, including “that sexual violence is ‘the worst’ harm, even worse than death, that can happen to women,” often placing them in a privileged position vis-à-vis other women and men affected by war. Otto, “The Exile of Inclusion,” 24. 58. Scully, “Vulnerable Women,” 117. Sandesh Sivakumaran has expressed a similar critique, though he acknowledges that the resolution description of the “problem of sexual violence” was not limited to females. Still, the exclusionary language of “women and girls” appeared when “specifying concrete, detailed measures of implementation or enforcement.” Sivakumaran, “Lost in Translation,” 266–68. 59. See UN Security Council, Resolution 1888 (on sexual violence), which, with the exception of a preambular paragraph, essentially replaced the “women and girls” language found in Resolutions 1325 and 1820 with “women and children”; Resolution 1894 (on civilians), preambular paras. 9, 17, and paras. 7(b), 21, and 32, all referencing “women and children.” Resolutions 1998 in 2011 and 2068 in 2012, both on children, continued with gender-neutral language, making no reference to boys, girls, or women. Resolution 1882 (on children) was gender neutral with regard to children, but it did not mention women. 60. Sivakumaran quotes one such report: “While women and girls are particular targets and are the majority of the victims of sexual violence, the case-law of the [ICTY] and the Special Court for Sierra Leone (SCSL) also bears testimony to the use of sexual violence against men.” Sivakumaran, “Lost in Translation,” 271, quoting UN SecretaryGeneral, Report of the Secretary-General Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 1820 (2008), UN Doc. S/2009/362, July 15, 2009. For discussion of ICTY prosecutorial strategy on this issue, see Chapter Three, pp. 99–100. 61. UN Security Council, Resolution 1960, preambular paras. 2 and 3. 62. Such responses became part of a growing literature on sexual violence against men in conflict. See, for example, Baaz and Stern, The Complexity of Violence, 43–47; Notes to Chapter Five 221 Grey and Shepherd, “‘Stop Rape Now?’”; Sivakumaran, “Lost in Translation”; Sivakumaran, “Sexual Violence against Men in Armed Conflict”; Solangon and Patel, “Sexual Violence against Men”; UN High Commissioner for Refugees, Working with Men and Boy Survivors; Zalewski et al., Sexual Violence against Men in Global Politics. 63. For example, Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon said, “While women and girls suffer disproportionately from these vicious crimes, men and boys are also targeted.” UN Security Council, 6984th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.6984, June 24, 2013, 3 [hereinafter UN Security Council, 6984th Meeting]. Nonetheless, according to Chloé Lewis’s analysis of the entire debate, only 19 (out of 60) statements referenced (and generally only briefly) men and boys as victims or survivors of sexual violence. “In contrast, and with varying degrees of substance, 325 references were made to female victims/survivors.” Lewis, “Systemic Silencing,” 216. 64. UN Security Council, Resolution 2331, preambular para. 12 and para. 10. The representative for Liechtenstein, also speaking on behalf of Switzerland and Australia, said, “We wish to highlight that men and boys should be guaranteed the same access to reparations and services. Recent studies on sexual violence against men and boys suggest that they also suffer from a non-recognition of sexual violence committed against them as sexual violence. That wrong needs to be corrected.” UN Security Council, 7847th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7847, Dec. 20, 2016, 37. The speakers for several states in the debate identified the victims of sexual violence and trafficking as “men, women and children.” 65. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, para. 32. For but two examples of such activists praising the inclusion of this paragraph, see Z. Pinar Erdem, “Men Can Experience Sexual Violence in War Too,” Pass Blue, May 3, 2019, https://www.passblue .com/2019/05/03/men-can-experience-sexual-violence-in-war-too/; Charu Hogg, “OPINION: U.N. Resolution Recognising Wartime Sexual Violence against Men and Boys Is Historic,” Thomson Reuters Foundation News, May 14, 2019, http://news.trust .org/item/20190514104242-vjkpx/. 66. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, preambular paras. 12, 19, and paras. 16(b), 32. 67. Resolutions 1265 and 1296 on civilians, for example, did not mention sexual violence, but they both addressed “women and children” as particularly vulnerable groups that require special attention. UN Security Council, Resolution 1265, preambular para. 4; Resolution 1296, para. 9. Resolution 1261 on children addressed rape as a form of “gender-based violence,” urging parties to armed conflict to “protect children, in particular girls, from rape and other forms of sexual abuse and gender-based violence.” UN Security Council, Resolution 1261, para. 10. 68. UN Security Council, Resolution 1325, para. 10 (emphasis added). 69. UN Security Council, “Security Council Adopts Text Requesting Detailed Information on Suspected Perpetrators of Sexual Violence during Armed Conflict,” press release, Dec. 16, 2010, https://www.un.org/press/en/2010/sc10122.doc.htm. 70. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on the Implementation of Security Council Resolutions 1820 (2008) and 1888 (2009), UN Doc. S/2010/604, Nov. 222 Notes to Chapter Five 24, 2010, para. 7. The report went on to emphasize that “like other conflict-related violence, sexual violence may also be motivated by ethnic, religious and underlying economic factors.” Ibid. 71. UN Security Council, Resolution 1960, para. 8. 72. UN Action, “Analytical and Conceptual Framing,” summary, Nov. 8, 2011, http://www.stoprapenow.org/uploads/advocacyresources/1321456915.pdf, 1. The complete document is not publicly available. 73. Ibid., 3. The summary further explained that “gender-based violence (GBV), which includes acts that are not sexual in nature, such as physical assault or the denial of economic resources, . . . is an overly-broad category for 1960 reporting purposes.” It also distinguished sexual violence from “harmful traditional practices” (without “specific justification” for equating them), “sexual exploitation and abuse” (which it claimed is dealt with elsewhere), and “survival sex” (“unless the circumstances are coercive and vitiate consent”). Ibid. It appears that the document might have been responding to criticisms from a number of different perspectives, including those regarding the zerotolerance policy on sexual exploitation and abuse. 74. Ibid. For discussion of these lobbying efforts, see Chapter One, pp. 47, 184n135. 75. All but one of the reports since Resolution 1960’s passage in 2010 are titled “Conflict-Related Sexual Violence.” The sole exception, issued in 2013, is titled “Sexual Violence in Conflict.” All reports include discussion of sexual violence against men and boys. The Secretary-General reports can be found on the website of the Office of the Special Representative of the Secretary-General on Sexual Violence in Conflict. “Secretary-General Annual Reports,” https://www.un.org/sexualviolenceinconflict/ digital-library/reports/sg-reports/. 76. WILPF, From Impunity to Accountability, 4. 77. Indeed, the most recent resolution on sexual violence in conflict as of October 2019 contained the most references to the language. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, paras. 15, 16(a), 16(d), 24, 28, 31. It also, for the first time, mentioned discrimination and structural inequalities based on gender as “root causes of sexual violence” that must be addressed. Ibid., preambular para. 12. For other uses of the term “sexual and gender-based violence” in the resolutions, see UN Security Council, Resolution 2106, paras. 9, 14, 16(c); Resolution 2122, preambular para. 9, and para. 9; and Resolution 2242, preambular para. 14 and paras. 6, 14. The term also appeared in human security resolutions outside the WPS agenda; for example, see UN Security Council, Resolution 2427, para. 18. 78. A 2016 report, for example, stated: “In my previous reports, I have underlined the need to address conflict-related sexual violence as part of a continuum of violence that is closely intertwined with broader attacks on gender equality and women’s human rights . . . Ending all forms of gender-based violence, including conflict-related sexual violence, remains a priority.” UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Women and Peace and Security, UN Doc. S/2016/822, Sept. 29, 2016, paras. 22–23. 79. UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, preambular para. 6. 80. Prosecutor v. Akayesu, Case No. ICTR 96-4, Judgement (ICTR Trial Chamber, Sept. 2, 1998), para. 731. This case is discussed in detail in Chapter Four, Section I. Notes to Chapter Five 223 81. See, for example, UN Security Council, Resolution 1888, para. 15; Resolution 2331, preambular para. 11; Resolution 2467, para. 16(c). 82. The video, “Stop Rape Now,” is also available at https://youtu.be/Pn7KFDhzyNU (uploaded June 7, 2008). 83. The Special Representative for SVIC also has a website on the UN domain that includes a page on UN Action. https://www.un.org/sexualviolenceinconflict/about-us/ un-action/. 84. This video is one of two on the website. Victims do not speak in either. Shame is most explicit in the video that I discuss here. For an analysis of the other video, which features Charlize Theron and Nicole Kidman, see Engle, “Celebrity Diplomacy and Global Citizenship.” 85. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 1820 (2008), UN Doc. S/2009/362, July 15, 2009, para. 19. 86. Ibid. 87. UN Security Council, 6453rd Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.6453, Dec. 16, 2010, 3 (statement of Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon). 88. Ibid. 89. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Conflict-Related Sexual Violence, UN Doc. S/2017/249, Apr. 15, 2017, para. 9. 90. Ibid., para. 10. 91. Global Network of Women Peacebuilders, “About GNWP,” https://gnwp.org /about/. 92. Global Network of Women Peacebuilders, “UNSCR 1960 and the Need for Focus on Full Implementation of UNSCR 1325: Open Letter to Member States of the Security Council Re: Res 1960,” Jan. 7, 2011, https://www.peacewomen.org/content/letter -unscr-1960-and-need-focus-full-implementation-unscr-1325-open-letter-member-states. 93. Ibid. 94. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Women and Peace and Security, UN Doc. S/2015/716, Sept. 16, 2015, para. 54. 95. UN Security Council, Resolution 1325, para. 11. For the language in resolutions preceding 1325, see UN Security Council, Resolution 1261, para. 3; Resolution 1265, para. 6; Resolution 1314, para. 2. 96. UN Security Council, Resolution 1325, para. 11. 97. For the title of the debate along with the Secretary-General’s remarks, see UN, “Understanding Extent of Sexual Violence in Conflict Essential for Effectively Protecting Women, Girls, Secretary-General Tells Security Council Debate,” press release, June 24, 2013, https://www.un.org/press/en/2013/sgsm15128.doc.htm. For the debate itself, in which nearly every speaker discussed the need to end impunity, see UN Security Council, 6984th Meeting. 98. UN Security Council, Resolution 2106, para. 3. 99. Ibid., para. 2. 100. UN Security Council, Resolution 2122, para. 12; Resolution 2242, para. 14, Resolution 2467, paras. 14–15. 224 Notes to Chapter Five 101. WILPF Secretary General Madeleine Rees estimates that “nearly 90% of the statements at the debate referenced the need for accountability and justice,” which she treats as a positive sign. “Madeleine Rees on UN Security Council Resolution 2467,” WILPF, Apr. 30, 2019, https://www.wilpf.org/madeleine-rees-on-un-security-council-resolution-2467/. 102. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, para. 14. Other impediments the paragraph lists are statutes of limitations, requirements of victim corroboration, exclusion of victim testimony, and failure to provide for closed hearings. 103. Chinkin and Rees, Commentary on Security Council Resolution 2467, 18. Elsewhere, Rees identified the criminal law language in the resolution as its “most potentially revolutionary element,” claiming that it “is more progressive than I have yet seen.” “Madeleine Rees on UN Security Council Resolution 2467.” 104. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, para. 16. 105. UN Security Council, 8514th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.8514, Apr. 23, 2019, 13 [hereinafter UN Security Council, 8514th Meeting]. 106. Ibid., 10. 107. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, preambular para. 14. See also similar language in UN Security Council, Resolution 2106, preambular para. 4. 108. UN Security Council, 7938th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7938, May 15, 2017, 4 [hereinafter UN Security Council, 7938th Meeting]. 109. UN Security Council, 8234th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.8234, Apr. 16, 2018, 3. See also her similar statement at UN Security Council, 8514th meeting, 5. For the identification and critique of the increased usage of the term “culture of impunity” as a principal aim of human rights advocacy, see generally Engle, “Anti-Impunity and the Turn to Criminal Law in Human Rights.” For a visual representation of the frequency of the term’s usage since the early 1990s, see ibid., 1078. 110. For an examination of data from 1989 to 2015, see Nordås and Nagel, “Continued Failure to End Wartime Sexual Violence.” This report updates the 1989–2009 data discussed in Cohen and Nordås, “Sexual Violence in Armed Conflict.” 111. UN Security Council, 8079th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.8079, Oct. 27, 2017, 13. See also Chinkin and Rees, Commentary on Security Council Resolution 2467, 12, reiterating that “the activity around [conflict-affected sexual violence] has failed to eradicate or even reduce its prevalence.” 112. See, for example, a statement by Special Representative on SVIC Pramila Patten during the debate on Resolution 2467: “Still, after a decade of concerted attention and action, the reality that we must face is that the implementation of resolutions, policies, agreements and commitments remains slow and that criminal accountability for these crimes remains elusive. We have not yet improved the situation on the ground in a sustained or meaningful way. Wars are still being fought on and over the bodies of women and girls.” UN Security Council, 8514th Meeting, 4. 113. Karen McVeigh, “Hague Hails ‘Tremendous Start’ to Sexual Violence Scheme Set Up with Jolie,” The Guardian, Nov. 23, 2018, https://www.theguardian.com/global -development/2018/nov/23/william-hague-hails-tremendous-start-sexual-violence -scheme-angelina-jolie. Notes to Chapter Five 225 114. UN Women, Preventing Conflict, Transforming Justice, Securing the Peace, 73. 115. See UN Security Council, Resolution 1325, para. 11. Identical language can be found in the following children’s resolutions with regard to amnesty for crimes against children more broadly: UN Security Council, Resolution 1314, para. 2; Resolution 1379, para. 9(a). 116. UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 4; Resolution 2106, para. 12; Resolution 2467, para. 30. The feasibility qualifier was also removed in the amnesty provision of a subsequent resolution on children. UN Security Council, Resolution 2143, para. 11. 117. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General Pursuant to Security Council Resolution 1820 (2008), UN Doc. S/2009/362, July 15, 2009, para. 22. 118. UN Secretary-General, Sexual Violence in Conflict: Report of the SecretaryGeneral, UN Doc. S/2013/149, Mar. 14, 2013, paras. 60, 128(f). 119. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Women and Peace and Security, UN Doc. S/2015/716, Sept. 16, 2015, para. 17. 120. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on the Implementation of Security Council Resolutions 1820 (2008) and 1888 (2009), UN Doc. S/2010/604, Nov. 24, 2010, para. 4. 121. Ibid. 122. UN Secretary-General, Sexual Violence in Conflict: Report of the SecretaryGeneral, UN Doc. S/2013/149, Mar. 14, 2013, para. 31. 123. Amnesty International, “New Amnesty Report Exposes Impunity for Conflict-Related Sexual Violence in Colombia,” press release, Oct. 1, 2012, https://www .amnestyusa.org/press-releases/new-amnesty-international-report-exposes-impunity -for-conflict-related-sexual-violence-in-colombia/. 124. See Introduction, p. 33. Language about the relationship between ending impunity and sustainable peace can be found as far back as Resolution 1820, which stressed that “the importance of ending impunity” for acts of sexual violence is intrinsic to the search for a “sustainable peace.” UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 4. That perspective has been reiterated during Security Council debates on the WPS agenda. In a 2017 debate, for example, states argued that fighting impunity through prosecution “contributes to the healing processes necessary for sustainable peace” and “helps us bring about reconciliation.” UN Security Council, 8079th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.8079, Oct. 27, 2017, 16, 73. For discussion of ways in which the “lasting peace” argument has been used in the discussion of amnesties more generally, see Engle, “AntiImpunity and the Turn to Criminal Law in Human Rights,” 1099–102. And for its use outside the amnesty context, see Nouwen, “Justifying Justice,” 339–40. 125. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Conflict-Related Sexual Violence, UN Doc. S/2017/249, Apr. 15, 2017, para. 26. For discussion of some of the debate surrounding impunity and the peace process, see Alviar García and Engle, “The Distributive Politics of Impunity and Anti-Impunity,” 235–37. 126. UN Security Council, Resolution 1960, para. 3. For extensive discussion and critique of this resolution, see Heathcote, “Naming and Shaming.” 226 Notes to Chapter Five 127. UN, “Security Council Reaffirms Commitment to Address Widespread Impact of Armed Conflict on Children, after Hearing over 60 Speakers in Day-Long Debate,” press release, Apr. 29, 2009, https://www.un.org/press/en/2009/sc9646.doc .htm. 128. UN, “Security Council Presidential Statement Condemns Sexual Violence in Conflict, Post-Conflict Situations, Urges Complete, Immediate Cessation of Such Acts,” press release, Feb. 23, 2012, http://www.un.org/press/en/2012/sc10555.doc.htm. 129. UN Security Council, 7938th Meeting, 5. 130. UN Security Council, 6984th Meeting, 4. 131. U.S. Institute of Peace, “Missing Peace Symposium: International Responses to Sexual Violence,” Feb. 14, 2013, available at https://youtu.be/0SL4LpKz470 (panel from 1:45:00 to 3:21:46). Bangura makes the quoted statement from 2:36:25 to 2:36:55. 132. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Conflict-Related Sexual Violence, UN Doc. S/2016/361, Apr. 20, 2016, para. 22. 133. UN Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on Conflict-Related Sexual Violence, UN Doc. S/2018/250, Mar. 23, 2018, para. 19. See also para. 98(g), which calls for support for local journalists and human rights defenders, in addition to traditional and religious leaders, to do the same. 134. UN Security Council, Resolution 2467, para. 19. 135. Ibid., para. 16(c). 136. MacKinnon, “Women’s September 11th,” 269. 137. See Chapter Two, p. 78. 138. MacKinnon, “Women’s September 11th,” 260. 139. UN Security Council, Resolution 2242, para. 11. 140. UN Security Council, 7704th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7704, June 2, 2016, 4. Bangura went on to say that “we must focus on divesting them of resources and degrading their capacity to communicate, travel, trade and do harm.” 141. UN Security Council, 7938th Meeting, 11. 142. See, for example, ibid., 47 (Bangladesh) and 49 (Argentina). 143. See, for example, Margot Wallström, “Statement of Government Policy in the Parliamentary Debate on Foreign Affairs,” Feb. 13, 2019, https://www.government .se/49132e/globalassets/government/dokument/utrikesdepartementet/statement-of -foreign-policy-2019. See also Aggestam and Bergman-Rosamond, “Swedish Feminist Foreign Policy in the Making.” 144. UN News Centre, “Interview with Margot Wallström, Special Representative on Sexual Violence in Conflict,” June 4, 2012, https://web.archive.org /web/20170621031825/http://www.un.org/apps/news/newsmakers.asp?NewsID=55. 145. UN Security Council, Resolution 2106, para. 5. 146. UN Security Council, Letter Dated 18 October 2018 from the Permanent Representative of the Netherlands to the United Nations Addressed to the President of the Security Council, Annex: Concept Note for the Arria-Formula Meeting on the Theme “Moving from a Culture of Impunity to a Culture of Deterrence: The Use of Sanctions in Addressing Sexual Violence in Conflict” to Be Held on 22 October 2018, UN Doc. Notes to Chapter Five 227 S/2018/932 [hereinafter Concept Note for the Arria-Formula Meeting]. For more on the UN’s Arria-Formula Meetings, see note 11 above. 147. Over time, the resolutions have contained an increasing level of commitment to and detail on sanctions. See UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 5; Resolution 1888, para. 10; Resolution 2106, para. 13; Resolution 2242, para. 6; Resolution 2467, paras. 10–12. Resolution 2331, on trafficking, also includes four different paragraphs on sanctions. UN Security Council, Resolution 2331, paras. 4, 12–14. 148. Concept Note for the Arria-Formula Meeting, para. 8. 149. Huvé, The Use of UN Sanctions to Address Conflict-Related Sexual Violence, 1. 150. Heathcote, “Naming and Shaming,” 14. Advocates continue to call for the annexes of credibly suspected parties in the Secretary-General reports to be used in the determination of sanctions. See, for example, Concept Note for the Arria-Formula Meeting, paras. 7, 8; Permanent Representative of the Netherlands to the UN, “Moving from a Culture of Impunity to a Culture of Deterrence: The Use of Sanctions in Addressing Sexual Violence in Conflict,” informal summary, Dec. 19, 2018, https://www .permanentrepresentations.nl/documents/publications/2018/12/19/informal-summary -arria-sexual-violence-in-conflict, para. 9. 151. For discussion of and responses to some of these due process considerations, including legal challenges that have been brought to the European Court of Human Rights, the European Court of Justice, and some national courts, see Permanent Mission of Greece to the UN, UN Sanctions: Humanitarian Aspects and Emerging Challenges, Jan. 19, 2015, http://www.hlr-unsanctions.org/HLR_WG3_report_final.19.1.15.pdf, especially paras. 41–50. 152. Chinkin, “International Human Rights, Criminal Law and the Women, Peace and Security Agenda.” See also London School of Economics Centre for Women, Peace and Security, “Preventing/Countering Violent Extremism and WPS.” 153. Chinkin, “International Human Rights, Criminal Law and the Women, Peace and Security Agenda,” quoting UN Women, Preventing Conflict, Transforming Justice, Securing the Peace, 15. 154. I am grateful to Vasuki Nesiah and Dianne Otto for working with me to identify these continuities. See Engle, Nesiah, and Otto, “Feminist Approaches to International Law.” 155. Heathcote, “Feminist Politics and the Use of Force,” 40–41. She references UN Security Council, Resolution 1820, para. 1; Resolution 1888, para. 1; and Resolution 1960, para. 1. See also Otto, “Contesting Feminism’s Institutional Doubles,” 206. 156. Nesiah, “Feminism as Counter-Terrorism.” 157. See Otto, “Women, Peace, and Security,” 8. Felicity Ruby (formerly Felicity Hill) also points to the invasion of Iraq as an example of the “instrumentalisation” of Resolution 1325 and women’s rights more generally to justify force. Ruby, “Security Council Resolution 1325,” 179. Ruby invites fellow advocates of 1325 “to ask how the Security Council has become the centre of our attention and why are we only talking about women when pre-1325 we also spoke about disarmament and conflict prevention.” Ibid., 178. 228 Notes to Chapter Five and Epilogue 158. Otto, “Power and Danger.” 159. Nesiah, “Feminism as Counter-Terrorism.” 160. Ní Aoláin, “The ‘War on Terror’ and Extremism,” 291. In terms of harm, Ni Aoláin convincingly argues: “The wider legitimacy conferred on the use of multilateral force across a range of fragile states, insecure environments and zones of both highand low-intensity conflict, and the increased status and deference given to maintaining and extending international security regimes by recourse to the rhetorical assertion of expanded terrorist threats, all increase the risk that women will be exposed to greater insecurity.” Ibid., 276. 161. UN Security Council, 7533rd Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7533, Oct. 13, 2015, 9. Epilogue 1. A Woman in Berlin, 61 (diary entry from May 1, 1945). 2. Calling the Ghosts: A Story about Rape, War, and Women, directed by Mandy Jacobson and Karmen Jelincic (New York, NY: Women Make Movies, 1996). 3. Murad, The Last Girl, 162. 4. Buss, “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War,’” 154–55. Buss argues not only that the hyper-attention makes invisible the larger context and causes of the Rwandan conflict, but that it makes invisible individual stories of rape, especially of Hutu women, that do not fit the mold. 5. Berlant, “Thinking about Feeling Historical,” 4. 6. Thanks to Janet Halley for introducing me to this book. For her review essay of the same, see Halley, “Rape in Berlin.” For her analysis of the history of the various publications in English and German and controversies surrounding them, including disagreements over authorship (many claim that the author was journalist Marta Hillers), see ibid., 91–99. 7. That said, A Woman in Berlin has long been embroiled in controversy over its veracity. Ibid. 8. For some other attempts to reread Hemingway’s female characters against the grain of many feminist critiques, see the essays in Broer and Holland, Hemingway and Women. 9. Halley, “Rape in Berlin,” 99. Because I read the diary not for its “truth,” but for the way it expands our imagination, I do not engage with the debate about the diary’s veracity. 10. Lesley Abdela, “Bosnia: Women Are Fighting Back,” Cosmopolitan (U.K.), Sept. 1994, 16. 11. Lines, Milicianas, 61. 12. Ibárruri, They Shall Not Pass, 195. Ibárruri later became secretary-general and then president of the Communist Party of Spain, holding the latter post until her death in 1989. See Paul Hofman, “Dolores Ibarruri, ‘La Pasionaria’ of Spanish Civil War, Dies at 93; An Indomitable Leftist,” New York Times, Obituaries, Nov. 13, 1989, B15; Lazitch and Drachkovitch, Biographical Dictionary of the Comintern, 190–91. For more on her life and career, see Sorel, Dolores Ibarruri. Notes to Epilogue 229 13. Lines, Milicianas, 138. Gerda Taro, the first female photographer to die on the front lines—crushed by a tank in 1937—captured a number of stunning images of militiawomen, many of which can be found in Schaber, Whelan, and Lubben, Gerda Taro. 14. In fact, many have speculated about who might have served as the model for Pilar, with guesses ranging from Ibárruri to Hemingway’s friend Gertrude Stein. See, for example, Comley and Scholes, Hemingway’s Genders, 46; and Waldmeir, “Chapter Numbering and Meaning in For Whom the Bell Tolls.” 15. Lines, Milicianas, 74. 16. Hemingway, For Whom the Bell Tolls, 103–29. In a 1954 letter to art historian Bernard Berenson, Hemingway, writing of “the obligation to invent truer than things can be true,” referred to this scene as one of the “things which I invented completely” and reported his own “complete astonishment that I could have invented as I did.” Hemingway, Selected Letters, 837. 17. Hemingway, For Whom the Bell Tolls, 118–19. 18. Ibid., 119. 19. Ibid., 125. 20. Ibid., 128. 21. Ibid. 22. Ibid., 127, 129. 23. Ibid., 99. 24. Murad, The Last Girl, 152. 25. Ibid., 153. 26. Ibid., 154–55. 27. For background on the two, as well as a critical analysis of judicial and media treatment of them, see Sjoberg and Gentry, Mothers, Monsters, Whores, 145–73. 28. Plavšić was initially charged with two counts of genocide, five counts of crimes against humanity, and one count of violating the laws of war. Prosecutor v. Plavšić, Case No. IT-00-39 & 40/1-S, Sentencing Judgement (ICTY Trial Chamber, Feb. 27, 2003), para. 5. 29. For an insightful article about the case that is centered around this quotation, see Drumbl, “She Makes Me Ashamed to Be a Woman.” 30. African Union, Rwanda: The Preventable Genocide, http://www.peaceau.org/ uploads/report-rowanda-genocide.pdf, para. 16.33. 31. Ibid., citing African Rights, Rwanda, Not So Innocent: When Women Become Killers (London: African Rights, 1995). 32. Ibid., paras. 16.33, 16.34. 33. Brown, “Female Perpetrators of the Rwandan Genocide,” 458. 34. Barbara Ehrenreich, “Feminism’s Assumptions Upended,” Los Angeles Times, May 16, 2004, https://www.latimes.com/archives/la-xpm-2004-may-16-op-ehrenreich16 -story.html. 35. Ibid. 36. Hemingway, For Whom the Bell Tolls, 73. 37. See Chapter One, pp. 48, 184–85n139. 230 Notes to Epilogue 38. Hemingway, For Whom the Bell Tolls, 154. 39. Ibid. 40. Ibid., 155. 41. Ibid. 42. Miriam Ticktin describes the reaction of French nurses working for Médecins Sans Frontières in the Congo Republic, “who found it strange” that “rape victims spoke directly about what happened to them.” As one said, “I doubt women in France would respond positively to those questions under such circumstances.” Ticktin, “The Gendered Human of Humanitarianism,” 260. 43. Hemingway, For Whom the Bell Tolls, 71. 44. Ibid., 350. 45. Ibid. 46. Ibid. 47. Ibid. 48. The diary covers the period from April 20 to June 2, 1945. For context on those dates in terms of the war, see Antony Beevor, introduction to A Woman in Berlin, xiii–xv. 49. A Woman in Berlin, 64. 50. Ibid., 115. 51. Ibid., 116. 52. First published in English in the United States in 1954, the diary was not published in German until five years later—and then by a Swiss publisher. Enzensberger, foreword to A Woman in Berlin, xi. 53. Ibid. 54. A Woman in Berlin, 257–61; Halley, “Rape in Berlin,” 108. 55. A Woman in Berlin, 259. 56. Halley, “Rape in Berlin,” 108. 57. A Woman in Berlin, 116. 58. Unlike the diarist, Murad gives few dates in her account, but other sources indicate that ISIS seized her village, Kocho, in mid-August 2014 and that she escaped captivity in November 2014. 59. Murad, The Last Girl, 119. 60. Ibid., 131. 61. Ibid., 132. 62. Ibid., 162. 63. Ibid., 138–39. 64. Ibid., 140–41. 65. Ibid., 161. 66. Ibid., 151. 67. Ibid., 161. 68. Ibid., 262. 69. Ibid., 295. 70. Ibid. Notes to Epilogue 231 71. For a reminder of debates over the use of the term, see Chapter One, pp. 40–42. 72. Chapter Two, pp. 65, 191n82. 73. Murad, The Last Girl, 162. 74. Ibid., 275. 75. A Woman in Berlin, 147. 76. Ibid., 149. 77. Murad, The Last Girl, 279. 78. Ibid., 265. 79. Ibid., 34. 80. Ibid., 39. 81. Ibid., 38–42, 148. 82. Ibid., 154. 83. UN Security Council, 7847th Meeting, UN Doc. S/PV.7847, Dec. 20, 2016, 9. Her comments on Resolution 2467 on sexual violence in conflict were more limited. See UN Security Council, 8514th Meeting, S/PV.8514, Apr. 23, 2019, 7–8. 84. Murad, The Last Girl, 306. 85. Kendall and Nouwen, “Representational Practices at the International Criminal Court.” See also Mégret, “The Strange Case of the Victim Who Did Not Want Justice.” 86. Kendall and Nouwen, “Representational Practices at the International Criminal Court,” 255. 87. A Woman in Berlin, 168. This page intentionally left blank Bibliography This bibliography is divided into two principal sections: (1) General Sources, which includes books, articles, and reports from nongovernmental and a few intergovernmental organizations, and (2) Documents from International Organizations, which is divided into treaties and conventions, international criminal law statutes, and UN resolutions. Many other sources—such as cases, websites, and items cited within a source I consulted—are not included in the bibliography because full citations can be found in the notes. Print copies of all documents that are listed here or in endnotes as “on file with the author” or that provide websites as their source may be found in an archive for the book deposited at the Tarlton Law Library at the University of Texas School of Law. I. General Sources Achuthan, Mahima, and Renee Black. “United Nations Security Council Resolution 1820: A Preliminary Assessment of the Challenges and Opportunities.” New York: Cordaid, 2009. African Rights. Rwanda: Death, Despair and Defiance. London: African Rights, 1994. Aggestam, Karin, and Annika Bergman-Rosamond. “Swedish Feminist Foreign Policy in the Making: Ethics, Politics, and Gender.” Ethics and International Affairs 30, no. 3 (2016): 323–34. Allen, Beverly. Rape Warfare: The Hidden Genocide in Bosnia-Herzegovina and Croatia. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996. Alonso, Harriet Hyman. Peace as a Women’s Issue: A History of the U.S. Movement for World Peace and Women’s Rights. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press, 1993. Alviar García, Helena, and Karen Engle. “The Distributive Politics of Impunity and Anti-Impunity: Lessons from Four Decades of Colombian Peace Negotiation.” In Engle, Miller, and Davis, Anti-Impunity and the Human Rights Agenda, 216–54. Amnesty International. Bosnia-Herzegovina: Rape and Sexual Abuse by Armed Forces. EUR 63/001/1993. Jan. 21, 1993. http://www.amnesty.org/en/library/info/ EUR63/001/1993/en. Amos, Valerie, and Pratibha Parmar. “Challenging Imperial Feminism.” Feminist Review 17 (2005): 3–19. 233 234 Bibliography Anghie, Antony, and B. S. Chimni. “Third World Approaches to International Law and Individual Responsibility in Internal Conflicts.” Chinese Journal of International Law 2 (2003): 77–103. Arcel, Libby Tata. “Deliberate Sexual Torture of Women in War.” In International Handbook of Human Response to Trauma, edited by Arieh Y. Shalev, Rachel Yehuda, and Alexander McFarlane, 179–93. New York: Springer, 2000. Arendt, Hannah. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. New York: Viking Press, 1963. Askin, Kelly D. “A Decade of the Development of Gender Crimes in International Courts and Tribunals: 1993 to 2003.” Human Rights Brief 11, no. 3 (2004): 16–19. ———. “Gender Crimes Jurisprudence in the ICTR: Positive Developments.” Journal of International Criminal Justice 3, no. 4 (2005): 1007–18. ———. “Prosecuting Wartime Rape and Other Gender-Related Crimes under International Law: Extraordinary Advances, Enduring Obstacles.” Berkeley Journal of International Law 21, no. 2 (2003): 288–349. ———. War Crimes against Women: Prosecution in International War Crimes Tribunals. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1997. Athanasiou, Athena. Agonistic Mourning: Political Dissidence and the Women in Black. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press, 2017. Baaz, Maria Eriksson, and Maria Stern. The Complexity of Violence: A Critical Analysis of Sexual Violence in the Democratic Republic of Congo. Stockholm: Swedish International Development Cooperation Agency, 2010. Baig, Laurel, Michelle Jarvis, Elena Martin Salgado, and Giulia Pinzauti. “Contextualizing Sexual Violence: Selection of Crimes.” In Brammertz and Jarvis, Prosecuting Conflict-Related Sexual Violence, 172–219. Barkan, Joanne. “As Old as War Itself: Rape in Foca.” Dissent 49, no. 1 (2002): 60–66. Barry, Kathleen. Female Sexual Slavery. New York: New York University Press, 1979. ———. “The Opening Paper: International Politics of Female Sexual Slavery.” In Barry, Bunch, and Castley, International Feminism, 21–31. Barry, Kathleen, Charlotte Bunch, and Shirley Castley, eds. International Feminism: Networking against Female Sexual Slavery. Report on Global Feminist Workshop against Traffic in Women. Rotterdam, the Netherlands, April 6–15, 1983. New York: International Women’s Tribune Centre, 1983. Bassiouni, M. Cherif. Foreword to Hazan, Justice in a Time of War, ix–xviii. Batinić, Jelena. “Feminism, Nationalism, and War: The ‘Yugoslav Case’ in Feminist Texts.” Journal of International Women’s Studies 3, no. 1 (2001): 1–23. Bell, Daniel A. “The East Asian Challenge to Human Rights: Reflections on an East West Dialogue.” Human Rights Quarterly 18, no. 3 (1996): 641–67. Berlant, Lauren. “Thinking about Feeling Historical.” Emotion, Space and Society 1, no. 1 (2008): 4–9. Bernstein, Elizabeth. “Carceral Politics as Gender Justice? The ‘Traffic in Women’ and Neoliberal Circuits of Crime, Sex, and Rights.” Theory and Society 41, no. 3 (2012): 233–59. Bibliography 235 ———. “Militarized Humanitarianism Meets Carceral Feminism: The Politics of Sex, Rights, and Freedom in Contemporary Antitrafficking Campaigns.” Signs 36, no. 1 (2010): 45–71. ———. “The Sexual Politics of the ‘New Abolitionism.’” Differences: Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 18, no. 3 (2007): 128–51. Bianchi, Linda. “The Investigation and Presentation of Evidence relating to Sexual Violence.” Paper presented at the Roundtable on Cooperation between the International Criminal Tribunals and Prosecuting Authorities, Arusha, Tanzania, November 26– 28, 2008. On file with author. ———. “The Prosecution of Rape and Sexual Violence.” In Sexual Violence as an International Crime: Interdisciplinary Approaches, edited by Anne-Marie de Brouwer, Charlotte Ku, Renée Römkens, and Larissa van den Herik, 123–50. Cambridge, UK: Intersentia, 2013. Boutros-Ghali, Boutros. “Address by the Secretary-General of the United Nations at the Opening of the International Conference on Population and Development.” St. Louis–Warsaw Transatlantic Law Journal 1995: 1–8. Boyle, Kevin. “Stock-taking on Human Rights: The World Conference on Human Rights, Vienna 1993.” Political Studies 43, no. 1 (1995): 79–95. Braithwaite, John. Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. Brammertz, Serge, and Michelle Jarvis, eds. Prosecuting Conflict-Related Sexual Violence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Brems, Eva. “Enemies or Allies? Feminism and Cultural Relativism as Dissident Voices in Human Rights Discourse.” Human Rights Quarterly 19, no. 1 (1997): 136–64. Briand, David P., and Leigh Swigart. Interview with Gabrielle Kirk McDonald. Brandeis Institutional Repository Ad Hoc Tribunals Oral History Project. East Hampton, NY, December 18, 2014. ———. Interview with Patricia Viseur Sellers. Brandeis Institutional Repository Ad Hoc Tribunals Oral History Project. The Hague, Netherlands, May 17, 2004. ———. Interview with Richard J. Goldstone. Brandeis Institutional Repository Ad Hoc Tribunals Oral History Project. Waltham, MA, Mar. 9, 2015. Bringa, Tone. Being Muslim the Bosnian Way: Identity and Community in a Central Bosnian Village. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996. Broer, Lawrence R., and Gloria Holland, eds. Hemingway and Women: Female Critics and the Female Voice. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 2002. Brown, Sara E. “Female Perpetrators of the Rwandan Genocide.” International Feminist Journal of Politics 16, no. 3 (2014): 448–69. Brownmiller, Susan. Against Our Will: Men, Women and Rape. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1975. ———. “Making Female Bodies the Battlefield.” In Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, 180–82. Bunch, Charlotte. “Beyond Either/Or: Feminist Options.” In Building Feminist Theory: Essays from Quest: A Feminist Quarterly, edited by the Quest staff, 44–56. New York: Longman, 1981. 236 Bibliography ———. “How Women’s Rights Became Recognized as Human Rights.” In The Unfinished Revolution: Voices from the Global Fight for Women’s Rights, edited by Minky Worden, 29–40. Bristol, UK: Policy Press, 2012. ———. “Network Strategies and Organizing against Female Sexual Slavery.” In Barry, Bunch, and Castley, International Feminism, 49–62. ———. “Women’s Rights as Human Rights: Toward a Re-Vision of Human Rights.” Human Rights Quarterly 12, no. 4 (1990): 486–98. Bunch, Charlotte, and Niamh Reilly. Demanding Accountability: The Global Campaign and Vienna Tribunal for Women’s Human Rights. New Brunswick, NJ: Center for Women’s Global Leadership, Rutgers University; New York: United Nations Development Fund for Women, 1994. Burić, Fedja. “Dwelling on the Ruins of Socialist Yugoslavia: Being Bosnian by Remembering Tito.” In Post-Communist Nostalgia, edited by Maria Todorova and Zsuzsa Gille, 227–43. New York: Berghahn Books, 2010. Burrows, Noreen. “International Law and Human Rights: The Case of Women’s Rights.” In Human Rights: From Rhetoric to Reality, edited by Tom Campbell, David Goldberg, Sheila McLean, and Tom Mullen, 80–98. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986. Buss, Doris. “The Curious Visibility of Wartime Rape: Gender and Ethnicity in International Criminal Law.” Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice 25, no. 1 (2007): 3–22. ———. “Learning Our Lessons? The Rwanda Tribunal Record on Prosecuting Rape.” In Rethinking Rape Law: International and Comparative Perspectives, edited by Clare McGlynn and Vanessa E. Munro, 61–75. New York: Routledge, 2010. ———. “Rethinking ‘Rape as a Weapon of War.’” Feminist Legal Studies 17, no. 2 (2009): 145–63. Buss, Doris, and Ambreena Manji, eds. International Law: Modern Feminist Approaches. Portland: Hart Publishing, 2005. Byrnes, Andrew. “Women, Feminism, and International Human Rights Law—Methodological Myopia, Fundamental Flaws or Meaningful Marginalisation?” Australian Year Book of International Law 12 (1988–89): 205–40. Campbell, Kirsten. “The Gender of Transitional Justice: Law, Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia.” International Journal of Transitional Justice 1, no. 3 (2007): 411–32. Carpenter, R. Charli. Forgetting Children Born of War: Setting the Human Rights Agenda in Bosnia and Beyond. New York: Columbia University Press, 2010. ———. “Surfacing Children: Limitations of Genocidal Rape Discourse.” Human Rights Quarterly 22, no. 2 (2000): 428–77. Cerna, Christina M. “Universality of Human Rights and Cultural Diversity: Implementation of Human Rights in Different Socio-Cultural Contexts.” Human Rights Quarterly 16, no. 4 (1994): 740–52. Cerna, Christina M., and Jennifer C. Wallace. “Women and Culture.” In Women and International Human Rights Law, vol. 1, edited by Kelly D. Askin and Dorean M. Koenig, 623–50. Ardsley, NY: Transnational Publishers, 1998. Bibliography 237 Chappell, Louise. The Politics of Gender Justice at the International Criminal Court: Legacies and Legitimacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Charlesworth, Hilary. “Feminist Methods in International Law.” American Journal of International Law 93, no. 2 (1999): 379–94. ———. “Human Rights as Men’s Rights.” In Peters and Wolper, Women’s Rights, Human Rights, 103–13. Charlesworth, Hilary, and Christine Chinkin. The Boundaries of International Law: A Feminist Analysis. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press, 2000. Charlesworth, Hilary, Christine Chinkin, and Shelly Wright. “Feminist Approaches to International Law.” American Journal of International Law 85, no. 4 (1991): 613–45. Chinkin, Christine. “International Human Rights, Criminal Law and the Women, Peace and Security Agenda.” London School of Economics Women, Peace and Security Working Paper Series, 2018. https://blogs.lse.ac.uk/wps/2018/01/11 /international-human-rights-criminal-law-and-the-women-peace-and-security -agenda-christine-chinkin-122018/. Chinkin, Christine, and Madeleine Rees. Commentary on Security Council Resolution 2467: Continued State Obligation and Civil Society Action on Sexual Violence in Conflict. London School of Economics Centre for Women, Peace and Security; WILPF (Women’s International League for Peace and Freedom), 2019. https://www.wilpf .org/wp-content/uploads/2019/07/19_0496_WPS_Commentary_Report_online .pdf. Cisse, Catherine. “The International Tribunals for the Former Yugoslavia and Rwanda: Some Elements of Comparison.” Transnational and Contemporary Problems 7 (1997): 103–18. Cmiel, Kenneth. “The Emergence of Human Rights Politics in the United States.” Journal of American History 86, no. 3 (1999): 1231–50. Coalition on Women’s Human Rights in Conflict Situations. Amicus Brief Respecting Amendment of the Indictment and Supplementation of the Evidence to Ensure the Prosecution of Rape and Other Sexual Violence within the Competence of the Tribunal. 1997). http://www.iccwomen.org/publications/briefs/docs/Prosecutor_v _Akayesu_ICTR.pdf. Cohen, Dara Kay. “Explaining Rape during Civil War: Cross-National Evidence (1980– 2009).” American Political Science Review 107, no. 3 (2013): 461–77. Cohen, Dara Kay, and Ragnhild Nordås. “Sexual Violence in Armed Conflict: Introducing the SVAC Dataset, 1989–2009.” Journal of Peace Research 51, no. 3 (2014): 418–28. Cohn, Carol, Helen Kinsella, and Sheri Gibbings. “Women, Peace and Security: Resolution 1325.” International Feminist Journal of Politics 6, no. 1 (2004): 130–40. Comley, Nancy R., and Robert Scholes. Hemingway’s Genders: Rereading the Hemingway Text. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994. Cook, Sam. “Security Council Resolution 1820: On Militarism, Flashlights, Raincoats, and Rooms with Doors—A Political Perspective on Where It Came From and What It Adds.” Emory International Law Review 23, no. 1 (2009): 125–39. 238 Bibliography Copelon, Rhonda. “Gender Crimes as War Crimes: Integrating Crimes against Women into International Criminal Law.” McGill Law Journal 46 (2000): 217–40. ———. “International Human Rights Dimensions of Intimate Violence: Another Strand in the Dialectic of Feminist Lawmaking.” American University Journal of Gender Social Policy and Law 11, no. 2 (2003): 865–76. ———. “Rape and Gender Violence: From Impunity to Accountability in International Law.” Human Rights Dialogue 2, no. 10 (2003). https://www.carnegiecouncil.org/ publications/archive/dialogue/2_10/articles/1052. ———. “Surfacing Gender: Reconceptualizing Crimes against Women in Time of War.” In Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, 197–218. Cossman, Brenda. “Turning the Gaze Back on Itself: Comparative Law, Feminist Legal Studies, and the Postcolonial Project.” Utah Law Review 1997, no. 2: 525–44. Craven, Matthew, Sundhya Pahuja, and Gerry Simpson. “Reading and Unreading a Historiography of Hiatus.” In International Law and the Cold War, edited by Matthew Craven, Sundhya Pahuja, and Gerry Simpson. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming. Dallmeyer, Dorinda G., ed. Reconceiving Reality: Women and International Law. Washington, DC: American Society of International Law, 1993. Davis, Patricia H. “The Politics of Prosecuting Rape as a War Crime.” International Lawyer 34, no. 4 (2000): 1223–48. de Brouwer, Anne-Marie. Supranational Criminal Prosecution of Sexual Violence. Antwerp: Intersentia, 2005. Desai, Shefali. “Hearing Afghan Women’s Voices: Feminist Theory’s Re-Conceptualization of Women’s Human Rights.” Arizona Journal of International and Comparative Law 16, no. 3 (1999): 805–44. Douglas, Lawrence. The Memory of Judgment: Making Law and History in the Trials of the Holocaust. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2001. Drumbl, Mark A. “She Makes Me Ashamed to Be a Woman: The Genocide Conviction of Pauline Nyiramasuhuko, 2011.” Michigan Journal of International Law 34, no. 3 (2013): 559–604. Eboe-Osuji, Chile. International Law and Sexual Violence in Armed Conflicts. Leiden: Brill, 2012. Effange-Mbella, Elsie. “On Support Measures to Victims and Witnesses Summoned to Appear before the Tribunal.” Paper presented at the ICTR Conference on Challenging Impunity, Arusha, Tanzania, November 7–9, 2006. On file with author. Eisler, Riane. “Human Rights: Toward an Integrated Theory of Action.” Human Rights Quarterly 9, no. 3 (1987): 287–308. Engle, Karen. “After the Collapse of the Public/Private Distinction: Strategizing Women’s Rights.” In Dallmeyer, Reconceiving Reality, 143–56. ———. “Anti-Impunity and the Turn to Criminal Law in Human Rights.” Cornell Law Review 100, no. 5 (2015): 1069–127. ———. “Celebrity Diplomacy and Global Citizenship.” Celebrity Studies 3, no. 1 (2012): 116–18. Bibliography 239 ———. “Culture and Human Rights: The Asian Values Debate in Context.” New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 32, no. 2 (2000): 291–334. ———. “Feminism and Its (Dis)contents: Criminalizing Wartime Rape in Bosnia and Herzegovina.” American Journal of International Law 99, no. 4 (2005): 778–816. ———. “International Human Rights and Feminism: When Discourses Meet.” Michigan Journal of International Law 13, no. 3 (1992): 517–610. ———. “International Human Rights and Feminisms: When Discourses Keep Meeting.” In Buss and Manji, International Law, 47–67. Engle, Karen, Zinaida Miller, and D. M. Davis, eds. Anti-Impunity and the Human Rights Agenda. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2016. Engle, Karen, Vasuki Nesiah, and Dianne Otto. “Feminist Approaches to International Law.” In International Legal Theory: Foundations and Frontiers, edited by Jeffrey L. Dunoff and Mark A. Pollack. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming. Etienne, Margareth. “Addressing Gender-Based Violence in an International Context.” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 18 (1995): 139–70. European Council Investigative Mission into the Treatment of Muslim Women in the Former Yugoslavia. Report to European Council Foreign Ministers (Warburton Mission Report). Copenhagen: Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Feb. 1993. http://www .womenaid.org/press/info/humanrights/warburtonfull.htm. Feimster, Crystal N. “Rape and Justice in the Civil War.” In The New York Times Disunion: A History of the Civil War, edited by Ted Widmer, with Clay Risen and George Kalogerakis, 180–83. New York: Oxford University Press. Fine, John. The Bosnian Church: Its Place in State and Society from the Thirteenth to the Fifteenth Century. London: Saqi, 2007. Fisher, Siobhan K. “Occupation of the Womb: Forced Impregnation as Genocide.” Duke Law Journal 46 (1996): 91–133. Folnegović-Šmalc, Vera. “Psychiatric Aspects of Rapes in the War against the Republics of Croatia and Bosnia-Herzegovina.” In Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, 174–79. Ford, Stuart. “Fairness and Politics at the ICTY: Evidence from the Indictments.” North Carolina Journal of International Law 39, no. 1 (2013): 46–113. Franke, Katherine M. “Putting Sex to Work.” Denver University Law Review 75, no. 4 (1998): 1139–80. Fraser, Arvonne. “Becoming Human: The Origins and Development of Women’s Human Rights.” Human Rights Quarterly 21, no. 4 (1999): 853–906. ———. She’s No Lady: Politics, Family, and International Feminism. Minneapolis, MN: Nodin, 2007. Garay, Amanda. “Women, Cultural Relativism, and International Human Rights: A Question of Mutual Exclusivity or Balance?” International Insights 12 (1996): 19–33. Gardam, Judith. “A Feminist Analysis of Certain Aspects of International Humanitarian Law.” Australian Year Book of International Law 12 (1988–1989): 265–78. ———. Non-Combatant Immunity as a Norm of International Humanitarian Law. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1993. 240 Bibliography Ghai, Yash. “Human Rights and Governance: The Asia Debate.” Australian Year Book of International Law 15 (1994): 1–34. Gilman, Nils. “Toward a History of the New International Economic Order.” Special issue, Humanity: An International Journal of Human Rights, Humanitarianism, and Development 6, no. 1 (2015). Ginn, Courtney. “Ensuring the Effective Prosecution of Sexually Violent Crimes in the Bosnian War Crimes Chamber: Applying Lessons from the ICTY.” Emory International Law Review 27, no. 1 (2013): 565–601. Goffman, Erving. Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1963. Goldstein, Anne. Forced Impregnation as a War Crime under International Law: A Special Report of the International Program. New York: Center for Reproductive Law and Policy, 1993. Goldstone, Richard. “Prosecuting Rape as a War Crime.” Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 32, no. 3 (2002): 277–86. ———. “The United Nations War Crimes Tribunals: An Assessment.” Connecticut Journal of International Law 12, no. 2 (1997): 227–64. Gourevitch, Philip. We Wish to Inform You That Tomorrow We Will Be Killed with Our Families: Stories from Rwanda. New York: Picador, 1999. Green, Jennifer, Rhonda Copelon, Patrick Cotter, and Beth Stephens. “Affecting the Rules for the Prosecution of Rape and Other Gender-Based Violence before the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia: A Feminist Proposal and Critique.” Hastings Women’s Law Journal 5, no. 2 (1994): 171–241. Grey, Rosemary, and Laura J. Shepherd. “‘Stop Rape Now?’: Masculinity, Responsibility, and Conflict-Related Sexual Violence.” Men and Masculinities 16, no. 1 (2013): 115–35. Gruber, Aya. “The Feminist War on Crime.” Iowa Law Review 92, no. 3 (2007): 741–833. ———. “Rape, Feminism, and the War on Crime.” Washington Law Review 84, no. 4 (2009): 581–660. Gunning, Isabelle R. “Arrogant Perception, World-Travelling and Multicultural Feminism: The Case of Female Genital Surgeries.” Columbia Human Rights Law Review 23, no. 2 (1992): 189–248. Gutman, Roy. Foreword to Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, ix–xiv. ———. A Witness to Genocide. New York: Lisa Drew Books, 1993. HadžiMuhamedović, Safet. Waiting for Elijah: Time and Encounter in a Bosnian Landscape. New York: Berghahn Books, 2018. Halley, Janet. “Rape at Rome: Feminist Interventions in the Criminalization of SexRelated Violence in Positive International Criminal Law.” Michigan Journal of International Law 30, no. 1 (2008): 1–124. ———. “Rape in Berlin: Reconsidering the Criminalisation of Rape in the International Law of Armed Conflict.” Melbourne Journal of International Law 9, no. 1 (2008): 78–124. ———. “Sexuality Harassment.” In Left Legalism/Left Critique, edited by Janet Halley and Wendy Brown, 80–104. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2002. Bibliography 241 ———. Split Decisions: How and Why to Take a Break from Feminism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006. Halley, Janet, Prabha Kotiswaran, Rachel Rebouché, and Hila Shamir. Governance Feminism: An Introduction. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 2018. Halley, Janet, Prabha Kotiswaran, Rachel Rebouché, and Hila Shamir, eds. Governance Feminism: Notes from the Field. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 2019. Hamzić, Vanja. “Ethnicity and International Law: Histories, Politics and Practices.” Book Review. Melbourne Journal of International Law 17, no. 2 (2016): 489–93. Hansen, Lene. Security as Practice: Discourse Analysis and the Bosnian War. New York: Routledge, 2006. Hazan, Pierre. Justice in a Time of War: The True Story behind the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia. Translated by James Thomas Snyder. College Station, TX: Texas A&M University Press, 2004. Heathcote, Gina. “Feminist Politics and the Use of Force: Theorising Feminist Action and Security Council Resolution 1325.” Socio-Legal Review 7 (2011): 23–43. ———. “Naming and Shaming: Human Rights Accountability in Security Council Resolution 1960 (2010) on Women, Peace and Security.” Journal of Human Rights Practice 4, no. 1 (2012): 1–24. Heathcote, Gina, and Dianne Otto, eds. Rethinking Peacekeeping, Gender Equality, and Collective Security. New York: Palgrave, 2014. Helsinki Watch. War Crimes in Bosnia-Hercegovina. New York: Human Rights Watch, 1992. https://www.hrw.org/reports/pdfs/y/yugoslav/yugo.928/yugo928full.pdf. Hemingway, Ernest. For Whom the Bell Tolls. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1996. ———. Selected Letters 1917–1961. Edited by Carlos Baker. New York: Scribner, 2003. Henry, Nicola. “Witness to Rape: The Limits and Potential of International War Crimes Trials for Victims of Wartime Sexual Violence.” International Journal of Transitional Justice 3, no. 1 (2009): 114–34. Higgins, Tracy E. “Anti-Essentialism, Relativism, and Human Rights.” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 19 (1996): 89–126. Hom, Sharon K. “Commentary: Re-Positioning Human Rights Discourse on ‘Asian’ Perspectives.” Buffalo Journal of International Law 3, no. 1 (1996): 209–34. Hoover Green, Amelia. “Repertoires of Violence against Non-Combatants: The Role of Armed Group Institutions and Ideologies.” PhD diss., Yale University, 2011. Hughes, Donna M., Lepa Mladjenović, and Zorica Mršević. “Feminist Resistance in Serbia.” European Journal of Women’s Studies 2, no. 4 (1995): 509–32. Huvé, Sophie. The Use of UN Sanctions to Address Conflict-Related Sexual Violence. Georgetown Institute for Women, Peace and Security, 2018. https://giwps.georgetown.edu/ resource/the-use-of-un-sanctions-to-address-conflict-related-sexual-violence/. Ibárruri, Dolores. They Shall Not Pass: The Autobiography of La Pasionaria. New York: International Publishers, 1976. ICTR (International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda). Prosecution of Sexual Violence: Best Practices Manual for the Investigation and Prosecution of Sexual Violence Crimes in Post-Conflict Regions: Lessons Learned from the Office of the Prosecutor for the In- 242 Bibliography ternational Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda. Jan. 30, 2014. http://www.irmct.org/sites /unictr.org/files/legal-library/140130_prosecution_of_sexual_violence.pdf. Independent International Commission on Kosovo. Kosovo Report: Conflict, International Response, Lessons Learned. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty. The Responsibility to Protect. Ottawa, ON: International Development Research Centre, 2001. http:// responsibilitytoprotect.org/ICISS%20Report.pdf. Jansen, Stef. Yearnings in the Meantime: ‘Normal Lives’ and the State in a Sarajevo Apartment Complex. New York: Berghahn Books, 2015. Jarvis, Michelle. “Overview: The Challenge of Accountability for Conflict-Related Sexual Violence Crimes.” In Brammertz and Jarvis, Prosecuting Conflict-Related Sexual Violence at the ICTY, 1–18. Joachim, Jutta. Agenda Setting, the UN, and NGOs: Gender Violence and Reproductive Rights. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2007. ———. “Shaping the Human Rights Agenda.” In Gender Politics in Global Governance, edited by Mary K. Meyer and Elisabeth Prügl, 142–60. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, 1999. Johnson, Paula C., and Leslye Amede Obiora. “Panel Discussion: How Does the Universal Declaration of Human Rights Protect African Women?” Syracuse Journal of International Law and Commerce 26, no. 2 (1999): 195–215. Kahan, Dan M. “What’s Really Wrong with Shaming Sanctions.” Texas Law Review 84, no. 7 (2006): 2075–96. Kalosieh, Adrienne. “Consent to Genocide?: The ICTY’s Improper Use of the Consent Paradigm to Prosecute Genocidal Rape in Foca.” Women’s Rights Law Reporter 24 (2003): 121–35. Kapur, Ratna. “The Tragedy of Victimization Rhetoric: Resurrecting the ‘Native’ Subject in International/Post-Colonial Feminist Legal Politics.” Harvard Human Rights Journal 15, no. 1 (2002): 1–38. Keck, Margaret E., and Kathryn Sikkink. Activists beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1998. Kendall, Sara, and Sarah Nouwen. “Representational Practices at the International Criminal Court: The Gap between Juridified and Abstract Victimhood.” Law and Contemporary Problems 76, no. 3/4 (2013): 235–62. Kennedy, David. The Dark Sides of Virtue: Reassessing International Humanitarianism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004. Kesić, Obrad. “Women and Gender Imagery in Bosnia: Amazons, Sluts, Victims, Witches, and Wombs.” In Gender Politics in the Western Balkans, edited by Sabrina P. Ramet, 187–202. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1999. Kesic, Vesna. “A Response to Catharine MacKinnon’s Article ‘Turning Rape into Pornography: Postmodern Genocide.’” Hastings Women’s Law Journal 5, no. 2 (1994): 267–80. Khushalani, Yougindra. Dignity and Honour of Women as Basic and Fundamental Human Rights. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1982. Bibliography 243 Kim, Nancy. “Toward a Feminist Theory of Human Rights: Straddling the Fence between Western Imperialism and Uncritical Absolutism.” Columbia Human Rights Law Review 25, no. 1 (1993): 49–106. Kinsella, Helen. The Image before the Weapon: A Critical History of the Distinction between Combatant and Civilian. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2011. Knop, Karen. “Of the Male Persuasion: The Power of Liberal Internationalism for Women.” Proceedings of the American Society of International Law Annual Meeting 93 (1999): 177–85. ———. “Re/Statements: Feminism and State Sovereignty in International Law.” Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems 3, no. 2 (1993): 293–344. Koskenniemi, Martti. “Between Impunity and Show Trials.” Max Planck Yearbook of United Nations Law 6 (2002): 1–35. Kritz, Neil J. “Coming to Terms with Atrocities: A Review of Accountability Mechanisms for Mass Violations of Human Rights.” Law and Contemporary Problems 59, no. 4 (1996): 127–52. Lazitch, Branko, and Milorad M. Drachkovitch. Biographical Dictionary of the Comintern. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution Press, 1986. Lewis, Chloé. “Systemic Silencing: Addressing Sexual Violence against Men and Boys in Armed Conflict and Its Aftermath.” In Heathcote and Otto, Rethinking Peacekeeping, Gender Equality, and Collective Security, 203–23. Lewis, Hope. “Between Irua and ‘Female Genital Mutilation’: Feminist Human Rights Discourse and the Cultural Divide.” Harvard Human Rights Journal 8 (1995): 1–56. Lilly, Carol S., and Jill A. Irvine. “Negotiating Interests: Women and Nationalism in Serbia and Croatia, 1990–1997.” East European Politics and Societies 16, no. 1 (2002): 109–44. Lines, Lisa. Milicianas: Women in Combat in the Spanish Civil War. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2012. Lixinski, Lucas. “’Treaty Interpretation’” by the Inter-American Court of Human Rights: Expansionism at the Service of the Unity of International Law.” European Journal of International Law 21, no. 3 (2010): 585–604. Lobwein, Wendy. “Experiences of the Victims and Witnesses Section at the I.C.T.Y.” In Large-Scale Victimisation as a Potential Source of Terrorist Activities: Importance of Regaining Security in Post-Conflict Societies, edited by Uwe Ewald and Ksenija Turkovic, 197–207. Amsterdam: IOS Press, 2006. London School of Economics Centre for Women, Peace and Security. “Preventing/ Countering Violent Extremism and WPS.” 2017. http://www.lse.ac.uk/women-peace -security/assets/documents/2017/LSE-WPS-PCVE-Key-Issues-Report.pdf. MacKinnon, Catharine A. Are Women Human? And Other International Dialogues. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2006. ———. Butterfly Politics. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2017. ———. “Crimes of War, Crimes of Peace.” In Are Women Human?, 141–59. ———. “Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: Toward Feminist Jurisprudence.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 8, no. 4 (1983): 635–58. 244 Bibliography ———. “Genocide’s Sexuality.” In Are Women Human?, 209–33. ———. “Oncale v. Sundowner Offshore Services, Inc., 96–568, Amici Curiae Brief in Support of Petitioner.” UCLA Women’s Law Journal 8, no. 1 (1997): 10–46. ———. “On Torture.” In Are Women Human?, 17–27. ———. “Pornography Left and Right.” Harvard Civil Rights–Civil Liberties Law Review 30 (1995): 143–68. ———. “Rape, Genocide, and Women’s Human Rights.” In Are Women Human?, 180–91. ———. “Remedies for War Crimes at the National Level.” Journal of the International Institute 6, no. 1 (1998). http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.4750978.0006.103. ———. “Women’s September 11th: Rethinking the International Law of Conflict.” In Are Women Human?, 259–80. Mamdani, Mahmood. “Beyond Nuremberg: The Historical Significance of the PostApartheid Transition in South Africa.” Politics and Society 43, no. 1 (2015): 61–88. Martin, Dianne L. “Retribution Revisited: A Reconsideration of Feminist Criminal Law Reform Strategies.” Osgoode Hall Law Journal 36, no. 1 (1998): 151–88. Martin, Mary, and Taylor Owen. “The Second Generation of Human Security: Lessons from the UN and EU Experience.” International Affairs 86, no. 1 (2010): 211–24. Mégret, Frédéric. “The Strange Case of the Victim Who Did Not Want Justice.” International Journal of Transitional Justice 12, no. 3 (2018): 444–63. Meister, Robert. After Evil: A Politics of Human Rights. New York: Columbia University Press, 2010. Meron, Theodor. “Answering for War Crimes: Lessons from the Balkans.” Foreign Affairs 76, no. 1 (1997): 2–8. ———. “On the Inadequate Reach of Humanitarian and Human Rights Law and the Need for a New Instrument.” American Journal of International Law 77, no. 3 (1983): 589–606. ———. “Rape as a Crime under International Humanitarian Law.” American Journal of International Law 87, no. 3 (1993): 424–38. Mertus, Julie. “When Adding Women Matters: Women’s Participation in the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia.” Seton Hall Law Review 38, no. 4 (2008): 1297–326. Mezey, Gillian. “Rape in War.” Journal of Forensic Psychiatry 5, no. 3 (1994): 583–97. Michel, Jean-Baptiste, Yuan Kui Shen, Aviva P. Aiden, Adrian Veres, et al. “Quantitative Analysis of Culture Using Millions of Digitized Books.” Science 331, no. 6014 (2011): 176–82. Milanovic, Marko. “The Impact of the ICTY on the Former Yugoslavia: An Anticipatory Postmortem.” American Journal of International Law 110, no. 2 (2016): 233–59. Miller, Alice M. “Sexuality, Violence against Women, and Human Rights: Women Make Demands and Ladies Get Protection.” Health and Human Rights 7, no. 2 (2004): 16–47. Miller, Zinaida. “Anti-Impunity Politics in Post-Genocide Rwanda.” In Engle, Miller, and Davis, Anti-Impunity and the Human Rights Agenda, 149–84. Mischkowski, Gabriela, and Gorana Mlinarevic. “ . . . And That It Does Not Happen to Anyone Anywhere in the World”: The Trouble with Rape Trials—Views of Witnesses, Bibliography 245 Prosecutors and Judges on Prosecuting Sexualised Violence during the War in the Former Yugoslavia. Cologne: medica mondiale e.V., 2009. https://www.medicamondiale.org /fileadmin/redaktion/5_Service/Mediathek/Dokumente/English/Documentations _studies/medica_mondiale_and_that_it_does_not_happen_to_anyone_anywhere _in_the_world_english_complete_version_dec_2009.pdf. Mohanty, Chandra Talpade. “Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses.” Feminist Review 30 (1988): 61–88. Moyn, Samuel. “Anti-Impunity as Deflection of Argument.” In Engle, Miller, and Davis, Anti-Impunity and the Human Rights Agenda, 68–94. ———. “From Antiwar Politics to Antitorture Politics.” In Law and War, edited by Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha Merrill Umphrey, 154–97. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2014. ———. The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2010. Murad, Nadia. The Last Girl: My Story of Captivity, and My Fight against the Islamic State. With Jenna Krajeski. New York: Tim Duggan Books, 2017. Nenadic, Natalie. “Femicide: A Framework for Understanding Genocide.” In Radically Speaking: Feminism Reclaimed, edited by Diane Bell and Renate Klein, 456–64. Melbourne: Spinifex Press, 1996. Nesiah, Vasuki. “Discussion Lines on Gender and Transitional Justice: An Introductory Essay Reflecting on the ICTJ Bellagio Workshop on Gender and Transitional Justice.” Columbia Journal of Gender and Law 15, no. 3 (2006): 799–812. ———. “Feminism as Counter-Terrorism: The Seduction of Power.” In Gender, National Security, and Counter-Terrorism: Human Rights Perspectives, edited by Margaret L. Satterthwaite and Jane Huckerby, 127–51. London: Routledge, 2013. ———. “Toward a Feminist Internationality: A Critique of U.S. Feminist Legal Scholarship.” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 16 (1993): 189–210. Ní Aoláin, Fionnuala. “Radical Rules: The Effects of Evidential and Procedural Rules on the Regulation of Sexual Violence in War.” Albany Law Review 60, no. 3 (1997): 883–905. ———. “Sex-Based Violence and the Holocaust: A Reevaluation of Harms and Rights in International Law.” Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 12, no. 1 (2000): 43–84. ———. “The ‘War on Terror’ and Extremism: Assessing the Relevance of the Women, Peace and Security Agenda.” International Affairs 92, no. 2 (2016): 275–91. Ní Aoláin, Fionnuala, Dina Francesca Haynes, and Naomi Cahn. On the Frontlines: Gender, War, and the Post-Conflict Process. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Niarchos, Catherine N. “Women, War, and Rape: Challenges Facing the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia.” Human Rights Quarterly 17 (1995): 649–90. Nordås, Ragnhild, and Robert Nagel. “Continued Failure to End Wartime Sexual Violence.” PRIO Policy Brief 7. Oslo: Peace Research Institute Oslo, 2018. https://www .prio.org/Publications/Publication/?x=11122. Nouwen, Sarah M. H. “Justifying Justice.” In Cambridge Companion to International Law, edited by James Crawford and Martti Koskenniemi, 327–51. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012. 246 Bibliography Nowrojee, Binaifer. “Making the Invisible War Crime Visible: Post-Conflict Justice for Sierra Leone’s Rape Victims.” Harvard Human Rights Journal 18 (2005): 85–106. ———. Shattered Lives: Sexual Violence during the Rwandan Genocide and Its Aftermath. Human Rights Watch, 1996. https://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/1996 _Rwanda_%20Shattered%20Lives.pdf. ———. “Your Justice Is Too Slow”: Will the ICTR Fail Rwanda’s Rape Victims? Geneva: United Nations Research Institute for Social Development, 2005. http://www.un risd.org/unrisd/website/document.nsf/(httpPublications)/56FE32D5C0F6DCE9C1 25710F0045D89F?OpenDocument. Obiora, Leslye Amede. “Feminism, Globalization, and Culture: After Beijing.” Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 4, no. 2 (1997): 355–406. Obote-Odora, Alex. “Rape and Sexual Violence in International Law: ICTR Contribution.” New England Journal of International and Comparative Law 12, no. 1 (2005): 135–60. Oloka-Onyango, J., and Sylvia Tamale. “‘The Personal Is Political,’ or Why Women’s Rights Are Indeed Human Rights: An African Perspective on International Feminism.” Human Rights Quarterly 17, no. 4 (1995): 691–731. Ong, Aihwa. “Strategic Sisterhood or Sisters in Solidarity? Questions of Communitarianism and Citizenship in Asia.” Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 4, no. 1 (1996): 107–35. Oosterveld, Valerie. “Atrocity Crimes Litigation Year-in-Review.” Northwestern Journal of International Human Rights 9, no. 3 (2011): 325–56. ———. “Gender-Sensitive Justice and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda: Lessons Learned for the International Criminal Court.” New England Journal of International and Comparative Law 12, no. 1 (2005): 119–34. ———. “Sexual Slavery and the International Criminal Court: Advancing International Law.” Michigan Journal of International Law 25, no. 3 (2004): 605–51. ———. “Sexual Violence Directed against Men and Boys in Armed Conflict or Mass Atrocity: Addressing a Gendered Harm in International Criminal Tribunals.” Journal of International Law and International Relations 10 (2014): 107–28. Orford, Anne. “Contesting Globalization: A Feminist Perspective on the Future of Human Rights.” Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems 8, no. 2 (1998): 171–98. Otto, Dianne. “Contesting Feminism’s Institutional Doubles: Troubling the Security Council’s Women Peace and Security Agenda.” In Governance Feminism: Notes from the Field, edited by Janet Halley, Prabha Kotiswaran, Rachel Rebouché, and Hila Shamir, 200–229. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2019. ———. “Disconcerting ‘Masculinities’: Reinventing the Gendered Subject(s) of International Human Rights Law.” In Buss and Manji, International Law, 105–31. ———. “The Exile of Inclusion: Reflections on Gender Issues in International Law over the Last Decade.” Melbourne Journal of International Law 10, no. 1 (2009): 11–26. ———. “Making Sense of Zero Tolerance Policies in Peacekeeping Sexual Economies.” In Sexuality and the Law: Feminist Engagements, edited by Vanessa Munro and Carl Stychin, 259–82. New York: Routledge, 2007. Bibliography 247 ———. “Power and Danger: Feminist Engagement with International Law through the UN Security Council.” Australian Feminist Law Journal 32, no. 1 (2010): 97–121. ———. “Rethinking the ‘Universality’ of Human Rights Law.” Columbia Human Rights Law Review 29, no. 1 (1997): 1–46. ———. “The Sexual Tensions of UN Peace Support Operations: A Plea for ‘Sexual Positivity.’” Finnish Yearbook of International Law 18 (2007): 33–58. ———. “A Sign of ‘Weakness’? Disrupting Gender Certainties in the Implementation of Security Council Resolution 1325.” Michigan Journal of Gender and Law 13 (2006– 2007): 113–73. ———. “Women, Peace, and Security: A Critical Analysis of the Security Council’s Vision.” In Oxford Handbook of Gender and Conflict, edited by Fionnuala Ní Aoláin, Naomi Cahn, Dina Francesca Hayes, and Nahla Valji, 105–18. New York: Oxford University Press, 2018. Patton, Charlotte. “Women and Power: The Nairobi Conference, 1985.” In Women, Politics, and the United Nations, edited by Anne Winslow, 61–76. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1995. Paul, James. “NGOs and the Security Council.” Global Policy Forum, 2004. https://www .globalpolicy.org/security-council/40406-ngos-and-the-security-council.html. Peters, Julie, and Andrea Wolper, eds. Women’s Rights, Human Rights: International Feminist Approaches. New York: Routledge, 1995. Pheterson, Gail. “Not Repeating History.” In Pheterson, A Vindication of the Rights of Whores, 3–30. ———, ed. A Vindication of the Rights of Whores. Seattle, WA: Seal Press, 1989. Physicians for Human Rights. Nowhere to Turn: Failure to Protect, Support and Assure Justice for Darfuri Women. In partnership with Harvard Humanitarian Initiative. Cambridge, MA: Physicians for Human Rights, 2009. https://phr.org/resources/nowhere -to-turn/. Pietilä, Hilkka, and Jeanne Vickers. Making Women Matter: The Role of the United Nations. 3rd ed. New York: Zed Books, 1996. Posner, Michael. “Reflections on the Vienna Conference on Human Rights.” Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the American Society of International Law 91 (1997): 317–21. Power, Samantha. “A Problem from Hell”: America and the Age of Genocide. New York: Basic Books, 2013. Rathgeber, Eva M. “WID, WAD, GAD: Trends in Research and Practice.” Journal of Developing Areas 24, no. 4 (1990): 489–502. Rieff, David. At the Point of a Gun: Democratic Dreams and Military Intervention. New York: Simon and Schuster, 2006. Robinson, Darryl. “The Identity Crisis of International Criminal Law.” Leiden Journal of International Law 21, no. 4 (2008): 925–64. Robinson, Darryl, and Gillian MacNeil. “The Tribunals and the Renaissance of International Criminal Law: Three Themes.” American Journal of International Law 110, no. 2 (2016): 191–211. 248 Bibliography Romany, Celina. “Black Women and Gender Equality in a New South Africa: Human Rights Law and the Intersection of Race and Gender.” Brooklyn Journal of International Law 21, no. 3 (1996): 857–98. Roth, Kenneth. “Defending Economic, Social and Cultural Rights: Practical Issues Faced by an International Human Rights Organization.” Human Rights Quarterly 26, no. 1 (2004): 63–73. Roth, Kenneth, Fernand Tesón, and Paige Arthur. “Ending Tyranny in Iraq: A Debate.” Oct. 6, 2005. http://www.carnegiecouncil.org/studio/multimedia/20051006b/index .html. Ruby, Felicity. “Security Council Resolution 1325: A Tool for Conflict Prevention?” In Heathcote and Otto, Rethinking Peacekeeping, Gender Equality, and Collective Security, 173–84. Rupp, Leila J. Worlds of Women: The Making of an International Women’s Movement. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997. Sander, Helke. “Prologue.” In Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, xvii–xxiii. Schaber, Irme, Richard Whelan, and Kristen Lubben, eds. Gerda Taro. New York: International Center of Photography; Göttingen: Steidl, 2007. Scott, Joan Wallach. The Fantasy of Feminist History. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2011. ———. The Politics of the Veil. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007. Scoular, Jane. The Subject of Prostitution: Sex Work, Law and Social Theory. New York: Routledge, 2015. Scully, Pamela. “Vulnerable Women: A Critical Reflection on Human Rights Discourse and Sexual Violence.” Emory International Law Review 23 (2009): 113–23. Sells, Michael A. The Bridge Betrayed: Religion and Genocide in Bosnia. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998. Shattuck, John. Freedom on Fire: Human Rights Wars and America’s Response. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003. Shattuck, John, and Joanne Myers. “Freedom on Fire: Human Rights Wars and America’s Response.” Interview transcript. Nov. 20, 2003. http://www.carnegiecouncil.org /studio/multimedia/20031120/index.html. Shepherd, Laura. “Power and Authority in the Production of United Nations Security Council Resolution 1325.” International Studies Quarterly 52 (2008): 383–404. Simić, Olivera. Regulation of Sexual Conduct in UN Peacekeeping Operations. New York: Springer, 2012. ———. Silenced Victims of Wartime Sexual Violence. New York: Routledge, 2018. Sivakumaran, Sandesh. “Lost in Translation: UN Responses to Sexual Violence against Men and Boys in Situations of Armed Conflict.” International Review of the Red Cross 92, no. 877 (2010): 259–77. ———. “Male/Male Rape and the ‘Taint’ of Homosexuality.” Human Rights Quarterly 27, no. 4 (2005): 1274–306. ———. “Sexual Violence against Men in Armed Conflict.” European Journal of International Law 18, no. 2 (2007): 253–76. Bibliography 249 Sjoberg, Laura. Women as Wartime Rapists: Beyond Sensation and Stereotyping. New York: New York University Press, 2016. Sjoberg, Laura, and Caron E. Gentry. Mothers, Monsters, Whores: Women’s Violence in Global Politics. London: Zed Books, 2007. Skjelsbæk, Inger. “Sexual Violence in the Post-Yugoslav Wars.” In Women and War: Power and Protection in the 21st Century, edited by Kathleen Kuehnast, Chantal de Jonge Oudraat, and Helga Hernes, 65–84. Washington, DC: U.S. Institute of Peace Press, 2011. Small, Michael. “Case Study: The Human Security Network.” In Human Security and the New Diplomacy: Protecting People and Promoting Peace, edited by Rob McRae and Don Hubert, 231–35. Montreal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 2001. Solangon, Sarah, and Preeti Patel. “Sexual Violence against Men in Countries Affected by Armed Conflict.” Conflict, Security and Development 12, no. 4 (2012): 417–42. Sorel, Andrés. Dolores Ibarruri, “Pasionaria”: Memoria Humana. Madrid: Exadra de Ediciones, 1989. Spahn, Elizabeth K. “Waiting for Credentials: Feminist Theories of Enforcement of International Human Rights.” American University Law Review 44, no. 4 (1995): 1053–84. Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. “Can the Subaltern Speak?” In Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, edited by Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg, 271–314. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1988. Stacey, Helen. “Legal Discourse and the Feminist Political Economy: Moving beyond Sameness/Difference.” Australian Feminist Law Journal 6 (1996): 115–34. Stark, Barbara. “Bottom Line Feminist Theory: The Dream of a Common Language.” Harvard Women’s Law Journal 23 (2000): 227–46. ———. “The ‘Other’ Half of the International Bill of Rights as a Postmodern Feminist Text.” In Dallmeyer, Reconceiving Reality, 19–60. Stiglmayer, Alexandra. Mass Rape: The War against Women in Bosnia-Herzegovina. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1994. ———. “The Rapes in Bosnia-Herzegovina.” In Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, 82–169. ———. “The War in the Former Yugoslavia.” In Stiglmayer, Mass Rape, 1–34. Stojanović, Slavica, Staša Zajović, and Miloš Urošević. Women for Peace. Belgrade: Women in Black, 2013. http://zeneucrnom.org/pdf/women_for_peace.pdf. Suchland, Jennifer. Economies of Violence: Transnational Feminism, Postsocialism, and the Politics of Sex Trafficking. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2015. Sullivan, Donna. “The Public/Private Distinction in International Human Rights Law.” In Peters and Wolper, Women’s Rights, Human Rights, 126–34. Thomas, Dorothy Q. “Conclusion.” In Peters and Wolper, Women’s Rights, Human Rights, 356–59. Thomas, Dorothy Q., and Michele E. Beasley. “Domestic Violence as a Human Rights Issue.” Human Rights Quarterly 15, no. 1 (1993): 36–62. Ticktin, Miriam. “The Gendered Human of Humanitarianism: Medicalising and Politicising Sexual Violence.” Gender and History 23, no. 2 (2011): 250–65. 250 Bibliography Tomkins, Silvan. “Shame-Humiliation and Contempt-Disgust.” In Shame and Its Sisters: A Silvan Tomkins Reader, edited by Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick and Adam Frank, 133–78. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1995. Toubia, Nahid. “Female Genital Mutilation.” In Peters and Wolper, Women’s Rights, Human Rights, 224–38. UN Division for the Advancement of Women. “Sexual Violence and Armed Conflict: United Nations Response.” Women2000. Apr. 1998. http://www.unwomen.org/en/digital -library/publications/1998/4/women2000-sexual-violence-and-armed-conflict -united-nations-response. UN High Commissioner for Refugees. Working with Men and Boy Survivors of Sexual and Gender-Based Violence in Forced Displacement. Geneva: UNHCR, 2012. http://www .refworld.org/docid/5006aa262.html. UN Women. Preventing Conflict, Transforming Justice, Securing the Peace: A Global Study on the Implementation of United Nations Security Council Resolution 1325. Oct. 12, 2015. http://wps.unwomen.org/pdf/en/GlobalStudy_EN_Web.pdf. UN World Conference on Human Rights. Report of the World Conference on Human Rights. UN Doc. A/CONF.157/24 (Part I). Oct. 13, 1993. ———. Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action. UN Doc. A/CONF.157/23. July 12, 1993. UN World Conference on Women. Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action. UN Doc. A/CONF.177/RES/1. Sept. 15, 1995. ———. Report of the World Conference to Review and Appraise the Achievements of the United Nations Decade for Women: Equality, Development and Peace. UN Doc. A/CONF.116/28/Rev.1. Nairobi: July 15–26, 1985. Van Schaack, Beth. “Engendering Genocide: Akayesu and the Affirmation of Genocidal Rape.” In Human Rights Advocacy Stories, edited by Denna Hurwitz, Margaret Satterthwaite, and Douglas Ford, 196–228. New York: Foundation Press, 2008. Vigeant, Matthew. “Unforeseen Consequences: The Constitutionality of Unilateral Executive R2P Deployments and the Need for Congressional and Judicial Involvement.” Columbia Journal of Law and Social Problems 47 (2010): 209–43. Vigneswaran, Kate. “Annex B: Charges and Outcomes in ICTY Cases Involving Sexual Violence.” In Brammertz and Jarvis, Prosecuting Conflict-Related Sexual Violence at the ICTY, 429–82. Viseur Sellers, Patricia. “Individual(s’) Liability for Collective Sexual Violence.” In Gender and Human Rights, edited by Karen Knop, 153–94. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. ———. “‘Tokyoisation’ of the ICTR’s Gender Jurisprudence.” Africa Legal Aid Quarterly (2007): 41–46. Viseur Sellers, Patricia, and Leo C. Nwoye. “Conflict-Related Male Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Jurisprudence.” In Zalewski et al., Sexual Violence against Men in Global Politics, 211–36. Viseur Sellers, Patricia, and Kaoru Okuizumi. “Intentional Prosecution of Sexual Assaults.” Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems 7, no. 1 (1997): 45–80. Bibliography 251 von Ragenfeld-Felman, Norma. “The Victimization of Women: Rape and Reporting of Rape in Bosnia-Herzegovina, 1992–1993.” Dialog: Internationale Zeitschrift für Kunst und Wissenschaft 6, no. 21 (1997): 3–26. Vranić, Seada. Breaking the Wall of Silence: The Voices of Raped Bosnia. Zagreb: Izdanja Antibarbarus, 1996. Waldmeir, Joseph. “Chapter Numbering and Meaning in For Whom the Bell Tolls.” Hemingway Review 8, no. 2 (1989): 43–45. Weissman, Deborah M. “The Human Rights Dilemma: Rethinking the Humanitarian Project.” Columbia Human Rights Law Review 35, no. 2 (2004): 259–336. WILPF (Women’s International League for Peace and Freedom). From Impunity to Accountability: Ending Impunity for Sexual and Gender Based Violence in Conflict and Post-Conflict Settings. Stockholm, 2011. https://ikff.se/wp-content/uploads/2015/07 /From-Impunity-to-Accountability-conf-report-2011.pdf. Wiltsher, Anne. Most Dangerous Women: Feminist Peace Campaigners of the Great War. London: Pandora Press, 1985. Wing, Adrien K., and Sylke Merchán. “Rape, Ethnicity, and Culture: Spirit Injury from Bosnia to Black America.” Columbia Human Rights Law Review 25, no. 1 (1994): 1–47. A Woman in Berlin. Eight Weeks in the Conquered City: A Diary. Translated by Philip Boehm. New York: Picador, 2005. Wood, Elisabeth. “Rape during War Is Not Inevitable: Variation in Wartime Sexual Violence.” In Understanding and Proving International Sex Crimes, edited by Morten Bergsmo, Alf Butenschøn Skre, and Elisabeth Wood, 389–419. Beijing: Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher, 2012. Woods, Andrew K. “Moral Judgments and International Crimes: The Disutility of Desert.” Virginia Journal of International Law 52, no. 3 (2012): 633–81. Woolf, Virginia. The Three Guineas. London: Hogarth, 1938. Wueger, Diana. “Women under Siege: Libya.” Women’s Media Center. Feb. 8, 2012. http://www.womensmediacenter.com/women-under-siege/conflicts/libya. Zalewski, Marysia, Paula Drumond, Elisabeth Prügl, and Maria Stern, eds. Sexual Violence against Men in Global Politics. New York: Routledge, 2018. Žarkov, Dubravka. The Body of War: Media, Ethnicity, and Gender in the Break-up of Yugoslavia. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2007. II. Documents from International Organizations A. Treaties and Conventions (Additional Protocol I). Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts. June 8, 1977. 1125 UNTS 3. (Additional Protocol II). Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to the Protection of Victims of Non-International Armed Conflicts. June 8, 1977. 1125 UNTS 609. 252 Bibliography Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide. 78 U.N.T.S. 277. Paris, Dec. 9, 1948. Entered into force Jan. 12, 1951. (Geneva I). Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick in Armed Forces in the Field. Aug. 12, 1949. 6 UST 3114, 75 UNTS 31. (Geneva II). Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded, Sick, and Shipwrecked Members of Armed Forces at Sea. Aug. 12, 1949. 6 UST 3217, 75 UNTS 85. (Geneva III). Geneva Convention Relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War. Aug. 12, 1949. 6 UST 3316, 75 UNTS 135. (Geneva IV). Geneva Convention Relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War. Aug. 12, 1949. 6 UST 3516, 75 UNTS 287. UN Charter. Adopted June 26, 1945. 59 Stat. 1031. B. International Criminal Law Statutes ICTY (International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia). Rules of Procedure and Evidence. IT/32/Rev.50. Feb. 11, 1994, last amended July 8, 2015. Available at http://www.icty.org/x/file/Legal%20Library/Rules_procedure_evidence /IT032Rev50_en.pdf. Law on the Establishment of the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia for the Prosecution of Crimes Committed during the Period of Democratic Kampuchea. NS/RKM/0801/12. Aug. 10, 2001, amended Oct. 27, 2004, by NS/ RKM/1004/006. Unofficial English translation available at https://www.eccc.gov.kh /sites/default/files/legal-documents/KR_Law_as_amended_27_Oct_2004_Eng.pdf. Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court. 2187 U.N.T.S. 3. Rome, July 17, 1998. Entered into force July 1, 2002. (Statute of the ICTY). UN Secretary-General. Report of the Secretary-General Pursuant to Paragraph 2 of Security Council Resolution 808 (1993). Annex: Statute of the International Tribunal, 36–48. UN Doc. S/25704. May 3, 1993. Adopted May 25, 1993, by UN Security Council Resolution 827 (1993). Last amended July 7, 2009, by UN Security Council Resolution 1877 (2009). Available as amended at http://www.icty .org/x/file/Legal%20Library/Statute/statute_sept09_en.pdf. (Statute of the ICTR). UN Security Council. Resolution 955 (1994). Annex: Statute of the International Tribunal for Rwanda, 3–15. UN Doc. S/RES/955(1994). Nov. 8, 1994. Last amended Dec. 16, 2009, by UN Security Council Resolution 1901 (2009). Available as amended at http://unictr.irmct.org/sites/unictr.org/files/legal -library/100131_Statute_en_fr_0.pdf. Statute of the Special Court for Sierra Leone. 2178 U.N.T.S. 145. Freetown, Jan. 16, 2002. Entered into force Apr. 12, 2002. UN Transitional Administration in East Timor. Regulation No. 2000/15, On the Establishment of Panels with Exclusive Jurisdiction over Serious Criminal Offenses. June 6, 2000. Available at http://mj.gov.tl/jornal/lawsTL/UNTAET-Law/Regulations%20 English/Reg2000-15.pdf. Bibliography 253 C. UN Resolutions UN General Assembly. Resolution 47/121: The Situation in Bosnia and Herzegovina. UN Doc. A/RES/47/121. Apr. 7, 1993. ———. Resolution 64/289: System-Wide Coherence. UN Doc. A/RES/64/289. July 21, 2010. UN Security Council. Resolution 237 (1967). UN Doc. S/RES/237(1967). June 14, 1967. ———. Resolution 713 (1991). UN Doc. S/RES/713(1991). Sept. 25, 1991. ———. Resolution 743 (1992). UN Doc. S/RES/743(1992). Feb. 21, 1992. ———. Resolution 757 (1992). UN Doc. S/RES/757(1992). May 30, 1992. ———. Resolution 771 (1992). UN Doc. S/RES/771(1992). Aug. 13, 1992. ———. Resolution 780 (1992). UN Doc. S/RES/780(1992). Oct. 6, 1992. ———. Resolution 787 (1992). UN Doc. S/RES/787(1992). Nov. 16, 1992. ———. Resolution 798 (1992). UN Doc. S/RES/798(1992). Dec. 18, 1992. ———. Resolution 808 (1993). UN Doc. S/RES/808(1993). Feb. 22, 1993. ———. Resolution 819 (1993). UN Doc. S/RES/819(1993). Apr. 16, 1993. ———. Resolution 824 (1993). UN Doc. S/RES/824(1993). May 6, 1993. ———. Resolution 827 (1993). UN Doc. S/RES/827(1993). May 25, 1993. ———. Resolution 955 (1994). UN Doc. S/RES/955(1994). Nov. 8, 1994. ———. Resolution 1261 (1999). UN Doc. S/RES/1261(1999). Aug. 30, 1999. ———. Resolution 1265 (1999). UN Doc. S/RES/1265(1999). Sept. 17, 1999. ———. Resolution 1296 (2000). UN Doc. S/RES/1296(2000). Apr. 19, 2000. ———. Resolution 1314 (2000). UN Doc. S/RES/1314(2000). Aug. 11, 2000. ———. Resolution 1325 (2000). UN Doc. S/RES/1325(2000). Oct. 31, 2000. ———. Resolution 1379 (2001). UN Doc. S/RES/1379(2001). Nov. 20, 2001. ———. Resolution 1460 (2003). UN Doc. S/RES/1460(2003). Jan. 30, 2003. ———. Resolution 1539 (2004). UN Doc. S/RES/1539(2004). Apr. 22, 2004. ———. Resolution 1564 (2004). UN Doc. S/RES/1564(2004). Sept. 18, 2004. ———. Resolution 1593 (2005). UN Doc. S/RES/1593(2005). Mar. 31, 2005. ———. Resolution 1612 (2005). UN Doc. S/RES/1612(2005). July 26, 2005. ———. Resolution 1674 (2006). UN Doc. S/RES/1674(2006). Apr. 28, 2006. ———. Resolution 1820 (2008). UN Doc. S/RES/1820(2008). June 19, 2008. ———. Resolution 1882 (2009). UN Doc. S/RES/1882(2009). Aug. 4, 2009. ———. Resolution 1888 (2009). UN Doc. S/RES/1888(2009). Sept. 30, 2009. ———. Resolution 1889 (2009). UN Doc. S/RES/1889(2009). Oct. 5, 2009. ———. Resolution 1894 (2009). UN Doc. S/RES/1894(2009). Nov. 11, 2009. ———. Resolution 1960 (2010). UN Doc. S/RES/1960(2010). Dec. 16, 2010. ———. Resolution 1970 (2011). UN Doc. S/RES/1970(2011). Feb. 26, 2011. ———. Resolution 1973 (2011). UN Doc. S/RES/1973(2011). Mar. 17, 2011. ———. Resolution 1998 (2011). UN Doc. S/RES/1998(2011) July 12, 2011. ———. Resolution 2068 (2012). UN Doc. S/RES/2068(2012). Sept. 19, 2012. ———. Resolution 2106 (2013). UN Doc. S/RES/2106(2013). June 24, 2013. ———. Resolution 2122 (2013). UN Doc. S/RES/2122(2013). Oct. 18, 2013. ———. Resolution 2143 (2014). UN Doc. S/RES/2143(2014). Mar. 7, 2014. 254 Bibliography ———. Resolution 2175 (2014). UN Doc. S/RES/2175(2014). Aug. 29, 2014. ———. Resolution 2225 (2015). UN Doc. S/RES/2225(2015). June 18, 2015. ———. Resolution 2242 (2015). UN Doc. S/RES/2242(2015). Oct. 13, 2015. ———. Resolution 2272 (2016). UN Doc. S/RES/2272(2016). Mar. 11, 2016. ———. Resolution 2331 (2016). UN Doc. S/RES/2331(2016). Dec. 20, 2016. ———. Resolution 2388 (2017). UN Doc. S/RES/2388(2017). Nov. 21, 2017. ———. Resolution 2427 (2018). UN Doc. S/RES/2427(2018). July 9, 2018. ———. Resolution 2467 (2019). UN Doc. S/RES/2467(2019). Apr. 23, 2019. Index Abdela, Lesley, 155–56 abortion, for rape victims, 63, 69–70, 132 Abu Ghraib prison, Iraq, female U.S. soldiers as perpetrators in, 159–60 Additional Protocol I, Geneva Conventions, 174n12, 212n67 Additional Protocol II, Geneva Conventions, 8, 102, 174n11, 203n70, 211n40 Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women, 44–45, 83, 183n120 African Rights (NGO), 104, 159, 209n19 agency, women’s, 152–55; military, 11, 60, 155–60, 171, 229nn13–14; political, 11, 60, 155, 170–71; sexual, 11, 82, 94–98, 161–64, 205nn96, 102 Akayesu, Jean-Paul, 103, 208–9n14 Akayesu, Prosecutor v. (ICTR): amicus brief for, 106, 108–9, 210nn31, 33, 211n46; charges in, 105–7; on coercion as inherent in armed conflict, 215n123; feminist reasoning and, 110–12; ICTR jurisprudence after, 112–16; on rape as genocidal, 103–16, 137, 208–9n14, 210n35 Alien Tort Statute, U.S., 188n34 Allen, Beverly, 61 American Convention on Human Rights, 176n22 amnesties for sexual violence crimes, 15, 143–44, 145, 225nn115–116, 124 Amnesty International (NGO): Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women and, 183n120; claims of systematic rape in Libya and, 75, 76; on Colombian peace process and amnesties for sexual violence crimes, 144–45; NGO Working Group and, 215n1; systematic rape claims in Libya and, 75, 76; on systematic rape in Bosnia, 20; women’s caucus of, 31 anti-colonial feminists, 26, 27, 28. See also Third World feminist critics and their critiques anti-imperialist feminists, 2, 34, 149, 181n68. See also Third World feminist critics and their critiques anti-impunity. See impunity anti-militarist feminists. See women’s peace movement and activism anti-nationalist and non-nationalist feminist groups, in the Yugoslavian conflict, 59, 189n43 anti-war feminists. See women’s peace movement and activism apartheid, 23, 26 Arab League, 193n121 Arendt, Hannah, 175n20 255 256 Index Armanda, Asja, 56 Asian values debate, 29, 31, 33, 179n45 Askin, Kelly, 65–66, 87, 191n85, 214n107 banality of evil, 13, 175n20 Bangura, Zainab, 4, 14, 123, 145–46, 226nn131, 140 Ban Ki-moon, 139, 145, 221n63. See also UN Secretary-General reports Barry, Kathleen, 40, 41, 182n104 al Bashir, Omar Hassan Ahmad, 70, 193n113 Bassiouni, Cherif, 74, 75, 76 Batinić, Jelena, 59, 189n43 Beijing Conference (1995), 27, 32, 33 Beijing Declaration and Platform, 33, 215n1 Bemba, Prosecutor v. (ICC), 205n111 Benard, Cheryl, 66 Benghazi. See Libya Berlant, Lauren, 152 Berlin, Battle of. See A Woman in Berlin Bernstein, Elizabeth, 13, 177n3 best practices manuals on sexual violence prosecution, 117–10, 120 Bianchi, Linda, 112, 117, 119, 212nn68–69, 213n96, 214n103 Bosnia and Herzegovina: claims of femicide in, 56; claims of gynocide in, 55, 61; ethnically mixed relationships before war in, 64, 65, 66, 95, 97, 205–6nn112–113; feeling Yugoslav in, 97, 206n116; mainstream responses to wartime rape in, 20–21; UN Action video (2007) on sexual violence in, 137–39, 138 (figure), 223nn83–4; UN Protection Force in, 51–52; Vienna Conference participation by women from, 43; Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action on violence against women in, 19; women on both sides of war in, 158. See also ICTY Bosnian Muslims: cultural and religious assumptions about, 56, 62, 64–65, 66, 192n98; on ICTY as biased against their ethnicity, 198n15; post-Kunarac indictments and convictions of, 201–2n54; rape charges and judgment against, 86–88; rapes by Serbs or Croats compared with rapes by, 43; response of religious leaders to rape, 65, 191n82 Bosnian Muslim women: as combatants, 69, 155; Croatian press on rape effects on, 67–68; ethnicity of children of rapes by Serbs of, 64–65, 108, 111, 190n75; feminist disagreements on labelling rapes of, 55–56, 61; ICTY on sexual consent by, 94–98, 205nn96, 102, 205–6nn111–114; media representations of rape of, 50, 185n1; medica mondiale