Science as Culture, Volume 8, Number 3, 1999 269 RUBBISH VALUES: Reflections on the Political Economy of Waste MARTIN O'BRIEN To the east of Calcutta, in an area called Dhapa where the city's wastes are dumped, thousands of people gain a living from the rotting rubbish. They pick over the piles of garbage and other items which they sell to middlemen for recycling. Some use the heaps of rotting waste to grow vegetables which they sell in the city (Davidson et al, 1992, p. 120). There's gold in them there landfills ... Pots of it (Swanton, 1998, p. vii). Thus, we do not find certain things necessary or exclude other things from consideration because we have certain needs or wishes, but rather, our understanding of our own needs and wishes is shaped by the things that we find necessary or that we exclude from consideration (Hertzberg, 1995, p. 112). • INTRODUCTION There are some things in our lives so obvious, so glaringly, manifestly and ubiquitously essential to carrying on in the world that we often fail to take note of them. Their facticity is so apparent that, whilst they do not escape our consciousness entirely, they seem to be beyond question, beyond analysis and reflection. One clear example is the process and activity of wasting. This is particularly true in the social sciences, and especially in the discipline of sociology. Aside from some moral polemics about conspicuous or excessive consumption, sociology has shied away from any systematic analysis of the social processes by which things become 'waste' and the social relationships that sustain and organize wastes as wastes. Sociological approaches to waste treat it as a depletion, dissipation or loss of value—generally as a by-product of greed, inefficiency or distorted economic relations. The classic, and oft-affirmed, expression of this Address correspondence to: Martin O'Brien, School of Education and Social Science, University of Derby, Mickleover, Derby DE3 5GX, E-mail: m.a.obrien@derby.ac.uk 0950-5431/99/030269-27 © 1999 Process Press 270 SCIENCE AS CULTURE view is Vance Packard's (1963) The Waste Makers. Whilst there are libraries filled with sociological analyses of production and consumption, there is next to nothing on waste. It is as if, for the discipline of sociology as a whole, waste is utterly immaterial (O'Brien, 1999). In this paper, I argue that waste is culturally, politically and economically a matter of the greatest sociological significance: that waste has its own materiality and is organized and sustained through identifiable social and political relationships. Waste is gendered, embodied, stratified and capitalized, racialized, industrialized, militarized and signified because wasting—like producing or consuming—is a contested social process. Waste is not a by-product, an excess or superfluous shadow of the 'concrete5 systems of production and consumption. It is not in itself a remaindered energy (Bataille, 1991), the social surplus of a system of capitalized nature (O'Connor, 1994), the material residue of degraded products (Jackson, 1996) nor even, common-sensically, dirt or 'matter out of place' (Douglas, 1966). Just as it makes no sense to theorize a 'product' outside of its productive framework, or a 'commodity' outside of its consumption framework, I suggest that it makes no sense to theorize a 'waste' outside of its wasting framework. Production and consumption are intertwined dynamics of social change that, on an everyday level, are achieved through practices, relationships and institutions. In the same way, I argue, 'wasting' refers to a comparable dynamic of social change, the elements of which drive technological innovation, instil and challenge social rights, roles and rules of access, encode cultural representations, and organize political hierarchies and regulatory frameworks. I do not have the space to develop each of these themes as fully as they deserve. Instead, I explore how a sociological analysis of wastes (here, as classes of everyday material objects) and wasting (the practices, relationships and institutions organizing what happens to those objects) exposes the emergent quality of political-economic values. I make some remarks in the introduction on 'political economy' as a branch of study or intellectual discipline. In the main, however, I reserve the term 'political economy' to refer to a regulated social framework for transacting values, comprising an arrangement of practices, relationships and institutions. My aim is to explore some of the practical, relational and institutional connections RUBBISH VALUES 271 that sustain, disrupt or transform the flows of waste in which contemporary social life is enmired. For the purposes of this exploration, I define waste as simultaneously a production resource and a consumption good: a bipolar object of political regulation and economic exchange. I define wasting not as a loss of value from objects but as a regulated exchange of value between objects: a framework or system for the conversion of value comparable to, and equally important as, a system of production or consumption. I focus on wasting, as a social process of value-transformation, as a counterpoint to the analysis of waste, as an excess or surplus of production and consumption. 1 I develop this analytical framework because an important consequence of the definition of waste as surplus or excess is that the social processes through which wasting is organized are underresearched and under-theorized. Waste has ended up, categorically, in the ontological dustbin of social theory. This 'disposal' of waste from the human sciences' analytical endeavours achieves an apogee in Mary Douglas' (1966) definition of 'dirt' as 'matter out of place'. In the inspired analysis oí Purity and Danger, Douglas explored the taboos, rituals and symbols that construct and maintain dirt as a separate cultural category; as a cognitive out-take from normal social life. Dirt is on the 'other side' of order and life, a negative ontology that grounds cultural categories of being and non-being, rights and duties in the actions and interactions of people of different genders, ages and social statuses. This thesis, extended by Thompson (1979), has inhabited, almost alone, an arid terrain. Sociology, by neglect, has been content to understand waste through the same conceptual lens that Douglas conceptualized dirt, but how, exactly, does matter exist 'out of place', not only as a cultural category, but as a material reality? What is the materiality of dirt's out-of-placedness? In responding to this question, I want to turn Purity and Danger on its head and show how, through social actions, relationships and institutions, the matter of dirt is put back in place; how the cultural process identified by Douglas is reversed in the political economy of waste and wasting. If dirt is matter out of place, wasting is its reversal, the in-placing of dirt such that dirt, materially, if not common-sensically, is matter both in-place and out-of-place at the same time. In these respects, my argument draws on but diverges from both 272 SCIENCE AS CULTURE functionalist social anthropology and contemporary Marxist political economy. It diverges from functionalist social anthropology in its insistence that dirt, pollution or waste is much more than a cultural category: it is a socially organized material value underpinning divers sectors of economic and political activity. It diverges from contemporary Marxist political economy in that it focuses on wasting as a process of value conversion rather than as a vehicle for the systemic internalization of capitalist production conditions. I do not deny that either the cultural categorization of dirt or the internalization of such conditions is a significant point of departure for analyzing waste. Instead, I