Discourse Processes ISSN: 0163-853X (Print) 1532-6950 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/hdsp20 Using story‐based causal diagrams to analyze disagreements about complex events Brian P. Shapiro , Paul van den Broek & Charles R. Fletcher To cite this article: Brian P. Shapiro , Paul van den Broek & Charles R. Fletcher (1995) Using story‐based causal diagrams to analyze disagreements about complex events, Discourse Processes, 20:1, 51-77, DOI: 10.1080/01638539509544931 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/01638539509544931 Published online: 07 Jun 2010. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 36 View related articles Citing articles: 1 View citing articles Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=hdsp20 DISCOURSE PROCESSES 20,51-77 (1995) Using Story-Based Causal Diagrams to Analyze Disagreements About Complex Events BRIAN P. SHAPIRO University of Arizona PAUL VAN DEN BROEK CHARLES R. FLETCHER University of Minnesota People often disagree about the causes of complex events. Previous research has shown that disagreement often results from cognitive and pragmatic constraints that govern people's tendency to attribute outcomes to partial rather than complete causes. This article applies the Trabasso, van den Broek, and Suh (1989) story-based procedures to a narrative of the 1987 stock market crash. The content and structure of the resulting causal diagrams are then used to analyze some opposing causal explanations that were offered by different investigative commissions. The diagrams reveal that some major disagreements involved conflicting interpretations of the crash's multiple indirect and psychological causes. The diagrams also show that some causal explanations were incomplete and implausible because they ignored or contradicted relevant events and causal relations. Implications for discourse comprehension research are discussed, and the advantages of using causal diagrams to mitigate constraints on causal comprehension and explanation are explored. People often disagree about the causes of complex events. The debate over the 1987 stock market crash is a good example. Different investigators had the knowledge and time to interpret the evidence, but they still reached opposing conclusions. For example, some investigators attributed the crash to changes in investors' long-term expectations, others attributed it to a general market panic, and yet others attributed it to a small number of large institutions which sold millions of dollars of securities in a matter of seconds. The 1987 crash is typical of causally complex events: Its outcomes were caused by multiple antecedent conditions, its causal relations were of various types, and many of its antecedent conditions directly caused each other but only indirectly caused the outcomes. We are grateful to Art Graesser, Susan Ranney, and three anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of this article. Correspondence and requests for reprints should be sent to Brian P. Shapiro, University of Arizona, Karl Eller School of Management, 301 McClelland Hall, Tucson, AZ 85721. 51 52 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER Research in the philosophy and psychology of causal reasoning has identified many reasons for people's failure to understand and agree about an event's causes. A scenario's complexity and the lack of a universal definition of causality often leave the analysis of causal relations open to multiple interpretations (Hart & Honore, 1985; Mackie, 1974). In addition, several cognitive and pragmatic constraints govern the tendency to attribute outcomes to partial rather than complete causes. Among these constraints are knowledge and memory limitations (Bloom, Fletcher, van den Broek, Reitz, & Shapiro, 1990; Chiesi, Spilich, & Voss, 1979; Spilich, Vesonder, Chiesi, & Voss, 1979), conversational constraints (Collingwood, 1940; Graesser & Franklin, 1990; Hilton, 1990; Mackie, 1974), and motivational biases (see Kunda, 1990, for a review). These constraints can lead different people to attribute the same event to different causes. This article demonstrates how the explicit representation of events as causal diagrams of nodes and causal relations can be used to analyze causal disagreements. It also explores how causal diagrams may reduce the cognitive and pragmatic constraints that make people unable or unwilling to communicate to others a complete event representation. Our approach is based on two common assumptions in cognitive psychology that link individuals' mental representations with their causal judgments and decisions. The first assumption is that an individual's mental representation of a scenario reflects his or her understanding of that scenario (Kintsch, 1988). Discourse comprehension research has provided extensive psychological evidence that readers construct causal network representations of stories in long-term memory (see van den Broek, 1990b, for a review). The second assumption is that judgment and decision making are mediated by an individual's mental representation (e.g., Newell & Simon, 1972). Pennington and Hastie (1986, 1988, 1992) have provided experimental evidence for both assumptions by demonstrating that jurors use story-like mental representations of trial evidence to reach their verdicts. Drawing on these psychologically validated assumptions, we propose that many disagreements can be traced to individuals' causal network representations of the disputed events. To illustrate this idea, we apply the Trabasso, van den Broek, and Suh (1989) procedures to a narrative of the 1987 stock market crash. We then use the resulting diagrams to analyze the opposing causal explanations offered by different investigative commissions. Unlike other procedures for constructing causal diagrams (e.g., see Axelrod, 1976; Hogarth, Michaud, & Mery, 1980; Maruyama, 1963; Sev6n, 1984), the Trabasso et al. procedures assign a story category to each event and causal relation. Our analysis demonstrates that the story categories are especially useful for analyzing opposing interpretations of the crash's multiple indirect and psychological causes. We also find that some investigative commissions' explanations were incomplete or implausible because CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 53 they omitted or contradicted some of the relevant events and causal relations. Our work extends previous research on the analysis of causal diagrams in several ways. First, whereas others have suggested that the analysis of causal diagrams could have implications for understanding disagreement about causal relations (e.g., see Einhorn & Hogarth, 1986; Hilton, 1990), we make explicit some of those implications. Second, discourse comprehension research has used causal diagrams to represent simple story events. We demonstrate that the story-based procedures generalize to a more naturalistic and complex narrative. The crash narrative is complex in part because its recursive event chains blur the distinction between cause and effect and between direct and indirect causes. Without those distinctions, existing discourse models might have difficulty finding good explanations for complex events (e.g., see Graesser & Franklin, 1990; Graesser, Lang, & Roberts, 1991). Finally, discourse models typically assume that most respondents will sincerely try to provide high-quality explanations. In contrast, we discuss the pragmatic constraints that can make people unwilling to reveal their complete event representations. This article is organized as follows: We first describe the Trabasso et al. (1989) procedures for constructing story-based causal diagrams. We then discuss the cognitive and pragmatic constraints that govern the tendency to attribute events to incomplete causes. Next, we use causal diagrams to analyze major disagreements about the 1987 crash. Finally, we compare our work with Graesser and Franklin's (1990) QUEST model of question answering, and we explore how causal diagrams may mitigate the constraints on causal comprehension and explanation. STORY-BASED CAUSAL NETWORK REPRESENTATIONS Researchers have noted that causal diagrams allow the causal role of each event to be defined in terms of its causal relations to other events in the diagram (cf. Danto, 1985; Graesser, 1981; Graesser & Clark, 1985; Pennington & Hastie, 1986; Trabasso et al., 1989). This article uses causal diagrams to evaluate the quality of opposing explanations for the 1987 stock market crash. A complete explanation for the crash should account for all known events and causal relations, and a plausible explanation should not contradict them (cf. Pennington & Hastie, 1993). We recognize that individuals who do not share the same causal model may reasonably disagree about the causal roles of hypothetical or future events (e.g., see Axelrod, 1976; Hogarth et al., 1980; Sev6n, 1984). However, the 1987 crash involved actual events whose occurrence was verified by several investigative commissions. This allows us to evaluate the relative completeness and plausibility of opposing causal explanations for the crash. SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER 54 Our approach is based