See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/342960887 AN ESSAY ON JOHN LOCKE'S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE Article · July 2020 CITATIONS READS 0 19,622 1 author: Ezinwanne Onwuka University of Nigeria 5 PUBLICATIONS 1 CITATION SEE PROFILE Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: Philosophy View project RELIGION, ANTHROPOMORPHISM AND GOD View project All content following this page was uploaded by Ezinwanne Onwuka on 15 July 2020. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. AN ESSAY ON JOHN LOCKE’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE Ezinwanne M. Onwuka Email: ezinwanne.dominion@gmail.com Abstract In any philosophical discourse, the word “knowledge” occupies a very important place. Before trying to know about things, philosophy finds it indispensable to undertake a consideration of the nature and possibility of knowledge. Questions like what is knowledge? How do we get knowledge? What are the sources of knowledge? have been the preoccupation of many renowned philosophers and this has led them to discuss knowledge in various ways from different perspectives. Rationalism and empiricism are the two philosophical schools of thought that have given diametrically opposite answers to the question(s) regarding the source of knowledge. The aim of this paper is to explain empiricism as a theory of knowledge with emphasis on John Locke’s theory of knowledge, as the foremost proponent of empiricism. Keywords: Knowledge, Ideas, Experience, Mind. Introduction Empiricism is perhaps as old as philosophy itself but it did not come to flourish in philosophy before the seventeenth century of the Christian era except only for a brief while at the time of the sophists of the early Greek period (Brightman, 1954). At the beginning of the modern age, a number of eminent philosophers increasingly applied the empiricist method in philosophical investigations. Through the works of thinkers like Locke (1632-1704), Berkeley (1685-1753) and Hume (1711-1779) during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, empiricism came to establish itself as a definite and vigorous creed in philosophy. As a branch of epistemology, empiricism disregards the concept of innate ideas and focuses entirely on experience and evidence as it relates to sensory perception. It rivals rationalism according to which reason is the ultimate source of knowledge. The philosophy of empiricism was first put forth Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |1 by John Locke’s in his book An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. According to Bertrand Russell (1945), this is his most important book and upon which his fame most securely rests. Therein, Locke argued that the only way by which man acquires knowledge is through experience. This paper is a holistic approach to John Locke’s empiricism. What is Empiricism? Empiricism, in philosophy, is the view that all concepts originate in experience, that all concepts are about or applicable to things that can be experienced, or that all rationally accepted beliefs or propositions are justifiable or knowable only through experience. This definition accords with the derivation of the word empiricism from the Greek word empeiria which means experience. It is a philosophical theory which argues that human knowledge is derived entirely from sensory experience. Accordingly, it rejects any (or much) use of a priori reasoning in the gathering and analysis of knowledge. According to the empiricists, experience provides the marks of criteria of knowledge and these criteria may be subsequently used to determine the extent of our knowledge. They emphasize that, sense experience is the only guide in our understanding of the world; that is, it is the only method and criterion of knowledge and truth. Thus, any opinion or judgment which cannot be established on the evidence of experience, is to be treated as uncertain, false or even as superstitious. In philosophical theories and everyday attitudes, the experiences referred to by empiricists are principally those arising from the stimulation of the sense organs, that is, from visual, auditory, tactile, olfactory and gustatory sensation. Lending credence to this, Hospers (1967) averred that they ultimately reduce all concepts, all knowledge and all scientific generalizations to sensations and perceptions. What all empiricists have in common is their rejection of innate ideas and their insistence that all knowledge derives from sense perception and is circumscribed by sense perception. They Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |2 all maintain that at birth the human mind is a blank slate – tabular rasa. (Omoregbe, 1998). From the foregoing, it can be said that, as a theory of knowledge, empiricism upholds the view that experience is the only source of knowledge, or that the senses alone can provide us with reliable knowledge about the world (Hossain, 2014). The common-sense view is that, the senses do provide us with knowledge of some sort and most people adopt this kind of empirical view. John Locke’s Theory of Knowledge John Locke was born in 1632 at Wrington, Somerset, and died seventy-two years later in 1704. He was one of the most famous philosophers and political theorists of the seventeenth century. He is often regarded as the founder of the school of thought known as British Empiricism, and he made foundational contributions to modern theories of limited, liberal government. In his most important work, Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke set out to offer an analysis of the human mind and its acquisition of knowledge. The main project of the Essay is an examination of the human understanding and an analysis of knowledge. He offered an empiricist theory according to which we acquire ideas through our experience of the world. Knowledge, then, consists of a special kind of relationship between different ideas. Locke opened Book IV of his Essay with the quote: “knowledge then seems to me to be nothing but the perception of the connexion and agreement, or disagreement and repugnancy of any of our ideas. Where this perception is, there is knowledge, and where it is not, there, though we may fancy, guess, or believe, yet we always come short of knowledge” (4.2.2, 525). What does Locke mean by the “connexion and agreement” and the “disagreement and repugnancy” of our ideas? An example might help. Bring to mind your idea of the colour white and your idea of the colour black. Locke thinks that upon doing Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |3 this you will immediately perceive that they are different, that is, they “disagree”. It is when you perceive this disagreement that you know the fact that white is not black. There are three dimensions along which there might be this sort of agreement or disagreement between ideas. First, we can perceive when two ideas are identical or non-identical. For example, knowing that sweetness is not bitterness consists in perceiving that the idea of sweetness is not identical to the idea of bitterness. Second, we can perceive relations that obtain between ideas. For example, knowing that seven (7) is greater than three (3) consists in perceiving that there is a size relation of bigger and smaller between the two ideas. Third, we can perceive when our idea of a certain feature accompanies our idea of a certain thing. For instance, if I know that ice is cold this is because I perceive that my idea of cold always accompanies my idea of ice. From this, it follows that Locke thinks that all of our knowledge consists in agreements or disagreements of one of these types. John Locke’s Critique of Innate Ideas It is obvious that if Locke is going to say that all ideas come from experience, he must reject the theory of innateness (Stumpf and Fieser, 2015). The first of the Essay’s four books is devoted to a critique of nativism, the doctrine that some ideas are innate in the human mind, rather than received in experience. He attacks previous schools of philosophy, such as those of Plato and Descartes, which maintain that there are certain ideas (units of mental content) which were neither acquired through experience nor constructed by the mind out of ideas received in experience. The usual justification for this belief in innate principles is that there are in the understanding certain innate principles stamped upon the mind of man, which the soul receives in its very first beginning, and brings into the world with it. In other words, certain principles exist to which all human beings universally assent. Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |4 Locke contends that, on the contrary, no principle is actually accepted by every human being. His contention is that the fact that not all humans have these ideas is enough evidence that they were not implanted in the human minds at birth, and that they are therefore acquired rather than innate. Furthermore, if universal agreement did exist about something, this agreement might have come about in a way other than through innate knowledge. Another argument of his directed against innate ideas is that human beings cannot have ideas in their minds of which they are not aware, so that people cannot be said to possess even the most basic principles until they are taught them or think them through for themselves. Still another argument is that because human beings differ greatly in their moral ideas, moral knowledge must not be innate. Locke attacks both the view that we have any innate principles (for example, the whole is greater than the part, do unto others as you would have done unto you, etc.) as well as the view that there are any innate singular ideas (for example, God, identity, substance, and so forth). The main thrust of Locke’s argument lies in pointing out that none of the mental content alleged to be innate is universally shared by all humans. As Locke saw the matter, the doctrine of innate ideas was superfluous because it contained nothing that he could not explain in terms of his empirical account of the origin of ideas (Stumpf and Fieser, 2015). John Locke on Ideas According to Locke, ideas are the fundamental units of our mental content and so they play an integral role in his explanation of the human mind and his account of our knowledge. Ideas, according to Locke, are the immediate objects of human knowledge (Omoregbe, 1998). This means that we have no direct knowledge of things themselves but only of our ideas about them. Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |5 How are ideas formed in our mind? Locke explains that when we perceive things, they impress themselves on our minds and leave their images (their copies) there. These images are the representatives of things in our minds, and these are our ideas of things (Omoregbe, 1998). Hence, ideas are mental objects. The implication is that when you perceive an external world object like an apple there is something in your mind which represents that apple. So when you think of an apple what you are really doing is thinking about the idea of that apple. On a different plane, ideas are mental actions. The thought here is that when you perceive an apple you are really perceiving the apple in a direct, unmediated way. Ideas are the mental act of making perceptual contact with the external world object. The implication of this, therefore, is that since the mind has access only to the ideas and not to the world of objects, we have certainty about the ideas alone. He distinguished between simple and complex ideas. Simple ideas constitute the chief source of the raw materials out of which our knowledge is made. These ideas are received passively by the mind through the senses. When we look at an object, ideas come into our minds in a single file. This is so even when an object has several qualities blended together. For example, a white lily has the qualities of whiteness and sweetness without any separation. Our minds receive the ideas of white and sweet separately because each idea enters through a different sense, namely, the sense of sight and the sense of smell. Sometimes different qualities enter by the same sense, as when both the hardness and coldness of ice come through the sense of touch. In this case, our minds sort out the difference between them because there are in fact two different qualities involved. Knowledge according to Locke, agrees with the realities of things, as the simple ideas we get represent things outside. In this sense, the simple ideas are the product of things operating on our minds. In other words, things outside us arise in us sensations that generate simple ideas. We are passive in their reception. This is a very fundamental assumption of Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |6 Locke’s empiricism. Locke thus assumes that there are things out there in the world and our simple ideas are copies of what is there in the world. Complex ideas, on the other hand, are not received passively but rather are put together by our minds as a compound of simple ideas. Unlike simple ideas, complex ideas are not copies and they do not refer to anything original out there. The human mind makes them. Here the emphasis is on the activity of our minds, which takes three forms: The mind (1) joins ideas, (2) brings ideas together but holds them separate, (3) and abstracts. Thus, my mind joins the simple ideas of whiteness, hardness, and sweetness to form the complex idea of a lump of sugar. My mind also brings ideas together but holds them separate for the purpose of thinking of relationships, as when I say that the grass is greener than the tree. Finally, my mind can separate ideas “from all other ideas that accompany them in their real existence” as when I separate the idea of man from John and Peter. John Locke on the Degrees of Knowledge After detailing the types of relations between ideas which constitute knowledge, Locke continues on to discuss the three “degrees” of knowledge in 4.2. These degrees seem to consist in different ways of knowing something. The first degree Locke calls intuitive knowledge. This is the highest degree of knowledge and the most certain of the three as Locke says, “Such kind of truths, the mind perceives at the first sight of the Ideas together, by bare Intuition, without the intervention of any other Idea; and this kind of knowledge is the clearest, and most certain, that humane frailty is capable of.” (4.2.1, 531). An agent possesses intuitive knowledge when he directly perceives the connection between two ideas. It is acquired by direct intuition, without any intermediary. An example of this kind of knowledge is mathematical knowledge. Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |7 Next is demonstrative knowledge. This is scientific knowledge, and it is acquired by experiment and demonstration. For example, most of us are unable to tell that the three interior angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles simply by looking at them. But most of us, with the assistance of a mathematics teacher, can be made to see that they are equal by means of a geometric proof or demonstration. This is the model for demonstrative knowledge. The third and lowest degree of knowledge is sensitive knowledge. It is the knowledge of particular things as they exist, and it is acquired through sense perception. Sensitive knowledge has to do with the relationship between our ideas and the objects in the external world that produce them. Locke claims that we can be certain that when we perceive something, an orange, for example, there is an object in the external world which is responsible for these sensations. Part of Locke’s claim is that there is a serious qualitative difference between biting into an orange and remembering biting into an orange. In other words, there is something in the phenomenological experience of the former which assures us of a corresponding object in the external world. The three degrees of knowledge can be summarized thus: Intuitive knowledge gives us certainty that we exist, demonstrative knowledge shows that God exists, and sensitive knowledge assures us that other selves and things exist but only as they are when we experience them (Stumpf and Fieser, 2015). John Locke on Substance and Qualities Furthermore, Locke argues that when we perceive things what we actually perceive in them are qualities (e.g. colour, height, size, hardness) which impress themselves in our minds, leaving their copies or images there. But we know that these qualities cannot exist on their own. They inhere in something, a substratum, which supports them and from which they are coming out. This substratum from which they are coming out, which