want to put an alternative thesis, namely, that the industrialized societies of the contemporary world, as I have explained elsewhere (O'Brien, 1999), are rubbish societies.2 They are societies whose modes of self-understanding, whose political, social and cultural systems are infused by a relationship to waste and wasting but which, at the same time, seek to deny the very fact that wasting is the basis on which those societies are able to develop and change. • THE DYNAMISM OF RUBBISH DISCOURSE An American Company, ETECH, has developed an entirely new way of cutting the landfill nappy burden. WeeTrain is a reusable miniature wetness detector which is slipped into a small, stretchy pocket on the wasteband of the nappy—and, used in conjunction with common sense training, is supposed to get babies out of nappies sooner (Green Futures, 1997, p. 15). Any culture that is capable of inventing, and rationalizing, an idea like 'landfill nappy burden' is a culture already steeped in a rubbish sensibility. It is a culture which sees its activities, interconnections, problems, opportunities and adventures as tied inextricably to wasting: that is, to processes, strategies and systems for dispersing, organizing, manipulating and wheeling and dealing in muck and filth. It is a culture to which muck and filth are central realities of everyday, institutional and imaginary life: the culture of a rubbish society. Compound phrases like 'landfill nappy burden' seem to suggest that waste is understood, that its 'burdens' can be counted and RUBBISH VALUES 273 controlled. But 'waste'—whether referring to nappies or otherwise— is a classic 'friction'; its imaginary referents never remain fixed: they generate personal representations and political discourses that grate against any culture that tries to tame them. The critical linguistics school would have a field day with the languages of industrialized ecology. They are the most productive and dynamic lexical fields of the present era, inventing and distributing new nouns and verbs at an astonishing rate of growth; but such languages are fully politicized, the referents they invoke are a feature of the growth of a political economy in which institutions and individuals are engaged in struggles over both meanings and material benefits: The [Packaging Responsibility Group] says in the medium to long term between £50m/yr and £100m/yr may be needed to stimulate activity to meet recovery targets, with £100m/yr by 2000 to realise objectives. The Lipworth Modified Converter Levy could then operate economically and should be introduced to raise funds from the packaging chain (Environment & Business Newsletter, 16 November 1994). When I first encountered the phrase 'Lipworth Modified Converter Levy' it reminded me of those early steam-driven apparatuses for raising water from mines—like the engine built by Thomas Newcomen at the dawn of the eighteenth century—a machine for extracting the unwanted in order to gain access to the desired. It turns out, however, that, superficially at least, not only is it nothing of the kind but it is the exact opposite of such a machine. It is a means of putting the desired into what appears to be unwanted, a means of adding value ('raising' coveted funds instead of hazardous water) or, at least, creating definite value where its status is ambiguous, where there is value to be had but no-one is able or willing to extract it. The levy exposes how absolutely necessary it is to establish a political economy in order for economic value to be realizable at all. There is not, in the case of waste, a prior political economy whose activities yield value to society. On the contrary, wasting represents a process of generating a political economy in order to confer values on objects. If waste, as the material form of collective dirt, is ambiguous this is because the process of wasting is a field of social, political and economic struggle. 274 SCIENCE AS CULTURE • NO SUCH THING AS DIRT? 'There is no such thing', writes Douglas (1966, p. 5), 'as absolute dirt: it exists in the eye of the beholder': If we shun dirt, it is not because of craven fear, still less dread or holy terror. Nor do our ideas about disease account for the range of our behaviour in cleaning or avoiding dirt. Dirt offends against order. Eliminating it is not a negative movement, but a positive effort to organise the environment. Dirt is an 'anomaly' that disturbs the certainty and pattern of life. It is culturally ambivalent. It is, at one and the same time, an essential element of cosmology and a disruption to that cosmology. Dirt and its symbols intervene in relations of gender, in ritual statuses and in the beliefs and hopes of a culture. Here, of course, is Douglas' famous paradox. 'Dirt' is matter out of place, it is matter that either is yet to be allotted its cultural and political space in the ordered world of a total culture or intrudes to disturb a culture's ordered totality. Yet, it is the very 'out of placedness' that makes dirt a meaningful cultural category. The very fact that dirt is 'out-placed', that it is wrongly or ill-fittingly located, is precisely what generates its unique and inescapable usefulness and worth. It is what enables a culture to distinguish—in its rules, norms, conventions and rituals—between order and disorder, being and non-being, life and death. It is something of a curiosity, then, that when Douglas turns her attention to the system of cultural goods (Douglas and Isherwood, 1979) the mis-located and out-placed dirt disappears from view. In the title and thematic structure of The World of Goods, dirt recedes to its pre-1966 invisibility. The world of goods is a world of desires and needs, of cultural systems and social relations, of wants, investments and wishes. Hence, the reader is urged to set 'the very idea of consumption ... back into the social process, not merely looked upon as a result or objective of work... Goods, work and consumption have been artificially abstracted out of the whole social scheme' (P- 12). Surprisingly, given the centrality of dirt and pollution in Purity and Danger, the 'whole social scheme' enunciated in The World of Goods no longer has any dirt in it. Dirt has evaporated from the anthropological schema by which Douglas and Isherwood seek to RUBBISH VALUES 275 make sense of the practice of consumption and the circulation of values that accompanies it. The World of Goods opens by asking why people want goods (chapter 1) why they save (chapter 2) and the uses of goods (chapter 3). It goes on to consider, amongst other things, consumption technologies, consumption periodicities and consumption classes. There is no chapter that says why (or how) people make dirt or waste goods, nor how dirt and waste enter and/or exit the cybernetic system. The book seeks to reorient social science's understanding of consumption behaviour and to redefine the nature of 'goods' in every field from economics to political science, yet strangely omits to acknowledge that the insight of Purity and Danger is of as much relevance to a system of consumption as it is to a system of ritual. The omission is not immaterial. It underpins a specific functional view of human needs and desires and represents the unspoken counterpoint to what a 'good' is and is not in The World of Goods. For example, Douglas and Isherwood write that 'Goods that minister to physical needs—food or drink—are no less carriers of meaning than ballet or poetry. Let us put an end to the widespread and misleading distinction between goods that sustain life and health and others that service the mind and heart—spiritual goods' (p. 72). This rhetorical flourish appears to make immediate sense: we can relate to the need for food and we can grant that some people may desire poetry. But what of goods