This article was downloaded by: [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] On: 15 February 2014, At: 03:44 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Journal of Political Ideologies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cjpi20 Politics, power and the state: a Marxist response to postanarchism Simon Choat a a School of Economics, History and Politics, Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences, Kingston University London, Penrhyn Road, Kingston-upon-Thames, Surrey, KT1 2EE, UK Published online: 14 Oct 2013. To cite this article: Simon Choat (2013) Politics, power and the state: a Marxist response to postanarchism, Journal of Political Ideologies, 18:3, 328-347, DOI: 10.1080/13569317.2013.831592 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13569317.2013.831592 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/termsand-conditions Journal of Political Ideologies, 2013 Vol. 18, No. 3, 328–347, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13569317.2013.831592 Politics, power and the state: a Marxist response to postanarchism Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 SIMON CHOAT School of Economics, History and Politics, Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences, Kingston University London, Penrhyn Road, Kingston-upon-Thames, Surrey KT1 2EE, UK ABSTRACT Recent years have seen the development of a new form of anarchism. Under the label ‘postanarchism’, writers such as Todd May, Saul Newman and Lewis Call have sought to combine the insights of anarchism with those of recent Continental philosophy, in particular post-structuralism. A central but neglected element of postanarchist thought is its critique of Marxism. The main aim of this article is to counter the postanarchist dismissal of Marxism. It will: introduce the key ideas and arguments of postanarchism; locate its critique of Marxism, demonstrating its importance to the postanarchist project; and highlight weaknesses in the postanarchist critique of Marxism. It argues that the postanarchist portrayal of Marxism is reductive and misleading. Contrary to postanarchist claims, many post-structuralists have drawn inspiration from Marxism rather than rejecting it: as such, Marxism anticipates many of the poststructuralist-inflected ideas of postanarchism, in particular their approach to the state, power, subjectivity and politics. In addition, some Marxist criticisms of classical anarchism apply equally to postanarchism, thus raising questions to which postanarchists should respond. Introduction Since the start of this century, anarchist theory and practice have seen something of a resurgence. In part this is reflected in the increasing prominence of anarchistinspired alter-globalization movements and protests.1 In addition, however, the past decade has seen the emergence and development of a new strand of anarchism known as ‘postanarchism’, represented by thinkers including Todd May, Saul Newman, Lewis Call and Richard Day.2 Postanarchism is an attempt to reread and renew the anarchist tradition using late 20th and 21st century Continental philosophers, in particular post-structuralists like Foucault and Deleuze. It offers a critical appropriation of anarchism—one which criticizes the weaknesses of classical anarchism while nonetheless drawing on its resources and arguments. Put simply, postanarchism is an anarchism relieved of the ontological baggage of q 2013 Taylor & Francis Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism Enlightenment humanism and rationalism.3 One of the ways in which postanarchism both defines itself and links itself to the classical anarchist tradition is through a critique of Marxism. Yet although postanarchists have explicitly and repeatedly detailed their criticisms of Marxism, this critique has so far received little comment from Marxists. This article seeks to remedy that neglect by offering a Marxist response to postanarchism. The main aim is to counter the postanarchist critique of Marxism by demonstrating the continuing relevance of the Marxist tradition. The postanarchist critique is flawed in important ways, misrepresenting both Marxism and the relationship between Marxism and post-structuralism. Rather than defending one particular variant of Marxism, I will argue that Marxism is a much richer and more fertile tradition than is claimed by postanarchism’s reductive reading. Indeed, many postanarchist arguments have much in common with Marxist theories. Although I am critical of postanarchism, my aim is not to dismiss it entirely in favour of Marxism. The broader goal of postanarchism—to combine the insights of post-structuralism with older traditions of radical thought—is laudable. It also makes some pertinent criticisms of classical anarchism, leading to some interesting claims about politics, power, subjectivity and the state. Many of these criticisms and claims, however, have in effect already been made by Marxists. In addition, however, many Marxist criticisms of classical anarchism can be applied to postanarchism and hence call for a response from postanarchists. It is not my aim here to tread over old ground or revive ancient enmities. Nonetheless, I will draw upon classical Marxist criticisms of anarchism, and my arguments can be placed in the context of a debate between anarchism and Marxism that has persisted since the 19th century. This debate has had enormous historical significance: both anarchists and Marxists have portrayed themselves as members of the same family4 and the disagreements between them have played a large role in shaping these two ideologies, with each defining themselves in opposition to the other. Yet the debate is not of merely theoretical or historical interest. It has had substantial material and political effects: the rise and fall of the First International, the course of the revolutionary movement in Russia and the outcome of the Spanish Civil War were all influenced by disagreements between anarchists and Marxists. It is a timely debate today because it is not only anarchism that is resurgent: Marxism too has seen a revival in recent years. In contrast to the jubilant proclamations of the death of Marxism that greeted the end of the Cold War, Marx’s ideas are now being turned to once more to help understand and navigate the problems faced by a globalized world. In the wake of a massive financial crisis that mainstream economists failed to predict or explain, many of the most perspicacious analyses of that crisis have come from Marxist and neoMarxist scholars.5 Given the significance of both anarchism and Marxism to radical politics today, it seems pertinent to assess the criticisms made of Marxism by the latest version of anarchism. In the first section of the article, I will explain what postanarchism is, detailing its central claims and its relationship with classical anarchism and 329 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 simon choat post-structuralism. The aim of this first section is to provide an introduction to postanarchism and to highlight its central criticisms of classical anarchism. Next, I will outline the postanarchist critique of Marxism, explaining why postanarchists reject Marxism and why this critique is so significant for their broader project: to a great extent the rejection of Marxism motivates and justifies their use of both anarchism and post-structuralism. Third, I will begin to formulate a Marxist response to this critique, questioning postanarchist claims about both Marxism and its relation to post-structuralism. Finally, I will develop this response by drawing on the classical Marxist engagement with anarchism, showing that many postanarchist criticisms of classical anarchism are anticipated by Marxism. My claim is not that Marxism has all the answers to our problems, but that it is unfair and unwise to dismiss it in the way that postanarchism has. Finally, two notes on terminology. First, if I have not considered the ‘postMarxism’ of thinkers like Laclau and Mouffe here, it is because post-Marxism and postanarchism have very different relations to their respective traditions. Whereas postanarchism is a critical appropriation of anarchism, post-Marxism— with its rejection of the centrality of class—is in effect a repudiation of Marxism. I offer a Marxist, rather than a post-Marxist, response to postanarchism. Second, although the thinkers labelled ‘postanarchist’ have given different names to their project—Todd May writes of ‘post-structuralist anarchism’ and Lewis Call of ‘postmodern anarchism’—there are more than enough commonalities to justify grouping them all under one title, and so for reasons of clarity and convenience I am going to adopt Saul Newman’s term and call them all ‘postanarchists’. Postanarchism and classical anarchism Postanarchism is a varied body of thought, but is perhaps best characterized as a critical appropriation of the anarchist tradition, revisiting the classical anarchism of 19th and early 20th century thinkers like Bakunin, Stirner and Kropotkin. In part, this means an attempt to renew anarchist ideas in order to apply them to present-day political and social developments—developments sometimes referred to using the name ‘postmodernity’.6 More than this, however, it means revitalizing anarchism using recent theoretical innovations—in particular post-structuralist concepts and arguments. This involves two related moves: first, demonstrating the affinities between classical anarchism and post-structuralism; second, using post-structuralism to criticize the weaknesses of classical anarchism. In brief, postanarchists use post-structuralism to criticize classical anarchism for its obsession with the state, its conception of power as purely repressive, its essentialist and humanist ontology, and its naive understanding of politics as something that can be abolished. Before examining these criticisms in more detail, and in order to attain a better understanding of the postanarchist project, we will look briefly at the affinities that it finds between classical anarchism and poststructuralism. 330 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism For postanarchists, there is ‘an ethical continuum’7 between classical anarchism and post-structuralism. They argue that although the post-structuralists themselves may not have explicitly characterized their own work as anarchist, poststructuralism can be seen as heir to the anarchist tradition, providing us with ‘a new type of anarchism’.8 Conversely, anarchism can be used to develop and articulate a post-structuralist politics, helping to counter the commonplace view of post-structuralism as a form of apolitical relativism or nihilism. To defend these claims, postanarchists point to the origins of post-structuralism in May 1968— events which played a large role in politicizing and shaping the views of poststructuralist thinkers such as Deleuze and Foucault, and which were strongly influenced by anti-authoritarian and anarchist currents and ideas.9 More importantly, postanarchists highlight a number of theoretical commonalities between classical anarchism and post-structuralism—in particular, common attitudes towards power and representation. As the postanarchists point out, a rejection of political representation is a key element of classical anarchism: if anarchists wish to abolish the state, it is because the state ‘is the ultimate form of political representation’, and they reject all forms of representation.10 This anarchist critique of representation, it is argued, is echoed and extended by post-structuralism. Like the classical anarchists, post-structuralist thinkers are suspicious of forms of political representation—or of ‘the indignity of speaking for others’ as Deleuze put it in an interview with Foucault.11 But poststructuralism deepens this critique by basing it on an epistemological critique of representation. Lyotard, for example, sought to show how the theoretical apparatus of representation both relies upon and obscures libidinal drives and intensities that cannot be represented.12 For Deleuze, the epistemological critique of representation is necessarily linked to a political critique of forms of power: representation calls on us merely to recognize what is already given—to endorse established values and institutions, rather than investigating their genesis or creating new values.13 Just as they reject all forms of representation, so do anarchists reject all forms of power—not merely the power of the state, but also that of the church, family, educational institutions, etc. Recognizing that power operates across a number of terrains and in many different ways, anarchists call for varied, decentralized and non-hierarchical forms of resistance. Postanarchists argue that this approach to power resonates with the post-structuralist view. If power is everywhere, as Foucault has claimed, it is not because we are all subjected to one overarching form of domination, but because power is found in all relationships, operating in every sphere of life, and exercised in multiple ways.14 Like the anarchists, Foucault calls for an ‘ascending analysis of power’ that begins with localized and immediate mechanisms of power.15 So for postanarchists, classical anarchism and post-structuralism are united in their suspicion of representation and their appreciation of the plurality of forms of power. Yet if post-structuralism is a ‘new type of anarchism’, it is because it also differs from classical anarchism in significant ways: post-structuralism does not merely replicate the insights of classical anarchism but builds upon them. 331 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 simon choat Although they think that the anarchist tradition provides the best template for radical politics today, postanarchists do not uncritically accept that tradition: they argue that post-structuralism must be used to criticize and supplement classical anarchism, with which they find a number of related problems. Above all, it is argued that classical anarchism has left us with an ambiguous legacy, its insights undermined by a certain Enlightenment naivety.16 While they applaud anarchism’s analysis of power—with its recognition that power can be found in many spheres of life and can take many forms—postanarchists argue that this analysis is undermined by a tendency to view power and resistance in naively Manichean terms: the evil and artificiality of power is counterposed to some natural, uncorrupted order which can act as a source of resistance.17 This Manicheanism can take one of two forms (or some combination of both). In the work of some classical anarchists, power is opposed to a benign human essence which is repressed by and which must be liberated from power.18 The artificiality and impurity of power are contrasted with the naturality and purity of the human essence.19 In the work of others, power is opposed to a broader notion of the innate rationality of society: an idea of an organic, self-regulating social order, which can be revealed through the discovery of positive natural laws yet which has been disrupted and suppressed by violent and irrational power.20 Using the tools of post-structuralism, postanarchists highlight a number of problems with this ‘rational-humanist paradigm’.21 In the first place, it undermines anarchism’s own insights into the plurality of power. The desire to abolish power as a whole leads classical anarchists to search for a single source of power— something that can be easily contrasted with the natural and harmonious social order. The source that they identify is the state, which becomes the focus of classical anarchism’s critique of power. So the recognition of the dispersed nature of power sits in tension with and is undermined by a reductionism that draws a crude distinction between ‘society’ on the one hand and ‘the state’ on the other. The classical anarchist analysis wavers between an acknowledgement of the many sources and forms of power and a preoccupation with the state as the epitome of power. Classical anarchists are criticized by postanarchists not simply for focusing on the state but, second, for their understanding of the way in which power operates. Power for the classical anarchists is always repressive: it is something that prohibits, conceals, excludes and prevents. Postanarchists counter this view of power with the post-structuralist position, wherein power is productive: power does not act simply by repressing individuals, but by constituting the very subject to which it is applied, so that the individual is herself or himself an effect or a product of power.22 The other side of classical anarchism’s naive conception of power is, third, a reliance on dubious ontological foundations. For classical anarchists, power is repressive, and what it represses is some social or human essence given to us by nature. By positing an essence of society or of human nature, the classical anarchists were searching for ‘a transcendental or quasi-transcendental ground from which to recover a pure, untainted source of resistance’.23 Inspired by poststructuralism’s suspicion of claims to essentialism, postanarchists propose a 332 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism deconstruction of anarchism’s ontological foundations.24 In particular, they reject classical anarchism’s humanism—that is, the idea that the human subject is rational, unified, and possesses certain essential characteristics.25 For postanarchists, the subject is never simply given but is constituted by discourses and practices of power. Finally, postanarchists argue that classical anarchism’s Manichean opposition between the artificiality of state power and the naturality of society and humanity leads to a naive understanding of politics. Equating politics with the authority of the state leads classical anarchists to demand the ‘total abolition of politics’: the abolition of the state and the end of politics are the same thing for classical anarchism.26 In contrast, postanarchists call for a more nuanced understanding of politics which recognizes its inevitability. Politics is necessary because even the abolition of the state requires political forms of organization and strategy, and will not simply occur spontaneously. Moreover, if society has no essence and power is everywhere then the very foundations of society become politicized: attempts to transform society cannot be characterized as the overthrow of politics and the return of natural order, but only as a political attempt to find an alternative articulation of social relations. These, then, are the four main criticisms of classical anarchism by postanarchism: it focuses too much on the state; it offers an inadequate theory of power; it relies too heavily on a humanist ontology; and it misunderstands the nature of politics. I will argue later that each of these criticisms of classical anarchism had already been articulated in certain (but not identical) ways by Marxism—and, hence, rather than dismissing Marxism, postanarchists should turn to it for insights. In reflection of recent trends within Continental political philosophy, some postanarchists have lately moved beyond post-structuralism to analyse the connections between anarchism and present-day thinkers like Alain Badiou and Jacques Rancière.27 These analyses follow a familiar pattern: drawing out the anarchist assumptions supposedly implicit in a thinker’s work, while simultaneously using that thinker to expose and remedy the naiveties of classical anarchism. Postanarchists have been careful to emphasize that they are not trying to reject or move beyond anarchism. As Newman explains: ‘postanarchism does not understand post to mean being “after” anarchism, but post in the sense of working at the limits of anarchist thought by uncovering its heterogeneous and unpredictable possibilities’.28 Despite this qualification, postanarchism has drawn criticism from other anarchists, in particular for its representation of classical anarchism.29 Some of these criticisms may be valid—although in many cases anarchists have clearly misunderstood both postanarchism and post-structuralism.30 It is not my intention, however, to assess these claims here: it is for postanarchists themselves to defend their arguments. Instead, I would like to examine an aspect of postanarchism that has been overlooked by its anarchist critics—and, indeed, by almost everyone else31—namely its views on Marxism. In doing so, I will argue that many of postanarchism’s criticisms of classical anarchism are entirely legitimate: it is just that many of them have already been expressed by Marxism. 333 simon choat Any rigorous assessment of postanarchism demands an analysis of its attitude towards Marxism because, as I will show in the next section, a critique of Marxism is central to postanarchism. Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 The postanarchist critique of Marxism The postanarchist critique of Marxism centres on three interrelated points. The first and most important claim is that Marxism is economically reductionist: it understands social conflict only in terms of class struggle, and it understands power only as the dominance of a particular economic class.32 Other forms of power and conflict are marginalized or ignored, and Marxism sets itself only one goal, namely the overthrow of capitalism. This reductive analysis of society leads, second, to an authoritarian politics. Because Marxists understand political power as ‘merely the organized power of one class for oppressing another’ (as Marx and Engels claim in the Manifesto33), they do not appreciate that power can have other sources and take other forms. In particular, they do not recognize that the state has its own autonomous power, irreducible to and distinct from its role in the perpetuation of class power. As such, they think that the state can be used as a neutral tool of revolutionary change, as in the transitional ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’.34 This, postanarchists claim, is in stark contrast to anarchism, which believes that the state is always oppressive, no matter what its form or who is in charge of it, and which thus seeks to smash the state rather than make use of it.35 The authoritarianism inherent in the plan for a dictatorship of the proletariat is according to postanarchism redoubled in the Marxist notion of the vanguard party, a notion which for postanarchists is also a consequence of Marxism’s economic reductionism: if there is only one struggle (the class struggle) and one source of oppression (capital) then it makes sense that those who can best understand this struggle are the ones to lead it. Even if the proletariat is not the most numerous class in society, it must lead the social struggle because of its unique position within society—and it must be led and disciplined by a party that can interpret and explain the struggle to the ignorant. If, on the other hand—and as anarchism recognizes—there are many different struggles, then the legitimacy of an avant-garde leadership is necessarily weakened, and it is those who are caught up in these many different struggles who are best placed to lead them.36 In place of the vanguard party, anarchists propose decentralized, spontaneous forms of political action that prefigure the free and equal society they are fighting for. According to postanarchism, the reductive privileging of a single site of oppression also leads Marxists, third and finally, to isolate a single political subject: because of its unique place within capitalist relations of production, the industrial proletariat can be the only agent of political change.37 Privileging the proletariat in this way, Marxism (it is claimed) overlooks or is dismissive of other potentially revolutionary actors and other forms of struggle. So for postanarchists, Marxism is reductionist, authoritarian, and has an impoverished understanding of political subjectivity. These flaws, postanarchists 334 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism argue, have had serious consequences: while the degradations of Stalinist and Maoist regimes cannot simply be seen as the inevitable result of the attempt to apply Marxist ideas, for postanarchists the disasters of 20th century communism at the very least help to confirm Marxism’s theoretical redundancy and validate the anarchist suspicion of the monolithic, centralizing and reductionist approach of Marxist theory.38 Marxism, in short, has been totalitarian in thought and practice.39 This critique of Marxism is not incidental to postanarchism. In fact, it can be said that a rejection of Marxism is the starting point of the whole project: it is in large part the alleged failure of Marxism that has led postanarchist thinkers to turn to anarchism in the first place. Postanarchists argue that in order to address the political problems that we face today, we need a radical politics—something which can take us beyond liberalism and social democracy, both of which are seen as complicit in the development and consolidation of a brand of neoliberalism that has preached a market fundamentalism at the same time as it has increased the powers of the state in the name of security.40 But for postanarchists we cannot turn to Marxism, which arguably dominated radical politics in the 20th century. Marxism, it is claimed, is not nearly radical enough to provide an adequate response to our contemporary political situation.41 Yet, as we have seen, postanarchists do not simply claim that Marxism is obsolete or went wrong at some point in the past, but rather that Marxism has never been radical enough: its inadequacies are systemic and ineradicable, and it is not a coincidence that Marxist regimes were among the most tyrannical of the 20th century. Faced with the failures of Marxism— represented and confirmed by the totalitarianism of the Soviet Union— postanarchists claim that we should turn instead to its great rival anarchism in order to help us develop a radical politics fit for the 21st century. But why turn to anarchism specifically? One reason is that the classical anarchists had already recognized the inadequacies of Marxism. In their critique of Marxism, postanarchists are drawing on thinkers like Bakunin, who are portrayed by postanarchism as presciently anticipating the problems of the Soviet Union.42 Classical anarchists had already criticized Marxism for its economic reductionism—its failure to recognize nonclass forms of power and non-capitalist sources of oppression—and they had already argued that this reductionism leads to authoritarianism. For Bakunin, the restricted focus and supposedly scientific status of Marxism’s social analysis lends itself to authoritarian forms of leadership: ‘since thought, theory, and science . . . are the property of a very few individuals, those few must be the directors of social life’.43 Bakunin argues that the state itself is a site of power—and not merely a reflection of the economic power of the bourgeoisie—and hence fiercely rejects the Marxist plan to use the state as a tool of revolution: he argues that ‘the only way to render any political power harmless, to pacify it and subdue it, is to destroy it . . . [T]here can be no guarantee against political power except its complete abolition’.44 Anarchists have long claimed that Marxism offers a narrow and dogmatic analysis of society, dismissive of classes like the peasantry who do not fit into that analysis. Many contemporary anarchists have updated this particular 335 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 simon choat criticism, arguing that while a focus on the industrial proletariat may have been understandable (if ultimately inadequate) in Marx’s day, it is entirely inappropriate today, when ecological, gender and racial questions—what the eco-anarchist Murray Bookchin calls ‘transclass issues’—have been put firmly on the political agenda. Bookchin argues that there is a need ‘to enlarge and broaden existing concepts of social oppression’: class remains a significant issue, but there is in addition a need to account for other social struggles, a need that Marxism cannot fulfil.45 Hence, the critique of Marxism places postanarchism firmly within the anarchist tradition: the suspicions of some contemporary anarchists notwithstanding, the strong hostility of postanarchists towards Marxism goes some way towards validating their anarchist credentials, providing one strand of continuity between the classical anarchism of Bakunin and others to the postanarchism of Newman and others. Yet as well as providing a connection to classical anarchism, in postanarchist eyes their rejection of Marxism provides a link to post-structuralism. For postanarchists, post-structuralism is characterized in large part by a suspicion of Marxism: ‘thinkers in this tradition—including Foucault, Lyotard and Deleuze—were all deeply influenced by the political experience of May ’68, and they became critical of what they saw as the totalizing and universalizing logic of Marxist theory’.46 In place of Marxism’s reductionism and authoritarianism, poststructuralism emphasizes contingency, heterogeneity and difference—the need to analyse specific situations at the micro-level rather than forcing events into a preestablished narrative of class struggle. Hence, the union of anarchism and poststructuralism is in part justified by a common critique of Marxism:47 postanarchism uses post-structuralism not merely to expose some of the weaknesses of classical anarchism, but also to reinforce its hostility to Marxism. The critique of Marxism thus plays a key role in both initiating and orienting postanarchism: the alleged deficiencies of Marxism are used to justify recourse to both classical anarchist and post-structuralist ideas. It would not be an exaggeration to state that the ‘failure’ of Marxism is the key underlying assumption of postanarchism. If Marxism as a form of radical politics had not ‘failed’ (as postanarchists claim it has), then there would be no need to return to classical anarchism in search of an alternative, nor to turn to post-structuralism for new ideas. Postanarchists develop their theory in a context that they define by reference to the ‘collapse’ of the Marxist project.48 Given the importance of the critique of Marxism to postanarchism, therefore, it is regrettable that so little attention has been paid to it. Regrettable, if also understandable: most commentary on postanarchism has so far come from anarchists themselves, and they are unlikely to question or challenge criticisms of Marxism. If Marxists, on the other hand, have thus far declined to engage with postanarchism, then this may reflect a traditionally patronizing attitude towards anarchism, which is often characterized as little more than a pale shadow of Marxism. Rather than simply dismiss postanarchism in these terms, however, I would like to interrogate its claims concerning Marxism. 336 a marxist response to postanarchism Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 A Marxist response I do not intend to try to refute every aspect of the postanarchist critique of Marxism. Indeed, the fundamental claim of that critique—that Marxism can tend towards economic reductionism, its focus on class struggle tending to obscure other forms of power and conflict—is well taken, although it is not exactly original: it is a claim that has been made not only by anarchists, but also by liberals, conservatives, feminists, social democrats, environmentalists and even many Marxists. But Marxism is an extremely broad and varied tradition: while it has its flaws, those flaws are not good reason to reject the entire tradition. In their reductive interpretation of Marxism, postanarchists overlook or ignore its breadth and variety. In doing so, they make a number of dubious claims about Marxism and its relation to post-structuralism. For postanarchists, following their anarchist predecessors, Marxism’s reductionism necessarily leads to forms of authoritarianism that are contrasted with the anarchist emphasis on decentralization. Richard Day, for example, contrasts a logic of hegemony—derived from Marx, Lenin and Gramsci, and which emphasizes political leadership and engagement with and use of the state—with a logic of affinity, which is inspired by anarchism and promotes ‘horizontal’ (rather than hierarchical) modes of political organization in which networks of activists operate outside of the state.49 Yet while this is an important debate within contemporary political theory,50 it is one which cuts across anarchist– Marxist lines: a number of recent thinkers working in the Marxist tradition have rejected the logic of hegemony and embraced horizontal, networked forms of organization and resistance.51 It is simplistic and inaccurate to equate Marxism with authoritarianism and anarchism with decentralization. Postanarchists might respond that the history of Marxist states confirms their suspicions concerning Marxism’s authoritarian tendencies. But the attempt to discredit an ideology by pointing to its concrete historical manifestations (arguing, for example, that the nightmare of Stalinism somehow disproves Marxism) is highly questionable, and for anarchists somewhat risky. For if it is true that an ideology can be judged in this way, then where does that leave anarchism? The history of anarchism ‘in practice’ since the 19th century is not a victorious or glorious one, and has instead frequently ended with anarchists being arrested, executed or otherwise defeated. Judging anarchism by it historical manifestations, in other words, would seem only to confirm the popular image of anarchism as a form of romantic but ultimately doomed idealism, with anarchists as martyrs to a noble but naive cause. If an ideology should be judged according to its results in practice, then it seems anarchism at least as much as Marxism must be considered a failure. Anarchism’s historical failures also bring into question the anarchist claim that radical change can be achieved without some measure of leadership and discipline: if it is true that political transformation can be attained without the kinds of party structures that Marxism has traditionally adopted, then why has anarchism not seen greater success? 337 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 simon choat In addition, the postanarchist attempt to discredit Marxist theory by pointing to its practical applications seems to confirm a well-established Marxist criticism of anarchism, namely that anarchists have offered only abstract and naive analyses of politics that pay too little attention to real, historical conditions. The postanarchist portrayal of Marxism is abstract and naive for at least two reasons. First, it conflates very different types of Marxism, subsuming what is a varied and heterogeneous body of thought under a single, teleological narrative, whereby all forms of Marxism lead ineluctably to the gulag. What of the many Marxist thinkers who have themselves offered critiques of the horrors of Stalinism? Second, the postanarchist portrayal implies a simplistic link between the weaknesses of an ideology and its historical embodiments, without addressing the social, economic, political and historical context within which theoretical arguments and concepts are created, developed and employed. This is not to say that Marxism does not have certain theoretical weaknesses or tendencies, nor that these have nothing to do with the weaknesses of Marxism in practice—but we should avoid simplistic connections between, for example, the texts of Marx and Soviet labour camps. What we need is a more nuanced and sophisticated analysis of the relations between theory and practice. Such an approach—which would trace the complex relations between forms of discourse and forms of power instead of seeing particular historical events as the results of inadequate ideas—would seem to have more in common with the post-structuralism to which postanarchists claim allegiance. This leads us to the next point: the attitude of post-structuralist thinkers towards Marxism is much more complex than postanarchists claim. Some poststructuralists were happy to be identified as Marxists: Deleuze, for example, explicitly asserted his commitment to Marxism on numerous occasions and was writing a book on the grandeur de Marx when he died.52 Deleuze and Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus is full of Marxist ideas and terminology, to the extent that the entire book can be considered a novel contribution to Marxist historical methodology as much as a critique of Freudian psychoanalysis.53 There are other poststructuralists who cannot plausibly be called Marxists, yet who nevertheless went out of their way to affirm Marx’s continuing contemporary significance. In Specters of Marx, for instance, Derrida may caution against Marxist metaphysical ontologies, but he also repeatedly insists on Marx’s contemporary importance, and explicitly places deconstruction in the tradition of Marxism.54 Derrida is sometimes portrayed as a thinker who kept silent on Marx until pressed to comment, but even in his earlier work he was emphasizing the necessity of an ‘encounter’ between Marxism and deconstruction, and he spent much of the 1970s giving seminars on Marx.55 Even a thinker like Foucault, who was frequently highly critical of Marxism, cannot be characterized as an anti-Marxist: he often explicitly praises Marx, placing him alongside Nietzsche as an originator of the kind of historical thought that Foucault himself sought to practise, and declaring that the study of history is necessarily influenced by Marx’s work.56 The point here is not that all post-structuralist thinkers were closet Marxists, but that even a cursory glance at their work begins to throw doubt on the postanarchist 338 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism claim that recent French philosophy—post-structuralism in particular—begins from a rejection of Marxism. Certainly, post-structuralists were suspicious of particular forms of Marxism (especially those propagated by the Communist Party) and they were clearly suspicious of some of Marx’s claims, but far from rejecting Marxism altogether they continued to assert its importance and draw upon its ideas.57 In contrast, they have almost nothing to say about anarchism and do not engage with any major classical anarchist. More recent thinkers such as Badiou and Negri have been even more explicit in their rejection of anarchism.58 For postanarchists, this dismissive attitude towards anarchism is a ‘disavowal’ of an unacknowledged anarchist ethos that runs through contemporary radical politics.59 But if contemporary thinkers have rejected anarchism, then perhaps this rejection is the result of a reasonable assessment of anarchism’s weaknesses rather than a disavowal of their own unspoken anarchist tendencies. Equally, if contemporary thinkers have continued to praise and use Marxism, then perhaps that is because Marxism cannot be as easily dismissed as postanarchists claim, and provides analyses that are more acute and enduring than those found in the anarchist tradition. The postanarchist position stretches credibility: postanarchists ask us to value the connections between anarchism and contemporary thought even though those contemporary thinkers explicitly repudiate anarchism, while simultaneously asking us to abandon Marxism even though those same contemporary thinkers continue to affirm Marxism’s importance. Marxism contra anarchism So far, I have called into question postanarchism’s reductive and somewhat simplistic interpretation of Marxism. I would now like to challenge that interpretation further by exploring what Marxism has to offer. We have seen that while postanarchists value classical anarchism for its critique of representation and its recognition of the plurality of forms of power and resistance, they also highlight its weaknesses. More specifically, they draw upon post-structuralism in order to criticize classical anarchism for: its preoccupation with the state; its naive conception of power as purely repressive; its essentialist ontology, in particular its humanism; and its call for the abolition of all politics. I aim to show that on each of these issues—the state, power, humanism and politics—postanarchists are closer to Marxism than they realize or acknowledge. In many cases, postanarchist claims have already been anticipated in some way by Marxism. This does not mean that postanarchism is redundant, nor that Marxism is always right while anarchism is always wrong—but it does suggest that postanarchists have been too quick to dismiss Marxism. Postanarchists argue that classical anarchism’s acknowledgement of the plurality of power is undermined by its obsession with the state—its tendency to see the state as the source of all evil and to believe that if the state is abolished then a spontaneous harmonious social order will prevail. If we look at Marxist critiques of classical anarchism, we can find similar arguments. Commentaries on the debate between anarchism and Marxism tend to focus on the question of whether 339 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 simon choat the state should be used as a tool of revolution. Important as this question is, the key differences between Marxist and anarchist views of the state lie elsewhere. Marxists have argued that the anarchist understanding of the state is too abstract: instead of analysing states as they actually exist in all their variety, anarchists treat as their enemy the state in general, ‘an abstract State, the State as such, a State that nowhere exists’.60 Rather than attacking an abstract idea of the State, Marxists claim that the state must be analysed in its wider context and in relation to other social forms and relations. It is for this reason that Marxists have offered analyses based on a very broad definition of the state as an organization that encompasses a range of social institutions. For both Gramsci and Althusser, for example, state apparatuses include not only courts, prisons, police forces, and so on, but also schools, churches, the media and even the family.61 As Gramsci says, the state is ‘the entire complex of practical and theoretical activities with which the ruling class not only justifies and maintains its dominance, but manages to win the active consent of those over whom it rules’.62 Importantly, Marxists argue further that the state must be understood in relation to capital—which in turn demands a rigorous analysis of the workings of the capitalist mode of production. Marxists have repeatedly criticized anarchists for their failure to provide such an analysis. When Marx criticizes the anarchist Proudhon, for example, it is not so much because of Proudhon’s deficient understanding of the state, but because he thinks Proudhon has inadequately understood the mechanics of capitalism. Postanarchists themselves have recognized the links between capital and the state,63 even though, like their anarchist forerunners, they have failed to provide any rigorous analysis of capitalism (preferring instead to resort to ethical condemnations of the status quo).64 Given this, it is strange that postanarchists have repudiated the theory that has done most to examine the links between the state and capitalism. The Marxist analysis of the state is arguably much richer than that offered by anarchism. Ultimately, classical anarchism has little to say about the state, beyond detailing its crimes and calling for its abolition. When they ask that anarchists move beyond their preoccupation with the state, postanarchists do not acknowledge that Marxism has already done this—not by reducing the state to an epiphenomenon of an underlying economic base, but by situating the state as a complex network of institutions within the context of broader, non-state social relations. This Marxist approach is arguably closer to post-structuralism than the anarchist theory of the state. From the point of view of Marxism, anarchism looks very much like a variety of what Foucault termed ‘state-phobia’, indulging in the ‘great fantasy of the paranoiac and devouring state’ and failing to distinguish between different types of state.65 This, of course, does not mean that Marxist theories of the state are without their problems: such theories are often overly simplistic, presenting the state as nothing more than a tool of the ruling class. But this is not a reason to reject Marxism altogether. The Marxist tradition of state theory remains valuable, not least because it provides one possible response to the postanarchist critique of anarchist state theory. 340 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism We saw that postanarchism also criticizes classical anarchism for its understanding of power and its essentialist humanism. These two criticisms are in effect two sides of the same charge: classical anarchism, it is argued, views power only as a repressive force, constraining and limiting the natural capacities of a human subject that is endowed with certain essential characteristics. One way to define postanarchism, therefore, is as a form of anarchism that no longer relies on humanism.66 It is clear that Marxism to some extent shares with classical anarchism a conventional view of power and the human subject. When Marx and Engels claim that ‘[p]olitical power . . . is merely the organized power of one class for oppressing another’,67 they do nothing to suggest that power is anything other than repressive. And for the young Marx at least, what the power of capital suppresses is our human nature—our unique ability to engage in creative labour. But there is also a different approach to the human subject that can be found in Marx and the Marxist tradition: an anti-humanist approach in which the subject is decentred and which anticipates post-structuralism. From 1845 and the Theses on Feuerbach, in which ‘the essence of man’ is portrayed as ‘the ensemble of the social relations’,68 Marx is committed to demonstrating the mutability and historicity of ‘human nature’, against all attempts to define the essential characteristics of ‘man’ in general. This antihumanist position has been a strong theme in Marxist thought, most obviously in the work of Althusser, who famously argued that the ‘philosophical (theoretical) myth of man’ should be ‘reduced to ashes’.69 Some postanarchists have argued that the anarchist Max Stirner might be seen as a forerunner of post-structuralist ideas about subjectivity: in arguing that the concept of ‘Man’ is nothing more than a form of power, an abstraction that enslaves the individual, Stirner completely rejects the idea that there is a fixed human essence.70 Yet as Marx and Engels point out in The German Ideology, Stirner’s weakness is that he sees the concept of ‘Man’—along with those of God, emperor, fatherland, and so on—as nothing more than an abstraction, and as such he believes that one can just personally decide to rid oneself of this abstraction in order to be free.71 He thus commits the error that Marx attributes to all Young Hegelians: believing that the world is ruled by ideas, Stirner thinks that one need only combat these ideas in order to achieve liberation. But as Marx argues, if one destroys the idea of the emperor, one still has the real, actually existing emperor to deal with. Likewise, if we rid ourselves of the concept of Man, we will still be left with the actual social relations that underlie this abstraction. For Marx, the aim of criticism is not merely to refute abstraction but to explain its genesis: to show how abstract ideas are related to material conditions. This is exactly what he tries to do when it comes to the human subject: rather than simply trying to abolish the concepts of ‘Man’ or ‘Human Nature’, Marx is interested in demonstrating how particular subjects are produced at the intersection of various social relations and practices. This is Marx’s task in the central pages of Capital— to show how capitalism produces the workers that it needs. The individual for Marx is not simply an abstraction, the invention of liberal ideology, or the ideal precondition or result of the exchange process. The individual is produced in a 341 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 simon choat series of concrete material operations: classified, trained and disciplined, individuals are combined and formed into a ‘collective worker’.72 It is this approach—investigating the constitution of the subject by power—that aligns Marx rather than Stirner or any other anarchist with post-structuralism. So although Marxism, like classical anarchism, at times relies on a repressive conception of power and a certain humanist essentialism, there can also be found in Marxism an investigation of the productivity of power that anticipates poststructuralism. Although anarchism recognizes the plurality of power, the claim that ‘power is everywhere’ is arguably not what is most distinctive about the poststructuralist approach. It is the claim that power is constitutive—rather than merely repressive—that marks the post-structuralist approach, and it is this claim that can be recognized in Marx’s analysis of forms of discipline that take place in the factory. This is why Foucault turns to Capital in order to illustrate the idea of the constitution of the subject as a productive force.73 In that light, the postanarchist position seems a little strange—defending classical anarchism in spite of its essentialism, yet rejecting Marxism even though it develops a critique of essentialism. The fourth and final criticism of classical anarchism that postanarchism makes is that it has a naive view of politics: conflating politics with the state, it believes that politics itself can be abolished. For postanarchists, this is mistaken: politics is both necessary and interminable: necessary because even anarchists must have some level of political organization and strategizing, however minimal; interminable because there is no ‘natural’ social order, but only contingent and inherently political articulations of the social. This critique of classical anarchism’s naive understanding of politics is to a large extent anticipated by Marxism. Indeed, for classical Marxists this was the key disagreement: when Marx, Engels and Lenin attacked anarchists it was not so much for their faulty approach to the party or revolution but, much more broadly, for their attitude towards politics. For Marxists, the anarchist abstention from politics is ill-advised, hypocritical and ultimately impossible. The classical anarchists believed that all forms of political action would necessarily entail compromise with the state and so could lead only to dictatorship or social-democratic reformism.74 As such, they ruled out all forms of political action: not merely the use of the state as a ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’, but also standing for or voting in government elections, lobbying the state for improved conditions (e.g. a shorter working day), and the formation of political parties. As the Russian anarchist Alexander Berkman put it: ‘so-called political “action” is, so far as the cause of the workers and of true progress is concerned, worse than inaction’.75 For Marxists, the anarchist rejection of political action is at once confused and naive. By dogmatically proscribing political action, anarchism denies the oppressed classes the most effective means of carrying out their struggle.76 Contrary to anarchist claims, political action does not entail acceptance of the status quo: ‘It is said’, writes Engels in response to anarchist demands for political abstention, ‘that every political act implies recognition of the status quo. But when this status quo gives us the means of protesting against it, then to make use of these 342 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism means is not to recognise the status quo’.77 To deny the working class the use of political action on the grounds that such action recognizes the state is, according to Marx, as foolish as claiming that a strike in the name of higher wages is illegitimate because it ‘recognises’ the wage system.78 In order to challenge the status quo, one must necessarily engage with it: to claim that all political action reinforces the dominant order is to slip into abstraction and to fail to discriminate between different types of political action. Marxists have argued further that even if they wanted to—and even if it was a good idea to do so—workers could not abstain from political action: ‘Absolute abstention from politics is impossible’.79 For Marxists, politics is not something that workers choose to enter or withdraw from: by virtue of being wage-labourers they are necessarily subjected to the political oppression imposed by the bourgeoisie, and thus thrown onto a political battlefield whether they are willing combatants or not. The anarchists themselves, despite their claims, are in fact involved in politics. They organize, agitate, criticize—and at times they have abandoned their principles entirely and engaged in elections and established new city states.80 It is just that they do not recognize their involvement, and deny themselves the most efficacious political means. Bakunin claimed that political action, if it does not lead to dictatorship, can lead only to parliamentarianism, as one ends up trying to wring concessions from the system instead of trying to overturn the system. For Marxists, however, it is anarchism itself which remains caught within parliamentarianism, because anarchists accept the liberal fallacy that politics concerns only the state: the equation of ‘politics’ with ‘state politics’ forms the basis of their vocal rejection of politics. Marxists, in contrast, go beyond bourgeois liberalism to recognize that politics can take place in other arenas: there is, for example, a politics of the workplace, and the oppression of exploited classes is ultimately and necessarily a political matter. By advocating political abstention, anarchism ends up capitulating to the dominant order rather than challenging it: ‘Subordination of the working class to bourgeois politics in the guise of negation of politics.’81 The Marxist and postanarchist critiques of the classical anarchist approach to politics are not identical, but they have strong similarities: for both Marxists and postanarchists, classical anarchists are naive to think that politics can be abolished and that radical change can take place without some form of political action. In summary, then, if it can be said that postanarchists have been too swift in their dismissal of Marxism, then this is in large part because many of their claims echo Marxist arguments. In some cases—such as the analysis of the state or the understanding of politics—Marxist criticisms of classical anarchism anticipate later postanarchist criticisms of anarchism. In other cases—such as the decentring of the subject and the rethinking of power—Marxism had already begun to develop arguments and ideas that anticipate themes that postanarchism draws from post-structuralism. In addition, however, there are Marxist criticisms of classical anarchism—such as the claim that it fails to offer a rigorous or thorough analysis of capitalism—that could equally apply to postanarchism and with which postanarchists would be well advised to engage, rather than dismissing them. 343 simon choat Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 Conclusions For postanarchists, Marxism is in effect irrelevant to our contemporary situation, exposed and surpassed by the advances of post-structuralism but unlike classical anarchism incapable of redemption. I have argued that this dismissal of Marxism is based on a misunderstanding not only of Marxism but also of post-structuralism. Contrary to postanarchist claims, the central thinkers of post-structuralism did not repudiate Marxism. This is not surprising, because Marxism anticipates many post-structuralist themes—and hence also many postanarchist themes. Where classical anarchists became preoccupied with the state, Marxists argued that the state needs to be analysed in its specific context, avoiding reliance on abstractions; where classical anarchists claimed that power represses some innate social or human goodness, many versions of Marxism adopted an anti-humanist perspective and analysed the ways in which forms of power constitute different subjects; where classical anarchism called for the abolition of politics, Marxism mocked the naivety of this position and emphasized the inevitability of political engagement. Even if Marxism did not anticipate post-structuralism and postanarchism in this way, the postanarchist dismissal of Marxism would still be too strong. It is true, as anarchists and postanarchists (and many others) have argued, that Marxism’s preoccupation with class struggle has tended to exclude other forms of power and conflict. But it is simplistic to claim that this necessarily leads to authoritarianism, and a form of crude reductionism to imply that it was the cause of Stalinism. In addition, however, the Marxist focus on class and economics is a useful corrective to anarchism (‘post’ or otherwise), which fails to offer any rigorous analysis of capitalism. Given the current political context—the biggest financial crisis for almost a century and a wave of austerity measures sweeping Europe—it would seem inopportune to ignore class or to abandon the ideology that more than any other has contributed to the analysis of class. Marxism is of course far from perfect, and there are elements of it that we may well want to leave behind. But it is such a large, varied and contradictory ideology that this kind of selective approach is inevitable. Moreover, it is hard to see how postanarchists could object to such an approach: after all, this is exactly how they treat classical anarchism, dispensing with its Enlightenment ontology while welcoming its insights into power and representation, picking and choosing which elements to adopt and which to discard. The post-structuralists themselves continued to draw upon Marxism, recognizing both that Marxism is too diverse and complex to reject en bloc and that it still has much to offer. If postanarchism genuinely wants to embrace the spirit of post-structuralism, then it should engage much more fully with Marxism. Acknowledgements For their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I would like to thank Elizabeth Evans, John Grant and the two anonymous assessors. 344 a marxist response to postanarchism Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 Notes and References 1. Uri Gordon, ‘Anarchism reloaded’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 12(1) (2007), pp. 29–48; David Graeber, ‘The new anarchists’, New Left Review, I(13) (2007), pp. 61–73; Saul Newman, ‘Editorial: the libertarian impulse’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 16(3) (2011), p. 239. 2. The literature on postanarchism continues to grow, but the key texts are Todd May, The Political Philosophy of Poststructuralist Anarchism (University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1994); Saul Newman, From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-Authoritarianism and the Dislocation of Power (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2001); Lewis Call, Postmodern Anarchism (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2002); Richard J. F. Day, Gramsci is Dead: Anarchist Currents in the Newest Social Movements (London: Pluto Press, 2005). 3. Saul Newman, ‘Postanarchism: a politics of anti-politics’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 16(3) (2011), p. 316. 4. Daniel Guérin, ‘Anarchism and Marxism’, in David Goodway (Ed.) For Anarchism: History, Theory, and Practice (London: Routledge, 1989), p. 118; Fredric Jameson, Representing Capital: A Commentary on Volume One (London: Verso, 2011), p. 150. 5. Costas Lapavitsas, ‘Financialised capitalism: crisis and financial expropriation’, Historical Materialism, 17(2) (2009), pp. 114– 148; Ben Fine, ‘Locating financialisation’, Historical Materialism, 18(2) (2010), pp. 97 –116; Robin Blackburn, ‘Crisis 2.0’, New Left Review, I(72) (2011), pp. 33–62. 6. Call, op. cit., Ref. 2. 7. Saul Newman, Unstable Universalities: Poststructuralism and Radical Politics (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2007), p. 15. 8. May, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 85. 9. N. J. Jun, ‘Deleuze, Derrida, and anarchism’, Anarchist Studies, 15(2) (2007), pp. 132–134. 10. May, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 47. 11. Cited in May, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 97; see Gilles Deleuze, Desert Islands and Other Texts 1953–1974, ed. David Lapoujade, trans. Michael Taormina (Los Angeles, CA: Semiotexte, 2004), p. 208. 12. Jean-Franc ois Lyotard, Libidinal Economy, trans. Iain Hamilton Grant (London: The Athlone Press, 1993). 13. Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (London: The Athlone Press, 1994). 14. Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality. Volume 1: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley (London: Allen Lane, 1979), p. 93. 15. Michel Foucault, “Society Must Be Defended”: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975–76, trans. David Macey (London: Penguin, 2004), p. 30. 16. Day, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 16; Newman, op. cit., Ref. 2. 17. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 2. 18. May, op. cit., Ref. 2. 19. Saul Newman, Power and Politics in Poststructuralist Thought: New Theories of the Political (London: Routledge, 2005), p. 39. 20. Saul Newman, The Politics of Postanarchism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2010), pp. 36 –37. 21. Ibid., p. 25. 22. Foucault, op. cit., Ref. 15, pp. 29–30. 23. May, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 65. 24. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 20, p. 5. 25. Call, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 15. 26. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 20, p. 37. 27. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 20; Todd May, The Political Thought of Jacques Rancière: Creating Equality (University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2008). 28. Saul Newman, ‘Editorial: postanarchism’, Anarchist Studies, 16(2) (2008), p. 101. 29. It has been claimed that the arguments of postanarchism and post-structuralism can already be found in classical anarchism: Jesse Cohn, ‘What is postanarchism “Post”?’, Postmodern Culture, 13(1) (2002), available at http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/postmodern_culture/v013/13.1cohn.html (accessed 24 August 2013); that post-structuralism should be interrogated by classical anarchism rather than the other way around: Allan Antliff, ‘Anarchy, power, and poststructuralism’, SubStance, 36(2) (2007), pp. 56–66; that classical anarchism has been misrepresented: Jesse Cohn and Shawn Wilbur, ‘What’s wrong with postanarchism?’, available at http://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/jesse-cohn-and-shawn-wilbur-what-swrong-with-postanarchism (accessed 20 June 2012); and that the very notion of ‘classical anarchism’ is something of a straw man: Nathan Jun, Anarchism and Political Modernity (London: Continuum, 2012). 30. To give one example: it has been argued (Antliff, op. cit., Ref. 29) that, contrary to postanarchism’s claims, classical anarchists do not see power as merely negative, but instead have a positive theory of power that recognizes the creative powers of the subject. But this misunderstands the stakes of the debate: the 345 simon choat 31. 32. 33. Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 34. 35. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. 46. 47. 48. 49. 50. 51. 52. 53. 54. 55. 56. 57. postanarchist position is not that classical anarchism fails to recognize that power can be ‘positive’, but that it fails to recognize that power is constitutive (of the subject). One exception is Benjamin Franks, who has offered the most rigorous assessment of postanarchism thus far: he does so from an anarchist perspective but questions and resists the rejection of class analysis by some postanarchists. See Benjamin Franks, ‘Postanarchism: a critical assessment’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 12(2) (2007), pp. 136– 138. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 31. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto, ed. David McLellan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 26. Saul Newman, ‘Anarchism, Marxism and the Bonapartist state’, Anarchist Studies, 12 (2004), pp. 36-59. Saul Newman, ‘Post-anarchism and radical politics today’, in Duane Rousselle and Süreyyya Evren (Eds.) Post-Anarchism: A Reader (London: Pluto Press, 2011), p. 50. May, op. cit., Ref. 27, pp. 80 –81. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 35, p. 51. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 33. Call, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 11. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 20, pp. 3, 17 –18. Call, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 6. Ibid., p. 68. Michael Bakunin, Statism and Anarchy, trans. Marshall S. Shatz (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 136. Ibid., p. 150. Murray Bookchin, Anarchism, Marxism, and the Future of the Left: Interviews and Essays, 1993– 1998 (Edinburgh: A. K. Press, 1999), pp. 273, 271. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 7, p. 3. Todd May, ‘Is post-structuralist political philosophy anarchist?’, Philosophy and Social Criticism, 15(2) (1989), p. 167. May, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 3; Newman, op. cit., Ref. 19, p. 156; Call, op. cit., Ref. 2, p. 11. Day, op. cit., Ref. 2; Richard J. F. Day, ‘Hegemony, affinity and the newest social movements: at the end of the 00s’, in Duane Rousselle and Süreyyya Evren (Eds.), Post-Anarchism: A Reader (London: Pluto Press, 2011). See, for example, Alexandros Kioupkiolis, ‘Radicalizing democracy’, Constellations, 17(1) (2010), pp. 137 –154. John Holloway, Change the World Without Taking Power: The Meaning of Revolution Today (London: Pluto Press, 2002); Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire (New York: The Penguin Press, 2004); Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Commonwealth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009). Gilles Deleuze, ‘Le “Je me souviens” de Gilles Deleuze’, Le Nouvel Observateur, 1619 (1995), p. 51; Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations 1972–1990, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), p. 171. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem and Helen R. Lane (New York: The Viking Press, 1977). Jacques Derrida, Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International, trans. Peggy Kamuf (New York: Routledge, 1994), pp. 68, 92. Jacques Derrida, Positions, trans. Alan Bass (London: Continuum, 2002), p. 62; the seminars on Marxism are discussed by Jason Smith, ‘Jacques Derrida: “Crypto-Communist”?’, in Jacques Bidet and Stathis Kouvelakis (Eds.), Critical Companion to Contemporary Marxism (Leiden: Brill, 2008), pp. 631–633. Michael Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (London: Tavistock Publications, 1977), p. 13; Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–1977, ed. Colin Gordon, trans. Colin Gordon et al. (New York: Pantheon Books, 1980), p. 53. For a relatively thorough analysis of the post-structuralist uses of Marx, see Simon Choat, Marx Through Post-Structuralism (London: Continuum, 2010). Other books that explore the fruitful connections between Marxism and post-structuralism include: Jason Read, The Micro-Politics of Capital: Marx and the Prehistory of the Present (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003); J. K. Gibson-Graham, Stephen A. Resnick and Richard D. Wolff (Eds.), Class and Its Others (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000); Jean-Jacques Lecercle, A Marxist Philosophy of Language, trans. Gregory Elliott (Leiden: Brill, 2006); Nicholas Thoburn, Deleuze, Marx and Politics (London: Routledge, 2003); Michael Ryan, Marxism and Deconstruction: A Critical Articulation (Baltimore, MD: The John Hopkins University Press, 1982). 346 Downloaded by [Moskow State Univ Bibliote] at 03:44 15 February 2014 a marxist response to postanarchism 58. Badiou claims that anarchism ‘has never been anything else than the vain critique, or the double, or the shadow, of the communist parties, just as the black flag is only the double or the shadow of the red flag’. More bluntly, Hardt and Negri state: ‘we are not anarchists’. See Alain Badiou, Polemics, trans. Steve Corcoran (London: Verso, 2006), p. 321; Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 350. 59. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 20. 60. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, ‘The Alliance of Social Democracy and the International Working Men’s Association’, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 23 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1988), p. 466. 61. Antonio Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, ed. and trans. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1971); Louis Althusser, ‘Ideology and ideological state apparatuses (Notes towards an Investigation)’, in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (London: NLB, 1971). 62. Gramsci, op. cit., Ref. 61, p. 244. 63. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 20, pp. 77 –80. 64. May, op. cit., Ref. 2. 65. Michel Foucault, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978–79, ed. Michel Senellart, trans. Graham Burchell (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), pp. 187 –188. 66. Newman, op. cit., Ref. 19, p. 49. 67. Marx and Engels, op. cit., Ref. 33, p. 26. 68. Karl Marx, ‘Theses on Feuerbach’, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1976), p. 4. 69. Louis Althusser, For Marx, trans. Ben Brewster (London: NLB, 1969), p. 229. 70. Andrew M. Koch, ‘Max Stirner: The last Hegelian or the first poststructuralist?’ Anarchist Studies, 5 (1997), pp. 95-107; Newman, op. cit., Ref. 2. 71. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Collected Works, vol. 5 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1976). 72. Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Volume One, trans. Ben Fowkes (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1976), pp. 466 –467. 73. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheridan (London: Allen Lane, 1977), p. 163. 74. Bakunin, op. cit., Ref. 43. 75. Alexander Berkman, What Is Communist Anarchism? (New York: Dover Publications, 1972), p. 125. 76. Frederick Engels, ‘The Congress of Sonvillier and the International’, In Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 23 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1988), p. 66. 77. Frederick Engels, ‘On the political action of the working class’, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 22 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1986), p. 418. 78. Karl Marx, ‘Political indifferentism’, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 23 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1988). 79. Engels, op. cit., Ref. 77, p. 417. 80. Frederick Engels, ‘The Bakuninists at work: an account of the Spanish Revolt in the summer of 1873’, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 23 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1988). 81. V. I. Lenin, ‘Anarchism and socialism’, in Collected Works, vol. V (Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1961), p. 328. 347