on rape effects on, 68; raped, estimating number of children born to, 190–91n79; as “raped women,” 67–69, 151, 152 Boutros-Ghali, Boutros, 180n62. See also UN Secretary-General reports boys: in Rome Statute, 135–36; as sexual violence targets, 2, 48, 82; in UN Security Council Resolutions, 124, 133–34, 221nn63–4, 75; video on sexual violence in conflict treatment of, 5, 11, 100. See also children; gender-neutral language; men Brđanin, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 89, 91 Broadbent, Ed, 39 Brownmiller, Susan, 58 Brustin, Stacy, 180n51 Bunch, Charlotte: Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women and, 45; Center for Women’s Global Leadership and, 29; on female sexual slavery, 182–83n105; at Harvard Human Rights Program conference (1988), 179–80n51; on non-aligned feminism, 183n109; sexual subordina- Index tion as focus for, 42; on socioeconomic violations against women, 35; as structural-bias feminist, 24; on transformative approach to human rights, 40; on VAW as clearer avenue for activism, 36; on war crimes against women at Vienna Tribunal, 38–39; on women’s caucuses within human rights organizations, 31; on “Women’s Rights Are Human Rights,” 30 Bush, George H. W., administration of, 53, 186n16 Bush, George W., administration of, 194n125 Buss, Doris, 112, 114 capital punishment, ICTR and, 102 carceral feminism, 13, 14, 20, 44–45, 141–44, 177n3 Carpenter, Charli, 63–64 Castley, Shirley, 42, 182–83n105. See also Bunch, Charlotte Čelebići (Prosecutor v. Mucić et al.) (ICTY), 86–87, 92, 202n59, 203n72, 206n117 Center for Constitutional Rights, 106 Center for Reproductive Policy and Law, 183n120 Center for Women’s Global Leadership, Rutgers University, 29, 32, 34, 35–36, 45. See also Global Tribunal on Violations of Women’s Human Rights Češić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 92 Ćetković, Nadežda, 61 Chappell, Louise, 201n53 Chapter VII of the UN Charter: ICTR establishment under, 101, 207n2; ICTY establishment under, 62, 80; intervention power and, 21, 52, 62, 177n10, 186n9 Charlesworth, Hilary, 26, 111–12, 178nn19, 21, 212n67 children: amnesties for crimes against, 257 225nn115–116; in armed conflict, Human Security Network on, 125; criminal laws against labor by or sexual abuse of, 42; forcibly transferred to another group, as genocidal, 63–64, 190n75; and women, as stand-in for “civilian,” 220n54; WPS resolutions on human security and, 126, 127 (table), 128, 132–33, 217n19, 221n67. See also boys; gender-neutral language; girls China, Security Council resolutions (2019) and, 131–32 Chinkin, Christine, 26, 141, 149, 224n111 civilians: UN peacekeeping forces abuses of, 130, 219n54; in war, roles of, 163–64; “women and children” as stand-in for, 220n54; WPS resolutions on human security and, 126, 127 (table), 128, 221n67. See also boys; children; girls; women Clinton, Bill, administration of, 54 Clinton, Hillary Rodham, 10, 71–72, 75, 193nn119, 121 Clooney, Amal, 142, 169 Cmiel, Kenneth, 78 Coalition on Women’s Human Rights in Conflict Situations, 105, 106 coercion: prostitution and, 40; sexual violence in conflict and, 94–96, 215n123; World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights on, 41–42. See also consent, as a defense to charges of rape and sexual violence Cold War, 21, 22, 52–53, 124 Colombia, Legal Framework for Peace (2012), amnesties included in, 144 colonialism, 19, 23, 26–28, 42, 197n166. See also Third World feminist critics and their critiques comfort women, during World War II, 38, 182n93 command responsibility, 208–9n14; 211n40 258 Index Commission of Experts’ reports on former Yugoslavia, 80 Commission of Experts’ reports on Rwanda, 102, 104–5, 108–9 Committee for Review of the Prosecution of Sexual Violence, 117 common Article 3, Geneva Conventions: on humiliating and degrading treatment, 91; ICTR and, 102; ICTY and, 84, 102, 199n26 conflict-related sexual violence. See sexual violence in conflict Congo, Democratic Republic of, 137 consent, as a defense to charges of rape and sexual violence: best practices manuals on, 119; feminist approaches to, 65, 85, 188n37, 205n96; ICC on, 160, 205n111, 215n123; ICTR on, 119, 160, 215n123; ICTY on, 85, 94–96, 160, 204n95, 205n96 Control Council Law No. 10, 198– 99nn19–20 Cook, Rebecca, 31 Copelon, Rhonda: Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women and, 45; on Akayesu, 106, 110–11; charges against Karadžić and, 106, 210n30; on gender violence as Vienna Conference topic, 43; on genocide claims in rape cases, 188n34; on including acts committed on the basis of gender in persecution, 90; on omission of “rape” from ICTY statute, 83; rape-on-all-sides position and, 44, 58, 107–8, 189n42; on shifting stigma from survivors to perpetrators, 174–75n13 Copenhagen Conference (1980), 23 Cossman, Brenda, 180n51 Costa Rica, on sexual violence in conflict, 217n21 counterterrorism: MacKinnon on, 77–78, 147; mobilizing, 172; Security Council trafficking resolutions and, 130–31; use of sexual violence to call for, 151–52, 154, 172; women’s participation in, 130, 146; WPS agenda and, 149–50. See also extremist groups and extremism; terrorists and terrorism crimes against humanity: amicus brief for Akayesu on, 108; al Bashir charged with, 193n113; definition of, 83, 198–99n19; enslavement as, 84, 87; ethnic essentialism and, 9, 82, 88–90, 95–97; ICTR on rape and sexual violence as, 103, 107, 113, 114, 211n40; ICTR statute on rape as, 102; ICTY on rape and sexual violence as, 82, 84, 87–90, 200–201n42; ICTY statute on rape as, 83; persecution as, 88–90, 202nn61–62, 203n70; relationship to genocide, 89, 105; torture as, 90. See also enslavement; international humanitarian law; persecution; torture criminal law. See impunity; international criminal law Croatia, 20, 51–52, 67–68 Croatian women, 55–56, 61 Croats, 43, 87, 88, 198n15, 201–2n54 cultural essentialism. See ethnic essentialism culturally sensitive universalism, 20, 32–34, 43, 180n62 culture: Asian values debates about, 29, 33, 179n45; call for sensitivity to in investigating sexual violence, 118; combating VAW as mediation of debates about, 35–36; of impunity, 46, 142–43, 148, 224n109; Muslim and Islamic, assumptions about, 65–67, 76; military intervention supported by representations of, 78; structural bias feminist treatment of, 25–26; Third World feminist critics on structural-bias feminist assumptions about, 27–28, 178n30; Western, critiques of, 28, 30. See also culturally sensitive universalism; ethnic essentialism; traditional and religious community leaders Index customary international law, 83, 84, 198n17, 199nn20, 21, 26 Da’esh. See ISIL Darfur, 70, 137, 192–93n112 de Brouwer, Anne-Marie, 204n78 Declaration of Commitment to End Sexual Violence in Conflict (UN), 4, 14, 173n6 Declaration on Preventing Sexual Violence in Conflict, Group of Eight, 4, 14, 15 Delalić, Zejnil, 201n43 Delić, Hazim, 201n43 deterrence: criminal law and, 14–15, 142–43, 145, 147–48, 176n27 development. See economic development Diaz Dennis, Patricia, 54 Dieng, Adama, 145 dignity, 8, 42, 92, 102, 153, 175n21, 191n87. See also honor; outrages upon personal dignity; shame and stigma discrimination and discriminatory intent, crime of persecution and, 89 domestic violence, 13, 40, 42, 45–46. See also sexual abuse “Don’t believe the thumbnail, this video is the stuff of nightmares”. See video (UK Foreign and Commonwealth Office, 2014) Dowd, Maureen, 72 dowry deaths, 25–26, 40, 178n30 Drakulić, Slavenka, 68 due process: lack of testimony and, 77; targeted sanctions against sexual violence and, 149, 227n151; victim shame in testifying and, 93, 101, 107, 116 Dworkin, Andrea, 56 economic and social rights: Asian values and, 29; feminist approaches to, 23, 24, 35, 38, 41, 42 economic development: economic 259 empowerment, women and, 129; right to, 29; rise of human rights advocacy and decreased attention to, 36–37, 37 (figure); sexual violence in conflict and, 139; UN World Conferences on Women and, 23, 29, 35; at Vienna Conference, 29, 31; violence against women and, 34–35, 36–37; WID, WAD, and GAD, 177n14 economic maldistribution: feminist approaches to, 2, 17, 26–28, 34, 39, 42; Global Tribunal and, 38, 39; issue displaced by focus on sexual violence in conflict, 2, 39, 151, 183n114; NIEO and, 26. See also Third World feminist critics and their critiques Effange-Mbella, Elsie, 118 Ehrenreich, Barbara, 159–60 enslavement: rape or sexual violence as, 84, 87. See also crimes against humanity; sexual slavery Enzensberger, Hans Magnus, 164 ethnically mixed relationships, in Bosnia, 64, 65, 66, 95, 97, 205–6nn112–113 ethnic cleansing: in Bosnia and Croatia and, 20; first Security Council resolution on, 186n7; in the former Yugoslavia, 80, 81, 197n3; as form of genocide, 52, 186n10; ICTY’s Kunarac decision on, 87–88; R2P on military intervention against, 55; U.S. on genocide in Bosnia vs., 53 ethnic essentialism: decline of critical feminist theories on, 78; ICTY and, 82, 88–90, 94–97; shame and, 9, 48; structural bias feminism and, 28, 56, 62–67, 82; Third World feminist critiques of cultural and, 27–28, 178n130. See also culture; shame and stigma ethnicity: centrality to crime of persecution (ICTY), 89–90; and consent in crimes against humanity (ICTY), 95–98; to distinguish genocidal rape 260 Index in former Yugoslavia, 51, 57–58; and genocide definition, 63, 107; and genocide in Rwanda (ICTR), 110–11; of offspring of inter-ethnic rapes in Yugoslavian conflict, 64–65, 108, 111, 190n75. See also Bosnian Muslims; Croats; culture; Hutus; Serbs; Tutsis European Council, 20, 177n7 evil. See banality of evil ex post facto law, ICTY statute on crimes against humanity and, 83 extremist groups and extremism: research on women’s participation in countering, 150; Resolution 2242 on countering, 147, 149, 228n160; sexual violence and, 79; traditional and religious leaders and shifting shame from victims to, 146; UN Women on countering strategies for, 130. See also counterterrorism; terrorists and terrorism Facio, Alda, 30 Feimster, Crystal, 174n10 female genital mutilation, 25–26, 40, 178n30, 179n41 female sexual slavery. See sexual slavery female subordination, 24, 98, 100. See also sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism; structuralbias feminists femicide, 56 feminists and feminisms: anti-war feminists, 18, 86, 149; carceral feminism, 13, 14, 20, 177n3; debates over meaning of rape in Yugoslavian conflict, 55–70; on genocidal rape in Akayesu, 110–12; governance feminism, 14, 185n140; liberal inclusion feminist approaches to international human rights and, 22–23; nationalist, anti-nationalist, and non-nationalist, in the Yugoslavian conflict, 59, 189n43; on rape as genocidal, 63–64; sex-positive feminists, 2, 18, 19, 40–42, 86; Vienna Conference organizing by, 29–32. See also structural-bias feminists; Third World feminist critics and their critiques; women’s human rights movement; women’s peace movement and activism Foča region, Bosnia. See Čelebići Folnegović-Šmalc, Vera, 69–70 For Whom the Bell Tolls (Hemingway): on fighting back against sexual assault attackers, 162–63; positive function of shame in, 170, 171; sexuality and conflict intertwined in, 161–62; sexual violence in conflict in, 16–17; on Spanish Civil War, 152–53; A Woman in Berlin compared with, 165; women as combatants in, 156, 157–58, 229nn13–14 Franke, Katherine M., 200n30 Fraser, Arvonne, 31, 35 Fund for a Feminist Majority, 183n120 Furundžija, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 87, 92, 99 GABRIELA (anti-Marcos women’s coalition), 30 Gacumbitsi, Prosecutor v. (ICTR), 114 Gaddafi, Mohammar, 70–71, 72, 73, 74–75. See also Libya Gardam, Judith, 175n21 gender: Genocide Convention and, 63; male sexual dominance as central to oppression on the basis of, 2, 24; not as part of the definition of genocide, 63, 111; as part of the definition of persecution as a crime against humanity, 90, 203n70; as structuring category of power for structural-bias feminists, 12, 19, 25, 28, 40, 51 gender-based violence: move to focus on conflict-related sexual violence instead of, 23, 82, 100, 124, 134–36, 221n67, 221–22n70, 222n73; sexual violence as paradigm, feminists on, 12, 42. See also Index sexual violence in conflict; violence against women gender-neutral language, 11, 22–23, 99, 132–34, 220n59 Geneva Conventions: Additional Protocol I, 174n12, 212n67; Additional Protocol II, 8, 102, 174n11, 203n70, 211n40; common Article 3 and ICTR, 102, 207n2, 211n40; common Article 3 and ICTY, 84, 102, 199n26; common Article 3 on humiliating and degrading treatment, 91; Fourth (1949), on rape, 8; Hague on rape and sexual violence as violations of, 4 genocidal rape: amicus brief for Akayesu finding of, 108–9, 210nn31, 33, 211n46; of Croats, 188n33; ethnic essentialism assumptions and, 62–67; feminist debates in former Yugoslavia over, 55–70; feminist debates in former Yugoslavia versus Rwanda over, 103; ICTR on, 8–9, 101, 107, 112; ICTY on, 82, 87–88, 200n29, 201n52; multiple understandings of, 62–67; in relationship to Darfur, 70, 137, 192–93n112; in Rwanda, Commission of Experts on, 104–5. See also military interventions genocidal-rape position, rape-on-allsides position versus, 56–62, 86, 189n42 genocide: al Bashir charged with, 193n113; as basis for military intervention, 53–55, 70; Commission of Experts on Genocide Convention violations in the former Yugoslavia, 80; Genocide Convention, 54, 62–65, 80, 84, 105, 110; ICTR convictions for, 101; ICTY charges of, 88; intent requirement, 8–9, 63; persecution as a crime against humanity relationship to, 89; relationship of ethnic cleansing to, 52–54; statutory defnitions, 62–63, 84, 102, 107; 261 UN’s failure to prevent, in Rwanda, 55. See also genocidal rape; international humanitarian law Georgetown Institute for Women, Peace and Security, 148, 149 Germany: Security Council resolutions and, 131–32, 134, 142; A Woman in Berlin publication in, 164. See also A Woman in Berlin Gerntholtz, Liesl, 196n143 Ginn, Courtney, 204n88 girls: in armed conflict, Resolution 1325 protection measures for, 122; armed conflict and, Human Security Network and resolutions on, 125; human rights organizations on abuses against, 31; sexual violence in conflict against, 2, 48, 221n63; as sexual violence targets, WPS agenda on, 124; UN Action video (2007) on sexual violence and, 138; UN Resolutions on protection of, 133; video on sexual violence in conflict treatment of, 5, 11–12, 100; vulnerability to sexual slavery of, 42. See also children; gender-neutral language Global Campaign for Women’s Human Rights, 29 Global Network of Women Peacebuilders, 140 global North, 22–23, 26–27, 34 global South, 17, 22–23, 28, 34. See also Third World feminist critics and their critiques Global Summit on Sexual Violence in Conflict (2014), 3–7, 6 (figure), 9, 123 Global Tribunal on Violations of Women’s Human Rights (Vienna 1993), 32, 34–35, 38–39, 43, 182n93 Goffman, Erving, 117 Goldberg, Suzanne, 180n51 Goldstone, Richard, 84–85 governance feminism, 14, 185n140 grave breaches, 4, 86, 108, 199n25, 262 Index 200n42. See also international humanitarian law; war crimes Group of Eight (G8), 4, 14, 15, 47 Gruber, Aya, 45 Gutman, Roy, 68, 192n98 Hadžihasanović et al., Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 201n44 Hague, William, 4, 9, 14, 123, 143 Hague Appeal for Peace, 215n1 Halley, Janet: on delinking honor and dignity from sexual offenses, 102; on feminists and Rome Statute drafting, 47, 87–88, 91, 184nn135–136, 203n70; on governance feminism, 14, 185n140; on meaning of literary narratives, 154; on structural-bias feminism and international criminal law, 185n140; on A Woman in Berlin, 154, 164, 228n6 Hamzić, Vanja, 206n115 Harvard Human Rights Program, “Women’s Human Rights: Possibilities and Contradictions” (1988), 30–31, 179–80n51 Heathcote, Gina, 146, 148, 149 Helsinki Watch (NGO), 198n10 Hemingway, Ernest, 153–54, 228n8, 229n14. See also For Whom the Bell Tolls Henry, Nicola, 204n88 Herzegovina. See Bosnia and Herzegovina heterosexuality and heteronormativity. See sexuality Hill, Felicity, 122, 124–25, 227n157 Holocaust, 61–62, 94 homophobia, stigma of sexual violence against a man and, 12, 175n19 homosexuality. See men; sexuality Honduras, inaction on disappearance of political activist in, 46, 184n133 honor: chastity and, 66, 92; of communities, 76, 77, 146; connection between sexual offenses and, 91–92, 102; For Whom the Bell Tolls on, 163; Murad on, 165, 167; rape as attack on, 8, 104, 109, 112, 175n21. See also shame and stigma humanitarian law. See international humanitarian law human rights. See human rights law; human rights NGOs; international human rights law and discourse; NGO Working Group; Vienna Conference; women’s human rights movement Human Rights Council, 53, 74, 75–76, 195n137 human rights hawks, 53, 54, 70, 72, 186n13, 194n124 human rights law. See international human rights law and discourse human rights NGOs, 29, 31, 37, 78. See also specific NGOs Human Rights Watch, 31, 109, 183n120, 196nn143, 151, 210n25. See also Helsinki Watch human security agenda, 126, 127 (table), 128, 132–33, 217n19, 221n67 Human Security Network, 125, 216n10, 217n15 humiliating and degrading treatment: Akayesu charges citing, 106, 110; ICTR’s Musema decision on, 113; ICTR statute on rape as, 102–3; ICTY on rape and sexual violence as, 84, 91–92, 199n25. See also outrages upon personal dignity; shame and stigma; war crimes humiliation. See shame and stigma Husak, Douglas, 98 Hutu Interahamwe (paramilitary organization), 105, 110, 114 Hutus, 103, 108, 109–10, 114, 211n54, 228n4. See also ICTR; Rwanda Ibárruri Gómez, Dolores, 156, 228n12 ICC (International Criminal Court): Index al Bashir warrant for arrest by, 70, 193n113; Bemba, Prosecutor v., 205n111; Darfur genocide case referred to, 70; establishment of, 44, 46–47, 81–82, 198n10; feminists on gender justice failures by, 201n53; on lack of consent and rape, 160, 205n11; Libyan human rights violations referred to, 71, 75, 197n161; on victims, 170, 176n27. See also Rome Statute ICTR (International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda): best practices manuals on sexual violence prosecution by, 117–10, 120; capital punishment and, 102; convictions for rape and sexual violence by, 103, 209nn16, 17; doctrinal function of shame and, 104–16; establishment of, 44, 81, 101–2, 207n2, 208nn5–6; mandate for, 101; on rape or sexual violence as genocide, 84; on redistribution of shame, 120–21; remaining duties of, MICT and, 198n13; as response after genocide occurred, 102; as response to rape and sexual violence, 16; on shame and stigma of rape, 8–9; shame as prosecutorial alibi and, 116–19; structural-bias feminists and, 47; witness testimony alternatives for, 76; women charged by, 158, 229n27 ICTR cases (International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda): Akayesu, Prosecutor v., 103–16, 137, 208–9n14, 209n24, 210n26; Gacumbitsi, Prosecutor v., 114; Musema, Prosecutor v., 113, 212nn72, 75; Nyiramasuhuko et al., Prosecutor v., 114, 229n29; Rukundo, Prosecutor v., 114–15 ICTY (International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia): Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women and, 45; convictions for rape and sexual violence 263 by, 103, 209n16; criminalizing sexual agency and ethnic difference, 94–98, 205nn96, 102, 205–6nn111–114; establishment of, 20–21, 80–81, 184n135, 