that, superficially, satisfy neither 'physical' needs nor 'spiritual' needs? For example, Douglas and Isherwood contrast Brillat-Savarin's and Barthes' discussions of the process of coffee making. BrillatSavarin, we learn, 'preferred coffee beans pounded by hand in Turkish fashion' in a wooden mortar, whilst Barthes was interested in the poetics of bean-crushing and supplied a semiotics of the powdering process (pp. 73-4). Yet, neither Brillat-Savarin nor Barthes, nor beyond them Douglas and Isherwood, indicates what happened to the coffee dregs after the brew had been savoured. They do not explore whether the deep brown sludge that remained in the coffee maker goes on to satisfy any physical or spiritual need. Does this mean that the sludge is not a good? Has the act of drinking coffee transformed what the beans are made of from a 'good' to a 'non-good'? Or has it transformed only a cultural representation of the coffee beans from a visible 'good' to an invisible 'bad'? Has the 276 SCIENCE AS CULTURE drinking of the coffeed liquid banished the dregs from the perceptible world of goods? What is the sludge, the sediment that Brillat-Savarin's brew leaves behind it: is it a good or is it dirt? Later, in the same chapter, the idea of a sediment, a trace, a collection of dregs is introduced, but by this stage Douglas and Isherwood have left behind them the empirical reality of coffee making and the brown sludge it produces. Now, sediments have become unsedimented: they have transformed into a coral-like structure of cultural supports: The stream of consumable goods leaves a sediment that builds up the structure of culture like coral islands. The sediment is the learned set of names and names of sets, operations to be performed on names, a means of thinking (p. 75). Brillat-Savarin's brew, then, leaves two sediments, not one. It leaves a first sediment that is crucial to culture and to meaningful social life and it leaves a second sediment that, it must be inferred, is entirely superfluous and incidental to culture and meaningful social life. Whilst the sediment of the coffee-making ritual supports a 'means of thinking', the sedimented sludge of the coffee-making act is left unthought entirely—a matter of marginal significance. In the very last chapter of The World of Goods, one finally finds an oblique reference to the second sediment—a throwaway line in a political polemic for greater economic and social equality—when Douglas and Isherwood accuse the inhabitants of 'society's top floor' of: shortening everyone's time perspective for the sake of their own competitive anxiety, generating waste while at the same time deploring it (p. 203). What does this mean? Are Douglas and Isherwood saying that society's 'bottom floor' do not waste? Or that they waste but do not deplore it? Surely, given the thesis of Purity and Danger, no social stratum could be understood as existing without a relation to dirt, pollution, muck and waste? There are, it appears, two contradictory theses on 'goods' and 'dirt', both of which have been hugely influential in the study of culture and consumption: (cognitively) dirt is matter out of place RUBBISH VALUES 277 and (empirically) ritual sediments nurture cultural growth. Yet, it is feasible to maintain this double standard on the empirical and cognitive relationships between dirt and culture only if the materiality of Brillat-Savarin's second sediment is ignored entirely. • WHERE DIRT MATTERS In fact, the second sediment itself inhabits a world of values and transactions, inventions and discoveries: it motivates commercial innovation and political struggle. In short, there is such a thing as 'dirt'—and where there's dirt, there's money—but the 'anomaly' of dirt does not lie in the latter's own intrinsic danger or pollution, nor even in the cultural categories that out-place dirt from normal social life. Rather, the anomaly is that dirt is a consumption good: it is a refracted part of the 'world of goods' that comprises a scheme of production and consumption. Human scientists, including those whose central aim is to tackle the materiality of waste, find themselves in an ontological mire when confronted with the complexities of waste. Tim Jackson (1996), for example, in an eloquent and persuasive attempt to show the value of a thermodynamic systems model for understanding industrial activity, represents an economy as a series of discrete, albeit interconnected processes. He urges industrialists and policy-makers to take up a preventative ecological strategy in which the focus is on the most efficient circulation of resources around an economy, rather than on cleaning up 'wasted' resources after their inefficient linear use. I do not have the space here to do justice to the details of Jackson's argument so I will draw attention only to two dimensions of his analysis. First, I will comment on the relationships between 'waste' and 'economy'. Second, I want to comment on the systemic materiality of waste. First, Jackson writes (pp. 61-3): Having served their purpose, [...] degraded products then pass to a further material stage, which I have called waste management. After passing through the waste management sector, materials will leave the economic system and re-enter the environment (emphasis in original). Note that the 'waste management stage' must be accomplished in a 'waste management sector': waste management is only a 'stage' 278 SCIENCE AS CULTURE in a model that has already sectoralized economic relationships with the environment. What is the basis of the sectoralization? How, moreover, has it come about that 'waste management' has come into existence as a material sector of economic activity? What is the phenomenology of waste management? The answer is provided immediately: Often this last stage [i.e. materials leaving the economic system via the waste management sector and re-entering the environment] in the life of products is referred to as disposal. But this stage is not just a question of throwing materials away and forgetting about them. The product will depart from the economic system and even from our consciousness. But we should always remember that materials we have disposed of continue to be subject to the laws of nature (p. 63). Waste management, then, is the last stage before materials leave the economic system: wastes are not things that have already left the system, they are produced and reproduced by it. If they were not part of the system, they could not be managed by it. What is it, then, that 'leaves' the system? Jackson contends that it is 'materials' that leave the system. Yet this formulation of the process forgets that an economic 'system' refers not to an arrangement of material objects but, rather, to an arrangement of material values. It is, in simplified form, a system of values that effectuates personal and social opportunities and preclusions. No industrial sector exists because of the material objectivity of what it manages. Industrial sectors exist because of the values that can be extruded from the exchange of those objects. This is why what is waste today will not be waste tomorrow and why what was, common-sensically, waste yesterday is now incorporated as an economic 'sector'. Furthermore, no economic decision has ever been made on the basis of the material objectivity of products. Economic decisions are made on the basis of the material value of products: on the basis of what some use of some product may generate outside of its inherent material objectivity. Second, I am not disputing that materials may be subject to the operation of 'natural laws'. The point is that there are important differences between the industrial and the economic, as there are between the objective and the valuable. Material objectivity is not the basis of economic activity. Once it