supports and in which they Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |8 inhere is what Locke calls substance. We can never know it directly because we can have no direct cognitive contact with it. We can only know the qualities that come out of it and which impress themselves on our minds. It is only by inference that we know of its existence since we know that these qualities cannot exist on their own. They must be existing in something and this is substance. The implication of this doctrine of Locke is that we can never know things as they are in themselves. We can only know our ideas of them. To describe in even more detail how we get our ideas, Locke turned his attention to the problem of how ideas are related to the objects that produce them. Do our ideas reproduce exactly the objects we sense? If, for example, we consider a balloon, what is the relation between the ideas that the balloon engenders in our minds and the actual nature of the balloon? We have ideas such as round, hard, white, and cold. To account for these ideas, Locke says that objects have qualities, and quality, for him, is the power (in an object) to produce any idea in our mind. (Stumpf and Fieser, 2015). The balloon, then, has qualities that have the power to produce ideas in our minds. Locke went further to make an important distinction between two different kinds of qualities in order to answer the question of how ideas are related to objects. He terms these qualities primary and secondary. Primary qualities are inseparable from a body and they remain in it even when it undergoes changes. For example, qualities of solidity, extension, figure and mobility, motion or rest, and number. Locke considers them as the original or primary qualities of the body, which produce simple ideas in us. They resemble what is in the object and their patterns do really exist in the bodies themselves. For example, the balloon looks round and is round; it appears to be moving and is moving. Thus, our ideas, caused by primary qualities, resemble exactly those qualities that belong inseparably to the object. In this sense, they are real Ezinwanne M. Onwuka |9 qualities, as they really exist in the bodies, whether anyone perceives them or not. On the other hand, secondary qualities are not in the objects themselves. They produce ideas in our minds that have no exact counterpart in the object. We have the idea of red when we see the balloon. But there is no redness in the balloon. What is in the balloon is the quality, the power to create in us the ideas of red. Secondary qualities have no resemblance of them in the body in which they are perceived. For example, in the case of a white rose, our idea of it does not resemble the rose considered in itself. What corresponds in the rose to our idea of white is its power of producing in us the idea of white through the action of imperceptible particles on our eyes. Primary qualities, then, refer to solidity, extension, figure, motion or rest, and number – or qualities that belong to the object. Secondary qualities, such as colours, sounds, tastes, and odours, do not belong to or constitute bodies except as powers to produce these ideas in us. The importance of Locke’s distinction between primary and secondary qualities is that through it he sought to distinguish between appearance and reality. (Stumpf and Fieser, 2015) Conclusion John Locke made significant contributions to the history of Modern Philosophy in both epistemology and political theory. He was influenced in many ways by Descartes, but in opposing Descartes’ Rationalist epistemology he established the starting point of Empiricism. Locke set out “to enquire into the origin, certainty, and extent of human knowledge.” He assumed that if he could describe what knowledge consists of and how it is obtained, he could determine the limits of knowledge and decide what constitutes intellectual certainty. His conclusion was that knowledge is restricted to ideas – not the innate ideas of the rationalists but ideas that are generated by objects we experience. Without Ezinwanne M. Onwuka | 10 exception, according to Locke, all our ideas come to us through some kind of experience. This means that each person’s mind is in the beginning like a blank sheet of paper upon which experience alone can subsequently write on. Ezinwanne M. Onwuka | 11 REFERENCES 1. Brightman, S. B. (1954) A Philosophy of Religion. (New York: Prentice Hall). 2. Copleston, F. (2003) A History of Philosophy: British Philosophy Hobbes to Hume, Vol. 5. (London: Continuum). 3. Edwards, P. (ed.) (1967) The Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. (New York: The Macmillan Company). 4. Hospers, J. (1967) An Introduction to Philosophical Analysis. (London: Printing Hall). 5. Hossain, F. M. A. (2014) A Critical Analysis of Empiricism. Open Journal of Philosophy, 4, 225-230 http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2014.43030 6. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, John Locke (1632-1704), Sourced from http://www.iep.utm.edu/locke/. Retrieved on May 12, 2020. 7. Locke, J. (1959) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Vol. II. (New York: Dover Publications). 8. Omoregbe, J. (1998) Epistemology: A Systematic and Historical Study. (Lagos: Joja Educational Research and Publishers Ltd). 9. Russell, B. (1945), A History of Western Philosophy (New York: Simon and Schuster). 10.Stumpf, S.E and Fieser, J. (2015), Philosophy: A Historical Survey with Essential Readings (New York: McGraw-Hill Education). Ezinwanne M. Onwuka View publication stats | 12