197–98nn5–6; feminist engagement in statute and rules of, 83–86, 200nn40–41; jurisdiction of, 199n21; male victims sexual violence and, 98–100, 200n30; mediation of feminist disagreements during, 86–90; pressure for U.S. military intervention prior to establishment of, 54; remaining duties of, MICT and, 198n13; as response to rape and sexual violence, 16, 44, 90–94, 199n25; on sexual injury, 124; solidifying the common sense on rape and sexual violence, 90–98; women charged by, 158, 229nn27–28 ICTY cases: Brđanin, Prosecutor v., 89, 91; Čelebići (Prosecutor v. Mucić et al.), 86–87, 92, 202n59, 203n72, 206n117; Češić, Prosecutor v., 92; Furundžija, Prosecutor v., 87, 92, 99; Hadžihasanović et al., Prosecutor v., 201n44; Karadžić, Prosecutor v., 200n29; Karadžić and Mladić, Prosecutor v., 202n55; Kunarac et al., Prosecutor v., 87–88, 90–91, 94–96, 201nn48, 52, 205n102; Kupreškić, Prosecutor v., 202n60; Kvočka et al., Prosecutor v., 91, 97; Nikolić, Prosecutor v., 93; Simić, Tadić and Zarić, Prosecutor v., 91; Stakić, Prosecutor v., 91; Tadić, Prosecutor v., 97, 198n17 imperialism. See anti-imperialist feminists; colonialism impunity: “culture of,” 46, 142–43, 148, 224n109; as precluding peace, 15, 225nn124, 125; use of sanctions in addressing sexual violence in conflict and, 148, 227nn147, 150; Vienna Declaration on, 44, 47; WPS agenda on, 141–43, 145–47, 223n97, 225n124 264 Index indecent assaults, 8, 102, 106, 174n12 Interahamwe, Hutu, 105, 110, 114 Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, 92, 176n22 Inter-American Court of Human Rights, 46 International Alert, 123, 215n1 International Commission of Inquiry, alleged Libyan violations of international human rights law and, 74, 75–76 International Commission of Inquiry on Darfur, 192–93n112 International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, 187n22 International Committee for Prostitutes’ Rights (ICPR), 41 international criminal law: Chapter VII of the UN Charter and, 62, 80, 81, 83, 101, 207n2; common sense about sexual violence in conflict and, 12–15, 82–83; feminists and emergence of, 13–14, 21–22, 39, 44–47, 140–47; Vienna Tribunal and development of, 32. See also ICTR; ICTY; impunity; international humanitarian law International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda. See ICTR International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY). See ICTY International Day of Violence against Women (November 25), 34 international humanitarian law: customary international law and, 199n20; early feminist consideration of, 175n21; early treatment of rape under, 8, 174n10; human security and WPS resolutions related to, 126, 127 (table); ICTR establishment and, 101; ICTY establishment and, 20–21, 80–81; NGO Working Group and, 125; relationship to human rights law, 13, 199n20; Vienna Conference and, 37–38. See also crimes against humanity; Geneva Conventions; genocide; grave breaches; international criminal law; war crimes International Human Rights Day (December 10), 34 international human rights law and discourse: in decision by ICTY, 92; in decision by Inter-American Court of Human Rights, 46; feminist liberal inclusion approaches to, 23; feminists and emergence of, 13, 21–22, 177n11; relationship to international humanitarian law, 13, 199n20; structural-bias critiques of, 23–26; Third World feminist critiques and, 26; turn to criminal law in, 13–14, 44–47, 140–47; Vienna Conference and, 28–44; violence against women and, 34–37. See also women’s human rights movement International Law Commission, 44 International Residual Mechanism for Criminal Tribunals (MICT), 198n13 International Women’s Human Rights Clinic, 106 Iraq invasions, 78, 227n157 ISIL (‘Islamic State of Iraq and the Levant’): Murad on women in, 158; Murad’s captivity by, 16; Murad’s narrative of, 167, 168–70; seizing Murad’s village, 230n58; slavery and sexual slavery by, 130, 165–66. See also Murad, Nadia Islamic law, 64–66 Joachim, Jutta, 46 Jolie, Angelina, 4, 10, 15, 123, 143, 145 journalists, 50, 68, 154, 185n1 Kadic v. Karadžić, 57, 106, 188n34 Kahan, Dan, 215n130 Kapur, Ratna, 27, 189n51 Karadžić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 200n29 Index Karadžić, Radovan, 57, 106, 188n34, 202n55, 210n30 Karadžić and Mladić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 202n55 Karemera et al., Prosecutor v. (ICTR), 113 Kareta (organization), 56, 59, 60 Keck, Margaret, 36 Kendall, Sara, 170, 175n13 Kennedy, David, 173n2 Kesić, Obrad, 59 Khushalani, Yougindra, 175n21 Kinsella, Helen, 10 Koh, Harold, 194n123 Kosovars, post-Kunarac indictments and convictions of, 201–2n54 Kosovo, 55, 81, 186n11. See also Yugoslavia, former Kovač, Radomir, 87, 201n48 Kristof, Nicholas, 73, 194–95n128 Kunarac et al., Prosecutor v. (ICTY): charges in, 87–88, 90–91, 201n52, 203–4n78; consent as element of rape and, 94–96, 205n102; convictions in, 201n48; sexual agency and ethnic difference in, 94–96, 205nn96, 102 Kupreškić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 202n60 Kvočka et al., Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 91, 97 land mines, Human Security Network on, 125 language. See gender-neutral language The Last Girl (Murad): on Murad’s ISIS captivity, 16–17, 153, 158, 165–66; time covered in, 230n58; A Woman in Berlin compared with, 165, 166. See also Murad, Nadia Legal Advisor for Gender Related Crimes, ICTY’s, 85. See also Viseur Sellers, Patricia Lewis, Chloé, 221n63 liberal inclusion feminist approaches to international human rights, 22–23 Libya, 70–77, 187n22, 194–95nn127–128; 265 Arab Jamahiriya, Security Council response to human rights violations in, 70–71. See also Gaddafi, Mohammar Lieber Code, 174n10 Lines, Lisa, 156 literary narratives: context of war foregrounded in, 168–70; countering common sense narratives with, 9–10, 171–72; legal, advocacy, policy, or journalistic narratives compared with, 154; structuring language for understanding rape and other violence in war with, 154 Lizza, Ryan, 194n124 Lowbwein, Wendy, 204n88 Lysistrata, fictional letter to, 60, 155 MacKinnon, Catharine: on distinguishing rape from everyday sex, 188n37; as lawyer in lawsuit against Karadžić, 57, 106, 188n34, 210n30; on military intervention to address violence against women, 77, 79, 147, 197nn165–166; as Moreno-Ocampo’s special advisor on gender, 73; on pornography, 187n31; on sexual violence against men, 98–99, 175n18, 178n26, 207n130; “On Torture” lecture (1990) by, 25, 187n26; on the Yugoslavian conflict, 43–44, 56–57, 58, 61 male domination, 24, 26, 28, 98, 100. See also men; patriarchal societies; patriarchy; structural-bias feminists Martin, Dianne, 45–46 mass rape. See systematic rape McDonald, Gabrielle Kirk, 85 media. See journalists medica mondiale, 68, 69, 192n98, 219n50 men: opposing military intervention in Libya, 72; sexual violence in conflict against, 2, 14, 48, 99, 135–36, 175n19, 178n26, 221nn63–4; structural-bias 266 Index feminists on sexual violence against, 24, 40, 99, 175n18, 178n26; victimization of women versus, 93–94; as victims of sexual violence, ICTY on, 82–83, 98–100, 207n128, 208n13; video on sexual violence in conflict treatment of, 5, 11, 100; Vienna Conference and, 31; WPS agenda on sexual violence against, 124, 133–34. See also male domination; perpetrators Merchán, Sylke, 65, 66, 190n75, 191n83 Meron, Theodor, 81, 175–76n22, 199n20 Mexico City Conference (1975), 23 Mezey, Gillian, 93 military interventions: after end of the Cold War, 22, 51–55; crisis governance and, 77–79; Darfur and calls for, 70, 192n112; finding rape in Libya and, 70–77; genocidal rape position and ethnic essentialism, 62–67; genocidal rape versus rape-on-all sides in former Yugoslavia and, 56–70; in Kosovo by NATO without Security Council authorization, 55; R2P and, 55, 70, 71, 187n22; as response to rape and sexual violence, 3, 16, 61, 152, 189n57. See also genocidal rape; human rights hawks Miller, Alice, 37, 39, 48 Mladić, Ratko, 202n55 Mlambo-Ngcuka, Phumzile, 129 Mohammed, Amina J., 142 Mohammed, Yanar, 150 Moreno-Ocampo, Luis, 73, 74–75, 76–77, 119 Moscow Declaration, 198–99n19 Moyn, Samuel, 177n11 Ms. Foundation for Women, 183n120 Mucić, Zdravko, 201n43 Muna, Maha, 122, 124–25 Murad, Nadia: on effect of U.S. sanctions on Iraq, 169; Last Girl memoir on ISIS captivity of, 16–17, 153, 158, 165–66; on Resolution 2331, 130, 169; and Resolution 2467 debate, 142, 231n83; on talking about everything, 152, 167, 168; time covered in memoir by, 230n58 Musema, Prosecutor v. (ICTR), 113, 212nn72, 75 Muslim communities. See Bosnian Muslims; traditional and religious community leaders nacija concept, in Bosnia, 97, 206nn113– 114 nacionalnost concept, in Bosnia, 97, 206n114 Nairobi Conference (1985): inclusion of women in development programs and, 23; NGO Forum and, 35; Peace Tent at, 35, 181n78, 216n9; VAW discourse and, 37, 181n73 Nairobi Forward-looking Strategies, 35, 37 naming and shaming, 13, 120–21, 145, 148–49, 215n129. See also shame and stigma nationalist feminist groups in the Yugoslavian conflict, 59, 189n43 NATO, 52, 55 Nenadic, Natalie, 56 Nesiah, Vasuki, 27, 149, 150, 185n139 New International Economic Order (NIEO), 26, 179n33 NGO Forum (1985), Nairobi Conference and, 35 NGOs. See human rights NGOs NGO Working Group (NGO Working Group on Women, Peace and Security), 122, 123, 125, 128, 215n1, 217n15 Ní Aoláin, Fionnuala, 85, 94, 150, 199n20, 228n160 Nikolić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 93 no-fly zone, for Libya, 71, 193nn119, 121 non-state actors, 25, 31, 46, 126, 148, 184n133. See also human rights NGOs; private sphere; terrorists and terrorism Index Nouwen, Sarah, 170, 175n13 Nowrojee, Binaifer, 109, 112, 116, 120 Nuremberg, International Military Tribunal at, 83 Nyiramasuhuko et al., Prosecutor v. (ICTR), 114, 159, 229n29 Obama, Barack, administration of, 71–73, 74, 193nn19, 123–124, 195n34 al-Obeidi, Eman, 72–73, 74, 194– 95nn127–128 Obiora, Leslye, 27, 28, 33 Obote-Odora, Alex, 117, 120 Office of the Prosecutor (OTP), ICTR’s, 116, 117–18. See also ICTR cases Office of the Prosecutor (OTP), ICTY’s, 84–85, 86–88, 99, 207n2. See also ICTY cases off our backs, 60–61 Omarska concentration camp, Bosnia, 93–94 Omerbašić, Ševko, 65, 191n82 Ong, Aihwa, 27, 28 Oosterveld, Valerie, 87, 99 Operation Deliberate Force, 52, 55, 185n6 ostracism. See shame and stigma Otto, Dianne: on culturally sensitive universalism, 33; on governance feminism, 14, 185n140; on Resolution 1325 and WPS agenda, 150, 216n4; on Resolution 1820, 149, 220n57 outrages upon personal dignity: Additional Protocol II, on rape as, 8, 102; ICTR statute and, 102–3, 106, 208n7; ICTY and, 84, 87, 90, 91–92, 102–3, 199nn25, 26, 203n78; rape and sexual violence as, 8, 91–92, 102–3, 203–4n78; Rome Statue’s delinking of rape and, 91, 102 Palestine, 38, 66 patriarchal societies, 66, 111 patriarchy, 23, 139, 178n19, 216n9. See also male domination 267 Patten, Pramila, 143, 224n112 peace: lasting, criminal justice and, 15, 118, 144–45, 225n124; sexual violence as preventing, 3–7, 15, 126–28, 174n8, 217n22; UN Resolutions on women building, 11, 123–25, 127 (table), 128, 129, 130. See also women’s peace movement and activism Peace Tent, at Nairobi Conference, 35, 181n78, 216n9 perpetrators: common sense about, 2, 82–83; emphasis on individual criminal accountability for, 4, 45, 82, 83, 120, 141, 198n14; men as, 2, 3, 10–12, 14, 98–99; naming and shaming of, 120–21, 123–24, 128, 145, 219n9; shifting shame and stigma from victim to, 9, 92–93, 120–21, 145–47, 170–71, 192n110; women as, 10, 98, 99, 158–60 persecution: based on gender, 90, 189n42, 203n70; discriminatory intent required for, 89, 202nn61–62; ethnic essentialism and, 88–90, 95; ICTY on rape and sexual violence as, 83–84, 88–90; as mediating feminist debates over genocidal rape, 89–90; Plavšić accused of, 99, 159; Rome Statute on rape and sexual violence as, 90, 203n70. See also crimes against humanity Pheterson, Gail, 41 Pillay, Navanethem (“Navi”), 44, 105–6, 210n29, 214n103 Plavšić, Biljana, 99, 156, 206–7nn124–125, 229n28 political agency: of Croatian and Serbian women, 60; A Woman in Berlin on, 170–71; women in war and, 11, 155–60 pornography, 2, 25, 40, 42, 56, 187n31 Power, Samantha, 53, 54, 71–72, 193n119 pregnancy, forced, 19, 38, 43, 87–88, 209n21. See also genocidal rape; rape Preventing Sexual Violence Initiative (PSVI), 4, 143 268 Index private sphere, 25, 28, 31, 77. See also public/private distinction prosecutorial discretion, 98 prostitution. See sex work public/private distinction, 24–25, 46, 178nn21, 25. See also private sphere Quindlen, Anna, 55, 61–62 R2P (Responsibility to Protect), 55, 70, 71, 187n22. See also military interventions racism, 26, 29, 42. See also colonialism rape. See genocidal rape; ICC; ICTR; ICTY; sexual violence in conflict; shame and stigma; systematic rape Reagan, Ronald, administration of, 45 Reagan-Gorbachev Summit Meetings in Reykjavik (1986), women’s voices at, 216n9 Rees, Madeleine, 141, 223–24n100, 224nn103, 111 Reilly, Niamh, 31, 35, 37–38, 219n49 religious leaders. See traditional and religious community leaders reproduction, 51, 108, 111. See also pregnancy, forced Republika Srpska, 99, 159 Responsibility to Protect (R2P), 55, 70, 71, 187n22. See also military interventions revenge: sexual violence attacks as trigger for, 217n21; sought by raped Bosnian Muslim women, 69–70 Rhodes, Ben, 193n119 Rice, Susan, 71–72, 73, 193n119 Robinson, Darryl, 98 Rome Statute: feminists and drafting of, 47, 87–88, 91, 102, 136, 184nn135–136, 203n70; ICTR statute and drafting of, 102–3; on persecution and gender, 90, 203n70; on sexual slavery, 47, 87–88, 201n50; on sexual violence crimes, 47, 87–88. See also ICC Roth, Kenneth, 120, 186n13 Rovera, Donatella, 75 Ruby, Felicity (formerly Felicity Hill), 122, 124–25, 227n157 Rukundo, Prosecutor v. (ICTR), 114–15 Rule 34, ICTY’s, Victims and Witnesses Unit established under, 85 Rule 96, ICTY’s, on sexual assault victim’s testimony, 85, 94, 98, 204nn94–96 Russia: Germany on WPS resolutions and, 131–32, 217n18; rapes by soldiers in Berlin from, 163–64, 167. See also A Woman in Berlin Rwanda, 55, 71, 137–39, 158–59. See also ICTR Rwandan Patriotic Front, 115 sanctions, targeting sexual violence, 148–49, 150–51, 227n147 Sand Creek Massacre, 174n10 Sander, Helke, 60, 155 Scott, Joan, 17 Scowcroft, Brent, 53, 54 Sells, Michael, 206n116 September 11 attacks, counterterrorism strategy after, WPS agenda and, 149 Serbian feminists, 59–60. See also Women in Black Serbs: claimed differences between Bosnian Muslims and, 62; ICTY and sexual activity between Bosnian Muslim women and, 94–98; on ICTY as biased against their ethnicity, 198n15; ICTY charges for sexual violence against other groups versus against, 88, 201n54; rape of, Serbian Orthodox religious leaders and, 191n82; rapes by, calls for military intervention and, 56, 188n33. See also genocidal rape sex: consent and, 65, 94–98, 119, 160–61, 163; hyper-attention to, 39, 48. See also sexual agency; sexuality sex-positive feminists, 2, 18, 19, 40–42, 86 Index sex trafficking, 13, 40, 42; UN Resolutions on, 130, 134, 147, 219n48. See also sexual slavery; sex work sexual abuse, 25, 42, 125, 130, 188n38, 219n44. See also domestic violence sexual agency: For Whom the Bell Tolls on, 161–62; ICTY’s presumptions and, 94–98, 205nn96, 102, 205–6nn111–114; A Woman in Berlin on, 163–64; women’s, denial of rape or sexual violence and, 11 sexual hierarchies, 134, 185n139 sexual injury, 124, 199n25. See also gender-based violence; sexual violence in conflict sexual integrity, personal dignity and, 92, 163 sexuality, 40–41, 48, 49, 78, 150, 161, 185n139. See also sexual agency sexual slavery: anti-sexual slavery feminists on, 40–42, 47, 182–83n105; ISIS captives and, 165–66; Kunarac decision and, 87; Rome Statute on, 47, 87–88, 201n50; sex-positive feminist positions on, 19, 40–41; in UN Resolutions, 130; Vienna Declaration on, 19, 38, 43. See also sex trafficking; sex work sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism: broadening of rape into category of sexual violence and, 82–83; debate within, 43–44, 50, 86; defined, 2, 24; effects of ascendance of, 16, 39, 48, 82–83, 100; international criminal law and, 44–47, 86; private sphere and, 25; views of women’s economic status and, 42. See also structural-bias feminists sexual violence in conflict: move from gender-based violence to, 134–36, 221n67, 221–22n70, 222nn73, 77; rise in use of term, 41 (figure); UN Security Council Resolutions on, 127 (table), 128, 129, 130, 131 (table), 131–32, 217n19. 