is recognized that an economy is RUBBISH VALUES 279 related only contingently to the objectivity of the things distributed within it, it is but a short step to recognizing that what leaves an economic system is not that objectivity. Objects never leave an economic system as such, because, qua their objectivity, they never enter it in the first place—even if, on another plane of analysis, it is granted that they may pass in and out of industrial sectors. Only certain dimensions of the values of material objects are economically depleted, converted and dispersed. Waste management is precisely the political economic activity that demonstrates this beyond doubt: 'waste' does not go away. If the physical and engineering sciences, as well as the human and policy sciences, have addressed waste as a temporary nuisance that can be 'cleaned up' or 'recovered', they struggle enormously to comprehend the immeasurable objectivity of nuclear 'waste'. Here is a material object that refuses to 'depart from the economic system'; one whose depletion is on a time scale so vast that it exceeds any conceivable scientific culture's capacity to 'clean up' the stains it leaves behind. Hence, the enormous current investment in trying to decipher the problem of whether radioactive reactor residues should be placed in a 'reversible' storage technology unambiguously within the economic system or in a partially 'safe' and 'irreversible' storage technology that seeks (impossibly) to 'dispose' of the problem. It is not my intention to undermine or reject what Jackson is arguing. Rather, I want to point out that the remarkable dominance of systems theory in contemporary applied social and environmental sciences is a cultural force, not a natural reflection of the reality of the world. In particular, the dominance of functionalist systems theory in applied social science and thermodynamic systems theory in applied environmental science has created some peculiar but telling homologies between completely different analytical enterprises. Compare Fine and Leopold (1993), for example, who (following Marx) distinguish between productive consumption and final consumption in a system of provision. Productive consumption refers to the commodities consumed by industry and the economic system in generating goods and services. Final consumption refers to the exit of commodities from the system of exchange through their use by individuals and groups. A system of provision, for Fine and Leopold, corresponds to the ways in which materials, investment, energy and labour are organized to realize a product or service. The 280 SCIENCE AS CULTURE most problematic, and least explored, element of this schema parallels the conceptual difficulties that Jackson's distinction between industrial and economic systems encountered. It is the idea that 'final consumption' represents the exit of commodities from a system of exchange. In the case of nuclear waste, it is strikingly obvious that, whilst it may lie around threatening planetary life even when it is not actively being 'exchanged', it cannot be said to have been 'finally consumed' by individuals and groups. Yet, nuclear waste only exposes in an obvious way what waste stands for: a means of managing the transformation of values characteristic of a world of goods. It indicates, clearly and frighteningly, that dirt matters: that dirt and waste have their own material objectivity that is not merely their 'outplacedness' and is not identical to the material objectivity of the 'needed' and 'desired' consumption goods in the formalized worlds of systems theory. Nuclear waste is the glowing tip of an (increasingly value-laden) rubbish heap that contains the brown sludge of Brillat-Savarin's brew, sensitizing us to the never-ending economic materiality of waste. • ALCHEMISTS OF THE RUBBISH SOCIETY On the night of 28 November 1988, Shanti lost her meagre possessions in the fire that consumed the makeshift houses in the Salimpur Netaji Colony, one of the many slums beside the railway track running through Calcutta. Shanti's shack was made of highly inflammable materials: plastic sheets, bamboo, jute bags and whatever else would give protection from the scorching sun and torrential rain (Davidson et al., 1992, p. 113). Let us imagine that, armed with some version of a systems model, the industrial sectors of the world's economies eliminated 99.9% of all their wastes: where would Shanti live? Out of what would Shanti and the millions of other oppressed, excluded and exploited people of the world build the scanty shelters that provide them with protection? If Shanti's house is constructed from the discarded and unwanted materials that have undergone their 'final consumption' phase, does this mean that her house is waste in the RUBBISH VALUES 281 common-sense meaning of this term: a superfluous and pointless nuisance? Or does it mean that the meagre construction materials of her home are not valuable enough for organized exploitation? What, then, is waste? 'Waste', I will suggest, is the archetypal consumption good of a rubbish society: 'simply another raw material', says Vasant Kumar of Cambridge University, that, with the help of modern day alchemists, can be turned into cash (Swanton, 1998, p. vii). But, contrary to popular opinion, the alchemists of the rubbish society are not primarily the scientists and technicians whose researches and inventions provide the industrial machinery for waste's rehabilitation. The alchemists of the rubbish society are town planners, environmental health departments, European Commissioners, Government Ministers and the Mafia: they are organized through bureaucratic and trading, rather than scholarly and scientific, organizations. The paraphernalia of their quasi-magical material conversions are definitions, plans and policies rather than gadgets, tools and gizmos. They thrive on the dynamism of rubbish and their political-economic role is precisely to maintain its material ambiguity: as matter out of and in place at the same time. It is this socially created and politically regulated ambiguity that underlies the economic value of dirt and determines that no social scheme is 'whole' without it: the material ambiguity of waste is the endlessly deferred completion of the social scheme of the rubbish society. I I Rubbish through the looking glass Obviously waste is a resource but waste ultimately is also a product for which no economic use has been found, can you see what I'm saying? I mean that's another way of defining it. It's a resource but anything you don't use as a resource is then a product for which economic use has not been found (17, p. 3. Interview with a Borough Client Services Officer, 27 September 1995). One of the striking characteristics of the materiality of rubbish is precisely how important it has become to extrude economic value from it. In contrast to common-sense conceptions of rubbish, it emerges that waste is not that which has no value; rather, it is that which motivates the search for value. The reference to finding an 282 SCIENCE AS CULTURE 'economic use' in the quote above is instructive: the search is not for a social or environmental or personal use. It is the search to renew, revitalize, refurbish and reaffirm the value of something that appears, superficially, to possess no value. Waste appears, here, as the mirror image of itself in itself: a resource and not a resource, a potential value and a potential non-value simultaneously. This is not a theoretical contradiction: it is the very being of waste in the rubbish society. In this society, the stage of final consumption is simultaneously the stage of productive consumption: the 'exit' of value from systems of exchange through their consumption and use by individuals is the immediate 'entry' of value into systems of exchange as materials for the generation of goods and services. In fact, waste never loses its consumption value, for the value of waste underpins major economic sectors, providing incomes for multinational conglomerates, local authorities and individual refuse operatives alike. Total UK spending on waste management alone— not including recycling, landfill-mining, and other forms of recovery—reached £2.8billion per annum in 1994. 