SCHOOL OF HISTORY, ARCHAEOLOGY AND RELIGION OFFICE USE: DATE OF RECEIPT COURSEWORK COVERSHEET STUDENT No. 21049123 SEMINAR TUTOR Dr Maria Fragoulaki INVESTIGATING THE ANCIENT WORLD: MODULE CODE HS3103 MODULE TITLE SUBMISSION DATE 28/04/2022 ESSAY TITLE YEAR OF STUDY First WORD COUNT SKILLS AND EVIDENCE Source Criticism of Pseudo-Aristotle’s Constitution of the Athenians 26.3–27.1 796 Please tick if you have registered a specific learning difficulty (e.g dyslexia, dyspraxia) with the Student Support Service: ☒ X TICK TO CONFIRM You must read this and ensure that you understand what you are confirming. The consequences of plagiarism are severe and will almost certainly lower your degree result. STUDENT DECLARATION I confirm that I have read the section on plagiarism in the School Students’ Handbook and the University Plagiarism and Unfair Practice Regulations, that this submission is entirely my own work, that all sources and quotations have been acknowledged, and that all works consulted are listed in the bibliography. ☒TICK TO CONFIRM Guidance Please use this template for your coursework submission. Please insert your module code and student number in the header: double-click on the header at the top of the next page, insert the module code and your student number, close header and footer. Please do not change the font size or line spacing. module code 3103 student number 21049123 Pseudo-Aristotle’s writing here is part of the full recording of the Athenian constitution and is suggested to have been written between 328BC and 322BC.1 It was written as an historical account of Pericles’ enactment of the new Athenian citizenship law in 450BC, as well as a recounting of his actions towards his advancement in Athenian society.2 However, since Pseudo-Aristotle is not singularly Aristotle it is unclear who originally wrote this, although according to P.J. Rhodes3 it was far more likely that a student of Aristotle simply attributed it to him. Pseudo-Aristotle focuses on the enactment of Pericles’ citizenship law as he sought to combat aristocrats and his audit of Cimon. This is common among contemporary sources as writers such as Plutarch who focused extensively on Pericles’ audit of Cimon and Pericles’ return to public life.4 Additionally, Aelian makes a reference, albeit in a different phrasing, to the law three times in his Varia Historia ensuring the source is reinforced by historical contemporaries.5 As an historical account of the Athenian constitution Pseudo-Aristotle gives a deeper insight into how the law was enacted. The depth of knowledge stated here leads many historians to believe Pseudo-Aristotle as having access to the Athenian government’s records, meaning that the writings are based on fact rather than anecdote.6 However, some historians doubt that Aristotle, and thus any writings from PseudoAristotle, are unbiased in their recordings of Pericles.7 This is due to Aristotle’s criticism of Thrasybulus and his plan to extend citizenship8 resulting in the belief that Aristotle and Pseudo-Aristotle were not only influenced by antidemocratic criticism but also agreed with Pericles’ restrictive law.9 This is severely detrimental to the usefulness of the source as it limits how historians can interpret Pericles’ actions within a democratic context. 1 Rackham 2013, 29. 2 Aristotle, The Athenian Constitution, 29. 3 Rhodes 1984, 1-208. 4 P. Papageorgiou 1997, 8. 5 Eliano and Johnson 1997, 1-245. 6 Hammond 1969, 203. 7 Jordović 2011, 47. 8 Rhodes 1993, 474-477. 9 Rhodes 1993, 474-477. 1 module code 3103 student number 21049123 Nevertheless, some aspects of the source are far more reliable; when PseudoAristotle states “he challenged the audits of Cimon who was a general, it came about that the constitution became still more democratic”,10 we know that his challenging is reliable because of the wide recording of Cimon’s audit by Plutarch.11 Furthermore, scholars such as Breebaart permit the source a greater sense of reliability as they agree with Pseudo-Aristotle that Pericles pushed Athens to become more democratic when he gave the common people of Athens Cleruchies and gratifications,12 a move which despite heavy criticism ultimately led to a more democratic constitution. Pseudo-Aristotle generally portrays Pericles positively, demonstrating how “having first distinguished himself when while still a young man”13. One example of this is within Pericles’ challenging of the Aeropagus, an important legal institution which at times ruled over Athens or acted as a court of law.14 Pseudo-Aristotle writes that “he took away some of the functions of the Areopagus… which resulted in emboldening the multitude, who brought all the government more into their own hands”,15 effectively praising Pericles as an anti-tyrant against what was known as the oligarchic like “Cleisthenic” period of governing.16 The idea of Pericles taking power away from the Aeropagus and enacting a new more democratic system can be supported by evidence with historians such as Morrison who state “The Cleisthenic constitution, with its election of the archons by vote and its powerful Areopagus, was more aristocratic than the Periclean.”17 arguing that Pericles’ reforms were a major change away from aristocracy. On the other hand, however, Plutarch writes that “Pericles may have been an important influence behind the events, but it was Ephialtes who actually brought about the reforms”18, stating that while Pericles was a major factor within this, he was not the leading figure. This disagreement undermines Pseudo-Aristotle’s writings as it can be 10 Pseudo-Aristotle, Constitution of the Athenians, 26.3–27.1. 11 Breebaart 1971, 260-272. 12 Breebaart 1971, 261. 13 Pseudo-Aristotle, Constitution of the Athenians, 26.3–27.1. 14 Blackwell 2003. 15 Pseudo-Aristotle, Constitution of the Athenians, 26.3–27.1. 16 Gomme and Morrison 1950, 76. 17 Gomme and Morrison 1950, 76. 18 Blackwell 2003. 2 module code 3103 student number 21049123 interpreted as personal bias towards Pericles, critically undermining the usefulness of this source. Overall, this excerpt has key insight into Pericles’ actions within Athenian politics as it demonstrates his citizenship law enactment, his challenging of the Areopagus and the result of his audit of Cimon. Although there is debate over the reliability of PseudoAristotle as a source on Pericles, due to the anti-tyrant and anti-democratic views and possible bias towards Pericles, his reliable work can be seen in its corroboration with Plutarch as well as his access to evidential sources at the time. In conclusion, the extract can be interpreted as useful historical evidence but Pseudo-Aristotle’s bias towards anti-tyrant/democratic movements and possible personal bias towards Pericles must be considered when using the writings as evidence. 3 module code student number 3103 21049123 Bibliography: Aristotle et al. 2013. The Athenian Constitution. University of Alberta., p. 29. Blackwell, C. 2003. The Council of the Areopagus. Available at: https://www.stoa.org/demos/article_areopagus@page=all&greekEncoding=Unicode C.html [Accessed: 28 April 2022]. Breebaart, A. 1971. Plutarch and the Political Development of Pericles. Mnemosyne 24(3), pp. 260-272. Carawan, E. 2008. Pericles the Younger and the Citizenship Law. Classical Journal 103(4), pp. 383-406. Eliano, C. and Johnson, D. 1997. An English translation of Claudius Aelianus' "Varia historia". Lewinston: Edwin Mellen Press. Gomme, A. and Morrison, J. 1950. Pericles Monarchos. The Journal of Hellenic Studies 70, pp. 76-77. H. Blok, J. 2009. Perikles' Citizenship Law: A New Perspective. Historia: Zeitschrift für Alte Geschichte 58(2), pp. 141-170. Hammond, N. 1969. Aristotle and Pericles - Johan Hendrik Schreiner: Aristotle and Pericles: A Study in Historiography. (Symbolae Osloenses, Fasc. Supplet. xxi.) Pp. 138. Oslo: Universitetsforlag, 1968. Paper. The Classical Review 19(2), pp. 203-206. Jordović, I. 2011. ARISTOTLE ON EXTREME TYRANNY AND EXTREME DEMOCRACY. 6 1, pp. 36-64. J. Sammons II, L. 2010. The Cambridge Companion to the Age of Pericles. Phoenix 64, pp. 153-178. 4 module code 3103 student number 21049123 Meyer, E. 1993. Epitaphs and citizenship in Classical Athens. The Journal of Hellenic Studies 113, pp. 99-121. P. Papageorgiou, A. 1997. The Citizenship Law of Perikles, 451/0 B.C., pp. 1-124. Rackham, H. 1952. Aristotle, Athenian Constitution,chapter 42. Available at: http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=aristot.+ath.+pol.+42 [Accessed: 26 April 2022]. Rhodes, P. 1993. A commentary on the Aristotelian Athenaion politeia. Clarendon Press., pp. 474-477. Rhodes, P. 1984. The Athenian Constitution. Penguin Classics., pp. 1-208. Walters, K. 1983. Perikles' Citizenship Law. Classical Antiquity 2(2), pp. 314-336. 5