Ecology is an eminently practical discipline, but the practical dilemmas of the ecological movement – and arguably of the environmental crisis itself are the consequences of our failure to comprehend the complexity and unity of nature theoretically. The ecological crisis is first and foremost an epistemological crisis. (Amrine, 2015, p. 45) This is opening of a far-ranging article published in the Goethe Yearbook in 2015, in which Frederick Amrine, professor of German at the University of Michigan and an anthroposophist, traces the taking up of an alternative set of tropes for thinking about the natural world, tropes which he claims originated with Johann Wolfgang Goethe (1749 -1832) in the early years of the nineteenth century. Amrine’s purpose is to provide a re-evaluation of Goethe’s scientific work which, as an alternative to scientific reductionism, was marginalized over the subsequent 150 years. His specific focus is on the work of an early twentieth century advocate of the Goethean legacy, whose writings have been taken up by philosophers Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908 1961) and Gilles Deleuze (1925- 1995) and Felix Guattari (1930-1992): the biologist and semiotician Jakob von Uexküll (1864-1944). In particular, von Uexküll’s thinking about music – not as mathematical purity, but as meaningful experience—has been taken up to reconfigure our relationship with the world, ‘to be with’ a living process unfolding in time. Furthermore, the music metaphor provides a conceptual understanding of how we can view living phenomenon as a whole realizing itself in time rather than reducing it to its parts. The other important concern of this paper is to show how Goethean scholarship indicates directions where phenomenology can be extended from the humanities to the ‘lifeworld’ directly - as in how in biology does ‘being’ manifest in matter or the ‘universal’ in the particular. Amrine is not alone in recognising an epistemological crisis. In The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy (1932), Edmund Husserl (1859-1938) not only challenged dominant scientific discourse by taking “consciousness” itself as his Archimedean fulcrum point, but offered phenomenology—“the study of the structures of our consciousness” (Seamon, 1998, p. 2)— as an alternative foundation for understanding our relationship with the world. Generally, it is recognised that the great achievement of the last three centuries has been the rise of science and its associated technologies. Husserl proposed that one way of understanding the overarching paradigm shift of the Enlightenment is in terms of the creation of the idea of a mental space unencumbered by anything other than ‘pure’ thinking’, as astrology gave way to astronomy, alchemy to chemistry, and so on (Moran, 2012, pp. 66-67). The focus of the Enlightenment moved towards the quantifiable, and specifically to that which was amenable to mathematical analysis. ‘Knowing’ became all but exclusively a question of aligning thinking, conceived of as ‘reason’ with determinant states of physical reality into external ‘objective’ knowledge, independent of the ‘subjective’ perspective of any given mind (Husserl, 1970). The extraordinary success of physics lead to a reductionist aspiration for all knowledge, and what C. P. Snow famously identified in the 1950s as what amounts to an all but insurmountable cultural division between the humanities and the sciences (Snow, 2007). Is there the possibility of a rapprochement between these divided cultures? Does the difficulty stem from the overgeneralisation of scientific method, not sufficiently differentiated according to its subject matter? Husserl argued that problem was deeper: Only a radical inquiry back into subjectivity—and specifically the subjectivity which ultimately brings about all world-validity, with its content and in all its prescientific and scientific modes, and into the "what" and the "how" of the rational accomplishments—can make objective truth comprehensible and arrive at the ultimate ontic meaning of the world. (Husserl, 1970, p. 69) In this paper, I will argue that the often-overlooked legacy of Goethe, and the anticipation, in his work, of many of the insights and directions towards which phenomenology, in the twentieth century, indicates the way towards a redressing of the overgeneralisation of the scientific method, and the damage this overgeneralisation has wrought on the world by a knowing which bridges the subject/object divide. According to Amrine, von Uexküll, a perhaps often-overlooked pioneer of both ecology and semiotics, “turn[ed] Darwin inside out”, by explaining that “the environment does not select among chance variations, rather the oak participates in a counterpoint in which oak and environment sing a duet” (Amrine, 2015, p. 50). Uexküll argues that environment is not blind to meaning as implied by Darwin, but the Umwelt (environment) is above all a context in which a specific meaning has been created through an exchange of Merkmale (sensory cues guiding behavior) and Wirkmale (the responsive behaviors themselves) (Amrine, 2015, p. 49). Uexküll felt that the nineteenth century biologist and pioneer of the science of genetics, Gregor Mendel had been more open to a non-reductionist paradigm, more aware that how important the interaction with the environment was: how the living organism is instrumental in creating its environment through its behaviour, so that “the behaviour of organisms is first and foremost an