'By 1995', notes Dicker (1997, p. 40): ... recycling had become a giant industry. The German Association for waste management and recycling, the BDE, had approximately 1,000 member firms and each employing about 150 people. Estimates for the total turnover of the industry lie between DM80 billion and DM100 billion. This puts it on a par with the insurance industry in Germany and well ahead of sectors such as telecommunications and engineering. It dwarfs the retail and steel sectors. The Danish waste tax—which was intended to minimize waste arising but which in fact merely led to a diversion of wastes from landfill to recycling schemes—netted DKr 625 million in its first year of operation {Warmer Bulletin 55, July 1997, p. 2). In this context, it is not surprising that one of the healthiest economic sectors of the present day is the waste sector. For example, Waste Management International announced pre-tax profits of £38.7 million for 1994, up 12.4% on 1993. Another waste management company, Shanks & McEwan, in spite of trading difficulties and internal boardroom disputes, made half year profits of £9.4 million in 1993; similar high profit ratios characterize much of the waste industry. As might be RUBBISH VALUES 283 expected in a market of this kind, even the insurance industries have been keen to cash in by establishing separate environmental management and risk services to cope with the increasing demand for environmental insurance specifically arising from wastes and pollution. Companies are merging and re-organizing to become stronger in the face of increasing competition in the provision of environmental (financial) services. Nor, in this context, is it surprising that the competitive struggle to extract value from waste has resulted in fierce legal contests between contractors and between contractors and local authorities. Private waste contractors have challenged each other in the courts in order to wrest lucrative waste contracts away from competitors (Riley, 1995). They have also challenged local authorities via the same route in order to make sure that no-one involved in planning and decision-making about waste can own shares in any waste disposal companies competing for contracts (Environment and Business Newsletter, 22 September 1993, p. 2), In this profitable, intensely competitive and highly active field one might expect that the 'product' with which the industry deals would be relatively clear cut; that all of the contributors in this stream of economic values would know exactly what they were dealing with, but this is not at all the case. The policy definition of 'waste' is purposefully ambiguous with no clear statement about the substance out of which the former is made. In some cases, 'waste' has been defined as a fuel for energy. This definition has been developed partly in order to enable a number of European states (notably the UK) to achieve an increase in the proportion of energy generated from 'renewable' sources. The idea that any portion of the 500 million tonnes of industrial, commercial, agricultural and household garbage constitutes a 'renewable resource' is a leap of imagination so large it can only be accounted for by asserting that some people have vested interests in its incineration. In other cases, a semantic and logical carousel has been erected to cope with the divergent and conflicting interests that have become entrenched in the exchange and management of rubbish. The UK Environmental Protection Act (EPA) [part II; section (75) 2] argues that an item which is waste may cease to be waste when it has been recovered within the meaning of the Framework Directive. In other words, you can never be sure that something really is 'waste' because waste exists only so long as it inhabits a defined waste-management 284 SCIENCE AS CULTURE stream—and even there, paradoxically, it generates value, whereupon it is not waste at all. For example, a used bottle that is reused by refilling it is not waste (it has been 'recovered'). The same bottle in a bottle bank that gets crushed and is reused later for a different purpose is waste according to the EPA. Although the material objectivity of the bottle is the same and although in both cases the bottle is used again for a second time, nonetheless, one placing of the bottle makes it 'not waste' and the other placing makes it 'waste'. Yet, even in its second placing, the 'waste' bottle is not an object for which an 'economic use has not been found'. 'Waste', then, is a multipurpose and multidimensional object providing several distinct satisfactions for its different users. It occupies the market niches of: fuel, recoverable, recyclable, residue or dredgings (amongst others), all of which circulate in different economic and political networks, and all of which in practice, in spite of (and sometimes because of) the EPA, are subject to different regulation and valuation systems. The waste 'sector' is a transformative political economy that bestows different values on objects that are never economically 'wasted' but, rather, undergo a process of valueconversion. If consumption is the mirror of production, waste is simultaneously the reflection and refraction of both. • THE CONVERSION OF VALUE [In] order to satisfy the demands of large-scale production, more and more of nature has to be destroyed. In this sense production under capitalism is consumption, not production; it gobbles that which is already there, and gives nothing back but waste (Brennan, 1993, p. 138). Since it depends on 'no longer being with', waste is nothing as such, it has a negative ontology. Waste is thus always in excess of being and—in Heidegger's terms—cannot be taken as 'ready-to-hand' (an investment of entities with human signification) as long as waste remains 'that which is to be shed' (van Loon, 1997, pp. 8-9). It is common to conceive of waste as 'nothing'. Yet, precisely RUBBISH VALUES 285 nothing could be further from the truth than this: every placement, every channelling, every organization of waste delivers a positive value to someone, somewhere.3 It involves an organization of labour (and an arrangement for its exploitation), a negotiated pricing system, a formalized system for carrying values from one institution to another, and a political hierarchy of controls and licensing conditions to co-ordinate membership of the waste-exploiting club (such as the European Waste Club, based in Madrid, or the National Association of Waste Disposal Contractors, based in London). In fact, it is more important that these relationships are established around wastes than for any other potential commodity for the simple reason that nobody owns them. Of all the commodities of industrial societies, wastes are certainly the most peculiar insofar as they are the only profitgenerating commodities that no-one seeks to possess: when a journalist is caught rooting through the bin-bags of celebrities s/he is charged, not with theft of property, but with trespass or invasion of privacy. Wastes are licensed to different organizations in different stages of their perpetually commodified lives in order to distribute the values they provide; but no-one 'owns' them. Whereas, for example, the UK Minerals Authority owns all the coal under the British Isles, there is no comparable UK Waste Authority that owns all the rubbish in your attic and your kitchen swing-bin (yet!). The consequence of this strange state of affairs is the emergence of ingenious forms of valuation. The 'Lipworth Modified Converter Levy', referred to above, is only one example of a network of competing valuation systems. Another example is the emergence of new forms of currency through which to trade wastes, such as the system of Packaging Recovery Notes (colloquially known as 'Prunes') which can be traded against the costs of packaging recycling and, ultimately, exchanged for cash. This is a new scheme which aims to increase the economic benefits of packaging recycling by formalizing and streamlining the trade-ability and saleability of waste commodities. Alternatively, the cash prices paid for waste commodities (such as glass) can be varied regionally (Environment and Business Newsletter, 22 September 1993, p. 5), in order to offset the transport costs of moving the rubbish raw materials from source to processor, or the values of those commodities can be 'weighted' according to where and how their values are channelled— through recycling, incineration or disposal arrangements, for 286 SCIENCE AS CULTURE example (Environment and Business Newsletter, 6 October 1993, p. 1). Lest it be thought that such schemes are simply marginal efforts to extract the insignificant traces of value from commodities that are on their last economic legs, Bontoux et al. (1996, pp. 9-10) remind us that: The amounts of resources at stake are enormous: tens of millions of tonnes of each [recyclable] material across Europe. The market forces have so far been clearly unable to fully mobilize this potential resource but this does not mean that recycling these currently lost resources cannot be profitable. Today, out of 600 million tonnes of secondary raw materials generated every year in the world, 200 million are traded internationally. The amounts and values of those resources are so enormous, in fact, that they attract the attentions of organized (as well as unorganized) crime: Ministers from the world's richest nations will today launch a crackdown on a 'phenomenal' increase in green crime. Smuggling banned chemicals, waste and wildlife—often by the Mafia—is now worth up to $40bn (£24bn) a year, making it the biggest illegal trade after drugs (Lean, 1998, p. 4). This last quotation illuminates Michael Thompson's (1998, p. 62) assertion that 'something like' a law of waste would be: 'the greater the physical and social distance waste travels the more shadiness there will be'. The point is that there exists a political economy of rubbish— with both licit and illicit forms—that is identifiable in its own right. There is no justification for conceiving of waste as 'nothing' or merely as an excess of consumption or 'being'. Waste, contra to the sociological canon bequeathed by Simmel (1990) and Veblen (1953), and proposed with vigour by Deleuze and Guattari (1983) and Bataille (1991), is neither the by-product of conspicuous consumption nor the remaindered energy of an excessive economy. Waste has its own positive being in a society awash with rubbish: a being that is a manufactured part of the world of goods and involves labour, exchange, licensing, regulation and profiteering. Elsewhere RUBBISH VALUES 287 (O'Brien, 1999; O'Brien and Penna, 1998; following Schultz, 1993), I have noted that recycling schemes, dependent on unpaid labour in the household, comprise a form of extractive labour which targets economically valuable objects in the industrial-domestic complex and supplies industry with a steadily increasing supply of raw materials. To return to my earlier theoretical discussion, here is a classic case of 'final consumption' (the exit of goods from a system of economic values) serving as 'productive consumption' (the entry of economic values as a system of goods). Many industries currently manufacture products with a view to their re-entry into systems of provision—many bottles and cans, packets and paper, cars and even supermarket trolleys are now made as objects that can be recycled when the appropriate political economic arrangements for realizing their value are in place. A portion of material value, as an element of productive consumption, is built into the commodity form of the object as an element of the process of final consumption. Hence, waste is not a joint or nearly identical product of consumer goods (Hardin, 1998, p. 10). It comprises, increasingly, what the product actually is. 'Waste' appears as a rising proportion of the commodity-value of production, and 'wasting' as an increasingly central condition of productive activity. Moreover, the 'building in' of value is not merely a technical achievement. In order to valorise rubbish-capital an arrangement of institutional relationships must be established that organizes more or less stable channels through which rubbish-values can flow. It is necessary, in short, to create rubbish-relationships, to organize the wasting process politically and temporally. Recycling is perhaps the most easily recognizable social arrangement of a rubbish political economy but it would be wrong to presume that it is the only such arrangement. Value is given to rubbish by burning it as well as by burying it, storing it or mining it. Consider the case of 'thermal recycling'—burning rubbish in an incinerator to generate energy. Burning rubbish is a complex task that is regulated under law—in some English Boroughs householders are not allowed to burn their own garden waste and setting fire to your old mattresses or the pile of old cardigans at the bottom of your wardrobe can land you in court. Just as individual householders are subject to the strictures of the legal system, so companies who apply for licences to burn waste in commercial incinerators must comply 288 SCIENCE AS CULTURE with a welter of environmental, health and safety regulations. But the commercial task is yet more complicated by the fact that the value-channels—the ways of realizing the economic values of rubbish—are fully politicized: the contexts in which the values of wastes are converted, the temporal rhythms of the conversion process and the addition or subtraction of different means of conversion are dynamic elements in the management and extraction of value. LJ Rubbish relationships The movement of rubbish values through institutionally regulated networks demands both the creation of economic relationships between 'rubbish' and other objects and services and the negotiation of periodicities, or temporal phases during which rubbish releases its economic values for exploitation. Such periodicities must parallel the investment, monitoring and accounting cycles of the industries and enterprises that take charge of different components of the rubbish channels. These two conditions comprise a commodification relationship—a negotiated order of value that is inflected by government policy, the market price of related goods and services and the constraints and opportunities facing waste transporters, contractors and licensers. The commodification of waste is illuminating because it reveals that, in order to valorise rubbish-capital, it is necessary to intervene into the relationships between specific institutions and organizations. Commodification is not a single transformative act that suddenly determines a market price for an object: it is a moment in a complex realignment of institutional relationships that draws on and, in some cases, disrupts, the values of other commodified objects. For example, O'Brien et al. (1996) noted that the commodity value of waste as a fuel for energy generation has been inflected by the politically motivated privatization of the utilities. The research reports that a Local Authority Environmental Services Committee met to discuss the construction of an energy-generating waste incinerator as a solution to their waste management problems. Amongst other things, the Committee noted that: Electricity privatisation has ushered in a new method of subsidising renewable energy projects and waste is considered as a renewable fuel. In future, such waste to energy projects as RUBBISH VALUES 289 [the project] would be supported by a levy on all electricity users, known as the non-fossil fuel obligation (Minutes of an Environmental Services Committee, p. 2; cited in O'Brien et al, 1996, p. 96). The 'renewability' of waste—i.e. the definition of waste as a non-diminishing resource—is a compact acknowledgement of altered relationships between Local Authorities responsible for waste management and private sector operatives battling to profit from waste. The Local Authority has a vested interest in retaining some influence over the plant (in order to ensure that its 'renewable' waste management strategy is 'sustainable') but the plant operator has a vested interest in avoiding contributions to Local Authority services under the 1989 Local Government and Housing Act. Consequently, a financial and regulatory compromise between the private energygeneration company and the Local Authority has to be reached. Thus, the Local Authority proposes: An equity investment of.£5M to justify investors' confidence in the project. [Borough consortium's] maximum equity investment indicated at 18% i.e. £900,000 in order to exclude [the company] from local authority company control provisions of the Local Government and Housing Act 1989 [Ibid, appendix A, p. l/c3; cited in O'Brien et al., 1996, p. 96). Here, the Local Authority takes an investment decision about project development based on the political and economic constraints enshrined in the 1989 Act. The decision protects the project from section 52 of the Act covering private-public sector commercial arrangements. By taking a specific level of equity in the project, the Local Authority offsets the benefits gained from a return on investment in the scheme against the regulations under which the company would have to operate if the initial investment were higher. These data extracts are introduced to illustrate that negotiations around the commodity status of objects are often not directed towards the objects themselves but towards the socio-economic and political transactions through which the object must pass in order for it to be a commodity. The commodification of wastes depends on establishing relationships between public and private organizations 290 SCIENCE AS CULTURE because they each separately have access to different techniques and opportunities for realizing the values of wastes. The commodification of waste goods and services is not a single situation, a once-and-for-all event. Instead, it is a negotiation of values and balancing of costs. The report from Her Majesty's Inspectorate of Pollution (as was) authorizing the construction of the plant uses the familiar formula to protect plant operators from too much liability: The authorisation is subject to the conditions in Schedules 1 to 8 [of the EPA]. Aspects of the process not regulated by those conditions are subject to a general condition implied by section 7(4) of the 1990 Act that the person carrying it on must use the best available techniques not entailing excessive cost [BATNEEC] (cited in O'Brien et al.s 1996, p. 95). A complex political and economic agenda addressing the financial, investment and technical details of the plant's construction and operation is reduplicated in the conditions under which the plant carries out its waste-managing and energy-generating services. These services similarly criss-cross a number of social and economic transactions, persisting at several distinct levels. It can be noted, for example, that the waste-managing, energy-generating company consists of three contractual sections: private members of the company (construction and operations contracts); sale of electricity (Electrical Supply Industry); and supply of refuse (sponsoring Local Authorities). Each of these groups holds different responsibilities and has different interests in the scheme's commodities. Furthermore, the Local Authority stipulated a condition on the acceptability of the plant to the effect that the business will ensure protection from market forces for 20 years in the first instance. Thus, the Local Authority is protected from the market and the company is protected from political controls over its operations and both have entered into an agreement to renew the resource 'waste' for a specified period of time. The commodity of waste is thereby conditioned (market and political protection) and established temporally (the phase lasts for 20 years). At the same time, the parameters of the commodity are divided into three discrete, albeit connected, units: operation, (energy-) service supply and fuel (or 'raw materials') supply. RUBBISH VALUES 291 'Waste'—as a corporal manifestation of dirt in contemporary society—is ambiguous not because of its culturally anomalous role in human relationships. It is ambiguous because it is organized as such in a political economy of rubbish values. Again, what is waste? ... my normal response would be it's [i.e. waste] a material at the end of a chain of use and re-use, that no longer has any particular value but then there is the caveat of course of waste that then goes on to produce energy from combustion you could argue still has some value. So it might well be that other than that it would be the final residue of the final process which has drawn out all valuable commodities from a material and I am talking then of the final residue—whatever that might be (I93 p. 1. Interview with a Principal Environmental Health Officer, 1996). The 'final' residue; 'whatever that might be': what 'final residue'? Is the 'final residue' the roofing of Shanti's shack, or does this latter constitute the commodity-form of a valuable material? Is the 'final residue' the object that is left after what Fine and Leopold name 'final consumption'? Or is the final residue a phantasmatic residue of value that resists the efforts of industrial sectors to economize their total operations? In fact, the 'final' residue is never reached for there is never a final residue of value: the final residue, as it is exposed here, is the trace of a political economy that never reaches completion: it is the unrepresentable constituent of a political economy in a state of perpetual emergence. Indeed, this emergent quality of the political economy of waste is a driving force in European integration: it is an economy of valuecomparability and a struggle over what tactics will most effectively marketize waste. This is precisely the position of the European Commission, whose review of the 5th Action Programme on the Environment proposed that:, The EU should develop instruments for achieving more effective waste management, such as taxes or charges, re-use or recovery systems, and along with the Member States of the EU should explore the possibilities for the creation and functioning of markets for recycled products (Stern, 1996, p. 42). 292 SCIENCE AS CULTURE Anyone, today, foolhardy enough to believe the neo-liberal mantra that markets, left to themselves, will result in the 'efficient' use of materials, energy and labour should examine the market for waste. This is a market whose rational economic actors are begging, cajoling, threatening and coercing the states of Europe to intervene politically into the circulation of wastes precisely because the 'spontaneous' emergence of markets does not generate the values that they want out of the rubbish heap. The instruments of this extended economy of rubbish values involve the law courts, Government ministries and departments, import-export regulations and taxpayers' subsidies of waste company operations. These instruments certainly streamline and channel the values of waste commodities but they appear to do nothing at all to stop waste arising. In fact, it appears that their aim and purpose is quite different: not to reduce waste arisings at all but to organize their profitability in a rubbish political economy. • CONCLUSION To transform the valueless into the valuable, the repugnant into the desirable, dirt into matter (in short, to reverse the process of putting matter 'out of place', as Mary Douglas defines dirt) is an impressive feat of political and technical development. It requires changes in social and economic policy, manipulations of national and international law, the development of networks and markets through which the values of muck and garbage can be realized, the organization of monitoring and accountancy systems and the instigation of new technical procedures for containing and channelling the materials as they flow from the depths of excrescence to the heights of affluence. If you add up all of the 'values' that rubbish represents you will find that, if any drastic change in our relationships to waste were to occur, economies would shudder if not die. If, tomorrow, the industrialized societies of the world decided no longer to produce and distribute the values of rubbish, the ensuing global economic shocks would make the recession of the 1930s look like a mislaid ten dollar bill. So, finally, the 'Lipworth Modified Converter Levy' really does make sense: it is an enigmatic engine indeed comparable to the RUBBISH VALUES 293 Newcomen steam apparatus but it is a political economic invention, rather than a mechanical invention, for raising value from rubbish. • Acknowledgements I am very grateful to Les Levidow, Martin O'Connor, Joost van Loon and Tom Horlick-Jones for comments, suggestions and advice on this paper. Thanks to Hugh McLachlan for the Hertzberg reference. D NOTES 1. In what follows, I use the terms 'rubbish' and 'waste' interchangeably. This is not because I am insensitive to the nuanced differences between their everyday meanings but because I am primarily concerned to demonstrate waste's political, social and economic materiality. Aside from some preliminary comments below, I leave a more detailed analysis of rubbish discourses for an ensuing paper. The paper is based in part on ESRC/EPSRC-funded research into coal and waste as fuels for energy-generation [Economic and Social Research Council/Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council research project funded under the Global Environmental Change programme, award number L320253136: 'An Environmental and Social Life Cycle Comparison of Coal and Waste as Fuels']. Extracts from interviews and industry documents presented in the paper derive from the data collected for that project, some of which appear in O'Brien et al. (1996). The paper is part of a developing personal research programme into the sociology of waste and wasting. My longer-term aim is to exhibit and, at least partially, rectify sociology's ignorance of the discourses and social processes in which waste is embroiled. 2. I define such societies in O'Brien (1999) as apogenic societies. 'Apo' from the Greek aporipto—to throw out or excress—combined with genic from Greek/Latin genesis. Such societies are apogenic to the extent that the means by which they seek to remove and dispose of ostensibly valueless rubbish creates the appearance of a value in commodified wastes. The phrase 'apogenesis' is an allusion to Ivan Illich's term 'iatrogenesis'. Thanks again to Anna Tsatsaroni for helping me with this; any error is mine. 3. I am not suggesting that such placements and channellings do not have negative effects. I am merely observing that, in the context of the positive political economy of waste I am unravelling, there is no warrant for the theoretical proposition that waste is 'nothing' or comprises a negative ontology. D REFERENCES Bataille, G. (1991) The Accursed Share: an Essay on General Economy, Vol. 1: Consumption, translated by Robert Hurley. New York: Zed Books. First published in 1967, Paris: Les Editions de Minuit. 294 SCIENCE AS CULTURE Bontoux, L., Leone, F., Nocolai, M. and Papameletiou, D. (1996) The Recycling Industry in the European Union: Impediments and Prospects. Draft of a study performed by the Institute for Prospective Technological Studies [IPTS] for the Committee on Environment, Public Health and Consumer Protection of the European Parliament. Sevilla, Spain: European Commission Joint Research Centre/IPTS. Brennan, T. (1993) History After Lacan. London: Routledge. Davidson, J., Myers, D. and Chakraborty, M. (1992) No Time to Waste: Poverty and the Global Environment. Oxford: Oxfam. Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1983) Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Dicker, J. (1997) 'The ring cycle', Green Futures, 7: 40-41. Douglas, M. (1966) Purity and Danger: An Analysis of Concepts of Pollution and Taboo. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Douglas, M. and Isherwood, B. (1979) The World of Goods: Towards an Anthology of Consumption. London: Allen Lane. Fine, B. and Leopold, E. (1993) The World of Consumption. London: Routledge. Hardin, R. (1998) 'Garbage in, garbage out', Social Research, Special Issue: 'Garbage', 65(1): 9-30. Hertzberg, Lars (1995) 'What a waste!', in Ralf Eriksson and Marcus Jäntti (Eds), Economic Value and Ways of Life. Aldershot: Avebury. Jackson, T. (1996) Material Concerns: Pollution, Profit and the Quality of Life. London: Routledge. Lean, G. (1998) 'Rich nations target rising green crime', Independent on Sunday, 5 April 1998: 4. O'Brien, M. (1999) 'Rubbish power: towards a sociology of the rubbish society', in J. Hearn and S. Roseneil (Eds), Consuming Cultures: Power & Resistance. Basingstoke: MacMillan. O'Brien, M., Clift, R. and Doig, A. (1996) Social and Environmental Life Cycle Assessment: Report of a Research Project. University of Surrey, Private Print. O'Brien, M. and Penna, S. (1998) 'Political ecology', in M. O'Brien and S. Penna (Eds), Theorising Welfare: Enlightenment and Modern Society. London: Sage. O'Connor, M. (1994) 'Entropy, liberty and catastrophe: on the physics and metaphysics of waste disposal', in P. Burley and J. Foster (Eds), Economics and Thermodynamics: New Perspectives on Economic Analysis. Dordrect/London: Kluwer. Packard, V. (1963) The Waste Makers. Harmondsworth: Pelican. Riley, K. (1995) 'Waste contracting: some observations from a developer'. Presentation to the Seminar organized by ETSU on behalf of the Department of Trade and Industry, Energy from Waste '95, St. John's Swallow Hotel, Solihull, 20 April. Schultz, I. (1993) 'Women and waste', Capitalism, Nature, Socialism, 4(2): 51-63. Simmel, G. (1990) The Philosophy of Money, edited by David Frisby, translated by Tom Bottomore and David Frisby. London: Routledge (second edition). First published 1900. RUBBISH VALUES 295 Stern, A. (1996) Environment: New European Policies for 1996-2000. The Mid-term Review of the European Union's Fifth Action Programme, study written for the conference organized by the Club de Bruxelles, 15-16 February 1996. Swanton, O. (1998) 'Tips for fortune-seekers', The Guardian Higher, 3 February 1998: vii. Thompson, M. (1979) Rubbish Theory: The Creation and Destruction of Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Thompson, M. (1998) 'Waste and fairness', Social Research, Special Issue: 'Garbage', 65(1), 55-73. van Loon, J. (1997) 'The embodiment of waste: untimely reflections on the biopolitics of technocracy', paper presented to the Time and Value conference organized by the Institute for Cultural Research, Lancaster University, 10-13 April 1997. Veblen, T. (1953) The Theory of the Leisure Class. New York: Mentor.