Religion and Rights: A Medieval Perspective Author(s): Brian Tierney Source: Journal of Law and Religion , 1987, Vol. 5, No. 1 (1987), pp. 163-175 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1051023 REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: https://www.jstor.org/stable/1051023?seq=1&cid=pdfreference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Law and Religion This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms RELIGION AND RIGHTS: A MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE* Brian Tierney** In this paper I want to present some background mater the interplay of religious concepts and rights theories d Christian middle ages. We may note at the outset that ther were elements in the Judeo-Christian tradition that could be condu- cive to the growth of a doctrine of rights, especially the fundament command to respect the person and property of our neighbor. Ronal Dworkin pointed out that the necessary basis of all other rights is an "abstract right to concern and respect taken to be fundamental and axiomatic."' The axiom entered the mainstream of medieval jurispru dence in the first words of Gratian's Decretum, the foundation of th whole subsequent structure of Western canon law. "The human race is ruled by two means, namely by natural law and usages. The law o nature is what is contained in the Law and the Gospel, by which each is ordered to do to another what he wants done to himself and is forbidden to do to another what he does not want done to himself."2 Or in modern language, one might say, "Show concern and respect." But if the notion of individual rights is implicit in Christian tradi- tion, it has not always been explicit. Developed in one way, Christian thought can lead to intolerance and persecution, to a denial of the rights that we should consider most basic.3 Developed in another way, Christianity can lead to an ideal of self-abnegation that implies an abandonment of all personal rights. Consider St. Benedict's instructions for his monks. "They should have absolutely nothing, not anything ... indeed it is not allowed to them to have their own bodies or wills in their own power."4 This seems to leave no room for any assertion of individual rights. So I don't want to suggest that in the Christian tradition there is some ineluctable development that leads inevitably from Luke to Locke-not with St. Benedict standing in the way. My argument is a more limited one, that in a specific, contin* © 1988 The Catholic University of America ** Bryce and Edith Bowmar Professor in Humanistic Studies at Cornell University. 1. R. DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY XV (1977). 2. GRATIAN, CONCORDANCE OF DISCORDANT CANONS (DECRETUM) 1140, Dist 1. 3. This theme is explored in Professor Noonan's paper in the present volume: Noonan, Principled or Pragmatic Foundations for the Freedom of Conscience, 5 J. L. AND RELIG. 203 (1987). 4. Rule of St. Benedict Ch. 33. 163 This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 164 JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 5 gent historical context, Western Europe in the twelfth centu interactions of religion and society did in fact form a new k Christian culture, a sort of seedbed in which theories of human and civil rights could take root and flourish. There are three aspects of medieval religion that I want t sider. First, and fundamental, is the concept of each human b a person, entitled to consideration as a person, capable of mor cernment and self-determination. I shall suggest that the spec velopment of this concept of personality in the jurisprudenc twelfth century contributed significantly to the whole future We tradition of individual natural rights. Second, we have to consider the church not just as a collect separate individuals but as a corporate community, sustaining its own, apart from the secular power, sometimes opposed to government, sometimes limiting the power of the state. This the medieval church in impeding the rise of royal absolutism haps its most obvious contribution to the growth of Western concepts. But there is still a third, more subtle yet significant aspe Christian thought-the relation between the individual Christ the church conceived of as a united whole, a mystical body. Th here is that the twelfth-century theology of the mystical body enced twelfth century law on the structure of corporate comm in general, including corporate political communities. So, in co ing individual rights within a medieval community, one can pu chain of argument that begins with abstract theological concep finishes with a consideration of very practical, down to earth ments like Magna Carta. It seemed appropriate to include som discussion of Magna Carta at the end of this paper, because, alt it is only one of many such charters of liberties that were is many parts of medieval Europe, it has acquired a symbolic sig cance in our legal tradition; and if one is concerned specifical the interplay of religion and rights, it is fitting to remember first clause of Magna Carta declares, "The English church free and shall have its rights entire ..." But let us begin with my first main theme, individual pers and the concept of natural rights. There exists now a subs modern literature exploring the new individualism or personal humanism of twelfth-century religious culture. (One good wo This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 163] MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE 165 synthesis, is called precisely The Discovery of the Ind recently Harold Berman has shown how a new concer ual intention and individual will helped to shape the w twelfth-century canon law, which he properly descri Western legal system.6 Yet there has been almost no how twelfth-century jurisprudence contributed to the vidual natural rights. One can read through a standar Strauss's on the history of natural right without e aware that there was a twelfth century at all.7 The origin of natural rights theories is usually date often in the seventeenth century. About 1610, for in defined the word ius not as objective law but as subje kind of power or faculty (facultas) inhering in a pers definitions become common among later authors. I work of twenty years ago, C. B. MacPherson associate teenth-century rights theories with the rise of early ism. He described such theories as a form of "possessive individualism," the ideology of a property-owning class that wanted only to legitimize its own power.9 Other scholars have found an earlier origin for rights theories in late medieval nominalism. Some emphasize the contribution of Jean Gerson who defined ius as "a faculty or power (facultas seu potestas) ... in accordance with right reason" Gerson, in turn, is usually seen as dependent on the great fourteenth-century nominalist philosopher, William of Ockham. A philosophy that attributed reality only to individuals, and that emphasized will rather than reason, naturally led to a doctrine of individual rights, it is suggested. Michel Villey, in particular, has argued that, before the fourteenth century, the expression ius naturale was always associated with a concept of cosmic harmony and that Ockham instituted a "semantic revolution" when he applied the term to a power of the individual person. Villey regarded this as a lamentable departure from a sounder earlier tradition, a result of "egoism" and "distorted Christian morality."10 5. C. MORRIS, THE DISCOVERY OF THE INDIVIDUAL, 1060-1200 (1972). 6. H. BERMAN, LAW AND REVOLUTION: THE FORMATION OF THE WESTERN LEGAL TRADITION (1983). 7. L. STRAUSS, NATURAL RIGHT AND HISTORY (1950). Strauss leaps from Plato and Aristotle to Hooker and Hobbes with only the briefest glance at Thomas Aquinas on the way. He does not consider medieval jurisprudence at all. 8. I DE LEGIBUS, § 2.5. 9. C.B. MACPHERSON, THE POLITICAL THEORY OF POSSESSIVE INDIVIDUALISM: HOB- BES TO LOCKE (1962). 10. M. VILLEY, LA FORMATION DE LA PENSEt JURIDIQUE MODERNE (1968). Idem, La This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 166 JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 5 But Villey could reach this conclusion only by ignoring al canonistic jurisprudence of the preceding centuries. Gratian, w defined ius naturale as the Golden Rule; "Do unto others a would have them do unto you." This might imply that others rights, but Gratian was still using the old language of precept, of vah that Professor Cover explained in his paper. Gratian, how went on to quote texts that gave other definitions of ius natur his early commentators undertook to classify and explore all t sible significances of the term. Among their definitions we of counter the language that modern historians have seen fourteenth-century innovation-ius naturale defined as a f power, force (facultas, potestas, vis) of the human personality greatest of the Decretists, Huguccio (c. 1190), distinguished ca between ius naturale as a rule of objective law and as a sub power of the soul, and he insisted that the latter meaning wa proper one. Huguccio was concerned precisely with the con human personality as moral and self-determining that I empha the outset.12 It was this already formed canonistic language th ham inherited. Ockham deployed this language for his own p in the Franciscan poverty disputes of the fourteenth century a son in turn transmitted it to the first early modern rights th The subject requires much more investigation, but I believe su investigation would establish that the first theories of individu ral rights were formed in the matrix of twelfth-century jur humanism. Let us turn now to my second major topic, the church considered not just as a collection of individuals, but as an ordered community, sustaining its own corporate life, independent of the secular power. Our First Amendment reminds us of this salutary arrangement and continually gives rise to new problems about civil rights, but the principle involved is no eighteenth-century invention. It goes back to the beginnings of Christianity when Jesus said "Render to Caesar the things that are Caesar's and to God the things that are God's." At first the Church grew up as an alien society within the Roman state, with its own separate institutions apart from the state. When the emgenegese du droit subjectif chez Guillaume d'Occam, ARCHIVES DE PHILOSOPHIE DE DROIT 97 (1964). 11. For some examples of such usages see R. WEIGAND, DIE NATURRECHTSLEHRE DER LEGISTEN UND DEKRETISTEN VON IRNERIUS BIS ACCURSIUS 145, 197, 209, 314 (1967). 