expression of meaning”(Amrine, 2015, p. 49). Uexküll offered a musical metaphor to explain this, inviting his reader to “suppose” that “two different scholars had been given a very illegible sheet of music”. Prior to the ascension of materialism, he suggests, they might have disputed which of the marks were notes and which were random inkblots. Materialism, however, “knows nothing of music”; it sees “nothing but inkblots” (TB 204-5) “[T]o find in the properties of living matter nothing more than the expression of a dance of atoms”, Uexküll argues, “is not only to be hard of hearing, but to be stone-deaf” (TB 205-6)” (Amrine, 2015, p. 50). For Uexküll, Amrine explains, “meaning proceeds biological form in the same way that melody precedes and organizes, but it is in no way the product of, physical tones” (Amrine, 2015, p. 51). Goethean scientist Craig Holdrege makes a similar point with his observation that when Goethe “encountered a view that made the presence or absence of a single part into an essential distinguishing characteristic he felt something was awry” (Holdrege, 2014, p. 12), he then undertook the research to investigate the claim. Holdrege sees a contemporary example of this in the idea there is hardly any difference between the DNA of humans and chimpanzees and so being human is the result of a small proportion of human DNA. He argues that Goethe would have taken issue with this (as he does) and points to research “that an organism dynamically orchestrates its genome and not the other way round” (Holdrege, 2014, p. 13). This is basically the argument Uexküll made, though in an earlier time context. Amrine shows how Merleau-Ponty took up Uexküll’s musical metaphor in his lectures on the Nature in the 1950s, collected in Nature: Course Notes from the College de France. In particular, Merleau-Ponty develops a musical conception of “organic time”: We think naturally that the past secretes the future ahead of it. But this notion of time is refuted by the melody. At the moment the melody begins, the last note is there, in its own manner. In a melody, a reciprocal influence between the first and the last note takes place, and we have to say that the first note is possible only because of the last, and vice versa. It is in this way that things happen in the construction of a living being” (Nature, 174 in (Amrine, 2015, p. 56) In the third course, Merleau-Ponty turns to the question of Nature and the Logos, and although he does not mention Goethe, his thinking takes on a decidedly Goethean flavour. “Nature” he observes, “can be thought of both as leaf or layer of total Being – the ontology of Nature as the way toward ontology . . What we are looking for ... is a true explication of Being. Thus for example the nature in us must have some relation to Nature outside us; moreover, Nature outside of us must be unveiled to us by the Nature we are. (Merleau-Ponty, 2003, pp. 205-206) The musician Victor Zuckerkandl (1896-1965) picked up the other end of the metaphorical stick, seeking to “understand musical form and meaning by comparing it systematically to a biological organism” (Amrine, 2015, p. 56) The idea is that, indeed, there is an overall structure to music, evident in its various elements—tones, melody, rhythm— and all this can be described and documented. The music itself, however can only be shown, for it is a kind of being-in which only becomes fully present “in the mind of the hearer” (Amrine, 2015, p. 57). The abiding biological metaphor is that music qua music grows from seed and that the totality of its meaning is there in potential from the onset. “[M]usic”, Zuckerkandl explains, is a meaning that unfolds in a dimension that is perpendicular to clock time” (Amrine, 2015, p. 57). Here Zuckerkandl appears to be echoing Merleau-Ponty’s musical conception of “organic time” referred to earlier. The French philosopher Gilles Deleuze and his French co-writer psychotherapist, Félix Guattari also look to Uexküll for an alternative perspective to scientistic accounts, also picking up on this musical metaphor. In What is Philosophy? they write: Every territory encompasses or cuts across the territories of other species, or intercepts the trajectories of animals without territories, forming interspecies junction points. It is in this sense that Uexkühl [sic] develops a melodic, polyphonic, and contrapunctal conception of nature…There is counterpoint whenever a melody arises as a “motif” within another melody, as in the marriage of a bumblebee and snapdragon. But it is not just these determinate melodic compounds . . . . that constitute nature; another aspect, an infinite symphonic plane of composition is also required...This is because territory does not merely isolate and join but opens onto cosmic forces that arise from within or come from without, and renders their effect on the inhabitant perceptible. The oak’s plane of composition is what supports or includes the force of the acorn’s development and the force of formation of raindrops (Deleuze & Guattari, 2009, pp. 185-186) Addressing the fundamental differences between philosophy and science, Deleuze and Guatari turn to Goethe as the “prime example of an arch-philosopher’s attempt to create a living event” (Amrine, 2015, p. 62).”For Deleuze,” Amrine observes, music is a privileged cognitive metaphor because it is more than just a metaphor: he sees life itself as immanent to music and music as immanent to life” (Amrine, 2015, p. 58). In a different text, “Kicking Away the Ladder”, Amrine