269 See also gender-based violence; ICC; ICTR; ICTY; victims; violence against women; worst crimes sex work: Barry’s position on, 182n104; debates on, 2, 19, 185n139; sex-positive feminists and, 40–41; sex trafficking workshop and, 102; World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights and, 42. See also sex trafficking; sexual slavery shame and stigma: alternative sentences in U.S. penal system and, 215n30; assumed to accompany sexual violence in conflict, 48, 91–92, 139–40; common sense about, summary of, 2, 7–9; communal shame, assumptions about, 8, 9, 105, 112, 139; doctrinally linking rape and genocide, 101; facilitating victim testimony and, 9, 10, 140, 154; feminists’ assumptions about rape and, 67–70, 191–92nn92–93; humiliation as same affect as, 192n103; ICTR case law assumptions about, 104, 106–7, 110, 115–16, 209n21; ICTY case law assumptions about, 91–92; Imam Omerbašić on, 65; individual shame, assumptions about communal shame and, 66, 92, 93, 109, 116, 140, 191n86; literary narratives on force of, 162–68; naming and, 120–21, 145, 215n129; as prosecutorial alibi, 116–19; shifting, from victim to perpetrator, 9, 92–93, 120–21, 145–46, 170–71, 192n110; Tomkins on humiliation and, 192n103, 208n10; of witnesses, prosecution obstacles presumably due to, 93, 101, 107, 116, 167–68, 204n88; WPS resolutions on assumptions about sexual violence in conflict and, 123–24. See also honor; humiliating and degrading treatment Shattered Lives (Nowrojee), 109, 116, 117, 118, 211n48 Shattuck, John, 54, 186n13, 186–87nn20– 21 270 Index Shestack, Jerome, 56, 62 Sierra Leone: Special Court for, 81, 208n8, 220n60; UN Action video (2007) on sexual violence in, 137–39, 138 (figure), 223nn83–4 Sikkink, Kathryn, 36 Simić, Tadić and Zarić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 91 Sivac, Nusreta, 151, 152 Sivakumaran, Sandesh, 175n19, 220n60 16 Days of Activism against Gender Violence (video, 1991), 34, 35 Smith, Gayle, 193n119 Spanish Civil War, 156, 229nn13–14. See also For Whom the Bell Tolls Special Court for Sierra Leone, 81, 208n8, 211n40 Special Representative on SVIC (Office of the Special Representative to the Secretary-General on Sexual Violence in Conflict), 123, 128, 223n83. See also Bangura, Zainab; Dieng, Adama; Patten, Pramila; UN Action; Wallström, Margot Spivak, Gayatri, 28 Srebrenica, Bosnia, 94, 204n92 Stakić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 91 Steiner, Henry, 179n51 Steinhauer, Jennifer, 196n148 Stiglmayer, Alexandra, 61, 69, 189n57 stigma. See shame and stigma St. James, Margo, 40, 41 “Stop Rape Now” (video), 137–39, 138 (figure), 223n82 structural-bias feminists: debate within over genocidal rape in former Yugoslavia, 43–44, 50, 86; defined, 2, 24; emergence of, 22; focus on sexual harm, 48–49; ICC and, 47, 73, 91, 102–3, 135–36, 160, 205n11; influence on international criminal law, summary and, 44–47; international human rights law and, 23–26; on male dominance and female subordination, 24, 98; on public/private distinction, 24–25; response to liberal inclusion approaches, 23–24; on sexual acts of violence against men, 98–99, 175n18, 178n26, 207n130; on Third World cultural practices, 25–28; Third World feminist critics and, 19–20, 26–28; women’s rights at Vienna Conference and, 19, 22. See also sexual subordination strand of structural-bias feminism; Third World feminist critics and their critiques Suchland, Jennifer, 36, 37, 42 Sudan: UN Mission in (UNMIS), 193n112. See also Darfur survival sex: as gender-based violence, 222n73; Murad on self-perception and, 164; A Woman in Berlin on, 163, 171 Sweden: on Security Council and feminist foreign policy, 148; on Security Council combating sexual violence, 143. See also Wallström, Margot systematic rape: in Berlin, 167; in Bosnia, international responses to, 20, 54; in Bosnia, Vienna Conference and, 43; as crime against humanity, 88; in Darfur, 70; feminists lobbying ICTY about, 83–84; in former Yugoslavia, Commission of Experts on violence and, 105; ICTY cases on, 87; ICTY resolution on, 81; in Libya, allegations of, 73–74, 76, 196n151; in Rwanda, Commission of Experts on allegations of, 109; UN Secretary-General report on investigation of, 197n3; Vienna Declaration on, 19, 31–32, 38. See also crimes against humanity; genocidal rape Tadić, Prosecutor v. (ICTY), 97, 198n17, 199n26, 200–201n42, 202n58 terrorists and terrorism, 79, 130, 139, 142, Index 146–47, 158. See also counterterrorism; extremist groups and extremism; ISIL; Murad, Nadia Third World feminist critics and their critiques: anti-sexual slavery feminists and, 42; Beijing debates and, 32; culturally sensitive universalism and, 32–34; on economic distribution and imperialism, 26–28, 34; emergence of, 22; on global North’s role in exploitation of women in global South, 11, 28, 34; international human rights law and, 26–28, 179n32; on structural-bias feminist approaches to culture, 26–28, 178n30; Vienna Conference debates and, 19–20, 32. See also culture; economic maldistribution; structural-bias feminists Ticktin, Miriam, 162, 183n114, 230n42 Tito, Josip Broz, 97 Tomkins, Silvan, 192n103, 208n10 torture: Brđanin conviction for, 91; Čelebići conviction for, 86–87; as crime against humanity, 83; as a grave breach, 86, 199n25; ICTY on, 83–84, 90–91, 92, 96, 203n72, 204n84; ICTY statute on, 83; Libya and, 76; public/ private distinction on, 24–25; rape or sexual violence as, 25, 76, 84, 86–87, 90–91, 210n33; shame or humiliation and, 92; as violation of customary international law, 83–84, 199n26; as a war crime, 83–84, 86, 199n26 Torture Victim Protection Act, U.S., 188n34 traditional and religious community leaders, 65, 146–47, 166–67, 191n82 trafficking. See sex trafficking transitional justice, 129, 185n139 Tutsis: Akayesu finding of genocidal rape against, 107–10; assumptions about shame and stigma among, 104, 109; Hutu genocide against, 103, 108; 271 participation of women in genocide against, 159; post-conflict Rwandan government led by, 102. See also ICTR; Rwanda UN Action (UN Action Against Sexual Violence in Conflict): on “conflictrelated sexual violence,” 100, 135–36; mission of, 123; on naming and shaming, 146; UN Resolution 1820 and, 126, 217n20; UN Resolution 2122 debate and, 129; video on shame and stigma of rape (2007), 137–39, 138 (figure), 223nn83–4; website, 223n83. See also Special Representative on SVIC UN Commission on Human Rights: on systematic rape in Bosnia, 20, 177n7. See also UN Special Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights UN Division for the Advancement of Women, 37 UN expert group meeting “Violence in the Family with Special Emphasis on Women,” 46 UN General Assembly, 52, 218n31 United Kingdom: Hague, as Foreign Secretary, 4, 9, 14, 123, 143; organizing of Preventing Sexual Violence in Conflict, 4; presidency of G8, 4, 47 United Kingdom, Foreign and Commonwealth Office: video (2014) released by, 3–7, 6 (figure), 15, 174n8 United States: Alien Tort Claims Act cases against Karadžić in, 57, 106, 188n34; considering military intervention in Bosnia, 52–54; failure to intervene in Rwandan genocide, 71; justifying military intervention to protect women, 197n166; military intervention in Libya and, 52–54, 72–74, 195n135, 196n148; Murad on Yazidis in Iraq and, 169–70; Security Council resolutions (2019) and, 131–32; 272 Index State Department, 54; War Powers Resolution, 72, 74. See also Libya Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 22–23 UN Mission in Sudan (UNMIS), 193n112 UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, 29 UN peacekeeping forces, 130, 217n21, 219n44 UN Protection Force (UNPROFOR), 51–52, 55, 185nn4–5 UN Secretary General. See Ban Ki-moon; Boutros-Ghali, Boutros; Special Representative on SVIC UN Secretary-General reports: on boys as victims of sexual violence, 221n75; on conflict-related sexual violence, 135, 136, 222nn75, 77–78; on excluding sexual violence crimes from amnesty, 144, 145; at fifteenth year of Resolution 1325 and, 129, 218n39; gender-neutral terms in, 133; on humanitarian grounds for military force, 186n11; on individual justice and impunity, 141; Resolution 1820 of requirements for, 128; on sexual violence and shaming, 139, 148–49 UN Security Council: Arria Formula Briefings by non-members of, 216n11, 226–27n146, 227n50; Chapter VII intervention powers of, 21, 62, 177n10, 186n9, 207n2; debates on conflict in former Yugoslavia in, 80; differences in resolutions setting up ICTY and ICTR, 102; on genocide in Darfur, 70, 192–93n112; human rights violations in Libya, 70–71; intervention power after Cold War end, 21, 52; peacekeeping in the former Yugoslavia and, 51–52; on sexual violence by terrorists, 146–47; on wartime rape in Bosnia and Herzegovina, 20. See also human security agenda; WPS agenda UN Security Council Resolution 1325: global study report at fifteenth year of, 129; human security agenda and, 126; to increase women’s participation in peacebuilding, 122; on individual prosecutions, 141; instrumentalism of, Iraq invasion and, 227n157; as not legally binding, 123, 216n4; post hoc legitimacy for 2003 military intervention in Iraq and, 149; production of, 217n15; on vulnerability of women and girls in conflict, 125–26; women’s peace activism and, 124–25, 216n3 UN Security Council resolutions: on armed conflict and civilians, children, or women, 126, 127 (table); on carceral response to sexual violence, 141–43, 224n102; condemning Libyan human rights violations, 71; establishing the ICTR, 44, 81, 101–2, 207n2, 208nn5–6; establishing the ICTY, 20–21, 80–81, 184n135, 197n5, 197–98nn5–6; on the former Yugoslavia, 51–52, 185n3; on gender-based violence, 222n73; gender-neutral language in, 132–34, 220n59; in human security context (1999–2019), 127 (table); ICTY and ICTR establishment, differences in, 102; to investigate genocide in Darfur, 192–93n112; on listing suspects of sexual violence, 145; military intervention in Libya under, 71–72; Murad’s testimony on prosecuting ISIS for genocide and, 130, 169–70; on the need for Israel to respect human rights during war, 176n22; NGO Working Group and, 122, 125, 128, 216n12; on preventing and countering violent extremism, 149, 150; primarily on women as peacebuilders, 11, 123–25, 127 (table), 128, 129, 130; primarily on women as victims of sexual violence, 4, 128, 131 (table), 147; refer- Index ring Libyan case to the ICC, 74; on removing procedural impediments, 141–42, 224n102; on Secretary General reporting requirements, 128; on sexual violence (2016–2017), 131 (table); on sexual violence as terrorist tactic, 146–47; on sexual violence in conflict, 4, 123, 126, 128–30, 131–33, 137, 149, 217nn18–19, 21–22; on shame shifting, 146–47; on UN Action’s work, 217n20; UNPROFOR establishment in the former Yugoslavia, 185n4; UN Women and, 129; on violence against children, 125; Wallström on reporting sexual violence under, 135 UN Special Rapporteur of the Commission on Human Rights, 67, 91, 104–5 UN War Crimes Commission, 174n10 UN Women (UN Entity for Gender Equality and the Empowerment of Women), 129, 130, 218n31, 219n50 UN World Conference on Human Rights (1993). See Vienna Conference UN World Conferences on Women, 26, 216n9. See also Beijing Conference; Copenhagen Conference; Mexico City Conference; Nairobi Conference Van Schaack, Beth, 210nn29, 35 VAW. See violence against women Velásquez-Rodríguez v. Honduras (1988), 46, 184n133 Viagra for Gaddafi’s troops, claims and debates about, 71, 73, 74–76 victims: attempts to find alternatives to testimony by, 118–19; boys as, 2, 48, 82; ICC and, 170; imagined shame and testimony of, 9, 10, 140, 154; men as, 2, 14, 48, 135–36, 175n19, 221nn63–4; prosecution obstacles due to shame of, 93, 101, 107, 116, 167–68, 204n88; as witnesses, ICTY on, 203n75; women 273 in war assumed as, 10, 155. See also specific groups e.g. Bosnian Muslim women, men, or individuals Victims and Witnesses Unit, ICTY’s, 85, 200n40 video (UK Foreign and Commonwealth Office, 2014), 7–8; as common sense about sexual conflict, 3–7, 6 (figure), 174n8; on perpetrators as male monsters against innocent (female) victims, 10–12; that criminal law will end in sexual violence in conflict, 12–15; that sexual violence prevents peace, 15 video (UN Action, 2007), on shame and stigma of rape, 137–39, 138 (figure), 223nn83–4 Vienna Conference (1993): Asian values debate, 29, 31, 33, 179n45; connecting sexual violence and sex trafficking, 42; consensus anticipated at, 28–29; culturally sensitive universalism at, 32–34, 43; ICTY establishment and discussions at, 21; petition to include women’s rights at, 29, 34; sex-positive feminist positions and discourse at, 41–42; sexual violence in conflict as topic of, 16, 37; Special Declaration on Bosnia and Herzegovina, 184n135; women’s human rights advocates attending, 22; women’s human rights and sexual violence in conflict as themes of, 18, 43; women’s human rights movement and, 18–19; Women’s Rights Are Human Rights at, 18–19, 29–30, 31, 44 Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action: amicus brief for Akayesu and, 106; Bunch on, 40; condemning impunity, 47; Pillay on achievements of, 44; on sexual slavery, 19, 38, 43, 44, 130; on sexual violence in conflict, 37; on women’s rights and elimination of violence against women, 19, 31 274 Index Vienna Tribunal on Violations of Women’s Human Rights, 32, 34–35, 38–39, 43, 182n93 Vietnam War, 173n1 Vigneswaran, Kate, 200n41, 201–2n54 violence against women (VAW): centrality of issue to women’s human rights movement, 19, 22, 34, 38, 39–40; displacement of issues of economic distribution, 34; as mediation of debates about culture, 35–36; and Nairobi Conference, 35, 181nn73, 77; narrowing to sexual violence in conflict, 43, 135–36; sexual violence as focus of, 40, 42; turn to criminal law responses to, 13, 45–46. See also sexual violence in conflict Violence Against Women Act, U.S. (1994), 45 Viseur Sellers, Patricia: on ICTR’s Akayesu decision, 103, 210n35; on ICTY’s Rule 96 on consent, 94, 204n94; as Legal Advisor for Gender Related Crimes, 85, 103; on OTP charges for sexual violence committed against men, 99; on prosecutorial discretion, 98 Vranić, Seada, 69, 205–6n112 Wallström, Margot: as Special Representative on SVIC, 75, 135, 145; as Sweden’s Minister of Foreign Affairs, 143, 148 war, women’s roles in: as combatants, 69, 155–60, 229nn13–14; as peacebuilders, WPS resolutions on, 11, 123–25, 127 (table), 128, 129, 130; as perpetrators, 10, 99, 158–60; as political actors, 11, 60, 155, 170–71; as victims of sexual violence, WPS resolutions on, 4, 128, 131 (table), 147. See also A Woman in Berlin; For Whom the Bell Tolls; Murad, Nadia; sexual violence in conflict; women’s peace movement and activism Warburton Report, 177n3 war crimes: Ad Hoc Women’s Coalition against War Crimes against Women, 44–45, 83; early prosecutions of rape for, 8, 174n10; Global Tribunal and, 34, 38, 39, 182n93; Helsinki Watch on tribunal on, 198n10; ICTR prosecutions for, 103, 208n7; ICTR statute on, 102–3; ICTY prosecutions for, 84–85, 86–87, 92, 96, 200n42, 201nn44, 48, 202n59, 203n78, 208n13; ICTY statute on, 83–84, 199nn22, 25; Libya and, 73, 74–77; Rome Statute on, 87, 184n135. See also Geneva Conventions; grave breaches; international humanitarian law, torture War Powers Resolution, U.S., 72, 74 Weissman, Deborah, 197n166 Wing, Adrien, 65–66, 190n75, 191n83 witnesses. See victims A Woman in Berlin: Eight Weeks in the Conquered City: controversies regarding, 228nn6–7, 9; as German diary during Berlin’s fall to Soviet forces (1945), 153; Halley on structures of language for rape and other violence in, 154; positive function of shame in, 170–71; publication of, 230n52; on rapes by Russian soldiers during Battle of Berlin, 163–64; on speaking of mass rape to other victims, 167–68; time covered by, 230n48 women: and children, coupling of, 10, 132, 133, 200n54; as combatants, 69, 155–60, 229nn13–14; in peacebuilding, WPS resolutions on, 11, 123–25, 127 (table), 128, 129, 130; as perpetrators, 10, 99, 158–60; political roles in war of, 11, 60, 155, 170–71; as sexual violence targets, WPS agenda on, 124; victimization of men versus, 93–94; as victims of sexual violence, WPS resolutions on, 4, 128, 131 (table), 147. See Index also gender-neutral language; sexual agency; victims Women for a Meaningful Summit, 216n9 Women in Black, 59–60, 189n50 Women’s Action Coalition, 183n120 women’s agency, 11, 60, 69–70, 78; A Woman in Berlin on, 170–71. See also sexual agency Women’s Commission for Refugee Women and Children, 215n1 Women’s Decade, 35, 181n75 women’s human rights movement: Cold War’s end and, 36; feminists approaches to human rights and, 23–28; international criminalization of sexual violence in conflict and, 45; rise in use of terms “women’s rights” and “human rights of women,” 18–19, 29–30, 30 (figure); VelásquezRodríguez case as paradigm shift for, 46–47, 184n133; Vienna Conference agenda and, 18–19. See also feminists and feminisms; Global Tribunal on Violations of Women’s Human Rights; international human rights law and discourse; Vienna Conference; Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action “Women’s Human Rights: Possibilities and Contradictions” (Harvard Human Rights Program, 1988), 30–31, 179–80n51 Women’s International League for Peace and Freedom (WILPF), 122, 123, 136 Women’s Media Center, 75 women’s peace movement and activism: Cold War and, 124; Peace Tent, at Nairobi Conference and, 35, 181n78, 216n9; in relation to other feminist positions, 2, 18, 86; UN Security Council WPS agenda and, 16, 125, 133, 149–50, 185n140, 216n3, 227n157; views on women’s victimization and, 124–25, 140; WILPF and, 122, 124, 136; Women 275 in Black, 59–60, 189n50. See also antiwar feminists; peace Women’s Rights Are Human Rights: rise in use of terms “women’s rights” and “human rights of women,” 18–19, 29–30, 30 (figure); Vienna Conference and, 18–19, 29–30, 31, 44 Women under Siege: Libya (Women’s Media Center), 75 Wood, Elisabeth, 176n26 Working Group on Engendering the Rwanda Tribunal, 106, 210n31 World Charter for Prostitutes’ Rights, 41–42 World War II, 38, 83, 182n93. See also A Woman in Berlin World Whores Congress (1985), 41 worst crimes: Akayesu charges on rape and sexual violence as, 110; case law produced under ICTY and ICTR and, 82; common sense about sexual conflict as, 7–10, 58; Global Network of Women Peacebuilders’ letter on rape as, 140; ICTR’s decisions on rape or sexual violence as, 113, 115; ICTY jurisprudence and solidifying common sense on, 90–94, 203n75; rape as, military intervention and, 51; WPS resolutions on sexual violence in conflict as, 123–24. See also sexual violence in conflict WPS agenda (Women’s Peace and Security Agenda): common sense about sexual conflict and, summary of, 123–24; on gender-based violence and conflict-related sexual violence, 12; human security agenda compared with, 126; militarization of, 149–50; sex trafficking resolutions and, 130–31; sexual violence treatment research and, 143; UN resolutions on sexual violence and, 122, 131 (table), 141; videos produced by, 137–39; women’s peacebuilding role versus women’s 276 Index passive victim role and, 140; women’s peace movement and origins of, 124– 25. See also counterterrorism; sexual violence in conflict; UN Action; UN Security Council Resolution 1325 WPS resolutions: binding legal obligations and, 215n5; in human security context, 125–26, 127 (table), 128–32, 219nn49–50; primarily on women as peacebuilders, 11, 123–25, 127 (table), 128, 129, 130; primarily on women as victims of sexual violence, 4, 128, 131 (table), 147; relationship to Chapter VII, 122–25; turn to criminal law and, 140–47, 148 Wright, Shelly, 26 Yazidis. See Murad, Nadia Yugoslavia, former: feminist debates over meaning of rape in conflict in, 55–70; military interventions in, arguments for, 53–54, 55–58; war in, women’s human rights advocates on sexual violence in conflict in, 19, 31–32, 37–38, 83–85. See also Bosnia and Herzegovina; Croatia; ICTY; Kosovo; Serbian feminists; Serbs Žarkov, Dubravka, 50, 66, 67–68 Stanford Studies in Human Rights Mark Goodale, editor Editorial Board Abdullahi A. An-Na’im Upendra Baxi Alison Brysk Rosemary Coombe Sally Engle Merry James Nickel Ronald Niezen Fernando Tesón Richard A. Wilson When Misfortune Becomes Injustice: Evolving Human Rights Struggles for Health and Social Equality Alicia Ely Yamin 2020 The Politics of Love in Myanmar: LGBT Mobilization and Human Rights as a Way of Life Lynette J. Chua 2018 Branding Humanity: Competing Narratives of Rights, Violence, and Global Citizenship Amal Hassan Fadlalla 2018 Remote Freedoms: Politics, Personhood and Human Rights in Aboriginal Central Australia Sarah E. Holcombe 2018 Letters to the Contrary: A Curated History of the UNESCO Human Rights Survey Mark Goodale 2018 Just Violence: Torture and Human Rights in the Eyes of the Police Rachel Wahl 2017 Bodies of Truth: Law, Memory, and Emancipation in Post-Apartheid South Africa Rita Kesselring 2016 Rights After Wrongs: Local Knowledge and Human Rights in Zimbabwe Shannon Morreira 2016 If God Were a Human Rights Activist Boaventura de Sousa Santos 2015 Digging for the Disappeared: Forensic Science after Atrocity Adam Rosenblatt 2015 The Rise and Fall of Human Rights: Cynicism and Politics in Occupied Palestine Lori Allen 2013 Campaigning for Justice: Human Rights Advocacy in Practice Jo Becker 2012 In the Wake of Neoliberalism: Citizenship and Human Rights in Argentina Karen Ann Faulk 2012 Values in Translation: Human Rights and the Culture of the World Bank Galit A. Sarfaty 2012 Disquieting Gifts: Humanitarianism in New Delhi Erica Bornstein 2012 Stones of Hope: How African Activists Reclaim Human Rights to Challenge Global Poverty Edited by Lucie E. White and Jeremy Perelman 2011 Judging War, Judging History: Behind Truth and Reconciliation Pierre Hazan 2010 Localizing Transitional Justice: Interventions and Priorities after Mass Violence Edited by Rosalind Shaw and Lars Waldorf, with Pierre Hazan 2010 Surrendering to Utopia: An Anthropology of Human Rights Mark Goodale 2009 Human Rights for the 21st Century: Sovereignty, Civil Society, Culture Helen M. Stacy 2009 Human Rights Matters: Local Politics and National Human Rights Institutions Julie A. Mertus 2009