12. Id. at 215. A more detailed appraisal of Villey's views is presented in my paper, Tierney, Ockham, Villey, and the Origin of Rights Theories, to appear in the forthcoming FESTSCHRIFT for Harold Berman. This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE 163] 167 perors became Christian in the fourth century, and subse whole Empire, there was indeed a possibility for a tim Church might become just a sort of Department of R imperial bureaucratic theocracy. But instead, the old tra tonomy was vigorously reasserted-for instance in th phrases of St. Ambrose (c. 380), "Palaces belong to th churches to the priesthood," and again, "Where matters concerned bishops judge Christian emperors, not empero A century later Pope Gelasius declared, in a famous ph are two means by which the world is chiefly governed, t thority of the priesthood and the royal power." In betw gustine had launched his haunting image of the two citie way of affirming that the Christian's ultimate allegiance be to the powers of this world.13 These early texts were not forgotten. On the contrary ploded into life again in the papal reform movement at th eleventh century-the papal revolution as Professor Berm calls it-when the church was threatened by a new kind theocracy, based this time on the German monarchy. threat Pope Gregory VII proclaimed as a sort of warcry the freedom of the church-libertas ecclesiae-the phr again and again in his letters. In the ensuing struggle, n could completely dominate the other. And so a kind of d permanently built into Western society. The church rem omous, claiming specific rights for itself and its member sisting that there was a whole sphere of human thought which was in principle outside the legitimate power of t government. When this tradition was challenged by new vine right monarchy in the sixteenth and seventeenth ce challenge evoked new forms of protest-one of them even tallized in our First Amendment. To understand the importance of all this we must bear in mind that the medieval situation was highly unusual. Theocratic absolu tism-the rule of a divine emperor, a sacred monarch-is a very com- mon form of human government. Karl Wittfogel described dozens of examples from all around the world in his book Oriental Despotism- ancient China, Japan, India, Egypt, Peru, Iran. But, in medieva Christendom, the resistance of the church always prevented nation 13. For a brief introduction to these texts and the whole problem of medieval church-stat relations see B. TIERNEY, CRISIS OF CHURCH AND STATE 1050-1300 (1964) [hereinafter Tierney]. This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION 168 [Vol. 5 monarchies from congealing into theocratic despotisms in individual rights would have been extinguished. The other si coin is that medieval kings were always strong enough to pr rise of an absolute, theocratic papacy when the popes were te assert such a role for themselves. The situation had many consequences both in theory and in practice. In theory, it was virtually impossible within this tradition to con- struct a doctrine of pure absolutism. The tradition shaped the thought even of those who tried to escape from it. I thought of this recently while re-reading Thomas Hobbes, perhaps the pre-eminent theorist of absolutism in the western tradition. Hobbes of course at- tacked the autonomy of the church as destructive of sovereignty. An absolute state, he wrote, could not tolerate alongside the tempora sovereign another "ghostly authority," "another kingdom, as it were kingdom of fairies," to which men also owed allegiance. The reason was plain. If any independent spiritual power could claim the right t determine what was sin it would soon challenge the right to declare what was law.14 It is so true of course. That is why Americans o various religious persuasions are constantly challenging laws that the perceive as legalizing sin. Hobbes was trying to be as absolute as he could. Subjects had no rights, he said, except in areas that the sovereign chose not to control that he "pretermitted." Hobbes mentioned as obvious examples the subjects' rights freely to contract with one another, to choose their own abodes, to bring up their children as they saw fit.15 Apparently he could not conceive of a sovereign who would meddle with suc things. But these are the very sinews of a modern totalitarian re gime-economic regulation, internal passports to control freedom of movement, indoctrination of the young through state control of al education. Hobbes went on to explain that the power of his sovereign was unlimited, but then added "otherwise than as he himself is the subject of God and bound thereby to observe the laws of nature. Later he observed that the laws of nature could be summed up in one sentence, "Do unto others as you would have them do unto you." So our basic axiom from Scripture and canon law has crept in by a back door. It may be that Hobbes was really an atheist and that such phrases are mere rhetoric. The point is, Hobbes was using the only rhetoric available to him and the only one likely to persuade the audi14. T. Hobbes, LEVIATHAN, 29. 15. 2 Id. at 21. 16. 2 Id. at 21, 26. This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 163] MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE 169 ence he wanted to persuade. Whatever his own religion, rated with the preconceptions of a Christian society. world of thought, the author of Leviathan could not even modern post-Christian monster, the totalitarian state. But I must get back to the Middle Ages. The persiste between church and state in that epoch not only impeded of absolutist doctrine. It stimulated new thinking abo tional rights. The most obvious one that came to be a direct result of the medieval conflicts between popes an the right of consent to government. When Pope Gregory depose King Henry IV in 1076, Henry declared that he w the grace of God." A papal supporter, Manegold of Laute testing this assertion, offered one of the first theories of based on consent and contract. At one point he inelegant the king to a hired swineherd who was removable by his people, if he failed to attend to his duties. More formall wrote, "If (the king) breaks the contract by which he w he has absolved the people from their duty of submissio It was not only papal supporters who used the argument sent. When, later on, the popes grew over-ambitious a claim that the power of all kings was derived from them found it expedient to use the same argument. John of Pa 1300) that a king did not derive his power from the pop God "and the people who elect or consent."18 A little lat of Padua, a more bitter anti-papalist, framed a pure doctr ernment by consent without any element of divine right. Marsilius' populist, anti-papalist, political theory was influenced in part by the practice of Italian city-state r there is an element of irony here. It was as allies of the p church-state conflicts of the twelfth century that the c Northern Italy, which would grow into the great city-s Renaissance, first won their freedom from imperial con was in those cities that the concept of civic rights-right ship-was first elaborately formulated. This mention of communes and cities leads to my th topic, the relationship of individual and community in m gious thought and in actual practice. The standard Marxi of Western rights theories is that they have always been b 17. Manegold of Lauterbach, in TIERNEY, supra note 13 at 78-80. 18. TIERNEY supra note 13, at 78-80, 206-210. This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 170 JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 5 ish individualism, "not on the association of man with man their separation." But medieval thought about rights was n on any such notion. It involved an awareness of the balance individual and community, one might say, of a creative ten tween them. This tension goes back to the beginnings of Christianity. Consider two texts from Paul's epistle to the Romans. In Romans 15 we read, "Each one of us will render an account of himself before Christ. .. ." There is no vision of human destiny more starkly individualistic than that of the last judgment that haunted medieval minds, when each soul would stand alone, naked, trembling before the divine judge. But now consider Romans 12, "We, although many, are one body in Christ," and again, "We are members one of another." Christian individualism was balanced by this vision of the church as one body, united to Christ as head, a body in which the members could help and sustain one another, spiritually through their prayers, and corporally through works of charity. This tension in Christian thought was mirrored by a tension in twelfth century social reality. So far, I have referred mainly to the individualism or humanism of that age. But this is a rather new understanding of twelfth century culture. Fifty years ago it was com- monly held that medieval people hardly had any sense of individuality, little awareness of themselves, except as members of corporate groups. We are now beginning to see that there is truth in both points of view. The twelfth century produced both brilliant self- aware individuals and an extraordinary, vigorous growth of new forms of corporate life-monasteries, cathedral chapters, collegiate churches, communes, boroughs, guilds, confraternities. Moreover, the very persons we most readily think of as vividly self-aware individuals were often associated with the growth of new kinds of communities-Bernard of Clairvaux and the Cistercians, Peter Abelard and the schools of Paris that grew into the University, Francis of Assisi and the vast Franciscan Order. The combination of intense individualism and intense corporatism may seem paradoxical but perhaps it is not really so. Human be ings become fully persons in intimate social intercourse with on another, not in desert-island isolation. Trying to explain the phenom enon, I wrote recently, "Perhaps it is only when persons become mor sharply aware of themselves as individuals that they need to reflec consciously on the rules by which they form themselves into organ- This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 163] MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE 171 ized groups."19 My point was that the actual growth of in the twelfth century was accompanied by a great new b cal thought about the nature of