sees this way of viewing nature as ‘music’ as part of an alternative ‘emerging’ scientific paradigm and provides more detail on Goethe’s contribution (Amrine, 2019, pp. 63-91). With Goethe’s own research it is in his morphological studies of the plant—how the plant undergoes metamorphosis over time—in which the musical metaphor is most obvious. Before addressing this, I will provide some background of how Goethe developed his plant studies. One of first things that impressed Goethe was the sheer scale and continuity of change in the leaf of a plant over its life cycle. Holdrege provides this chart of leaf growth of the wild radish: (Holdrege, 2014, p. 16) Goethe was also particularly interested in abnormalities and commissioned paintings of them in plants to help his research. (Holdrege, 2014, p. 18) What interested Goethe here was in the picture on the left was the upper leaf taking on the character and appearance of the petal and in the picture on the right the way the petal and leaf are not separated and take on features of each. This and many other reinforcing observations lead him to a Heraclitian view of change in the plant: “If we look at all these Gestalten, especially the organic ones, we will discover that nothing in them is permanent, nothing at rest or defined—everything is in a flux of continual motion. This is why German frequently and fittingly makes use of the word Bildung [formation] to describe the end product and what is in process of production as well…. When something has acquired a form it metamorphoses immediately into a new one.” (Goethe 1995, pp. 63-4) ( cited in (Holdrege, 2014, p. 16) Within this process Goethe was able to distinguish different stages in which metamorphic change takes place: Whether the plant grows vegetatively, or flowers and bears fruit, the same organs fulfil nature’s laws throughout, although with different functions and often under different guises. The organ which expanded on the stem as a leaf, assuming a variety of forms, is the same organ which contracts in the calyx, expands again in the petal, contracts in the reproductive parts, only to expand finally as the fruit (para.115; in Goethe 1995, p. 96, cited in (Holdrege, 2014, p. 19), From these patient observations, in which care is taken not to replace observations with abstractions, Goethe eventually comes to have enhanced insights into what he calls the ‘archetypal phenomena’ (Zajonc, 1998). It is the leaf, he realised, which is the true Proteus, hiding or revealing itself in all plant forms. He eventually came to an experience of this ‘moving reality’ as the archetypal plant (Holdrege, 2014, p. 19). Philosopher Ron Brady makes a link between the understanding Goethe’s morphology with a musical metaphor and coming to an intuitive concept or ‘essence’ in Husserlian language: The music moves, but its gesture is not made by the notes. Nor does the musician make the gesture – he only follows it. The melody itself acts as the directive power behind the whole process, leading the musician and placing the notes: a felt power, in response to which we make metaphors of the “drive” and “force” of a passage. As experienced, melody is never something done, a mere effect, but something doing, a causal activity. This fact gives melody a cognitive status . . . Without the melody, we could have no understanding of why one thing follows another, no law governing before and after. It acts, therefore, as if it were a conceptual standard explaining the why and wherefore of the sounds. Yet it gains this cognitive power only to the degree that it is directly perceived- felt- as the directive energy. It is both experience, and idea, percept and concept or better an intuitive concept ( 157-158) (Amrine, 2019, pp. 80-81). Where Goethe anticipates Husserl’s phenomenological advocacy for intuitively apprehended disclosure of qualities is in his performative thoughts. Goethe wishes others to follow him in being able to ‘be with’ or ‘hear as a whole’ metamorphic changes that occur as any plant goes the archetypal series of expansions and contractions that take it from the infinite variations of seed to leaf to flower to fruit and back to seed, even as audience can be with a troupe of dancers or eurythmists1 as they take them on a transformative journey through a living sequence of expansions and contractions. This was not, for Goethe, an abstract idea, but a ‘truth’ experience, as a conversation with friend and fellow poet and playwright Friedrich von Schiller, (1759-1805) shows. When Goethe shared his understanding of the archetypal plant through a sketch, Schiller replied “That is not an experience, but an idea.” Goethe responded, “Then I can be very glad that I have ideas without knowing it, and even see them with my eyes.” Physicist, Walter Heitler, with good reason interprets this as illustrating Goethe’s enormous imaginative power and suggests the ‘eyes’ referred to are not bodily ones and that ‘idea’ here is being referred to is done in a Platonic sense (Heitler, 1998, p. 62). 1 Eurythmy is an art of movement developed by Rudolf Steiner. The popularity of musical metaphor by philosophers Merleau-Ponty, Deleuze and Guattari and Brady is in no small part due to its usefulness in being able to imagine the wholeness or totality of the lived experience of an organic process unfolding in time. There is however another important aspect of Goethe’s research, as indicated in the introduction, how Goethe anticipates Husserl’s “generic science aiming to uncover the manner in which meanings originate”(Moran, 2012, p. 298) through disclose of the intuitive concept or essence. For as Henri Bortoft argues, [t]here is another crucial aspect to Husserl and Goethe approaching the organising idea in cognitive perception. With Husserl and Goethe, the idea apprehended, as in the archetypal plant, is not a generalization, but an experience of unity in diversity, an intuitive concept (Bortoft, 2007, pp. 123-137). What is Goethe’s understanding of this intuitive concept? Henri Bortoft describes Goethe’s insight not as the type of ‘universal’ generalized from a number of particular instances, but rather arising in the intuitive mind and involving a reversal of perception: Instead of a movement of mental abstraction from the particular to the general, there is a perception of the universal shining in the particular . . . In other words the particular becomes symbolic of the universal . . . Goethe’s description of the primal phenomenon as “an instance worth a thousand, bearing all in itself” has to be understood in terms of this relationship between the universal and the particular (Bortoft, 2007, p. 79)/ In this respect, physicist and Goethe scholar Walter Heitler notes that the universal is no longer an individual phenomenon: It is, as Goethe calls it, the idea of a whole group of phenomena, or in the parlance of modern science, the point of convergence of a certain class of phenomena. Just as the point of convergence of a mathematical series is not identical with any one of its members, so this phenomenon at the outward boundary of physics is something that has no concrete existence. It is, as was said, the idea of a phenomena, which Goethe terms the archetypal phenomenon ( Urphanomen) and describes thus: ideal, as that perceivable; real, as that perceived; symbolic, because it comprehends all instances; identical with all instances (Heitler, 1998, pp. 59-60) How do we compare the archetypal plant with modern molecular biology? Heitler takes up this question. According to contemporary thought, the hereditary factors and the morphology of an organism are understood to be determined by the chemical structure of the DNA. Heitler suggests that it would be a mistake identify the archetypal plant with the DNA, he considers that: “The molecules can only be a material substrate for just this idealike formative principle or archetypal plant”, using terms similar to Uexküll’s, making clear the future research needed in these areas: If we draw an analogy, the structure of the DNA molecule is to the archetypal plant as the ink-smeared type in the printer’s press is to the poem that it will print. In no way at all do we understand what the relationship between the chemical structure and the formative principle actually is….or how the plant goes about changing the formative principle into form (Heitler, 1998, pp. 63-64). In conclusion: yesterday I made a case for conceiving alternative relationships to nature from the mastery model advocated by the pioneers of modern science, Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon, proposing the insights of phenomenology as a real alternative. Today, I have fleshed this out, suggesting that an understanding of music affords a conception of how to be with the dynamic nature of change in the natural world, and that, with his research into the archetypal plant, Goethe pioneered a phenomenological science of the ‘life world’ showing how an apprehension of the ‘universal’ can illuminate the particular as in the archetypal plant. So, if we accept Frederick Amrine’s argument that environmental crisis is “the consequence of our failure to comprehend the complexity and unity of nature theoretically”, we can move beyond that failure by exploring the emerging paradigm offered by Goethean-influenced phenomenology and consider nature musically. References Amrine, F. (2015). The Music of the Organism: Uexküll, Merleau -Ponty, Zuckerkandl, and Deleuze as Goethean Ecologists in Search of a New Paradigm. Goethe Yearbook, 22, 45-72. doi:https://doi.org/10.1353/gyr.2015.006 Amrine, F. (2019). Kicking Away the Ladder: The Philosophical Roots of Waldorf Education. . New York: Waldorf Publications. Bortoft, H. (2007). The Wholeness of Nature: Goethe's Way Of Science. Edinburgh: Floris. Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (2009). What is Philosophy (H. Tomlinson & G. Burchill, Trans.). London: Verso. Heitler, W. (1998). Goethean Science. In D. Seamon & A. Zajonc (Eds.), Goethe's Way of Science: A Phenomenology of Nature (pp. 55-70). New York: State University of New York. Holdrege, C. (2014). Goethe and the Evolution of Scince. In Context, #31, 10 - 23. Husserl, E. (1970). The Crisis of The European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (D. Carr Ed.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature: course Notes from the College de France (R. Vallier, Trans.). Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. Moran, D. (2012). Husserl's Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge Press. Seamon, D. (1998). Goethe, Nature, and Phenomenology: An Introduction In Goethe's Way of Science: A Phenomenology of Nature (pp. 1 to 14). New York: State University of New York Snow, C. P. (2007). The Two Cultures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zajonc, A. (1998). Goethe and the Science of his Time. In D. Seamon & A. Zajonc (Eds.), Goethe's Way of Science: A Phenomenology of Nature (pp. 15-32). New York: State University of New York.