on extensively used and psychologically validated systems for representing the causal structure of narrative events (e.g., see Graesser & Franklin, 1990; Trabasso et al., 1989). Under this approach, the construction of a causal diagram involves three steps: (a) identification of nodes that correspond to the scenario's events, (b) identification of causal relations, and (c) assembly of the diagram. Each event and causal relation is also assigned to one of several story categories. This section summarizes the Trabasso et al. procedures for assigning the categories and describes the psychological properties of causal diagrams. Trabasso et al.'s Causal Network Model Story Events. Trabasso et al.'s (1989) causal network model is a representation of how people reason about story events. The model assigns each story event to one of five categories, represented as labeled nodes in Figure 1. Setting information (S) introduces story characters in time and space. Goals (G) are a protagonist's desired outcomes. Attempts (A) are a protagonist's goal-directed actions. Outcomes (O) are events and conditions that may or may not satisfy a protagonist's goals. Reactions (R) are a protagonist's mental states or internal reactions. These categories resemble event classifications developed by others (e.g., see Graesser & Clark, 1985; Graesser & Franklin, 1990; Mandler & Johnson, 1977; Schank & Abelson, 1977). The causal network model implies that a complete story or explanation of human behavior must include each event category. For example, a story is incomplete if it fails to describe the reasons for a protagonist's behavior. S 0) — Figure 1. Causal network model story events and causal relations (adapted from Trabasso, van den Broek, and Suh, 1989). The event categories are S (setting information), G (goals), A (attempts), O (outcomes), and R (reactions). The causal relation categories are M (motivational, "9 (psychological), <E> (physical), and E (enablement). CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 55 Mandler and Johnson (1977) also reported evidence that incomplete stories are more difficult to comprehend and recall. Causal Relations. The labeled arcs in Figure 1 represent causal relations among the event categories. Trabasso et al. (1989) and van den Broek (1990a) described four criteria that have enabled researchers to reliably identify causal relations among pairs of events. These criteria have been discussed at length in philosophy (e.g., Hume, 1739/1964; Lewis, 1976; Mackie, 1974), law (Hart & Honore, 1985), and psychology (e.g., Bindra, Clarke, & Shultz, 1980; Downing, Sternberg, & Ross, 1985; Einhorn & Hogarth, 1986; van den Broek, 1988). Temporal priority stipulates that a cause cannot occur after its effect. Temporal sequence is an important structural feature of scripts (e.g., see Schank & Abelson, 1977). Ohtsuka and Brewer (1992) have also reported that it is often easier to comprehend discourse when its structure corresponds to the temporal structure of the underlying events. Operativity further stipulates that in order for a direct causal relation to exist between cause and effect, the cause must be active (have causal force) when the effect occurs. For candidate causal pairs that satisfy both temporal priority and operativity, causal relations are identified by judging whether the antecedent is necessary or sufficient in the circumstances for the consequent (van den Broek, 1990a, 1990b). An antecedent is considered necessary in the circumstances for a consequent if it satisfies the counterfactual criterion "If the antecedent had not occurred in the circumstances, then the consequent would not have occurred" (Hart & Honore, 1985; Lewis, 1976; Mackie, 1974). An antecedent is considered sufficient in the circumstances for a consequent if it satisfies the criterion "If the antecedent occurs in the circumstances and the usual events are allowed to run on from there, then the consequent will occur" (Hart & Honore, 1985; Mackie, 1974). The phrase in the circumstances recognizes that causal judgments also depend on the investigator's knowledge or assumptions about the circumstances surrounding the alleged cause (cf. Einhorn & Hogarth, 1986; Hart & Honore, 1985; Mackie, 1974). In Figure 1, all of the causal relations assume that both temporal priority and operativity are satisfied. The categories of causal relations that can exist among each pair of events are determined as follows. A causal relation is motivational (M) if the antecedent describes goal information and if necessity in the circumstances is satisfied. The causal relation is psychological (^) if the antecedent describes an internal state or reaction (R) and if necessity in the circumstances is satisfied. The causal relation is physical (<I>) if it is neither motivational nor psychological and if sufficiency in the circumstances is satisfied. All other causal relations are enablement (E). 56 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER Psychological Properties of Causal Diagrams These procedures produce a branching network of categorized events and causal relations with many psychologically valid properties. For example, events with many causal connections to other events are recalled or summarized more often (Black & Bower, 1980; Fletcher & Bloom, 1988; Graesser & Clark, 1985; Trabasso, Secco, & van den Broek, 1984; Trabasso & van den Broek, 1985), recalled more quickly (O'Brien & Myers, 1987), and rated as more important (O'Brien & Myers, 1987; Trabasso & Sperry, 1985; Trabasso & van den Broek, 1985; van den Broek, 1988) than otherwise similar events with fewer causal connections. The content and structural properties of causal diagrams also successfully predict people's goodness-of-answer judgment latencies and their answers to causal questions (Graesser & Franklin, 1990; Graesser et al, 1991). However, people's mental representations of stories tend to have fewer causal relations than networks constructed with the Trabasso et al. (1989) procedures (e.g., see Bloom et al., 1990; Fletcher & Bloom, 1988; McKoon & Ratcliff, 1992). Moreover, when people give causal explanations, they often attribute outcomes to partial, rather than complete, causes (Einhorn & Hogarth, 1986; Hart & Honore, 1985; Hilton, 1990; Mackie, 1974; Mill, 1872/1973). Thus, in reality, individuals tend to be unable or unwilling to acquire and communicate to others a complete event representation. Cognitive and pragmatic constraints can explain this tendency. CONSTRAINTS ON CAUSAL COMPREHENSION AND EXPLANATION In this section, we first describe partial causes and their relation to the events in a causal diagram. We then discuss the cognitive and pragmatic constraints that govern the tendency to attribute events to partial rather than complete causes. Partial Causes and Their Relation to Events in a Causal Diagram The Trabasso et al. (1989) criteria for evaluating causal necessity and causal sufficiency in the circumstances recognize that each single event in a causal diagram is only a partial cause. For example, a protagonist's behavior is only partly caused by the goal because other events and circumstances are also required to produce the behavior. As such, a protagonist's goal may be considered necessary but not sufficient for his or her behavior. More formally, Mackie (1974) used the term INUS condition to denote an insufficient and necessary part of an unnecessary but sufficient set of conditions for an outcome in the assumed causal field. Mackie also used the term minimal sufficient condition to denote a sufficient set of INUS conditions for an outcome. Using these terms, a protagonist's goal CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 57 is an INUS condition and hence only part of a minimal sufficient condition for his or her behavior. In this article, we consider a causal diagram or explanation to be complete if it describes a minimal sufficient condition for each known event. We also consider a causal diagram or explanation to be plausible if it does not contradict the known facts (cf. Pennington & Hastie, 1993). In a subsequent section, we show how a causal diagram can be used to evaluate the completeness and plausibility of opposing causal explanations, but first we discuss the cognitive and pragmatic constraints that govern people's tendency to attribute events to incomplete and implausible causes. Cognitive Constraints Memory and knowledge limitations are among the most influential cognitive constraints on causal attribution. These constraints can prevent people from encoding and retrieving relatively complete event representations. Memory Limitations. Working memory limitations are known to constrain the number of direct causal relations that readers can encode among pairs of events (Bloom et al., 1990; Fletcher & Bloom, 1988; Gernsbacher, Varner, & Faust, 1990; Just & Carpenter, 1992; Keenan, Baillet, & Brown, 1984; McKoon & Ratcliff, 1992; Myers, Shinjo, & Duffy, 1987; Trabasso & Suh, 1993). Although long-term memory retrieval may supply missing information, it requires additional processing effort (Bloom et al., 1990; O'Brien, 1987; O'Brien & Myers, 1987) and may displace other information from working memory (see Just & Carpenter, 1992, for a review). Some readers tend to search long-term memory only when they cannot identify a sufficient (or "adequate") causal relation among clauses that are already activated in working memory. Many readers also tend to avoid extensive retrieval in the absence of specific processing goals that encourage more elaborative encoding (Bloom et al., 1990; Fletcher & Bloom, 1988; van den Broek, Risden, & Husebye-Hartmann, 1995; see McKoon & Ratcliff, 1992, for a review). In summary, memory limitations can prevent people from encoding and retrieving causal relations. Knowledge Limitations. Psychologists have long recognized that prior knowledge provides an efficient and effective structure for encoding and retrieving domain-related information (e.g., Bartlett, 1932; Chiesi et al., 1979; Graesser & Clark, 1985; Rumelhart, 1980; Schank & Abelson, 1977; Spilich et al., 1979). However, a relevant schema must be activated in order to influence encoding and retrieval (Bransford & Johnson, 1972; Smith & Swinney, 1992). If more than one schema is available, only the activated schema strongly influences comprehension (e.g., Pichert & Anderson, 1977). Along these lines, an individual's perspective may selectively acti- 58 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER vate a particular schema and, thus, make some events appear more salient than others. For example, research on actor-observer differences has demonstrated that observers tend to attribute the causes of an actor's negative behavior to the actor's enduring traits, whereas actors tend to attribute their own negative behavior to situational variables (see Watson, 1982, for a review). Jones and Nisbett (1972) suggested that actor-observer differences may result from the actors perceiving situational variables as standing out in relation to their predispositional traits (the causal field). In contrast, observers may perceive the actor's traits as figural against the background of other situational variables. An implication is that individuals who do not share the same knowledge or perspective may disagree about an event's causes. In summary, an individual's ability to identify causal relations depends on cognitive constraints such as limited attentional capacity and available background knowledge. Pragmatic Constraints Pragmatic intentions can also make an individual's causal explanations incomplete. Conversational constraints and motivational biases are among the most influential pragmatic constraints. Conversational Constraints. Mackie (1974) observed that the purpose of a conversational exchange often dictates which of several candidate causes are most relevant to an explanation. Hilton (1990) used Grice's (1975) conversational maxims to further characterize how people's causal explanations are governed by such interpersonal factors as who does the explaining, to whom the explanation is given, and why the explanation is needed. For example, the maxim of relevance enjoins speakers to stick to the point and not give irrelevant answers, and the maxim of quantity enjoins speakers to provide no more information than is necessary in the exchange. To follow these maxims, a cooperative explainer must either know or assume what the explainee already knows and then try to fill the gap in the explainee's knowledge. Similarly, Graesser and Franklin's (1990) QUEST model of question answering predicts that good answers to causal questions will vary depending on the question category (e.g., why, how, enable, when, and what-isthe-consequent questions). QUEST also predicts that different questions will lead people to access their event representations in different ways. An implication is that a cooperative individual who overtly attributes an event to a partial cause may nevertheless covertly understand its complete cause. Thus, some disagreements may occur simply because conversational constraints lead different individuals to attribute the same event to different parts of the same implicitly agreed-upon minimal sufficient condition. CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 59 Motivational Biases. Most theories of discourse comprehension and question answering assume that individuals will sincerely try to follow Grice's (1975) maxim of quality. That maxim directs speakers to say something they know not to be false and to avoid saying something for which they lack sufficient evidence (see also Hilton, 1990). However, causal attributions are also known to be highly selective and directionally biased, especially when people attempt to justify their beliefs or try to persuade others to reach a particular conclusion (e.g., Bettman & Weitz, 1983; Staw, 1980; Tetlock, 1983, 1985; Tetlock & Boettger, 1989). An explanation is selective if it reports only some of an event's relevant antecedent conditions, and it is biased if an alternative explanation may also be supported by the available evidence (Kunda, 1990). A biased explanation can mislead people who are unable to evaluate the explanation's quality. In summary, cognitive and pragmatic constraints can lead different individuals to attribute the same events to different partial causes. The next section uses causal diagrams to analyze opposing causal explanations for the 1987 crash. A subsequent section explores how causal diagrams may mitigate the cognitive and pragmatic constraints on causal attribution. CAUSAL ANALYSIS OF THE 1987 CRASH Several investigative commissions reconstructed the same 1987 stock market crash events but they disagreed about its causes. In this section, we first describe a causal network model of how computerized trading strategies can cause a crash. We then apply the model to a narrative of crash events and use the resulting diagrams to analyze some major disagreements. Cascade Theory: A Causal Model of Program Trading in Stocks and Futures Most popular theories of stock market psychology attribute large stock price declines to a fundamental change in investors' rational expectations or to a general market panic wherein large numbers of individuals collectively drive prices downward. In contrast, the cascade theory attributes severe market declines to a small number of large institutions whose computerized trading strategies can sell millions of dollars of securities in a matter of seconds (see the Appendix for a brief summary of computerized trading strategies). The October 1987 crash provided investigators with a unique opportunity to investigate the validity of the cascade theory claims. As described in a subsequent section, some people disagreed with the cascade theory. Table 1 and Figure 2 use a causal network model to describe the cascade theory, as summarized by the Commodity Futures Trading Commission (CFTC; 1988b, p. 2). As in the causal model of Figure 1, the cascade theory 60 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER TABLE 1 Events in the Cascade Theory of Program Trading's Role During a Stock Market Crash O^ Stock prices begin to decline S2: as a result of fundamentally negative economic news. G3: Portfolio hedgers want to hedge their stock portfolios against falling stock prices, A4: so they sell futures, O5: and this causes index futures prices to decline. O6: Stock index futures trade at a significant discount to the underlying stock index. G7: Index arbitrageurs want to profit from the price disparity in the stock and futures indices, A8: so they buy the relatively underpriced futures A,: and they sell the relatively overpriced basket of stocks. O10: Stock prices decline further. Note. Based on Commodity Futures Trading Commission (1988b, p. 2). uses psychological categories to explain how program trading transforms initial stock price declines into steeper declines. In addition to the Trabasso et al. (1989) categories, we use a ^PGM category to link nodes where a protagonist's goals and internal reactions are not explicitly mentioned. Schank and Abelson (1977) observed that, when people explain behavior, they often leave out intervening mental states, particularly when the mental states are easily inferred. ^ G M is shorthand for the psychological causation (^) [sometimes also an unstated antecedent internal reaction, R]) of an unstated goal (G) which motivates subsequent events (M). The cascade theory begins with an initiating event. This is represented in Figure 2 as fundamentally negative economic news (S2). This initiating event (S2) psychologically motivates some traders to sell stocks (not explicitly shown in Figure 2), which then causes initial stock price declines (Oj). Computerized trading practices then amplify the initial declines as follows: Portfolio insurers who want to hedge their stock portfolios against falling stock prices (G3) sell futures (A4). This causes a decline in the futures index (O5). These events cause the futures index to trade at a significant discount to the underlying stock index (O6). Index arbitrageurs then want Figure 2. The cascade theory of program trading's role during a stock market crash (events based on Commodity Futures Trading Commission, 1988b, p. 2). CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 61 to profit from the price disparity in the stock and futures indices (G7). Therefore, they buy the relatively underpriced futures index (A8) and sell the relatively overpriced stock index (A9). These trades cause stock prices to decline further (O10). The feedback loops show that if the process continues, stock prices will continue to cascade downward. In the following, we apply the cascade theory to two major event sequences of the crash. Causal Diagrams of Crash Events The events in our causal diagrams are based on excerpts from the Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms' (1988, pp. 29-34) narrative of crash events. The Task Force's conclusions are widely regarded as the most objective and complete of the various investigative reports (Waldman, 1988). Table 2 and Figure 3 describe the week before the crash. It begins with two causal chains of events (Sx-A6) that precipitated the initial stock price declines (O7). It then describes how computerized program trading strategies amplified those declines. During that time, the Dow Jones Industrial Average fell more than 250 points. Over the weekend, it was widely publicized that many portfolio insurers and mutual funds had fallen significantly beTABLE 2 Events of the Week Before the 1987 Stock Market Crash St: O2: O3: A4: R5: A6: O7: A8: O9: A 10 : Su: O I2 : A 13 : O, 4 : R15: R I6 : Rw: R18: A,,: A 20 : In response to disappointingly poor merchandise trade figures, the dollar declined in currency markets. Long-term interest rates rose. In addition, congressional filing of antitakeover tax legislation made takeover stocks appear less attractive, prompting risk arbitrageurs to sell stocks of takeover candidates. Stock prices declined. Investors in mutual funds called to redeem their shares. Mutual funds fell far behind in their selling programs. Mutual funds sold large volumes of stock. During this time, $60 to $90 billion of equity assets (e.g., stocks) were under portfolio insurance administration. Portfolio insurers fell behind in selling programs, so they actively sold large volumes of futures. Futures index prices declined. Index arbitrageurs understood the selling strategies of portfolio insurers and mutual funds and saw them fall behind in their selling programs. The index arbitrageurs anticipated the huge forced selling by portfolio insurers and mutual funds, and they anticipated repurchasing stock at lower prices. The index arbitrageurs therefore sold more stock than they bought, and they bought only some futures. Note. Based on Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms (1988, pp. 29-30). 62 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER Figure 3. The week before the 1987 stock market crash (events based on Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms, 1988, pp. 29-30). hind in their selling programs. Consequently, by the time the New York Stock Exchange opened for trading on the following Monday, index arbitrageurs (among others) were already poised to sell large volumes of stocks in anticipation of the other institutions' huge forced selling. Table 3 and Figure 4 describe the morning of October 19,1987—the day of the crash. This scenario begins with the selling pressure that accumulated over the weekend. It then describes how interactive and reactive program trading in stocks and futures amplified the declines. These events set the stage for steeper declines during the afternoon of the crash. Analysis of Causal Relations Causal diagrams can be used to analyze the causal roles of their events along four dimensions: direct causes, indirect causes, sufficiency in the CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 63 TABLE 3 Events of the Morning of the 1987 Stock Market Crash S,: A large selling pressure accumulated over the weekend. S2: Sell orders rapidly accumulated when the New York Stock Exchange opened at 9:00 a.m. Monday, S3: and there were few buyers. O4: Consequently, most of the Dow Jones Industrial Average stocks did not open until after much delay. O5: Until 11:00 a.m., the Dow Jones Industrial Average was based in part on Friday's closing prices. O6: From 9:00 a.m. to 11:00 a.m., the Dow Jones Industrial Average declined sharply, A7: as large numbers of shares were sold by mutual funds A8: and large numbers of shares were sold by index arbitrageurs. S9: Meanwhile, the Chicago Mercantile Exchange opened on time. O10: Portfolio insurers who fell behind in their selling programs on Friday A u : sold large numbers of futures contracts throughout the morning. O]2: Futures contract prices declined more than the stock index prices. O13: A large but illusory discount existed between the futures and stock indices. R14: The size of the discount made selling stocks rather than futures relatively more attractive. S15: One portfolio insurer who had the authority to sell stocks A]6: sold 13 baskets of stocks worth $100 million each. R17: Index arbitrageurs believed that the large but illusory discount was real, R,8: and saw a tremendous profit opportunity. A19: Many index arbitrageurs sold the stock index and, R20: thinking that the prices of futures contracts would decline even further, A21: delayed buying the futures contracts. R22: The discount of futures relative to stocks made the stock market appear weak and overpriced to investors Ku: who were discouraged from buying stocks. Note. Based on Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms (1988, pp. 30-34). circumstances, and necessity in the circumstances. This analysis provides a basis for evaluating the quality of opposing causal explanations. Direct Causes. Discourse comprehension research has shown that an event's perceived causal centrality and importance generally increase with the number of direct causal relations with other events. We can use direct causal relations as an index of causal centrality and importance in our diagrams. The most central node in Figure 3 has seven direct causal relations (see O7). The two most central nodes in Figure 4 have eight and five direct causal relations (O6 and O13, respectively). These highly central nodes all refer to securities prices. The significant discount (O13) is especially noteworthy because it shows that an abnormally large price disparity existed between the stock and futures indices. Its causal centrality shows that it had an important and pervasive influence on subsequent market behavior. 64 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER (8) Figure 4. The morning of the 1987 stock market crash (events based on Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms, 1988, pp. 3C*-34). Indirect Causes. An event's indirect causal relations also define its causal role. Consider, for example, the Securities and Exchange Commission's (SEC's) conclusion about the indirect role of market psychology: In addition to direct effects, the existence of futures trading and the use of derivative products in index-related trading strategies, in our view, had a significant indirect [italics added] impact on the markets—particularly on October 19—in the form of negative market psychology. The knowledge by market participants of the existence of active portfolio insurance strategies created, in our view, a market "overhang" effect in both the futures and stock markets. (SEC, 1988, p. xiii) CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 65 Our diagrams show that indirect causes are necessary to adequately explain the steep stock price declines. In Figure 3, the causal role of O 7 (stock price declines) is more clearly evident if one traces beyond its direct consequences through intervening psychological events (R15, R17, and R18) to its more distant and indirect consequences (A10, A13, A19, and A20). These indirect consequences of O 7 are also its direct or indirect causal antecedents. In Figure 4, the causal role of O13 (the discount of futures relative to stocks) is more clearly evident if one traces through its direct psychological consequences (R14, R17, and R22) to its more distant and indirect consequences (A16, A19, A21, and R23). These indirect consequences of O 13 in turn directly caused further stock price declines (O6) and indirectly caused additional futures price declines (O12). These events ultimately caused the discount (O13) to widen further. Notably, Figure 4 also shows only indirect causal relations between futures sales and stock sales (e.g., see A u and A19). As discussed later, the absence of a direct causal relation between those events led some investigators to disagree about the causes of the crash. Causal Sufficiency. The criterion of sufficiency in the circumstances recognizes that no single event by itself is sufficient for an outcome. Consistent with the cascade theory, Figures 3 and 4 show that the stock price declines were caused by a complex web of interactive and reactive program trading. Because each trading strategy was necessary but not sufficient for the crash, an explanation is incomplete if it attributes the crash to only one trading strategy. An explanation is also incomplete if it ignores the psychological determinants of trading behavior. For example, a complete explanation for why index arbitrageurs sold more stocks than they bought (A19 in Figure 3) must include the arbitrageurs' beliefs about others' imminent trades (R1S-R18 in Figure 3). An explanation would be incomplete if it considered only the prevailing securities prices (O 7 and O14) and the portfolio insurers' actual sales of futures (A13). Counter)'actual Necessity. A single event may also be considered causally important if its counterfactual removal would have significantly altered the course of subsequent events. The criterion of necessity in the circumstances discussed earlier allows the investigator to consider the counterfactual consequences of removing specific events. For example, Figure 4 shows that if stocks had opened on time (contrary to O4), the posted stock prices would have declined more sharply (contrary to O6). This in turn would have reduced the size of the discount (contrary to O13). Similarly, if futures trading on the Chicago Mercantile Exchange had not begun until most stocks had opened (contrary to S9), portfolio insurers would not have sold futures contracts (contrary to A n ) . Again, this would 66 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER have resulted in a smaller discount. Some investigators' recommendations regarding how to prevent future crashes reveal that the investigators considered these counterfactual implications. In summary, the analysis of direct causes, indirect causes, causal sufficiency, and causal necessity can provide a more complete understanding of an event's causal role. The causal analysis also provides a basis for evaluating the quality of opposing causal explanations. Analysis of Disagreements Some investigators attributed the crash to all of the major program trading strategies, others attributed the crash to only a few of those strategies, and yet others attributed the crash to fundamental changes in investors' perceptions. In this section, we use our causal diagrams to analyze two kinds of causal disagreement. In the first case, different people attributed the crash to different parts of the same implicitly agreed-upon minimal sufficient condition. In the second case, different people attributed the crash to different minimal sufficient conditions. Different Parts of the Same Minimal Sufficient Condition. Two investigative commissions who offered relatively complete causal explanations agreed that both the portfolio insurers and the index arbitrageurs played a significant role during the crash: While index arbitrageurs may not have accounted for a substantial part of total daily volume, they were particularly active during the day at times of substantial price movements. They were not, however, the primary cause of the movements; rather, they were the transmission mechanism for the pressures initiated by other institutions. (Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms, 1988, p. 42) Futures trading and strategies involving the use of futures were not the "sole cause" of the market break. Nevertheless, the existence of futures on stock indexes and the use of the various strategies involving "program trading" were a significant factor in accelerating and exacerbating the declines. (SEC, 1988, p. xiii) Both conclusions are consistent with the cascade theory's claim that each trading strategy contributes to a crash. In contrast, some portfolio insurers who actively sold futures denied their role in the crash. When told that portfolio insurance influenced 20% of stock selling during the crash, one portfolio insurance manager asked "What about the other 80%?" (Wallace, 1988, p. Dl). His question implicitly argues that portfolio insurance alone was not a sufficient cause. Other portfolio insurance managers argued that the real damage was done by CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 67 index arbitrageurs who traded in anticipation of the portfolio insurers' trades. Those managers placed more explanatory weight on index arbitrage than on their own portfolio insurance trading behavior. By not fully acknowledging their own role in the crash, the managers' explanations were less complete than those of the aforementioned investigative commissions. Node density, causal distance, and actor-observer differences might explain why the portfolio insurers were more willing to blame the index arbitrageurs than themselves. The portfolio insurers' actions (A13 of Figure 3; An and A16 of Figure 4) have an average of 3.33 causal relations. That is slightly more than the 2.8 average causal relations for the index arbitrageurs' actions (A19 and A20 of Figure 3; A8, A19, and A2i of Figure 4). In addition, three nodes representing index arbitrageurs' actions have direct causal relations with declining stock prices. In contrast, only one node representing portfolio insurers' actions has a direct causal relation with declining stock prices. These differences in node densities and causal distance might have made it more difficult for the money managers to understand their own role in the crash. The portfolio insurers' conclusions may also be attributed to actor-observer differences. From the portfolio insurers' perspective, their own actions may have appeared to them as standing conditions, whereas the index arbitrageurs' actions may have stood out as events in relation to the causal field. Whatever the specific reasons for disagreement, all of the portfolio insurers managers did attribute the crash to at least part of the same minimal sufficient condition that was identified by the SEC (1988) and the Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms (1988). When pressed further, one manager conceded this point: "I'm not saying that portfolio insurance was not part of the fabric of the decline. But that fabric has many more threads than portfolio insurance" (Wallace, 1988, p. D8). Thus, the manager's initial disagreement with the investigative commissions was more apparent than real. His later comments reveal that he at least implicitly agreed with the minimal sufficient condition described by the cascade theory. We now turn to a more fundamental disagreement about the cascade theory. Different Minimal Sufficient Conditions. Two investigative commissions agreed that the minimal sufficient condition described in the cascade theory is a valid description of the crash. Although those commissions placed more explanatory weight on program trading practices, they also acknowledged the role of precipitating conditions: Whatever the causes of the original downward pressure on the equity market, the mandate of the Task Force was to focus on those factors which transformed this downward pressure into the alarming events of the stock market decline. (Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms, 1988, pp. 1-2) 68 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER We may never know what precise combination of investor psychology, economic developments and trading technologies caused the events of October. Instead, the Report attempts to reconstruct the trading activity during the October market break and analyze how the trading systems for stock and its derivatives (i.e., options and futures) may have contributed to the rapidity and depth of the market decline. (SEC, 1988, p. xi) In contrast, the CFTC concluded that the massive selling of stocks and futures "was precipitated by an unprecedented change in investors' perceptions and was not initiated by technical trading strategies which interacted with each other and the stock market" (CFTC, 1988b, p. 1). By denying program trading's role, the CFTC implicitly argued that the precipitating conditions alone were a sufficient cause. To support its conclusion, the CFTC analyzed stock and futures trades in 5- and 10-min intervals in the days surrounding the crash. It found that portfolio insurance sales of futures was neither particularly heavy when stock prices fell the most, nor particularly light when stock prices began to recover. The CFTC argued that its findings "cast substantial doubt upon both the cascade theory and the supposition that futures prices were leading the stock market as reasonable representations of what occurred during the morning of October 19" (CFTC, 1988a, p. vi). The CFTC's disagreement with the other commissions is fundamental. It is not merely an example of attributing the same event to different parts of the same implicitly agreed-upon minimal sufficient condition. Unlike the other investigative commissions, the CFTC argued that the minimal sufficient condition for the crash did not include program trading. When taken at its face value, the CFTC's conclusion appears to discredit the cascade theory. Some people might further argue that the opposing conclusions about program trading's role are supported by different yet equally valid causal models. However, our diagrams clearly show that the commission's conclusion is neither complete nor plausible. For example, by analyzing the time series of only actual stock and futures trades, the CFTC's explanation is incomplete because it failed to consider the pervasive psychological causes that were widely known to have influenced trading during the crash (see also Gamill & Marsh, 1988). Even a layperson can see from our diagrams that the interactions among different program traders must be explained at least in part by those psychological causes. The CFTC's explanation is also implausible because it assumes a direct causal relation between portfolio insurance and index arbitrage trading behavior. Our diagrams explicitly show that only indirect causal relations existed between sales of futures and sales of stocks (e.g., see nodes A n and A19 in Figure 4). The absence of a direct causal relation between those events argues against finding a direct correlation between the trading volumes of stocks and futures. CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 69 Why, then, did the CFTC offer its implausible explanation? One possibility is that the CFTC's staff members simply did not know about the indirect and psychological causes before it published its own report. Such knowledge limitations are not tenable, for several reasons. First, the CFTC officially restated its conclusions in a press release after the other investigative reports had been published. It is difficult to conceive how knowledge limitations could explain why the CFTC's experienced staff would have overlooked or misunderstood the other reports. Second, the CFTC's explanation can account for all of the setting information (Sj-Ag in Figure 3; all other S nodes in Figures 3 and 4), all of the actual buying and selling behavior in both the stock and futures markets (A), and all of the actual stock and futures price outcomes (O). In contrast, its explanation fails to account for 10 out of 43 nodes (approximately 23%), all of which are psychological responses (R). This observed frequency of omitted psychological responses is significantly greater than the approximately 2.6 psychological responses that would be expected if the 10 nodes were randomly omitted, X*(l) = 27.58, p < .001. Finally, the 10 omitted events do not have more direct causal relations than the price outcomes' other causal antecedents and consequences, Mann-Whitney U = 146.0,p > .5, one-tailed. This argues against an interaction between causal density and the CFTC staff members' cognitive ability to understand the causal relations. Another possibility is that the CFTC's opposition to the cascade theory can be attributed to pragmatic factors, such as the desire to dissuade decision makers from imposing costly regulations on the futures markets. Although we do not have direct empirical evidence to implicate the role of pragmatic factors, many market observers believed that the CFTC's conclusions were biased and self-serving (e.g., see Waldman, 1988). In summary, we have used story-based causal diagrams to analyze opposing explanations for the 1987 crash. The diagrams reveal that the portfolio insurers' and CFTC's explanations were incomplete because they failed to account for all known events and causal relations and that the CFTC's explanation was implausible because it asserted the existence of direct causal relations between events whose causal relations were only indirect. Our analysis of the diagrams' content and structural properties suggests that cognitive constraints may plausibly account for some of the portfolio insurers' incomplete explanations. In contrast, the CFTC's selective explanation was likely driven by motivational rather than cognitive factors. DISCUSSION Stock market crashes, oil spills, and civil wars are examples of complex and undesirable events that affect many lives. In order to effectively control such events, it is useful to understand their causes. However, the causes of 70 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER a complex event can be a source of major disagreement. Our objective has been to illustrate how story-based causal diagrams can facilitate the analysis of such disagreements. We applied the Trabasso et al. (1989) procedures to a narrative of 1987 crash events, and then used the resulting story-based diagrams to analyze some major disagreements about the causes of the crash. Our analyses yielded four main findings. First, some explanations for the crash were incomplete because they omitted known events and causal relations. The story categories in our diagrams further highlighted that one incomplete explanation selectively omitted almost the entire category of psychological events. Second, one investigative commission's explanation was implausible because it asserted the existence of direct causal relations between events whose causal relations were in fact only indirect. Third, the diagrams distinguished between two kinds of causal disagreement. One disagreement involved attribution to different parts of the same implicitly agreed-upon set of conditions, whereas the other disagreement involved attribution to different sets of conditions. Fourth, an analysis of the diagrams' content and structural properties revealed that cognitive factors can plausibly account for some but not all of the incomplete explanations for the crash. In summary, story-based causal diagrams can facilitate the analysis of causal relations in complex settings. In the following, we compare our approach to Graesser and Franklin's (1990) QUEST model of question answering. We then explore the possible advantages of using causal diagrams to aid causal comprehension and explanation. Components of Good Causal Explanations Our objective has been to use causal diagrams to identify the components of a complete and plausible explanation for complex events. Following Pennington and Hastie (1993), we have argued that a complete explanation should account for all known events and causal relations and that a plausible explanation should not contradict them. In contrast, the objective of Graesser and Franklin's (1990) QUEST model is to incorporate known cognitive constraints on people's ability to find good answers to question about an event's causal role in a knowledge structure. Accordingly, QUEST uses three psychologically validated search criteria that simulate people's tendency to give incomplete answers. An arc search procedure selects candidate nodes in the knowledge structure that are on legal paths connected to the queried node and prunes out nodes that are on illegal paths. For example, a good answer to a why-event question should include the event's antecedents but not its consequences. Constraint satisfaction avoids irrelevant and implausible answers by pruning out answers that are inconsistent with the content of the queried node. Finally, a structural distance constraint selects nodes that are structurally CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 71 close to the queried node, such that the quality of an answer is negatively correlated with the number of arcs between the answer node and the queried node. QUEST'S search criteria may be unable to identify a complete causal explanation for a complex event, for two reasons. First, recursive event chains in complex settings such as the 1987 crash blur the distinction between cause and effect, and they diminish the usefulness of the distinction between direct and indirect causes. Without those distinctions, QUEST would have difficulty finding good explanations for complex events. Second, QUEST'S search criteria may sometimes give high quality ratings to incomplete answers. For example, many of the incomplete explanations for the 1987 crash correctly attributed the stock price declines to some of their direct causal antecedents and thereby would satisfy QUEST'S search criteria. This suggests that a more global search criterion is needed to identify the components of a more complete explanation. Such a criterion might, for example, identify all of an event's direct and indirect causal antecedents in a causal diagram. The more complete set of nodes could then be used to evaluate the relative completeness of different causal explanations for the event, as we have done in our analysis of the 1987 crash. A global search criterion would be useful to decision makers, inasmuch as complete causal explanations provide a better basis for making good decisions about how to control events. Although a global search criterion might enable QUEST to identify the components of a complete causal explanation, in reality cognitive and pragmatic constraints lead most individuals to attribute events to incomplete rather than complete causes. In the following, we briefly describe how causal diagrams may reduce those constraints. Advantages of Causal Diagrams Earlier we reviewed evidence that knowledge and memory limitations can prevent individuals from fully understanding all of an event's causal relations. Generalizing from prior research on the use of external memory aids to facilitate judgment and decision making (e.g., see Fischhoff, 1982), an explicit causal diagram may reduce the memory constraints on a person's ability to encode and retrieve causal relations. For example, a causal diagram may allow an investigator to more fully consider the causal roles of already identified events before gathering additional evidence, to consider one part of the event representation without losing sight of the other parts, and to counterfactually trace the consequences of adding or removing events without having to rely on limited memory. Discourse comprehension research has demonstrated that schematic knowledge greatly facilitates the encoding and retrieval of event relations (e.g., see Bransford & Johnson, 1972; Chiesi et al., 1979; Pichert & Ander- 72 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER son, 1977; Smith & Swinney, 1992; Spilich et al, 1979). Although the Trabasso et al. (1989) causal network model is not a complete substitute for domain-specific knowledge, its story categories identify the basic components of a complete and plausible event explanation. As such, the categories can help identify incomplete explanations and can guide the search for missing information. For example, if physical events alone do not sufficiently explain a protagonist's behavior, the causal network model model would direct attention to the protagonist's goals and internal reactions. Finally, pragmatic constraints can also lead people to.attribute outcomes to incomplete causes. For example, it is probably not a coincidence that the investigative commissions with close ties to the stock market tended to blame the crash on the futures markets, and vice versa. Other studies have shown that people tend to be less willing to offer incomplete or implausible explanations when they expect that their explanations will be scrutinized by others (e.g., Kunda, 1990; Tetlock, 1983, 1985). Those studies suggest that if the causal structure of a scenario is made available to all interested parties through an explicit causal diagram, biased explanations will be offered less often, and those that are offered will less likely survive others' careful scrutiny. Nonetheless, it should also be recognized that an explicit causal diagram may sometimes hinder rather than help comprehension. Just as some readers tend to process information passively and conduct little elaborative or reconstructive processing unless they are explicitly instructed to do so (e.g., McKoon & Ratcliff, 1992), individuals may engage in less elaborative processing when they are given a preconstructed causal diagram. Research on availability biases has demonstrated that individuals are often misled by problem representations and may have difficulty retrieving other relevant but unspecified information from memory (e.g., see Fischhoff, Slovic, & Lichtenstein, 1978; Mehle, Gettys, Manning, Baca, & Fisher, 1981; Tversky & Kahneman, 1973; see also Pennington & Hastie, 1988). Along these lines, a causal diagram might make individuals less likely to spontaneously generate other relevant causes that they might identify without the diagram. A causal diagram may also induce a hindsight bias whereby individuals assign a higher probability to a past outcome than they would have estimated in foresight (see Hawkins & Hastie, 1990, for a review). Such hindsight and availability biases might make the causal relations in a causal diagram appear more plausible than is warranted. These potential disadvantages highlight the importance of carefully constructing causal diagrams that are objectively complete and unbiased. Altogether, the representation of complex events as networks of causally related nodes can provide a powerful tool for analyzing a scenario's causal structure and for understanding why people misunderstand or dis- CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 73 agree about causal relations. The methods described in this article, if carefully applied, can provide such a tool. That such a tool is needed is illustrated by the description of a triple-murder trial case in 1994 in Russia's first jury trial since the Bolsheviks banned juries in 1917: There was no verbatim transcript of the trial. Neither the defense nor the prosecution thought to make diagrams or maps to help jurors visualize an extremely complicated web of events that may or may not have occurred during the night in question. "It's our first experience with juries," said Yevgeny Ciderenko, deputy justice minister for reform. "Later, we'll have such things" (Stead, 1994, p. 4). REFERENCES Axelrod, R. (Ed.). (1976). The structure of decision: The cognitive maps of political elites. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Bartlett, F.C. (1932). Remembering: An experimental and social study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bettman, J.R., & Weitz, B.A. (1983). Attributions in the board room: Causal reasoning in corporate annual reports. Administrative Science Quarterly, 28, 165-183. Bindra, D., Clarke, K.A., & Shultz, T.R. (1980). Understanding predictive relations of necessity and sufficiency in formally equivalent "causal" and "logical" problems. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 109, 422-433. Black, J.B., & Bower, G.M. (1980). Story understanding as problem solving. Poetics, 9, 223-250. Bloom, C.P., Fletcher, C.R., van den Broek, P., Reitz, L., & Shapiro, B.P. (1990). An online assessment of causal reasoning during comprehension. Memory and Cognition, 18, 65-71. Bransford, J.D., & Johnson, M.K. (1972). Contextual prerequisites for understanding: Some investigations of comprehension and recall. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11, 717-726. Chiesi, H.L., Spilich, G.J., & Voss, J.F. (1979). Acquisition of domain-related information in relation to high and low domain knowledge. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 257-274. Collingwood, R.G. (1940). An essay on metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Commodity Futures Trading Commission. (1988a). Final report on stock index futures and cash market activity during October 1987 to the U.S. Commodity Futures Trading Commission. The Division of Economic Analysis and the Division of Trading and Markets. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Commodity Futures Trading Commission. (1988b, February 1). [News release]. Washington, DC: CFTC. Danto, A.C. (1985). Narration and knowledge. New York: Columbia University Press. Downing, C.J., Sternberg, R.J., & Ross, B.H. (1985). Multicausal inference: Evaluation of evidence in causally complex situations. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 114, 239-263. Einhorn, HJ., & Hogarth, R.M. (1986). Judging probable cause. Psychological Bulletin, 99, 3-19. Fischhoff, B. (1982). Debiasing. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases (pp. 422-444). New York: Cambridge University Press. 74 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER Fischhoff, B., Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein, S. (1978). Fault trees: Sensitivity of estimated failure probabilities to problem representation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 4, 330-334. Fletcher, C.R., & Bloom, C.P. (1988). Causal reasoning in the comprehension of simple narratives. Journal of Memory and Language, 27, 235-244. Gamill, J.F., & Marsh, T.A. (1988). Trading activity and price behavior in the stock and stock index futures markets in October 1987. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 2, 25-44. Gernsbacher, M.A., Varner, K.R., & Faust, M.E. (1990). Investigating differences in general comprehension skill. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 16, 430-445. Graesser, A.C. (1981). Prose comprehension beyond the word. New York: Springer-Verlag. Graesser, A.C., & Clark, L.F. (1985). The structures and procedures of implicit knowledge. Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Graesser, A.C., & Franklin, S.P. (1990). QUEST: A cognitive model of question answering. Discourse Processes, 13, 279-303. Graesser, A.C., Lang, K.L., & Roberts, R.M. (1991). Question answering in the context of stories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 120, 254-277. Grice, H.P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics: Vol. 3. Speech acts (pp. 41-58). New York: Academic. Hart, M.L.A., & Honore, A.M. (1985). Causation in the law. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hawkins, S.A., & Hastie, R. (1990). Hindsight: Biased judgments of past events after the outcomes are known. Psychological Bulletin, 107, 311-327. Hilton, D.J. (1990). Conversational processes and causal explanations. Psychological Bulletin, 107, 65-81. Hogarth, R.M., Michaud, C., & Mery, J. (1980). Decision behavior in urban development: A methodological approach and substantive considerations. Acta Psychologica, 45, 95117. Hume, D. (1964). A treatise of human nature. Aalen, West Germany: Scientia Verlag. (Original work published 1739). Jones, E.E., & Nisbett, R.E. (1972). The actor and the observer: Divergent perceptions of the causes of behavior. In E.E. Jones, D.E. Kanouse, H.H. Kelley, R.E. Nisbett, S. Valins, & B. Weiner (Eds.) Attribution: Perceiving the causes of behavior (pp. 79-94). Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press. Just, M.A., & Carpenter, P.A. (1992). A capacity theory of comprehension: Individual differences in working memory. Psychological Review, 99, 122-149. Keenan, J.M., Baillet, S.D., & Brown, P. (1984). The effects of causal cohesion on comprehension and memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 23, 115126. Kintsch, W.A. (1988). The role of knowledge in discourse comprehension: A construction-integration model. Psychological Review, 95, 163-182. Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 480-498. Lewis, D.K. (1976). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Mackie, J.L. (1974). The cement of the universe (pp. 29-58). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Mandler, J.M., & Johnson, N.S. (1977). Remembrance of things parsed: Story structure and recall. Cognitive Psychology, 9, 111-151. Maruyama, M. (1963). The second cybernetics: Deviation-amplifying mutual causal processes. American Scientist, 51, 164-179. McKoon, G., & Ratcliff, R. (1992). Inference during reading. Psychological Review, 99, 440-466. Mehle, T., Gettys, C.F., Manning, C., Baca, S., & Fisher, S. (1981). The availability explanation of excessive probability judgments. Acta Psychologica, 49, 127-140. CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 75 Mill, J.S. (1973). System of logic. In J.M. Robson (Ed.), Collected works of John Stuart Mill (Vols. 7-8). Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press. (Original work published 1872). Myers, J.L., Shinjo, M., & Duffy, S.A. (1987). Degree of causal relatedness and memory. Journal of Memory and Language, 26, 453-465. Newell, A., & Simon, H.A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. O'Brien, E.J. (1987). Antecedent search processes and the structure of text. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 13, 278-290. O'Brien, E.J., & Myers, J.L. (1987). The role of causal connections in the retrieval of text. Memory and Cognition, 15, 419-427. Ohtsuka, K., & Brewer, W.F. (1992). Discourse organization in the comprehension of temporal order in narrative texts. Discourse Processes, 15, 317-336. Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1986). Evidence evaluation in complex decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 242-258. Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1988). Explanation-based decision making: Effects of memory structure on judgment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 14, 521-533. Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1992). Explaining the evidence: Tests of the story model for juror decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 189-206. Pennington, N., & Hastie, R. (1993). Reasoning in explanation-based decision making. Cognition, 49, 123-163. Pichert, J.W., & Anderson, R.C. (1977). Taking different perspectives on a story. Journal of Educational Psychology, 69, 309-315. Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms. (1988, January). Report of the Presidential Task Force on Market Mechanisms: Submitted to the President of the United States, The Secretary of the Treasury, and the Chairman of the Federal Reserve Board. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Rumelhart, D. (1980). Schemata: The building blocks of cognition. In R. Spiro, B. Bruce, & W. Brewer (Eds.), Theoretical issues in reading comprehension (pp. 33-58). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Schank, R.C., & Abelson, R.P. (1977). Scripts, plans, goats, and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Securities and Exchange Commission. (1988). The October 1987 market break: A report by the division of market regulation. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Sev6n, G. (1984). Cognitive maps of past and future economic events. Acta Psychologica, 56, 71-79. Smith, E.E., & Swinney, D.A. (1992). The role of schemas in text: A real-time examination. Discourse Processes, 15, 303-316. Spilich, G.J., Vesonder, G.T., Chiesi, H.L., & Voss, J.F. (1979). Text processing of domainrelated information for individuals with high and low domain knowledge. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 275-290. Staw, B.M. (1980). Rationality and justification in organizational life. IN B.M. Staw & L.L. Cummings (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 2), (pp. 45-80). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Stead, D. (1994, January 5). Russia, where jury trial fulfills a dream. The Christian Science Monitor, p. 4. Tetlock, P.E. (1983). Accountability and the perseverance of first impressions. Social Psychology Quarterly, 46, 285-292. Tetlock, P.E. (1985). Accountability: A social check on the fundamental attribution error. Social Psychology Quarterly, 48, 227-236. 76 SHAPIRO, VAN DEN BROEK, AND FLETCHER Tetlock, P.E., & Boettger, R. (1989). Accountability: A social magnifier of the dilution effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 388-398. Trabasso, T., Secco, T., & van den Broek, P. (1984), Causal cohesion and story coherence. In G. Bower (Ed.), Learning and motivation (Vol. 15). San Diego, CA: Academic. Trabasso, T., & Sperry, L.L. (1985). Causal relatedness and importance of story events. Journal of Memory and Language, 24, 595-611, Trabasso, T., & Suh, S. (1993). Understanding text; Achieving explanatory coherence through online inferences and mental operations in working memory. Discourse Processes, 16, 3-34. Trabasso, T., & van den Broek, P. (1985). Causal thinking and the representation of narrative events. Journal of Memory and Language, 24, 612-630. Trabasso, T., van den Broek, P., & Suh, S. (1989). Logical necessity and transitivity of causal relations in stories. Discourse Processes, 12, 1-25. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207-232. van den Broek, P. (1988). The effects of causal relations and hierarchical position on the importance of story statements. Journal of Memory and Language, 27, 1-22. van den Broek, P. (1990a). The causal inference maker: Towards a process model of inference generation in text comprehension. In D.A, Balota, G.B. Flores d'Arcais, & K. Rayner (Eds.), Comprehension processes in reading (pp, 423-445). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. van den Broek, P. (1990b). Causal inferences in the comprehension of narrative texts. In A.C. Graesser & G.H. Bower (Eds.), Psychology of learning and motivation: Vol. 25. Inferences and text comprehension (pp. 175-194). San Diego, CA: Academic. van den Broek, P., Risden, K., & Husebye-Hartman, E. (in press). The role of readers' standards for coherence in the generation of inferences during reading. In R.F. Lorch, Jr., & E.J. O'Brien (Eds.), Sources of coherence in text comprehension. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Waldman, S. (1988, February 15). Adding up the crash reports: Studies in self-interest. Newsweek, p. 54. Wallace, A.C. (1988, January 13). Portfolio insurers reject blame. New York Times, pp. D1, D8. Watson, D. (1982). The actor and the observer: How are their perceptions of causality divergent? Psychological Bulletin, 92, 682-700. APPENDIX Summary of Computerized Program Trading in Stocks and Futures Various computerized program trading strategies bought and sold large volumes of stocks and futures during the crash. Stocks represent corporate ownership claims. Normally, stock prices depend primarily on corporations' current and future earnings. Stock prices generally fall when more shares of stock are waiting to be sold than bought (supply exceeds demand). Conversely, stock prices generally rise when more shares are waiting to be bought than sold (demand exceeds supply). Futures contracts represent promises to deliver stocks (or a specified equivalent cash settlement) at a specified time. Futures contract prices depend primarily on the price of the underlying stock (or portfolio of stocks) and, thus, normally CAUSAL DIAGRAMS 77 rise and fall with stock prices. Many stocks and futures are traded in "baskets" or portfolios of securities, each with its own price index. For example, the Standard and Poor's (S&P) 500 stock index is a weighted average of the prices of 500 underlying stocks, and the price of the corresponding S&P 500 futures contract is normally based on the price of the underlying S&P 500 stock index. During the crash, futures traded at an abnormally large discount relative to stocks. The trading strategies of index arbitrageurs, portfolio insurers, and mutual funds received much of the blame for the abnormal discount between futures and stocks. Their computerized strategies used the stock and futures indices to buy and sell millions of dollars of securities in a matter of seconds. Index arbitrageurs attempted to profit from price disparities between stocks and futures by selling the higher priced stock index and buying the lower priced futures index. In addition, many pension and endowment funds used portfolio insurance strategies to mechanically compute optimal stock-to-cash ratios for stock portfolios. During the crash, these strategies automatically generated buy and sell orders based on the prevailing trends in stock prices. Because trading of futures contracts usually could be accomplished more quickly and at lower cost than trading of stocks, most portfolio insurers attempted to adjust their stock-to-cash ratios by selling futures contracts rather than by selling the stocks directly. The cash raised by selling futures contracts was expected to provide an effective hedge against falling stock prices. Finally, many mutual funds allowed their customers to redeem their shares on demand. During the crash, those mutual funds received many customer redemption requests and therefore had to sell large blocks of shares.