corporations, especially onists. Here again, as so often, medieval canon law w interaction between abstract theology and day to day so the new law of corporations, which affected the actual co dieval groups, was itself influenced by the theology of body. This was pointed out long ago by Maitland, th legal historians.20 More recently Ernst Kantorowicz has detail the interplay of theological and juridical concepts thought about the structure of corporate groups.21 One interplay was that the medieval corporation was often co a new way, not simply as an association of members but union of a head and members. Like Christ and the ch bishop and cathedral chapter, abbot and monks, mayor tion, eventually king and parliament. The same pattern and practice keeps recurring. Moreover medieval corpor developed by the canonists was intensely concerned with individuals within corporate communities. A cathedral c stance, by virtue of his membership in the corporate cat ter, held some rights in common with the other memb rights also included an individual right in his own preb re-which he could defend at law if necessary. As Mai with his usual epigrammatic force, "The corporation ag almost resolved into a mere collection of corporations s Again there was a link between these legal doctrines turn are related to Christian theological concepts-and t civil liberties in day to day life. For the vast extension of that occurred in the twelfth century came through the g ters of rights to corporate communities, churches, borou for instance; but often the rights were of a kind that cou exercised only by individuals, e.g. the right of a merchan go freely. Earlier medieval society had certainly recogn ual rights, especially feudal rights, but there was nothi egalitarian about them. A baron's right was typically an 19. B. TIERNEY, RELIGION, LAW AND THE GROWTH OF CONSTITUTIONAL THOUGHT 37 (1982). 20. POLLOCK AND MAITLAND. THE HISTORY OF ENGLISH LAW 495 (2d ed. 1898). "Now the idea of the Church as the mystical body of Christ has had an important influence on the growth of the law of corporations. ..." 21. E. KANTOROWICZ, THE KING'S TWO BODIES (1957). 22. POLLOCK & MAITLAND, supra note 20, at 507. This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 172 JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 5 from royal jurisdiction, a right to dominate others. One of cherished of feudal rights was the right to have a gallows. rights or liberties, exemptions from official meddling in cer of life, began to be granted to corporate communities, they new tone and quality and became diffused through much classes of the population. From the twelfth century on thousands of urban communities acquired such rights t purchase or negotiation or sometimes outright rebellion-ri freedom from arbitrary taxation and arbitrary arrest, free servile dues, the right to be tried by one's own townfolk i town court, and the right to elect a mayor and other city offic was rich soil where later more generalized theories of ci would take root and grow. As Alan Harding observed, "Urb ties gave content to the idea of individual liberty."23 Perhaps we can even fit Magna Carta into this context of ening civic liberties. There have been many interpretations enigmatic document. Some historians have seen it as a nobl of national liberty; others' at the opposite extreme, interpr selfish contrivance of reactionary feudal barons. Many Magna Carta do deal explicitly with the barons' feudal claim claims if you will. But others contain the great broad princi have echoed down the centuries in our common law. "No free man shall be taken or imprisoned . . . save by the lawful judgment of his peers and by the law of the land." "To no one will we sell, to no one will we deny or delay right or justice." The interpretations that dwell on the Charter's more generous provisions often emphasize the role of Stephen Langton, the great theologian and Archbishop of Canterbury, who negotiated on behalf of the barons. But recently J. C. Holt, while acknowledging Langton's influence, suggested a new way of looking at the Charter. He sees it as a vast communal privilege, inspired in part by the privileges already granted to various other corpo- rate communities like boroughs and cities. "Just as communal liberties had been won by a sworn association whereby citizens pledged themselves to fight for their liberties, so the barons pledged themselves to fight for the liberties of the realm." Holt adds that the barons "envisaged the establishment of one great 'commune of all the land'."24 He suggests that if we look at Magna Carta in this way- with reference to earlier communal charters of liberties-we can ex- 23. Harding, Political Liberty in the Middle Ages, SPECULUM 442 (July 1980). 24. J.C. HOLT, MAGNA CARTA 48-49 (1965). This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 163] MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE 173 plain without anachronism how the apparently "progre the Charter could naturally have found expression in a p dal document of the earlier thirteenth century. But a problem remains. Could anyone's mind, ar have made the conceptual leap involved in considering th ple of a realm as a corporate entity comparable to the city commune? Holt mentions in this connection the A stable Priory which refer to Magna Carta as a charter "c liberties of the realm." But this is still vague. The A assert that the whole realm could be conceived of as an single incorporated city. It is difficult to say anything Magna Carta at this date, but perhaps I can add anot information here. We now know a good deal about R res, the Prior of Dunstable at the time of Magna Carta days he had been a famous canonist, known to the l Bologna as Ricardus Anglicus; and in one of his canonis taries, discussing the origin of royal authority, Ricardu corporate body of a city can confer jurisdiction ... how the corporate body of a whole realm." It is precisely th that Holt suggests might have been present in people's Still Ricardus is only a witness to the mentalite of we are looking for an intersection of religious ideas an cepts in Magna Carta the most important figure is Langton who was actually there at Runnymede helping the terms of the Charter. We are learning more about His role in the drafting of Magna Carta was first strong perhaps exaggerated, by Kate Norgate. She wrote, " were drawn up by Stephen Langton with the concurrenc bishops who were at hand, and of the few lay barons, who were statesmen.... "26 This view has been contested. But most contemporary scholarly work attributes a substantial, though not exclusive, role to Langton in shaping the final version of Magna Carta Much of Langton's earlier theological work remains unedited, but w do know something about the views on law and political thought that 25. On the text of Ricardus see B. TIERNEY, RELIGION 22 (1982). The phrase communia totius terrae actually occurs in MAGNA CARTA Clause 61. Holt renders this as "the commun of the whole land" in accordance with his own understanding of the Charter (p. 335). Bu communia is usually translated more neutrally as "community." See, e.g., STEPHENSON AND MARCHAM, SOURCES OF ENGLISH CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY 125 (1937), "... the commu nity of the entire country .. ." 26. K. NORGATE, JOHN LACKLAND 234 (1922). This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION 174 [Vol. 5 he expressed in them.27 Like Richard de Mores, Langton re the people of a realm as forming one corporate community, envisaged them not as an enlarged city but rather as a m church, a congregatio fidelium-as behooved an archbishop a Langton maintained that the duty of a king was to defend t of layfolk and the peace of the church.28 He wrote that th should always espouse the cause of the poor "because the blo poor is the blood of Christ."29 Some parts of Magna Carta to understand if we try to see them through the eyes of a Langton and not just through those of a resentful feudal ba It remains true obviously, that the grant to free men ex whole population of serfs; but the point is that the whole political order was now being defined as a structure of right principle was capable of indefinite extension. Moreover the did not take so very long. Already by the fourteenth centur ment redefined Magna Carta's "free man" as any person "of estate or condition." And Parliament also redefined the vag the land" as meaning "due process of law"-already the phrase that has become so familiar to us.30 No doubt Ma came to mean many things that its framers had never inte doubt a myth of Magna Carta grew up. But, as Holt agai served, "The myth ... was part of the document's potential. was so because Magna Carta emerged from an exceptionally fertile medieval Christian culture. To understand documents like Magna Carta in all their complexity we need to know somet about the structure of medieval communities in general, and abou rights of individuals within those communities, and even about all-embracing vision of the church as a Christian community w which particular medieval institutions took shape. We have considered some complicated aspects of mediev thought. But the points I have made can be summed up in a few ple sentences. In the twelfth century a concern for the moral integr of human personality led to the first stirrings of natural rights ries. An autonomous church asserted its own rights and limited 27. The best introduction is still F.M. POWICKE, STEPHEN LANGTON (1928). 28. Quoted in J.W. BALDWIN, MASTERS, PRINCES AND MERCHANTS: THE SOCIA VIEWS OF PETER THE CHANTER AND HIS CIRCLE 111 (1970). "Just as it is for the cler elect a bishop, as it is for all the faithful of the realm ... to establish for themselves a rul may guard the rights of layfolk and the peace of the church." 29. G. DuBY, THE THREE ORDERS: FEUDAL SOCIETY IMAGINED 320 (1978). 30. F. THOMPSON, MAGNA CARTA: ITS ROLE IN THE MAKING OF THE ENGLISH CON- STITUTION 69 (1948). This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 163] MEDIEVAL PERSPECTIVE 175 power of the state so that it never be civic rights grew up within a context were shaped in part by the growing l have broader implications. They sugges did not have their origin either in ear medieval nominalism; rather they are r tion of Christian humanism that ha culture. This content downloaded from 132.174.250.220 on Mon, 08 Feb 2021 02:19:20 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms