A LECTURE ON PLATO'S APOLOGY Author(s): James Redfield Source: The Journal of General Education , July 1963, Vol. 15, No. 2 (July 1963), pp. 93108 Published by: Penn State University Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/27795866 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of General Education This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATO'S APOLOGY James Redfield Note: This lecture was delivered to a second-year course in the Humanities at the College of the Univer sity of Chicago. This course explores various literary modes ? in particular history, philosophy, and rhetoric. In my lecture I tried to do two things at once: to suggest a possible reading of the text before the students, and, further, to encourage the students to question the modal categories of the course. I am going to talk to you today about Plato's Apology of Socra tes. In this course you read the Apology as an example of a literary mode, an example of rhetoric as distinguished from his tory and philosophy. I think we all know what history and philosophy are ? history is what is written by historians, philoso phy what is written by philosophers. But we do not have, in our world, people called rhetoricians, and so it is difficult to say at a na?ve level what we mean by rhetoric. Sometimes we mean by rhetoric simply the way in which a man makes persuasive whatever he has to say; we can speak of the rhetoric of an his torian, a philosopher, a novelist, or even of a poet. Or else we restrict rhetoric to a few kinds of speeches ? to cases in court or political speeches; we speak of Clarence Darrow or Winston Churchill as great rhetoricians. In either case, while rhetoric may be useful at certain moments and to certain professions, it is not a profession in itself. The primary skill of the lawyer lies in his knowledge of the law, of the statesman in his judgment of politi cal situations; good rhetoric helps, but it helps men who are pro fessionally something else; it is an instrument to their real skill. In fifth-century Athens, on the other hand, in the world of the Apology, there were professional rhetoricians just as today there are philosophers and historians; rhetoric was a special profession. It was, in fact, one of the most distinguished professions. A pro fessional man serves his community; communities produce the 93 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION professions they require. So the Athenian rhetorician was a prod uct of the special structure of the Athenian political community. Athens, as you know, was a direct democracy. Athens was like our democracy in that final authority belonged to the ma jority of citizens; Athens was unlike our democracy in that im mediate authority also belonged directly to the people. The Athenian system was democracy without representation and without bureaucracy. We elect a congress to pass our laws and a president to carry them out; our president appoints subordi nate administrators and a judiciary. The Athenian people was its own congress and judiciary, and to a large extent its own ad ministration. It is hard for us to imagine just how direct this system was. The whole people, or as many as turned up in the assembly on any given day, voted on each law, as if we should be governed by daily referendums. There was no general budget; each expenditure was introduced as a separate bill and had to be approved by a majority of the assembly. There were, of course, officials, both elected and chosen by lot, but they had very little authority. Hardly any official act could be performed without a special vote by the people. Details too minor to be discussed be fore the assembly came up before the law courts, which were as much an administrative as a judicial branch. Officials usually had power only to initiate a case before the courts; the authority of a popular vote was required for any proceeding. Athenian politics, then, was radically democratic; but it was not equalitarian. All Greek political thought begins with the assumption that society is divided into two classes: variously called the rich and the poor, the few and the many, or the good and the bad. The Greek tradition treats this division as a fact of nature; no one ever proposes to alter it. There will always be a few people with money and influence and many people without. For this reason, oligarchy is, for the main Greek tradition, the natural constitution. Even many Athenians looked upon democracy as a highly unnatural form of government. Democ racy hardly existed outside of Athens. Most Greek cities were run by a few wealthy families who shared the offices between them and made decisions by mutual agreement, without reference to the people. These cities were divided into a political and a nonpolitical class. The many were not expected to concern them 94 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATO's APOLOGY selves with the affairs of the community, and on the whole they did not. Politics was the birthright of the men who belonged to the great houses. Athens became a democracy without any radical change in its social structure. The political class continued to exist in Athens, and it continued to be the political class. There is no known case in which a poor man was elected to a high office of the fifth-century Athenian government. The men who held the offices of honor and responsibility ? who became generals, am bassadors, treasurers ? were members of the great houses. But they held office without authority; they had responsibility with out power. Any official ? this happened even to Pericles ? could be removed from office by popular vote, at any time. Furthermore, an official could not take any important step with out the authorization of a popular vote. Political leaders carried on their policy by constant reference to the assembly; administra tors had constantly to secure decisions in the popular courts. Athens, then, was a democracy based on inequality. The re sult was a certain kind of balance of power. To the political class belonged initiative; to the many belonged authority. All the citizens could vote in the assembly, but they voted on the issues as defined by the speakers in debate, and the speakers were usually rich men. In the law courts the people decided the cases, but the litigants were again usually rich men. The democratic institutions regulated relations between the classes. This arrangement was, I think, accepted by both sides. Per haps the best proof of this is that the system was continued for more than a century without ever being written into law. In theory anyone could be elected to office, anyone could propose motions in the assembly, anyone could prosecute a statesman for corruption. If all these things remained the privilege of a limited class it was because nearly everyone approved of the arrange ment. The class division was not constitutional but customary; those who attempted to cross the class line were restrained with the usual sanctions of custom: ridicule and contempt. In fact, during the best years of the democracy, the arrange ment was beneficial to both sides. The people had their affairs managed for them by men who were raised for politics ? whose main occupation, in fact, was, after business, politics ? while the 95 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION rich received the honor and sometimes the more material privi leges which come to men in office. Politics was carried on by means of a constantly re-created agreement between the few and the many. This system, I think, explains the importance of rhetoric in Athenian society. Rhetoric was the mode of reference, of com munication between the few and the many. Only the few were actually in touch with affairs ? this was a society without news papers or any form of mass communications. Only the few dealt with facts. Before the people could vote, everything had to be turned into words; events had to be, as it were, translated into speeches. The many did not really decide between policy and policy, but between speech and speech. Rhetoric was the funda mental weapon of politics, and therefore the primary skill of the politician. Nearly all political questions were decided by a de bate, speech against speech, and the best speech usually won; without the power of speech a statesman could do nothing. In our society rhetoric is seldom more than an ornament on the serious business of things; in Athens it was at the heart of the operation of the society. The ordinary Athenian gentleman felt the need for rhetoric not so much in the assembly as in the law courts. Not every rich man took part in politics, and it was a full-time career only for a few, but any rich man could expect to come before the courts at one time or another. Because the courts handled, not only crimes and suits for damages, but the kind of administrative de tail which in our society is controlled by civil servants, an ap pearance in court was a normal part of everyday life. In the popular courts a man contested his tax liabilities, claimed an ex emption from military service, argued his right to a pension from the state treasury. And in the courts rhetoric was more than ever a necessity. These courts were without judges and without pro fessional lawyers, which is almost to say, without law. There were written laws, but as there were no courts of appeal the panel was not bound to abide by them; they decided on facts and law at once. There was no judge to enforce rules of relevance or discipline of argument; the issues in the case were defined by the parties as they went along. A man's whole career was likely to 96 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATO'S APOLOGY be put on trial in the course of a prosecution for some trivial offense. A lawsuit, then, was man against man and speech against speech. There was no notion of "the state of Illinois vs Mr. Peter Jones." As there were no official prosecutors, all prosecutions, even for murder or treason, were private. A law suit was a con test between two men, with the panel of jurors as umpire; which ever man made the greater impression would emerge the victor. Since not everyone has the power of words, a professional class of speech-writers grew up. A man had to speak for him self, but no one could prevent him from getting someone else to write his speech for him; he would then commit it to memory and deliver it as well as he could. A number of men made a good living by writing these speeches for considerable fees. These men were the professional rhetoricians. They were not lawyers; they had no special skill in the law; their profession de manded the pure skill of speech. The Apology is written in the tradition of these professional law court speeches. Plato is the greatest Greek stylist, and the speech he wrote is the greatest of all law court speeches. But it is not a new kind of speech. Plato was a virtuoso; he loved to write in the style of other men, or according to the rules of some traditional pattern; the Apology follows the classic pattern of the Athenian court speech. Through the years the rhetoricians had developed a vari ety of technical devices which turn up in one speech after an other. They had developed, for instance, a standard form. It was systematized and elaborated centuries later by the rhetorical teachers of the Roman empire, but in the early speeches, those contemporary with Socrates, the form is quite simple; there are four parts. First there is an introduction in which the speaker introduces himself and defines the issue between himself and his opponents; then there is a narration in which he relates the facts of the case in a way favorable to himself. Following this comes the refutation, in which the speaker answers the arguments of his opponents ? if he is the first speaker he will try to anticipate his opponent's line of defense. Finally there is a peroration in which the speaker appeals to the emotions of the jury and to the Gods. 97 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION Socrates' speech follows this four part form exactly. (Please notice, by the way, that when I speak of the Apology as a classic law court speech I mean only the long first section, which con cludes with the vote of the jury condemning Socrates. The second section, in which Socrates proposes his punishment, and the third part, spoken after he has been condemned to death, have no parallel in the literature of the courts; we will have to con sider them later.) Socrates' speech, then, follows the classic four part form. Each part, however, is subtly transformed, turned to a different purpose from that of an ordinary defense speech. Socrates begins by saying that he has no skill in speech, that in the skill of rhet oric he is absolutely outclassed by his adversaries, that he is a poor man who has no experience of public life. These remarks are commonplaces of the introduction; a gentleman will try for sympathy of the democratic jurors by claiming to be a simple man very much like themselves. In Socrates' mouth, however, these commonplaces have a new meaning. Socrates defines rhet oric, for instance, as the art of lying; when he says he is no rhetorician he is also saying that he is a better man than those who are. If he is a poor man it is not because he is ordinary but because he has adopted an extraordinary kind of holy poverty; if he has taken no part in politics it is because his life is devoted to something more important than politics. In the same way when Socrates comes to define the issues in the case he redefines them. He says that he has to answer, not one indictment, but two; the formal prosecution lodged against him is only the shadow of an informal prosecution which has been going on for years. The real charge against him has been lodged by the comic poets, and through them by the community as a whole. His real accusers are not present, or, if they are, they are not at the prosecutor's table but in the jury box; the real is sue is not between Socrates and Meletus but between Socrates and Athens. Socrates proposes in the introduction to defend his whole way of life. So when he turns to the narration he does not talk about particular offenses; he tells the story of his life. This again is not unusual; a man will often ask that a long career of public service be weighed in his favor against some particular offense, 98 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATO'S APOLOGY and speakers sometimes take the opportunity of defending their whole careers in connection with some trivial case. Socrates, however, turns the narration also to a new purpose. Instead of contrasting his supposed offenses with the rest of his life he as serts that his life, offenses and all, is part of a single and neces sary pattern. If the effect he had on the young men was unfor tunate, if he questioned traditional beliefs about the Gods, it was not his fault; these things were made necessary by his whole pattern of life, and that pattern was imposed upon him by God. He does not exactly deny the offense charged; he justifies it as a part of his whole career, and he demands that the career be judged as a whole. An ordinary speaker says: if my life as a whole has been virtuous you should forgive those parts of it which are not. Socrates says: if the whole is virtuous, the parts are virtuous also. And this is in keeping with the Socratic idea of ethics. Ethics, for him, is not a matter of particular moral or immoral acts; it is a matter of living well, of the development of the soul toward virtue in a complete life of learning and doing. There is no valid moral question except the question of a man s whole character. So in the refutation Socrates makes no attempt to argue particular points of fact or of law. Instead he puts his prosecutor on the stand and subjects him to a brief Socratic dialogue. Soc rates' refutation is not addressed to the question: is the charge true? but to the question: what does the charge mean? He asks of Meletus a reasoned explanation of the indictment, and has no difficulty in reducing everything Meletus says to nonsense. Soc rates does not answer the charge; he makes it disappear. His refutation is a reflection of the whole character of the Socratic quest, which is not so much a quest for truth as a quest for mean ing. In the Republic, for instance, Socrates does not try to show that Polemarchus is wrong about justice; he tries to show that he has no real idea about it at all. So in the Apology he does not try to show that Meletus is wrong about the impiety of Socrates; he demonstrates that Meletus has no solid idea of impiety in gen eral. And in so doing he excludes the prosecution from the case; the real issues lie between Socrates and the jury, and only Socra tes can tell his judges the real meaning of the trial. 99 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION Well then, men of Athens, I am not guilty according to the indictment of Meletus, I dont need much of a defense; what I have said is enough. As I said before the hatred against me is felt by many people and has been for a long time; you all know that. This it is that will convict me, and not Mele tus or Any tus. . . . (28a) So Socrates' real task is not the refutation of Meletus, but the refutation of Athens. The clearest reversal of the traditional form, however, comes after this in the peroration. A plea for justice is normally followed by a plea for mercy; in the peroration the de fendant appeals to the jury to remember his innocent children, and, in the name of the Gods, to spare him. Socrates devotes his peroration to an attack on perorations. He does not appeal to the jury; he instructs them in their obligations. There is no justice, gentlemen, in making an appeal to the jury to go against its judgment; nor in getting free by such an appeal. Justice is to teach and to persuade. Nor is the juror supposed to give judgment according to his pleasure; he is supposed to decide. He has given his oath not to favor those who appeal to him, but to judge according to the laws. We ought not to accustom you to break your oaths, nor ought you to accustom yourselves; for neither of us would be pious that way. Do not think, men of Athens, that I ought to do things here before you which I do not believe to be noble or just or pious, especially, by Zeus, when I am de fending myself against a charge of impiety. . . . Obviously if I were to persuade you and shift you from your oaths I would demonstrate that I do not believe in the existence of Gods, and in a peculiar way I would accuse myself by my defense. . . . But I do believe in them, men of Athens, as do none of my accusers, and I commit my case to you and to God to judge me as will be best for me and for you. (35b-d) Throughout the Apology Socrates refuses to accept the nor mal limitations of the case. He dismisses the formal indictment and addresses his defense to a different charge. He dismisses his accusers ? suggesting that they are playing some kind of un happy practical joke ? and speaks directly to the many. And in the peroration he denies the whole validity of Athenian trial by rhetoric. Rhetoric is an instrument, a tool for attaining a practical 100 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATo's APOLOGY end. The purpose of the rhetorician is to persuade ? to win his case, to pass his law, to carry his point. The language of the rhetorician is a means; good rhetoric is rhetoric which attains the end. A rhetorician can be judged only in terms of his success. Socrates rejects this notion of rhetoric from beginning to end ? from the beginning of his speech, where he says that the function of a good rhetorician should be to tell the truth, to the end, where he refuses to appeal to the emotions of the jury. Later, Socrates says that if he had wept and begged he would have been acquit ted. To have done so, then, would have been good rhetoric; Soc rates is convicted because his speech is governed by another standard; this standard, he says, makes rhetoric irrelevant. Socrates' attitude toward rhetoric is a part of his whole atti tude toward the community. The Socratic attitude toward the community, in fact, is at the heart of the speech, and we will have to consider it in some detail. The best place to begin, I think, is with Socrates' examination of Meletus. Come here Meletus and tell me this. What is it you think so much about; isn't it the excellence of the young? Certainly. Well then, tell the jury; who makes them better? You must know, since you worry about it. You are the one, after all, who found me out, their corruptor, as you say; you brought me here and are prosecuting me. Come on, now, tell us, who makes them better? . . . You see, Meletus, you are silent, you have nothing to say? . . . Tell us, my friend, who makes them better? The laws. That's not what I asked you; what man, who knows these laws? These gentlemen here, Socrates, the jury. What do you mean, Meletus? Are these men able to educate the young and make them better? Certainly. D'you mean all of them, or can some of them, and others cannot? All of them. Good news, by Hera; there is a great surplus of im provers. But what about the men in the gallery? Do they improve the young or not? 101 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION They too. What about the council . . . and the assembly ? do those men corrupt the youth? Or do they also make them better? Those too. Evidently every Athenian produces decent young men except me; I alone corrupt them. It that what you mean? That's just what I do mean. Surely I must be the unhappiest of men. But answer me this. Is that the way it is with horses ? men at large im prove them, and only one man corrupts them? Or isn't it just the opposite; there is only one man who makes them better, or very few, men who are skilled in horsemanship? And most people, if they have to do with horses, corrupt them? Isn't that true about horses and about any other kind of animal? Yes it is true whether you and Anytus admit it or not. It would certainly be a great stroke of good luck for the young, if one man only corrupted them while all the rest im proved them. But you have made it perfectly clear, Mele tus, that you have never thought a bit about the young. . . . (24c-25c) It is impossible to sympathize with Meletus; he is a fool and Socrates makes short work of him. Personalities aside, however, it has always seemed to me that Meletus has the best of the case. After all, how do people become virtuous or vicious? In our society this question comes up in relation to the sources of crime and delinquency. We usually assume that people go wrong be cause of their environment, their upbringing. The Athenians asked the same kind of question, but they more often asked it about the virtuous. According to their view of human nature criminals required no explanation; man is naturally disposed to aggression and deceit. How, then, do men become virtuous? No one teaches them, as horses are taught and broken to the bit. Evidently virtue is something one acquires from environment, as a result of living in a community; it is not taught by anybody; in a sense it is taught by everybody. Ordinary decent behavior, as opposed to the virtue of the saint or the prophets, is a function of life in an ordinary civilized community. Meletus is fuzzily groping toward the position given a full and explicit statement 102 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATO'S APOLOGY by Protagoras in Plato's dialogue the Protagoras. Protagoras de fines virtue as those qualities which men must possess to be mem bers of a community; therefore virtue belongs to all the members of the community, and they all teach it to one another. Men are virtuous, in fact, as the result of the formal and informal pres sures of the community; their acts are restrained by the law and their private opinions are shaped by public opinion. We cannot, therefore, pick out particular teachers of virtue; everyone teaches it to his neighbor in the course of living a civilized life. The standards of virtue are produced by a kind of unspoken agree ment of all with all. When Socrates asks Meletus about men who break horses, he evidently means that it would be as reasonable to find ex perts in the raising of men as in the raising of horses. By this he implies that the community is not a reliable guide to virtue. In a sense, "he accuses himself by his defense;" by showing that Mele tus does not know anything about justice he implies that the jury does not know anything about it either. If the many cannot produce virtue in the young they probably cannot recognize it in Socrates; Socrates, as it were, rejects their verdict in advance. So Socrates proves himself a dangerous man. In the whole length of his speech Socrates never tries to prove any loyalty to the community. Instead he appeals to a higher authority; his way of life, he says, was sent him by God. The Delphic oracle had said that he was the wisest of men. This oracle puzzled Socrates, who never had any pretensions to wis dom; he then set out to examine his neighbors, to search for wisdom ? but he found them all wanting. The oracle ? the voice of God ? set Socrates upon his quest for meaning; as with Meletus so with every man he met; none of them could tell him why they did anything, or what they meant by goodness. The Socratic examination is the most radical form of rejec tion of the community. The community lays down the standards of action; given the community standard of value the only rele vant questions are questions of fact. The community says that murder is wrong; the only question asked in court is: did this man commit murder? Socrates asks: why is murder wrong? What is wrongness? He rejects the whole fabric of opinions that the community had gradually built up; he demands, in its place, 103 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION a rational standard of action, a rational understanding of moral ity. Socrates was not particularly antidemocratic; he denied the authority of government altogether. So he is careful to point out that he opposed both the democracy and the tyranny which suc ceeded it. He was careful to fulfill the formal obligations which the community laid upon him ? service in the army, for in stance ? for he looked upon such things as a debt which must be paid, but he rejects the moral authority of the city. "I am fond of you, men of Athens, I even love you, but I shall obey the God rather than you, and as long as I draw breath I shall never leave off my philosophy, admonishing you and showing you to yourselves." (29d) His mission is not obedience to the city, but its moral reformation. Socrates presents himself as a man of humility, but the power of his personality comes from his demonic pride. He says that he knows nothing except his own ignorance, but he claims to be able to judge the ignorance of others, and judge it worse than his own. He, who is on trial for impiety, claims to be the only really pious man in the city. He mentions the young men who so loved to watch him make fools of the most respectable citizens; but he refuses to take any responsibility for the effect his methods might have on those less gifted by nature than him self. Throughout the Apology his defense is that he could not have done otherwise, and that, if his disruption of the community did harm, it is the community which is at fault. Socrates' remarks on the fear of death are, I think, the final touch in his rejection of the community. Death, he says, is not necessarily a bad thing; it may even be the greatest human good. In any case he is not to be deterred by death, about which he is ignorant, from obedience to the God, which he knows is his duty. By saying this Socrates implicitly says that he is beyond the power of the community. He is not afraid of the strongest sanc tion which the community can impose; if they kill him they, not he, will be the loser. The Apology, then, is not rhetoric but anti-rhetoric; Socrates does not try to persuade the community of his loyalty; he de fines the distance between himself and the community. He does not try to win the case; he tries to lose it with honor. To me there is something suicidal about the Apology ? or perhaps that 104 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATo's APOLOGY is too strong; but one can see, I think, that Socrates is resigned. That the vote was so close, he says, surprised him. It would have been unreasonable if the case had turned out any other way. When we talk about Socrates and his community we must remember that the community was something very different for him from what it is for us. For an Athenian gentleman like Soc rates (and he was born to money and power, even if he gave them up) the community was not the whole city; the many made the decisions and passed the laws; in a sense they and they only were the community. It was the agreement of the many, all with all, which produced legality and justice; the few rich men were governed by this community, but did not belong to it. The com munity mediates between opposing rich men; community stand ards are not self-generated by the community; the community develops them by choosing between this rich man and that. Under these circumstances, the idea of virtue which we found implicit in Meletus and explicit in Protagoras looks very different. Since the rich do not belong to the class which makes the decisions, they do not participate in the moral community; the decisions of the many are imposed on the few. Or else, by force of rhetoric, the few manipulate the many. The many, as I said, are dependent on the few for their whole picture of the world around them; the issues are defined by the rhetoric of the few. Under these conditions the relation between a gentleman and the community to which he is supposed to be loyal becomes more and more artificial. He is tied to the community without being a member of it; to some extent, with the skill of rhetoric, he himself can modify the terms of the relation. For Socrates such a situation is totally irrational. Only an individual can be rational; a body of men, never. When two in dividuals appeal to a mass of men, the rational appeals to the ir rational. Socrates, I think, is certainly undemocratic, but not be cause of class prejudice. The few are no better than the many; all parts of the city are equally responsible for this absurd situa tion. Only Socrates, trying to turn men away from the opinion of the many to a consideration of the nature of the good, is a true statesman. The Apology, then, is anti-rhetoric in two senses. It does not ask for the consent of the many; it demands their agreement; the 105 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION function of a speaker, says Socrates, is "to teach and to persuade." And the foundation of the Socratic teaching is a distrust of rhet oric and of the kind of community that sets rhetoric at the center of its affairs. What then is Socrates' aim? Certainly not acquittal; a Soc rates before a popular court is sure to be convicted. An acquit tal would have been a terrible anticlimax, almost a disaster. Soc rates tells us the real meaning of the case only after he has been condemned, in the second and third parts of the Apology. These speeches, as I said, have no parallel in the literature; the last part, in fact, is not in the strict sense rhetoric at all; since the case has already been decided, it has no practical function. At the end of his speech Socrates explains to the jury that con demned him the meaning of his condemnation. He presents them with his death as a kind of legacy, a memorial to the claim of the man of reason to be superior to the opinions of the many. The community drops away from him gradually; in the little speech on the punishment he says that he is the most valuable member of the community, that he should be rewarded; in his final speech he says that he is more important than the whole city put together. At the end Socrates says that he has, in fact, won his case, that men will remember, not Socrates as a man who lived in Athens, but Athens as the city which killed Socrates. And in that, at least, he was right. What, then, do we mean when we call the Apology a great work of rhetoric? As a law court speech it was a failure; Socra tes lost. In any case this is not a law court speech; it is not by Socrates; it is by Plato. No one knows how close the Apology comes to the speech which Socrates actually gave. It might be a verbatim record; it might be free invention. Probably it is some where between the two. Even if it were a verbatim record, how ever, Plato's purpose in publishing it could not be, in the strict sense, rhetorical; Socrates was already dead, beyond the reach of law or politics. We could consider the Apology a work of philosophy. It is not only the defense of a particular philosopher; it is the defense of the life of philosophy in general. I have talked about the im plications of the Apology for the relation between the life of rea son and the community, for the relation between a single act and 106 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms A LECTURE ON PLATO'S APOLOGY a whole life; those are philosophical implications. As a matter of fact, since Plato was the sort of philosopher he was, his philoso phy shows through every line of this speech. Consider, for ex ample, the implications I found in Socrates' brief exchange with Meletus. I would not have seen these implications if I had not read the Protagoras. And, in a sense, the Apology is both an in troduction to and a summary of the whole of Plato's philosophy. I am inclined, however, to think of the Apology more as history than philosophy. The trial of Socrates is an unexplained historical event; it is not at all clear why Socrates was prosecuted or why he was convicted. In any case the trial is, as an historical event, too good to be true. Anyone who handles historical ma terials over a period of time develops a sense for incidents which are too dramatic or which fit together too neatly; these are the incidents most likely to have been invented. The trial of Socrates is exactly such an incident; if the evidence for it were not ex ceptionally good I would be convinced that it was a legend fabri cated by Plato's academy. The Apology shows the old philoso pher, who has spent his life in the service of the state and of his fellow man, abruptly and irrationally prosecuted for impiety before a popular court incapable of understanding him, and go ing calmly to his death; his martyrdom is the capstone to his whole career. As Socrates says, it is not much life they have de prived him of, and they have given him in exchange the im mortality of a sacrifice. If we see the case that way, however, it is because of Plato. Socrates must have been prosecuted by those prosecutors in that year for some reasons belonging to that time and those men. But these particular reasons never appear in the Apology; they are, for Plato, trivial. The real cause of Socrates' death is Socra tes' life; the opinions of particular prosecutors and a particular jury are insignificant in comparison to the catastrophic failure which is the central fact of Athenian history: Athens' failure to accept Socrates. So particular times and men disappear from view; in the Apology the trial of Socrates is a dramatic expression of the universal issue of politics: the confrontation of philosopher and community. And this, in turn, is consistent with the Platonic view of history. Nothing for Plato can be learned from the particular; 107 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE JOURNAL OF GENERAL EDUCATION what is important is the universal latent in particular events. Not Socrates and Anytus, but philosopher and politician; this is the real confrontation. So the Platonic Apology is the truest history of the trial ? much truer than any verbatim account ? because it shows us the true meaning of the case. That Plato has imposed upon the world his view of the case so completely that it is now impossible to construct any other, is in itself a triumph of a cer tain kind of rhetoric: the rhetoric of a philosopher writing history. 108 This content downloaded from 128.195.75.31 on Mon, 09 Jan 2023 04:40:30 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms